fbpx
Wikipedia

Misanthropy

Misanthropy is the general hatred, dislike, distrust, or contempt of the human species, human behavior, or human nature. A misanthrope or misanthropist is someone who holds such views or feelings. The word originates from the Greek words μῖσος mīsos 'hatred' and ἄνθρωπος ānthropos 'man, human'. Misanthropy involves a negative evaluative attitude toward humanity that is based on mankind's flaws. Misanthropes hold that these flaws characterize all or at least the great majority of human beings and that there is no easy way to rectify them short of a complete transformation of the dominant way of life. Various types of misanthropy are distinguished in the academic literature based on what attitude is involved, at whom it is directed, and how it is expressed. Either emotions or theoretical judgments can serve as the foundation of the attitude. It can be directed at all humans without exception or exclude a few idealized people. In this regard, some misanthropes condemn themselves while others consider themselves superior to everyone else. Misanthropy is typically associated with either a destructive outlook aiming to hurt other people or an attempt to flee society. Other types of misanthropic responses include activism by trying to improve humanity, quietism in the form of resignation, and humor mocking the absurdity of the human condition.

Engraving depicting the play Le Misanthrope by Molière

The negative misanthropic outlook is based on different types of human flaws. Moral flaws are often seen as the main factor. They include cruelty, indifference to the suffering of others, selfishness, injustice, and greed. They may result in harm to humans and animals, like genocides and factory farming of livestock. Other flaws include intellectual flaws, like dogmatism and cognitive biases, as well as aesthetic flaws concerning ugliness and lack of sensitivity to beauty. Many debates in the academic literature discuss whether misanthropy is a valid viewpoint and what its implications are. Proponents of misanthropy usually point to human flaws and the harm they have caused as a sufficient reason for condemning humanity. Critics have responded to this line of thought by claiming that severe flaws concern only a few extreme cases, like mentally ill perpetrators, but not humanity at large. Another objection is based on the claim that humans also have virtues besides their flaws and that a balanced evaluation might be overall positive. A further criticism rejects misanthropy because of its association with hatred, which may lead to violence, and because it may make people friendless and unhappy. Defenders of misanthropy have responded by claiming that this applies only to some forms of misanthropy but not to misanthropy in general.

A related issue concerns the question of the psychological and social factors that cause people to become misanthropes. They include becoming disillusioned with someone that was adored before, socio-economic inequality, and living under an authoritarian regime. Misanthropy is relevant in various disciplines. It has been discussed and exemplified by philosophers throughout history. Examples include Heraclitus, Diogenes, Thomas Hobbes, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Arthur Schopenhauer, and Friedrich Nietzsche. Misanthropic outlooks form part of some religious teachings discussing the deep flaws of human beings, like the Christian doctrine of original sin. Misanthropic perspectives and characters are also found in literature and popular culture. They include William Shakespeare's portrayal of Timon of Athens, Molière's play The Misanthrope, and Gulliver's Travels by Jonathan Swift. Misanthropy is closely related to but not identical to philosophical pessimism. Many misanthropes promote antinatalism, the view that humans should abstain from procreation.

Definition

Misanthropy (a word of 17th century origin, from the Greek misanthrōpos[1]) is traditionally defined as hatred or dislike of humankind.[2][3] In contemporary philosophy, the term is usually understood in a wider sense as a negative evaluation of humanity as a whole based on humanity's vices and flaws.[4][5] This negative evaluation can express itself in various forms, hatred being only one of them. In this sense, misanthropy has a cognitive component based on a negative assessment of humanity and is not just a blind rejection.[4][5][6] Misanthropy is usually contrasted with philanthropy, which refers to the love of humankind and is associated with efforts to increase human well-being, for example, through charitable aid or donations. However, the two terms do not contradict each other and the same person may be a misanthrope in one sense and a philanthrope in another sense.[7][8][9]

One central aspect of all forms of misanthropy is that their target is not local but ubiquitous. So the negative attitude is not just directed at some individual persons or groups of people but at humanity as a whole.[10][11][12] This distinguishes misanthropes from racists, misogynists, and misandrists, which hold a negative attitude toward certain races or genders.[6][13][14] So these forms of discrimination and intolerance are not general characteristics of misanthropes.[6] It has been argued that misanthropy does not need to be universal in the sense that a person literally dislikes every human being. Instead, it depends on the person's horizon. For example, a villager who loathes every other villager without exception is a misanthrope if their horizon is limited to only this village.[15]

