fbpx
Wikipedia

Dialectic

Dialectic (Greek: διαλεκτική, dialektikḗ; German: Dialektik), also known as the dialectical method, refers originally to dialogue between people holding different points of view about a subject but wishing to arrive at the truth through reasoned argumentation. Dialectic resembles debate, but the concept excludes subjective elements such as emotional appeal and rhetoric.[1] It has its origins in ancient philosophy and continued to be developed in the Middle Ages.

Hegelianism refigured "dialectic" to no longer refer to a literal dialogue. Instead, the term takes on the specialized meaning of development by way of overcoming internal contradictions. Dialectical materialism, a theory advanced by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, adapted the Hegelian dialectic into a materialist theory of history. The legacy of Hegelian and Marxian dialectics has been criticized by philosophers such as Karl Popper and Mario Bunge, who considered it unscientific.

Dialectic implies a developmental process and so does not naturally fit within classical logic. Nevertheless, some twentieth-century logicians have attempted to formalize it.

History edit

There are a variety of meanings of dialectic or dialectics within Western philosophy.

Classical philosophy edit

In classical philosophy, dialectic (διαλεκτική) is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter-arguments, advocating propositions (theses) and counter-propositions (antitheses). The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition, or of a synthesis, or a combination of the opposing assertions, or a qualitative improvement of the dialogue.[2][3]

The term "dialectic" owes much of its prestige to its role in the philosophies of Socrates and Plato, in the Greek Classical period (5th to 4th centuries BC). Aristotle said that it was the pre-Socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea who invented dialectic, of which the dialogues of Plato are examples of the Socratic dialectical method.[4]

Socratic method edit

The Socratic dialogues are a particular form of dialectic known as the method of elenchus (literally, "refutation, scrutiny"[5]) whereby a series of questions clarifies a more precise statement of a vague belief, logical consequences of that statement are explored, and a contradiction is discovered. The method is largely destructive, in that false belief is exposed and only constructive in that this exposure may lead to further search for truth.[6] The detection of error does not amount to a proof of the antithesis. For example, a contradiction in the consequences of a definition of piety does not provide a correct definition. The principal aim of Socratic activity may be to improve the soul of the interlocutors, by freeing them from unrecognized errors, or indeed, by teaching them the spirit of inquiry.

In common cases, Socrates uses enthymemes as the foundation of his argument.[citation needed]

For example, in the Euthyphro, Socrates asks Euthyphro to provide a definition of piety. Euthyphro replies that the pious is that which is loved by the gods. But, Socrates also has Euthyphro agreeing that the gods are quarrelsome and their quarrels, like human quarrels, concern objects of love or hatred. Therefore, Socrates reasons, at least one thing exists that certain gods love but other gods hate. Again, Euthyphro agrees. Socrates concludes that if Euthyphro's definition of piety is acceptable, then there must exist at least one thing that is both pious and impious (as it is both loved and hated by the gods)—which Euthyphro admits is absurd. Thus, Euthyphro is brought to a realization by this dialectical method that his definition of piety is not sufficiently meaningful.

In another example, in Plato's Gorgias, dialectic occurs between Socrates, the Sophist Gorgias, and two men, Polus and Callicles. Because Socrates' ultimate goal was to reach true knowledge, he was even willing to change his own views in order to arrive at the truth. The fundamental goal of dialectic, in this instance, was to establish a precise definition of the subject (in this case, rhetoric) and with the use of argumentation and questioning, make the subject even more precise. In the Gorgias, Socrates reaches the truth by asking a series of questions and in return, receiving short, clear answers.

Plato edit

In Platonism and Neoplatonism, dialectic assumed an ontological and metaphysical role in that it became the process whereby the intellect passes from sensibles to intelligibles, rising from idea to idea until it finally grasps the supreme idea, the first principle which is the origin of all. The philosopher is consequently a "dialectician".[7] In this sense, dialectic is a process of inquiry that does away with hypotheses up to the first principle.[8] It slowly embraces multiplicity in unity. The philosopher Simon Blackburn wrote that the dialectic in this sense is used to understand "the total process of enlightenment, whereby the philosopher is educated so as to achieve knowledge of the supreme good, the Form of the Good".[9]

Medieval philosophy edit

Logic, which could be considered to include dialectic, was one of the three liberal arts taught in medieval universities as part of the trivium; the other elements were rhetoric and grammar.[10][11][12][13]

Based mainly on Aristotle, the first medieval philosopher to work on dialectics was Boethius (480–524).[14] After him, many scholastic philosophers also made use of dialectics in their works, such as Abelard,[15] William of Sherwood,[16] Garlandus Compotista,[17] Walter Burley, Roger Swyneshed, William of Ockham,[18] and Thomas Aquinas.[19]

This dialectic (a quaestio disputata) was formed as follows:

  1. The question to be determined ("It is asked whether...");
  2. A provisory answer to the question ("And it seems that...");
  3. The principal arguments in favor of the provisory answer;
  4. An argument against the provisory answer, traditionally a single argument from authority ("On the contrary...");
  5. The determination of the question after weighing the evidence ("I answer that...");
  6. The replies to each of the initial objections. ("To the first, to the second etc., I answer that...")

Modern philosophy edit

The concept of dialectics was given new life at the start of the 19th century by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, whose dialectical model of nature and of history made dialectics a fundamental aspect of reality, instead of regarding the contradictions into which dialectics leads as evidence of the limits of pure reason, as Immanuel Kant had argued.[20][21] Hegel was influenced by Johann Gottlieb Fichte's conception of synthesis, although Hegel didn't adopt Fichte's "thesis–antithesis–synthesis" language except to describe Kant's philosophy: rather, Hegel argued that such language was "a lifeless schema" imposed on various contents, whereas he saw his own dialectic as flowing out of "the inner life and self-movement" of the content itself.[22]

In the mid-19th century, Hegelian dialectic was appropriated by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels and retooled in what they considered to be a nonidealistic manner. It would also become a crucial part of later representations of Marxism as a philosophy of dialectical materialism. These representations often contrasted dramatically and led to vigorous debate among different Marxist groups.[23]

Hegelian dialectic edit

The Hegelian dialectic describes changes in the forms of thought through their own internal contradictions into concrete forms that overcome previous oppositions.[24]

This dialectic is sometimes presented in a threefold manner, as first stated by Heinrich Moritz Chalybäus, as comprising three dialectical stages of development: a thesis, giving rise to its reaction; an antithesis, which contradicts or negates the thesis; and the tension between the two being resolved by means of a synthesis.[25][26]