Both misanthropes and their critics agree that negative features and failings are not equally distributed, i.e. that the vices and bad traits are exemplified much more strongly in some than in others. But for misanthropy, the negative assessment of humanity is not based on a few extreme and outstanding cases: it is a condemnation of humanity as a whole, including the more ordinary cases.[4][11] Because of this focus on the ordinary, it is sometimes held that these flaws are obvious and open to see for everyone but people tend to ignore them or even praise them as virtues due to their intellectual flaws.[16] Some see the flaws as part of human nature as such.[17][16] Others also base their view on non-essential flaws, i.e. what humanity has come to be. This includes flaws seen as symptoms of modern civilization in general. Nevertheless, both groups agree that the relevant flaws are "entrenched". This means that there is either no or no easy way to rectify them and nothing short of a complete transformation of the dominant way of life would be required if that is possible at all.[18][19]

Types

Various types of misanthropy are distinguished in the academic literature. They are based on what attitude is involved, how it is expressed, and whether the misanthrope includes themselves in their negative assessment.[20][21][22] The differences between them often matter for assessing whether misanthropy is a faulty and self-contradictory outlook or a respectable philosophical position.[23][24] An early categorization is due to Immanuel Kant, who distinguishes between positive and negative misanthropes. Positive misanthropes are active enemies of humanity. They wish harm to other people and undertake attempts to hurt them in one form or another. Negative misanthropy, on the other hand, is a form of peaceful anthropophobia that leads people to isolate themselves. They wish others well despite seeing serious flaws in them. Kant associates negative misanthropy with moral disappointment due to previous negative experiences with others.[20][25]

Another distinction focuses on whether the misanthropic condemnation of humanity is only directed at other people or at everyone including oneself. In this regard, self-inclusive misanthropes are consistent in their attitude by including themselves in their negative assessment. This type is contrasted with self-aggrandizing misanthropes, who either implicitly or explicitly exclude themselves from the general condemnation and see themselves instead as superior to everyone else.[21][26] In this regard, it may be accompanied by an exaggerated sense of self-worth and self-importance.[27] According to Joseph Harris, the self-aggrandizing type is more common even though this outlook seems to undermine its own position by constituting a form of hypocrisy.[28] A closely related categorization is due to Irving Babbitt, who distinguishes misanthropes based on whether they allow exceptions in their negative assessment. In this regard, misanthropes of the naked intellect regard humanity as a whole as hopeless. Tender misanthropes, on the other hand, exclude a few idealized people from their negative evaluation. Babbitt cites Rousseau and his fondness for natural uncivilized man as an example of tender misanthropy and contrasts it with Swift's thorough dismissal of all of humanity.[29][30]

A further way to categorize forms of misanthropy is in relation to the type of attitude involved toward humanity. In this regard, Toby Svoboda distinguishes the attitudes of dislike, hate, contempt, and judgment. A misanthrope based on dislike harbors a distaste in the form of negative feelings toward other people.[10] Misanthropy focusing on hatred involves an intensive form of dislike that includes the additional component of wishing ill upon others and, at times, of trying to realize this wish.[31] In the case of contempt, the attitude is not based on feelings and emotions but on a more theoretical outlook. It leads misanthropes to see other people as worthless and look down on them while excluding themselves from this assessment.[32] If the misanthropic attitude has its foundation in judgment, it is also theoretical but does not distinguish between self and others. It is the view that humanity is in general bad without implying that the misanthrope is in any way better than the rest.[33] According to Svoboda, only misanthropy based on judgment constitutes a serious philosophical position. Misanthropy focusing on contempt is biased against other people while misanthropy in the form of dislike and hate is difficult to assess since these emotional attitudes often do not respond to objective evidence.[34]

Misanthropic forms of life

 
Misanthropy is often associated with the tendency to avoid social contacts, as portrayed in painting The Misanthrope by Pieter Bruegel the Elder.

Misanthropes can also be distinguished based on the form of life they use to respond to the misanthropic outlook. In this regard, misanthropy is usually not restricted to a theoretical opinion but involves an evaluative attitude that calls for a practical response. This is realized in different forms of life that come with different dominant emotions and various practical consequences for how to lead one's life.[4][35] These responses to misanthropy are sometimes presented through simplified prototypes that may be too crude to accurately capture the mental life of any single person but instead aim to portray common attitudes among groups of misanthropes. The two responses most commonly associated with misanthropy involve either destruction or fleeing from society. The destructive misanthrope is said to be driven by a hatred of humankind and aims at tearing it down, with violence if necessary.[4][36] For the fugitive misanthrope, fear is the dominant emotion and leads the misanthrope to seek a secluded place in order to avoid the corrupting contact with civilization and humanity as much as possible.[4][6]