By contrast, the terms abstract, negative, and concrete suggest a flaw or an incompleteness in any initial thesis. For Hegel, the concrete must always pass through the phase of the negative, that is, mediation. This is the essence of what is popularly called Hegelian dialectics.[27]

To describe the activity of overcoming the negative, Hegel often used the term Aufhebung, variously translated into English as "sublation" or "overcoming", to conceive of the working of the dialectic. Roughly, the term indicates preserving the true portion of an idea, thing, society, and so forth, while moving beyond its limitations. What is sublated, on the one hand, is overcome, but, on the other hand, is preserved and maintained.[28]

As in the Socratic dialectic, Hegel claimed to proceed by making implicit contradictions explicit: each stage of the process is the product of contradictions inherent or implicit in the preceding stage. On his view, the purpose of dialectics is "to study things in their own being and movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories of understanding".[29]

For Hegel, even history can be reconstructed as a unified dialectic, the major stages of which chart a progression from self-alienation as servitude to self-unification and realization as the rational constitutional state of free and equal citizens.

Marxist dialectic edit

Marxist dialectic is a form of Hegelian dialectic which applies to the study of historical materialism. Marxist dialectic is thus a method by which one can examine social and economic behaviors. It is the foundation of the philosophy of dialectical materialism, which forms the basis of historical materialism.

In the Marxist tradition, "dialectic" refers to regular and mutual relationships, interactions, and processes in nature, society, and human thought.[30]: 257 

A dialectical relationship is a relationship in which two phenomena or ideas mutually impact each other, leading to development and negation.[30]: 257  Development refers to the change and motion of phenomena and ideas from less advanced to more advanced or from less complete to more complete.[30]: 257  Dialectical negation refers to a stage of development in which a contradiction between two previous subjects gives rise to a new subject.[30]: 257  In the Marxist view, dialectical negation is never an endpoint, but instead creates new conditions for further development and negation.[30]: 257 

Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, writing several decades after Hegel's death, proposed that Hegel's dialectic is too abstract.[31] Against this, Marx presented his own dialectic method, which he claimed to be "direct opposite" of Hegel's method.[32]

Marxist dialectics is exemplified in Das Kapital. As Marx explained dialectical materialism,

it includes in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of things, at the same time, also, the recognition of the negation of that state, of its inevitable breaking up; because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence; because it lets nothing impose upon it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary.[33]

Class struggle is the primary contradiction to be resolved by Marxist dialectics because of its central role in the social and political lives of a society. Nonetheless, Marx and Marxists developed the concept of class struggle to comprehend the dialectical contradictions between mental and manual labor and between town and country. Hence, philosophic contradiction is central to the development of dialectics: the progress from quantity to quality, the acceleration of gradual social change; the negation of the initial development of the status quo; the negation of that negation; and the high-level recurrence of features of the original status quo.

Friedrich Engels further proposed that nature itself is dialectical, and that this is "a very simple process, which is taking place everywhere and every day".[34]

In Marxism, the dialectical method of historical study is intertwined with historical materialism, the school of thought exemplified by the works of Marx, Engels, and Vladimir Lenin.

For Lenin, the primary feature of Marx's "dialectical materialism" (Lenin's term) is its application of materialist philosophy to history and social sciences. Lenin's main contribution to the philosophy of dialectical materialism is his theory of reflection, which presents human consciousness as a dynamic reflection of the objective material world that fully shapes its contents and structure.

Later, Stalin's works on the subject established a rigid and formalistic division of Marxist–Leninist theory into dialectical materialism and historical materialism. While the first was supposed to be the key method and theory of the philosophy of nature, the second was the Soviet version of the philosophy of history.

Dialectical naturalism edit

Dialectical naturalism is a term coined by American philosopher Murray Bookchin to describe the philosophical underpinnings of the political program of social ecology. Dialectical naturalism explores the complex interrelationship between social problems, and the direct consequences they have on the ecological impact of human society. Bookchin offered dialectical naturalism as a contrast to what he saw as the "empyrean, basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism" of Hegel, and "the wooden, often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox Marxists".[35]

Theological dialectics edit

Neo-orthodoxy, in Europe also known as theology of crisis and dialectical theology,[36][37] is an approach to theology in Protestantism that was developed in the aftermath of the First World War (1914–1918). It is characterized as a reaction against doctrines of 19th-century liberal theology and a more positive reevaluation of the teachings of the Reformation, much of which had been in decline (especially in western Europe) since the late 18th century.[38] It is primarily associated with two Swiss professors and pastors, Karl Barth[39] (1886–1968) and Emil Brunner (1899–1966),[36][37] even though Barth himself expressed his unease in the use of the term.[40]

In dialectical theology the difference and opposition between God and human beings is stressed in such a way that all human attempts at overcoming this opposition through moral, religious or philosophical idealism must be characterized as 'sin'. In the death of Christ humanity is negated and overcome, but this judgment also points forwards to the resurrection in which humanity is reestablished in Christ. For Barth this meant that only through God's 'no' to everything human can his 'yes' be perceived. Applied to traditional themes of Protestant theology, such as double predestination, this means that election and reprobation cannot be viewed as a quantitative limitation of God's action. Rather it must be seen as its "qualitative definition".[41] As Christ bore the rejection as well as the election of God for all humanity, every person is subject to both aspects of God's double predestination.

Dialectic prominently figured in Bernard Lonergan's philosophy, in his books Insight and Method in Theology. Michael Shute wrote about Lonergan's use of dialectic in The Origins of Lonergan's Notion of the Dialectic of History. For Lonergan, dialectic is both individual and operative in community. Simply described, it is a dynamic process that results in something new:

For the sake of greater precision, let us say that a dialectic is a concrete unfolding of linked but opposed principles of change. Thus there will be a dialectic if (1) there is an aggregate of events of a determinate character, (2) the events may be traced to either or both of two principles, (3) the principles are opposed yet bound together, and (4) they are modified by the changes that successively result from them.[42]

Dialectic is one of the eight functional specialties Lonergan envisaged for theology to bring this discipline into the modern world. Lonergan believed that the lack of an agreed method among scholars had inhibited substantive agreement from being reached and progress from being made compared to the natural sciences. Karl Rahner, S.J., however, criticized Lonergan's theological method in a short article entitled "Some Critical Thoughts on 'Functional Specialties in Theology'" where he stated: "Lonergan's theological methodology seems to me to be so generic that it really fits every science, and hence is not the methodology of theology as such, but only a very general methodology of science."[43]

Criticisms edit

Friedrich Nietzsche viewed dialectic as a method that imposes artificial boundaries and suppresses the richness and diversity of reality. He rejected the notion that truth can be fully grasped through dialectical reasoning and offered a critique of dialectic, challenging its traditional framework and emphasizing the limitations of its approach to understanding reality.[44] He expressed skepticism towards its methodology and implications in his work Twilight of the Idols: "I mistrust all systematizers and I avoid them. The will to a system is a lack of integrity".[45]: 42  In the same book, Nietzsche criticized Socrates' dialectics because he believed it prioritized reason over instinct, resulting in the suppression of individual passions and the imposition of an artificial morality.[45]: 47 

Karl Popper attacked the dialectic repeatedly. In 1937, he wrote and delivered a paper entitled "What Is Dialectic?" in which he criticized the dialectics of Hegel, Marx, and Engels for their willingness "to put up with contradictions".[46] He argued that accepting contradiction as a valid form of logic would lead to the principle of explosion and thus trivialism. Popper concluded the essay with these words: "The whole development of dialectic should be a warning against the dangers inherent in philosophical system-building. It should remind us that philosophy should not be made a basis for any sort of scientific system and that philosophers should be much more modest in their claims. One task which they can fulfill quite usefully is the study of the critical methods of science".[47] Seventy years later, Nicholas Rescher responded that "Popper's critique touches only a hyperbolic version of dialectic", and he quipped: "Ironically, there is something decidedly dialectical about Popper's critique of dialectics."[48]

The philosopher of science and physicist Mario Bunge repeatedly criticized Hegelian and Marxian dialectics, calling them "fuzzy and remote from science"[49] and a "disastrous legacy".[50] He concluded: "The so-called laws of dialectics, such as formulated by Engels (1940, 1954) and Lenin (1947, 1981), are false insofar as they are intelligible."[50] Poe Yu-ze Wan, reviewing Bunge's criticisms of dialectics, found Bunge's arguments to be important and sensible, but he thought that dialectics could still serve some heuristic purposes for scientists.[51]

Even some Marxists are critical of the term "dialectics". For instance, Michael Heinrich wrote, "More often than not, the grandiose rhetoric about dialectics is reducible to the simple fact that everything is dependent upon everything else and is in a state of interaction and that it's all rather complicated—which is true in most cases, but doesn't really say anything."[52]

Formalization edit

Since the late 20th century, European and American logicians have attempted to provide mathematical foundations for dialectic through formalisation,[53]: 201–372  although logic has been related to dialectic since ancient times.[53]: 51–140  There have been pre-formal and partially-formal treatises on argument and dialectic, from authors such as Stephen Toulmin (The Uses of Argument, 1958),[54][55][53]: 203–256  Nicholas Rescher (Dialectics: A Controversy-Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge, 1977),[56][57][53]: 330–336  and Frans H. van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst (pragma-dialectics, 1980s).[53]: 517–614  One can include works of the communities of informal logic and paraconsistent logic.[53]: 373–424 

Defeasibility edit

Building on theories of defeasible reasoning (see John L. Pollock), systems have been built that define well-formedness of arguments, rules governing the process of introducing arguments based on fixed assumptions, and rules for shifting burden.[53]: 615–675  Many of these logics appear in the special area of artificial intelligence and law, though the computer scientists' interest in formalizing dialectic originates in a desire to build decision support and computer-supported collaborative work systems.[58]

Dialog games edit

Dialectic itself can be formalised as moves in a game, where an advocate for the truth of a proposition and an opponent argue.[53]: 301–372  Such games can provide a semantics of logic, one that is very general in applicability.[53]: 314 

Mathematics edit

Mathematician William Lawvere interpreted dialectics in the setting of categorical logic in terms of adjunctions between idempotent monads.[59] This perspective may be useful in the context of theoretical computer science where the duality between syntax and semantics can be interpreted as a dialectic in this sense. For example, the Curry-Howard equivalence is such an adjunction or more generally the duality between closed monoidal categories and their internal logic.[60]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ See Gorgias, 449B: "Socrates: Would you be willing then, Gorgias, to continue the discussion as we are now doing [Dialectic], by way of question and answer, and to put off to another occasion the (emotional) speeches (rhetoric) that (the sophist) Polus began?"
  2. ^ Ayer, A. J.; O'Grady, J. (1992). A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers. p. 484.
  3. ^ McTaggart, J. M. E. (1964). A commentary on Hegel's logic. New York: Russell & Russell. p. 11.
  4. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, IX 25ff and VIII 57 [1].
  5. ^ "Elenchus - Wiktionary". 8 February 2021.
  6. ^ Wyss, Peter (October 2014). "Socratic Method: Aporeia, Elenchus and Dialectics (Plato: Four Dialogues, Handout 3)" (PDF). open.conted.ox.ac.uk. University of Oxford, Department for Continuing Education.
  7. ^ Reale, Giovanni (1990). History of Ancient Philosophy. Vol. 2. Translated by Catan, John R. Albany: State University of New York. p. 150.
  8. ^ Republic, VII, 533 c-d
  9. ^ Blackburn, Simon (1996). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  10. ^ Abelson, P. (1965). The seven liberal arts; a study in mediæval culture. New York: Russell & Russell. Page 82.
  11. ^ Hyman, A., & Walsh, J. J. (1983). Philosophy in the Middle Ages: the Christian, Islamic, and Jewish traditions. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co. Page 164.
  12. ^ Adler, Mortimer Jerome (2000). "Dialectic". Routledge. Page 4. ISBN 0-415-22550-7
  13. ^ Herbermann, C. G. (1913). The Catholic encyclopedia: an international work of reference on the constitution, doctrine, and history of the Catholic church. New York: The Encyclopedia press, inc. Page 760–764.
  14. ^ From topic to tale: logic and narrativity in the Middle Ages, by Eugene Vance, p.43-45
  15. ^ "Catholic Encyclopedia: Peter Abelard". Newadvent.org. 1 March 1907. Retrieved 3 November 2011.
  16. ^ Kretzmann, Norman (January 1966). William of Sherwood's Introduction to logic. U of Minnesota Press. pp. 69–102. ISBN 9780816603954.
  17. ^ Dronke, Peter (9 July 1992). A History of Twelfth-Century Western Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 198. ISBN 9780521429078.
  18. ^ Delany, Sheila (1990). Medieval literary politics: shapes of ideology. Manchester University Press. p. 11. ISBN 9780719030451.
  19. ^ "Catholic Encyclopedia: St. Thomas Aquinas". Newadvent.org. 1 March 1907. Retrieved 20 October 2015.
  20. ^ Nicholson, J. A. (1950). Philosophy of religion. New York: Ronald Press Co. p. 108.
  21. ^ Kant, I.; Guyer, P.; Wood, A. W. (2003). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 495. ISBN 9780758339010.
  22. ^ Maybee, Julie E. (Winter 2020). "Hegel's Dialectics § 3. Why does Hegel use dialectics?". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  23. ^ Henri Lefebvre's "humanist" dialectical materialism (Dialectical Materialism [1940]) was composed to directly challenge Joseph Stalin's own dogmatic text on dialectical materialism.
  24. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (2010). Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline: Part 1, Science of Logic. Cambridge Hegel Translations. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 34–35. ISBN 9780521829144. OCLC 651153726. the necessity of the connectedness and the immanent emergence of distinctions must be found in the treatment of the fact itself, for it falls within the concept's own progressive determination. What propels the concept onward is the already mentioned negative which it possesses in itself; it is this that constitutes the truly dialectical factor. [...] It is in this dialectic as understood here, and hence in grasping opposites in their unity, or the positive in the negative, that the speculative consists.
  25. ^ Historische Entwicklung der spekulativen Philosophie von Kant bis Hegel [Historical development of speculative philosophy from Kant to Hegel] (in German) (Fourth ed.). Dresden-Leipzig. 1848 [1837]. p. 367.
  26. ^ The Accessible Hegel by Michael Allen Fox. Prometheus Books. 2005. p. 43. Also see Hegel's preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), secs. 50, 51, pp. 29, 30.
  27. ^ Maybee, Julie E. (Winter 2020). "Hegel's Dialectics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2024-02-11.
  28. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1812). Hegel's Science of Logic. London: Allen & Unwin. p. §185.
  29. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1874). "The Logic". Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (2nd ed.). London: Oxford University Press. p. Note to §81.
  30. ^ a b c d e Ministry of Education and Training (Vietnam) (2023). Curriculum of the Basic Principles of Marxism-Leninism. Vol. 1. Translated by Nguyen, Luna. Banyan House Publishing. ISBN 9798987931608.
  31. ^ Marx, Karl (1873) Capital Afterword to the Second German Edition, Vol. I [2]
  32. ^ Marx, Karl. "Afterword". link=Das Kapital [Capital] (in German). Vol. 1 (Second German ed.). p. 14. Retrieved 28 December 2014 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
  33. ^ Marx, Karl, (1873) Capital Vol. I, Afterword to the Second German Edition.
  34. ^ Engels, Frederick, (1877) Anti-Dühring, Part I: Philosophy, XIII. Dialectics. Negation of the Negation.
  35. ^ Biehl, Janet, ed. (1997). The Murray Bookchin reader. London; Washington, DC: Cassell. p. 209. ISBN 0304338737. OCLC 36477047.
  36. ^ a b "Original Britinnica online". Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  37. ^ a b "Britannica Encyclopedia (online)". Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  38. ^ "Merriam-Webster Dictionary(online)". Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  39. ^ . Archived from the original on 2005-05-10. Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  40. ^ See Church Dogmatics III/3, xii.
  41. ^ Karl Barth, The Epistle to the Romans (1933), p. 346
  42. ^ Bernard J.F. Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, Collected Works vol. 3, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1992, pp.217-218).
  43. ^ McShane, S.J., Philip (1972). Foundations of Theology. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press. p. 194.
  44. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (2001). The Gay Science. Cambridge University Press. p. 117. ISBN 9780521636452.
  45. ^ a b Nietzsche, Friedrich (1997). Twilight of the Idols or How to Philosophize with a Hammer. Hackett. ISBN 978-0872203549.
  46. ^ Karl Popper,Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge [New York: Basic Books, 1962], p. 316.
  47. ^ Karl Popper,Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge [New York: Basic Books, 1962], p. 335.
  48. ^ Rescher, Nicholas (2007). Dialectics: A Classical Approach to Inquiry. Frankfurt; New Brunswick: Ontos Verlag. p. 116. doi:10.1515/9783110321289. ISBN 9783938793763. OCLC 185032382.
  49. ^ Bunge, Mario Augusto (1981). "A critique of dialectics". Scientific materialism. Episteme. Vol. 9. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 41–63. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-8517-9_4. ISBN 978-9027713049. OCLC 7596139.
  50. ^ a b Bunge, Mario Augusto (2012). Evaluating philosophies. Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. 295. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 84–85. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-4408-0. ISBN 9789400744073. OCLC 806947226.
  51. ^ Wan, Poe Yu-ze (December 2013). "Dialectics, complexity, and the systemic approach: toward a critical reconciliation". Philosophy of the Social Sciences. 43 (4): 411–452. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.989.6440. doi:10.1177/0048393112441974. S2CID 144820093.
  52. ^ Heinrich, Michael (2004). "Dialectics—A Marxist 'Rosetta Stone'?". An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx's Capital. Translated by Alexander Locascio. New York: Monthly Review Press. pp. 36–37. ISBN 9781583672884. OCLC 768793094.
  53. ^ a b c d e f g h i Eemeren, Frans H. van; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2014). Handbook of argumentation theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5. ISBN 9789048194728. OCLC 871004444.
  54. ^ Toulmin, Stephen (2003) [1958]. The uses of argument (Updated ed.). Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511840005. ISBN 978-0521827485. OCLC 51607421.
  55. ^ Hitchcock, David; Verheij, Bart, eds. (2006). Arguing on the Toulmin model: new essays in argument analysis and evaluation. Argumentation library. Vol. 10. Dordrecht: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-4938-5. ISBN 978-1402049378. OCLC 82229075.
  56. ^ Hetherington, Stephen (2006). "Nicholas Rescher: Philosophical Dialectics". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (2006.07.16).
  57. ^ Jacquette, Dale, ed. (2009). Reason, Method, and Value: A Reader on the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag. doi:10.1515/9783110329056. ISBN 9783110329056.
  58. ^ For surveys of work in this area see, for example: Chesñevar, Carlos Iván; Maguitman, Ana Gabriela; Loui, Ronald Prescott (December 2000). "Logical models of argument". ACM Computing Surveys. 32 (4): 337–383. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.702.8325. doi:10.1145/371578.371581. And: Prakken, Henry; Vreeswijk, Gerard (2005). "Logics for defeasible argumentation". In Gabbay, Dov M.; Guenthner, Franz (eds.). Handbook of philosophical logic. Vol. 4 (2nd ed.). Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 219–318. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.295.2649. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0456-4_3. ISBN 9789048158775.
  59. ^ Lawvere, F. William (1996). "Unity and identity of opposites in calculus and physics". Applied Categorical Structures. 4 (2–3): 167–174. doi:10.1007/BF00122250. S2CID 34109341.
  60. ^ Eilenberg, Samuel; Kelly, G. Max (1966). "Closed Categories". Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra: 421–562. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-99902-4_22. ISBN 978-3-642-99904-8. S2CID 251105095.

External links edit

dialectic, varieties, language, dialect, greek, διαλεκτική, dialektikḗ, german, dialektik, also, known, dialectical, method, refers, originally, dialogue, between, people, holding, different, points, view, about, subject, wishing, arrive, truth, through, reaso. For varieties of language see dialect Dialectic Greek dialektikh dialektikḗ German Dialektik also known as the dialectical method refers originally to dialogue between people holding different points of view about a subject but wishing to arrive at the truth through reasoned argumentation Dialectic resembles debate but the concept excludes subjective elements such as emotional appeal and rhetoric 1 It has its origins in ancient philosophy and continued to be developed in the Middle Ages Hegelianism refigured dialectic to no longer refer to a literal dialogue Instead the term takes on the specialized meaning of development by way of overcoming internal contradictions Dialectical materialism a theory advanced by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels adapted the Hegelian dialectic into a materialist theory of history The legacy of Hegelian and Marxian dialectics has been criticized by philosophers such as Karl Popper and Mario Bunge who considered it unscientific Dialectic implies a developmental process and so does not naturally fit within classical logic Nevertheless some twentieth century logicians have attempted to formalize it Contents 1 History 1 1 Classical philosophy 1 1 1 Socratic method 1 1 2 Plato 1 2 Medieval philosophy 1 3 Modern philosophy 1 3 1 Hegelian dialectic 1 3 2 Marxist dialectic 1 3 3 Dialectical naturalism 2 Theological dialectics 3 Criticisms 4 Formalization 4 1 Defeasibility 4 2 Dialog games 4 3 Mathematics 5 See also 6 References 7 External linksHistory editThere are a variety of meanings of dialectic or dialectics within Western philosophy Classical philosophy edit In classical philosophy dialectic dialektikh is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter arguments advocating propositions theses and counter propositions antitheses The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition or of a synthesis or a combination of the opposing assertions or a qualitative improvement of the dialogue 2 3 The term dialectic owes much of its prestige to its role in the philosophies of Socrates and Plato in the Greek Classical period 5th to 4th centuries BC Aristotle said that it was the pre Socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea who invented dialectic of which the dialogues of Plato are examples of the Socratic dialectical method 4 Socratic method edit Main article Socratic method The Socratic dialogues are a particular form of dialectic known as the method of elenchus literally refutation scrutiny 5 whereby a series of questions clarifies a more precise statement of a vague belief logical consequences of that statement are explored and a contradiction is discovered The method is largely destructive in that false belief is exposed and only constructive in that this exposure may lead to further search for truth 6 The detection of error does not amount to a proof of the antithesis For example a contradiction in the consequences of a definition of piety does not provide a correct definition The principal aim of Socratic activity may be to improve the soul of the interlocutors by freeing them from unrecognized errors or indeed by teaching them the spirit of inquiry In common cases Socrates uses enthymemes as the foundation of his argument citation needed For example in the Euthyphro Socrates asks Euthyphro to provide a definition of piety Euthyphro replies that the pious is that which is loved by the gods But Socrates also has Euthyphro agreeing that the gods are quarrelsome and their quarrels like human quarrels concern objects of love or hatred Therefore Socrates reasons at least one thing exists that certain gods love but other gods hate Again Euthyphro agrees Socrates concludes that if Euthyphro s definition of piety is acceptable then there must exist at least one thing that is both pious and impious as it is both loved and hated by the gods which Euthyphro admits is absurd Thus Euthyphro is brought to a realization by this dialectical method that his definition of piety is not sufficiently meaningful In another example in Plato s Gorgias dialectic occurs between Socrates the Sophist Gorgias and two men Polus and Callicles Because Socrates ultimate goal was to reach true knowledge he was even willing to change his own views in order to arrive at the truth The fundamental goal of dialectic in this instance was to establish a precise definition of the subject in this case rhetoric and with the use of argumentation and questioning make the subject even more precise In the Gorgias Socrates reaches the truth by asking a series of questions and in return receiving short clear answers Plato edit In Platonism and Neoplatonism dialectic assumed an ontological and metaphysical role in that it became the process whereby the intellect passes from sensibles to intelligibles rising from idea to idea until it finally grasps the supreme idea the first principle which is the origin of all The philosopher is consequently a dialectician 7 In this sense dialectic is a process of inquiry that does away with hypotheses up to the first principle 8 It slowly embraces multiplicity in unity The philosopher Simon Blackburn wrote that the dialectic in this sense is used to understand the total process of enlightenment whereby the philosopher is educated so as to achieve knowledge of the supreme good the Form of the Good 9 Medieval philosophy edit Logic which could be considered to include dialectic was one of the three liberal arts taught in medieval universities as part of the trivium the other elements were rhetoric and grammar 10 11 12 13 Based mainly on Aristotle the first medieval philosopher to work on dialectics was Boethius 480 524 14 After him many scholastic philosophers also made use of dialectics in their works such as Abelard 15 William of Sherwood 16 Garlandus Compotista 17 Walter Burley Roger Swyneshed William of Ockham 18 and Thomas Aquinas 19 This dialectic a quaestio disputata was formed as follows The question to be determined It is asked whether A provisory answer to the question And it seems that The principal arguments in favor of the provisory answer An argument against the provisory answer traditionally a single argument from authority On the contrary The determination of the question after weighing the evidence I answer that The replies to each of the initial objections To the first to the second etc I answer that Modern philosophy edit The concept of dialectics was given new life at the start of the 19th century by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel whose dialectical model of nature and of history made dialectics a fundamental aspect of reality instead of regarding the contradictions into which dialectics leads as evidence of the limits of pure reason as Immanuel Kant had argued 20 21 Hegel was influenced by Johann Gottlieb Fichte s conception of synthesis although Hegel didn t adopt Fichte s thesis antithesis synthesis language except to describe Kant s philosophy rather Hegel argued that such language was a lifeless schema imposed on various contents whereas he saw his own dialectic as flowing out of the inner life and self movement of the content itself 22 In the mid 19th century Hegelian dialectic was appropriated by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels and retooled in what they considered to be a nonidealistic manner It would also become a crucial part of later representations of Marxism as a philosophy of dialectical materialism These representations often contrasted dramatically and led to vigorous debate among different Marxist groups 23 Hegelian dialectic edit Hegelian dialectic redirects here For the Prodigy album see Hegelian Dialectic The Book of Revelation See also Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Dialectics speculation idealism The Hegelian dialectic describes changes in the forms of thought through their own internal contradictions into concrete forms that overcome previous oppositions 24 This dialectic is sometimes presented in a threefold manner as first stated by Heinrich Moritz Chalybaus as comprising three dialectical stages of development a thesis giving rise to its reaction an antithesis which contradicts or negates the thesis and the tension between the two being resolved by means of a synthesis 25 26 By contrast the terms abstract negative and concrete suggest a flaw or an incompleteness in any initial thesis For Hegel the concrete must always pass through the phase of the negative that is mediation This is the essence of what is popularly called Hegelian dialectics 27 To describe the activity of overcoming the negative Hegel often used the term Aufhebung variously translated into English as sublation or overcoming to conceive of the working of the dialectic Roughly the term indicates preserving the true portion of an idea thing society and so forth while moving beyond its limitations What is sublated on the one hand is overcome but on the other hand is preserved and maintained 28 As in the Socratic dialectic Hegel claimed to proceed by making implicit contradictions explicit each stage of the process is the product of contradictions inherent or implicit in the preceding stage On his view the purpose of dialectics is to study things in their own being and movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories of understanding 29 For Hegel even history can be reconstructed as a unified dialectic the major stages of which chart a progression from self alienation as servitude to self unification and realization as the rational constitutional state of free and equal citizens Marxist dialectic edit Marxist dialectic is a form of Hegelian dialectic which applies to the study of historical materialism Marxist dialectic is thus a method by which one can examine social and economic behaviors It is the foundation of the philosophy of dialectical materialism which forms the basis of historical materialism In the Marxist tradition dialectic refers to regular and mutual relationships interactions and processes in nature society and human thought 30 257 A dialectical relationship is a relationship in which two phenomena or ideas mutually impact each other leading to development and negation 30 257 Development refers to the change and motion of phenomena and ideas from less advanced to more advanced or from less complete to more complete 30 257 Dialectical negation refers to a stage of development in which a contradiction between two previous subjects gives rise to a new subject 30 257 In the Marxist view dialectical negation is never an endpoint but instead creates new conditions for further development and negation 30 257 Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels writing several decades after Hegel s death proposed that Hegel s dialectic is too abstract 31 Against this Marx presented his own dialectic method which he claimed to be direct opposite of Hegel s method 32 Marxist dialectics is exemplified in Das Kapital As Marx explained dialectical materialism it includes in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of things at the same time also the recognition of the negation of that state of its inevitable breaking up because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence because it lets nothing impose upon it and is in its essence critical and revolutionary 33 Class struggle is the primary contradiction to be resolved by Marxist dialectics because of its central role in the social and political lives of a society Nonetheless Marx and Marxists developed the concept of class struggle to comprehend the dialectical contradictions between mental and manual labor and between town and country Hence philosophic contradiction is central to the development of dialectics the progress from quantity to quality the acceleration of gradual social change the negation of the initial development of the status quo the negation of that negation and the high level recurrence of features of the original status quo Friedrich Engels further proposed that nature itself is dialectical and that this is a very simple process which is taking place everywhere and every day 34 In Marxism the dialectical method of historical study is intertwined with historical materialism the school of thought exemplified by the works of Marx Engels and Vladimir Lenin For Lenin the primary feature of Marx s dialectical materialism Lenin s term is its application of materialist philosophy to history and social sciences Lenin s main contribution to the philosophy of dialectical materialism is his theory of reflection which presents human consciousness as a dynamic reflection of the objective material world that fully shapes its contents and structure Later Stalin s works on the subject established a rigid and formalistic division of Marxist Leninist theory into dialectical materialism and historical materialism While the first was supposed to be the key method and theory of the philosophy of nature the second was the Soviet version of the philosophy of history Dialectical naturalism edit Dialectical naturalism is a term coined by American philosopher Murray Bookchin to describe the philosophical underpinnings of the political program of social ecology Dialectical naturalism explores the complex interrelationship between social problems and the direct consequences they have on the ecological impact of human society Bookchin offered dialectical naturalism as a contrast to what he saw as the empyrean basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism of Hegel and the wooden often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox Marxists 35 Theological dialectics editNeo orthodoxy in Europe also known as theology of crisis and dialectical theology 36 37 is an approach to theology in Protestantism that was developed in the aftermath of the First World War 1914 1918 It is characterized as a reaction against doctrines of 19th century liberal theology and a more positive reevaluation of the teachings of the Reformation much of which had been in decline especially in western Europe since the late 18th century 38 It is primarily associated with two Swiss professors and pastors Karl Barth 39 1886 1968 and Emil Brunner 1899 1966 36 37 even though Barth himself expressed his unease in the use of the term 40 In dialectical theology the difference and opposition between God and human beings is stressed in such a way that all human attempts at overcoming this opposition through moral religious or philosophical idealism must be characterized as sin In the death of Christ humanity is negated and overcome but this judgment also points forwards to the resurrection in which humanity is reestablished in Christ For Barth this meant that only through God s no to everything human can his yes be perceived Applied to traditional themes of Protestant theology such as double predestination this means that election and reprobation cannot be viewed as a quantitative limitation of God s action Rather it must be seen as its qualitative definition 41 As Christ bore the rejection as well as the election of God for all humanity every person is subject to both aspects of God s double predestination Dialectic prominently figured in Bernard Lonergan s philosophy in his books Insight and Method in Theology Michael Shute wrote about Lonergan s use of dialectic in The Origins of Lonergan s Notion of the Dialectic of History For Lonergan dialectic is both individual and operative in community Simply described it is a dynamic process that results in something new For the sake of greater precision let us say that a dialectic is a concrete unfolding of linked but opposed principles of change Thus there will be a dialectic if 1 there is an aggregate of events of a determinate character 2 the events may be traced to either or both of two principles 3 the principles are opposed yet bound together and 4 they are modified by the changes that successively result from them 42 Dialectic is one of the eight functional specialties Lonergan envisaged for theology to bring this discipline into the modern world Lonergan believed that the lack of an agreed method among scholars had inhibited substantive agreement from being reached and progress from being made compared to the natural sciences Karl Rahner S J however criticized Lonergan s theological method in a short article entitled Some Critical Thoughts on Functional Specialties in Theology where he stated Lonergan s theological methodology seems to me to be so generic that it really fits every science and hence is not the methodology of theology as such but only a very general methodology of science 43 Criticisms editSee also Category Critics of dialectical materialism Friedrich Nietzsche viewed dialectic as a method that imposes artificial boundaries and suppresses the richness and diversity of reality He rejected the notion that truth can be fully grasped through dialectical reasoning and offered a critique of dialectic challenging its traditional framework and emphasizing the limitations of its approach to understanding reality 44 He expressed skepticism towards its methodology and implications in his work Twilight of the Idols I mistrust all systematizers and I avoid them The will to a system is a lack of integrity 45 42 In the same book Nietzsche criticized Socrates dialectics because he believed it prioritized reason over instinct resulting in the suppression of individual passions and the imposition of an artificial morality 45 47 Karl Popper attacked the dialectic repeatedly In 1937 he wrote and delivered a paper entitled What Is Dialectic in which he criticized the dialectics of Hegel Marx and Engels for their willingness to put up with contradictions 46 He argued that accepting contradiction as a valid form of logic would lead to the principle of explosion and thus trivialism Popper concluded the essay with these words The whole development of dialectic should be a warning against the dangers inherent in philosophical system building It should remind us that philosophy should not be made a basis for any sort of scientific system and that philosophers should be much more modest in their claims One task which they can fulfill quite usefully is the study of the critical methods of science 47 Seventy years later Nicholas Rescher responded that Popper s critique touches only a hyperbolic version of dialectic and he quipped Ironically there is something decidedly dialectical about Popper s critique of dialectics 48 The philosopher of science and physicist Mario Bunge repeatedly criticized Hegelian and Marxian dialectics calling them fuzzy and remote from science 49 and a disastrous legacy 50 He concluded The so called laws of dialectics such as formulated by Engels 1940 1954 and Lenin 1947 1981 are false insofar as they are intelligible 50 Poe Yu ze Wan reviewing Bunge s criticisms of dialectics found Bunge s arguments to be important and sensible but he thought that dialectics could still serve some heuristic purposes for scientists 51 Even some Marxists are critical of the term dialectics For instance Michael Heinrich wrote More often than not the grandiose rhetoric about dialectics is reducible to the simple fact that everything is dependent upon everything else and is in a state of interaction and that it s all rather complicated which is true in most cases but doesn t really say anything 52 Formalization editThis section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic History edit history Since the late 20th century European and American logicians have attempted to provide mathematical foundations for dialectic through formalisation 53 201 372 although logic has been related to dialectic since ancient times 53 51 140 There have been pre formal and partially formal treatises on argument and dialectic from authors such as Stephen Toulmin The Uses of Argument 1958 54 55 53 203 256 Nicholas Rescher Dialectics A Controversy Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge 1977 56 57 53 330 336 and Frans H van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst pragma dialectics 1980s 53 517 614 One can include works of the communities of informal logic and paraconsistent logic 53 373 424 Defeasibility edit This section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic Defeasibility edit history Building on theories of defeasible reasoning see John L Pollock systems have been built that define well formedness of arguments rules governing the process of introducing arguments based on fixed assumptions and rules for shifting burden 53 615 675 Many of these logics appear in the special area of artificial intelligence and law though the computer scientists interest in formalizing dialectic originates in a desire to build decision support and computer supported collaborative work systems 58 Dialog games edit This section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic Dialog games edit history Main articles Game semantics and Dialogical logic Dialectic itself can be formalised as moves in a game where an advocate for the truth of a proposition and an opponent argue 53 301 372 Such games can provide a semantics of logic one that is very general in applicability 53 314 Mathematics edit Mathematician William Lawvere interpreted dialectics in the setting of categorical logic in terms of adjunctions between idempotent monads 59 This perspective may be useful in the context of theoretical computer science where the duality between syntax and semantics can be interpreted as a dialectic in this sense For example the Curry Howard equivalence is such an adjunction or more generally the duality between closed monoidal categories and their internal logic 60 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Psychology portal Dialectica A philosophical journal De Dialectica Various works on dialectics and logical reasoning Dialectical behavior therapy Psychotherapy for emotional dysregulation Dialectical research Form of qualitative research which utilizes the method of dialectic Dialogic Use of conversation to explore the meaning of something Doublethink Simultaneously accepting two mutually contradictory beliefs as correct False dilemma Informal fallacy involving falsely limited alternatives Reflective equilibrium State of balance among a set of beliefs arrived at by considering general principles Relational dialectics Interpersonal communication theory Tarka sastra Indian science of dialectics logic and reasoningPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Unity of opposites Central category of dialectics said to be related to non duality in a deep sense Universal dialecticReferences edit See Gorgias 449B Socrates Would you be willing then Gorgias to continue the discussion as we are now doing Dialectic by way of question and answer and to put off to another occasion the emotional speeches rhetoric that the sophist Polus began Ayer A J O Grady J 1992 A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations Oxford UK Blackwell Publishers p 484 McTaggart J M E 1964 A commentary on Hegel s logic New York Russell amp Russell p 11 Diogenes Laertius IX 25ff and VIII 57 1 Elenchus Wiktionary 8 February 2021 Wyss Peter October 2014 Socratic Method Aporeia Elenchus and Dialectics Plato Four Dialogues Handout 3 PDF open conted ox ac uk University of Oxford Department for Continuing Education Reale Giovanni 1990 History of Ancient Philosophy Vol 2 Translated by Catan John R Albany State University of New York p 150 Republic VII 533 c d Blackburn Simon 1996 The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press Abelson P 1965 The seven liberal arts a study in mediaeval culture New York Russell amp Russell Page 82 Hyman A amp Walsh J J 1983 Philosophy in the Middle Ages the Christian Islamic and Jewish traditions Indianapolis Hackett Pub Co Page 164 Adler Mortimer Jerome 2000 Dialectic Routledge Page 4 ISBN 0 415 22550 7 Herbermann C G 1913 The Catholic encyclopedia an international work of reference on the constitution doctrine and history of the Catholic church New York The Encyclopedia press inc Page 760 764 From topic to tale logic and narrativity in the Middle Ages by Eugene Vance p 43 45 Catholic Encyclopedia Peter Abelard Newadvent org 1 March 1907 Retrieved 3 November 2011 Kretzmann Norman January 1966 William of Sherwood s Introduction to logic U of Minnesota Press pp 69 102 ISBN 9780816603954 Dronke Peter 9 July 1992 A History of Twelfth Century Western Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 198 ISBN 9780521429078 Delany Sheila 1990 Medieval literary politics shapes of ideology Manchester University Press p 11 ISBN 9780719030451 Catholic Encyclopedia St Thomas Aquinas Newadvent org 1 March 1907 Retrieved 20 October 2015 Nicholson J A 1950 Philosophy of religion New York Ronald Press Co p 108 Kant I Guyer P Wood A W 2003 Critique of pure reason Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 495 ISBN 9780758339010 Maybee Julie E Winter 2020 Hegel s Dialectics 3 Why does Hegel use dialectics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Henri Lefebvre s humanist dialectical materialism Dialectical Materialism 1940 was composed to directly challenge Joseph Stalin s own dogmatic text on dialectical materialism Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 2010 Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline Part 1 Science of Logic Cambridge Hegel Translations Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press pp 34 35 ISBN 9780521829144 OCLC 651153726 the necessity of the connectedness and the immanent emergence of distinctions must be found in the treatment of the fact itself for it falls within the concept s own progressive determination What propels the concept onward is the already mentioned negative which it possesses in itself it is this that constitutes the truly dialectical factor It is in this dialectic as understood here and hence in grasping opposites in their unity or the positive in the negative that the speculative consists Historische Entwicklung der spekulativen Philosophie von Kant bis Hegel Historical development of speculative philosophy from Kant to Hegel in German Fourth ed Dresden Leipzig 1848 1837 p 367 The Accessible Hegel by Michael Allen Fox Prometheus Books 2005 p 43 Also see Hegel s preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit trans A V Miller Oxford Clarendon Press 1977 secs 50 51 pp 29 30 Maybee Julie E Winter 2020 Hegel s Dialectics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2024 02 11 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1812 Hegel s Science of Logic London Allen amp Unwin p 185 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd ed London Oxford University Press p Note to 81 a b c d e Ministry of Education and Training Vietnam 2023 Curriculum of the Basic Principles of Marxism Leninism Vol 1 Translated by Nguyen Luna Banyan House Publishing ISBN 9798987931608 Marx Karl 1873 Capital Afterword to the Second German Edition Vol I 2 Marx Karl Afterword link Das Kapital Capital in German Vol 1 Second German ed p 14 Retrieved 28 December 2014 via Marxists Internet Archive Marx Karl 1873 Capital Vol I Afterword to the Second German Edition Engels Frederick 1877 Anti Duhring Part I Philosophy XIII Dialectics Negation of the Negation Biehl Janet ed 1997 The Murray Bookchin reader London Washington DC Cassell p 209 ISBN 0304338737 OCLC 36477047 a b Original Britinnica online Retrieved 2008 07 26 a b Britannica Encyclopedia online Retrieved 2008 07 26 Merriam Webster Dictionary online Retrieved 2008 07 26 American Heritage Dictionary online Archived from the original on 2005 05 10 Retrieved 2008 07 26 See Church Dogmatics III 3 xii Karl Barth The Epistle to the Romans 1933 p 346 Bernard J F Lonergan Insight A Study of Human Understanding Collected Works vol 3 ed Frederick E Crowe and Robert M Doran Toronto University of Toronto 1992 pp 217 218 McShane S J Philip 1972 Foundations of Theology Notre Dame Indiana University of Notre Dame Press p 194 Nietzsche Friedrich 2001 The Gay Science Cambridge University Press p 117 ISBN 9780521636452 a b Nietzsche Friedrich 1997 Twilight of the Idols or How to Philosophize with a Hammer Hackett ISBN 978 0872203549 Karl Popper Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge New York Basic Books 1962 p 316 Karl Popper Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge New York Basic Books 1962 p 335 Rescher Nicholas 2007 Dialectics A Classical Approach to Inquiry Frankfurt New Brunswick Ontos Verlag p 116 doi 10 1515 9783110321289 ISBN 9783938793763 OCLC 185032382 Bunge Mario Augusto 1981 A critique of dialectics Scientific materialism Episteme Vol 9 Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 41 63 doi 10 1007 978 94 009 8517 9 4 ISBN 978 9027713049 OCLC 7596139 a b Bunge Mario Augusto 2012 Evaluating philosophies Boston studies in the philosophy of science Vol 295 New York Springer Verlag pp 84 85 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 4408 0 ISBN 9789400744073 OCLC 806947226 Wan Poe Yu ze December 2013 Dialectics complexity and the systemic approach toward a critical reconciliation Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 4 411 452 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 989 6440 doi 10 1177 0048393112441974 S2CID 144820093 Heinrich Michael 2004 Dialectics A Marxist Rosetta Stone An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx s Capital Translated by Alexander Locascio New York Monthly Review Press pp 36 37 ISBN 9781583672884 OCLC 768793094 a b c d e f g h i Eemeren Frans H van Garssen Bart Krabbe Erik C W Snoeck Henkemans A Francisca Verheij Bart Wagemans Jean H M 2014 Handbook of argumentation theory New York Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 978 90 481 9473 5 ISBN 9789048194728 OCLC 871004444 Toulmin Stephen 2003 1958 The uses of argument Updated ed Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 CBO9780511840005 ISBN 978 0521827485 OCLC 51607421 Hitchcock David Verheij Bart eds 2006 Arguing on the Toulmin model new essays in argument analysis and evaluation Argumentation library Vol 10 Dordrecht Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 4938 5 ISBN 978 1402049378 OCLC 82229075 Hetherington Stephen 2006 Nicholas Rescher Philosophical Dialectics Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 07 16 Jacquette Dale ed 2009 Reason Method and Value A Reader on the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher Frankfurt Ontos Verlag doi 10 1515 9783110329056 ISBN 9783110329056 For surveys of work in this area see for example Chesnevar Carlos Ivan Maguitman Ana Gabriela Loui Ronald Prescott December 2000 Logical models of argument ACM Computing Surveys 32 4 337 383 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 702 8325 doi 10 1145 371578 371581 And Prakken Henry Vreeswijk Gerard 2005 Logics for defeasible argumentation In Gabbay Dov M Guenthner Franz eds Handbook of philosophical logic Vol 4 2nd ed Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 219 318 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 295 2649 doi 10 1007 978 94 017 0456 4 3 ISBN 9789048158775 Lawvere F William 1996 Unity and identity of opposites in calculus and physics Applied Categorical Structures 4 2 3 167 174 doi 10 1007 BF00122250 S2CID 34109341 Eilenberg Samuel Kelly G Max 1966 Closed Categories Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra 421 562 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 99902 4 22 ISBN 978 3 642 99904 8 S2CID 251105095 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Dialectic nbsp Look up dialectic in Wiktionary the free dictionary v Dialectic algorithm An algorithm based on the principles of classical dialectics Hegel s Dialectics entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Dialectic Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 8 11th ed 1911 p 156 Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic by J M E McTaggart 1896 at marxists org Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Dialectic amp oldid 1217110185, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.