The contemporary misanthropic literature has also identified further less-known types of misanthropic lifestyles.[4] The activist misanthrope is driven by hope despite their negative appraisal of humanity. This hope is a form of meliorism based on the idea that it is possible and feasible for humanity to transform itself and the activist tries to realize this ideal.[4][37] A weaker version of this approach is to try to improve the world incrementally to avoid some of the worst outcomes without the hope of fully solving the fundamental problem.[38] The quietist misanthrope, on the other hand, takes a pessimistic approach toward what the individual can do for bringing about a transformation or significant improvements. In contrast to the more drastic reactions of the other responses mentioned, they resign themselves to quiet acceptance and small-scale avoidance.[39][4] A further approach is focused on humor based on mockery and ridicule at the absurdity of the human condition, for example, because humans hurt each other and risk future self-destruction for trivial concerns like a marginal increase in profit. This way, humor can act both as a mirror to portray the terrible truth of the situation and as its palliative at the same time.[40]

Forms of human flaws

A core aspect of misanthropy is that its negative attitude toward humanity is based on human flaws.[41][4] Various misanthropes have provided extensive lists of flaws, including cruelty, greed, selfishness, wastefulness, dogmatism, self-deception, and insensitivity to beauty.[42][43][4] These flaws can be categorized in many ways. It is often held that moral flaws constitute the most serious case.[19][44] Other flaws discussed in the contemporary literature include intellectual flaws, aesthetic flaws, and spiritual flaws.[45][19]

 
Moral flaws of human beings are exemplified in harm done to humans by other humans, like the mass killings during the Holocaust.

Moral flaws are often identified with tendencies to promote what is bad or with inappropriate attitudes toward values.[46][47] They include cruelty, indifference to the suffering of others, selfishness, moral laziness, cowardice, injustice, greed, and ingratitude. The harm done because of these flaws can be divided into three categories: harm done directly to humans, harm done directly to other animals, and harm done indirectly to both humans and animals by harming the environment. Examples of these categories include the Holocaust, factory farming of livestock, and pollution causing climate change.[48][19][49] In this regard, it is not just relevant that human beings cause these forms of harm but also that they are morally responsible for them. This is based on the idea that they can understand the consequences of their actions and could act differently. However, they decide not to, for example, because they ignore the long-term well-being of others in order to get short-term personal benefits.[50]

Intellectual flaws concern cognitive capacities. They can be defined as what leads to false beliefs, what obstructs knowledge, or what violates the demands of rationality. They include intellectual vices, like arrogance, wishful thinking, dogmatism, stupidity, and gullibility, as well as cognitive biases, like the confirmation bias, the self-serving bias, the hindsight bias, and the anchoring bias.[51][52][46] Intellectual flaws can work in tandem with all kinds of vices: they may deceive someone about having a certain vice and thereby prevent them from addressing it and improving themself, for example, by being mindless and failing to recognize their flaws. They also include forms of self-deceit, wilful ignorance, and being in denial about something.[53][54] Similar considerations have prompted some traditions to see intellectual failings, like ignorance, as the root of all evil.[55][56][57]

Aesthetic flaws are usually not given the same importance as moral and intellectual flaws, but they also carry some weight for misanthropic considerations. These flaws relate to beauty and ugliness. They concern ugly aspects of human life itself, like defecation and aging, ugliness caused by human activities, like pollution and litter, and inappropriate attitudes toward aesthetic aspects, like being insensitive to beauty.[58][59][19]

Psychological and social causes

Various psychological and social factors have been identified in the academic literature as possible causes of misanthropic sentiments. The individual factors by themselves may not be able to fully explain misanthropy but can show instead how it becomes more likely.[24] For example, it is often argued that undergoing disappointments and disillusionments in life increases the tendency to adopt a misanthropic outlook.[60][61] In this regard, the more idealistic and optimistic the person initially was, the stronger this reversal and the following negative outlook tend to be.[60] This type of psychological explanation is already found in Plato's Phaedo. In it, Socrates explains that misanthropy arises when a person trusts and admires someone without knowing them sufficiently well. If it is then discovered later that the admired person has serious flaws, the initial attitude may be reversed and universalized to apply to all others. This leads to general distrust and contempt toward other humans. It becomes more likely if the admired person is a close friend and if it happens more than once.[62][63] This form of misanthropy may be accompanied by a feeling of moral superiority in which the misanthrope considers themselves to be better than everyone else.[60] Other types of negative personal experiences in life may have a similar effect. Andrew Gibson uses this line of thought to explain why some philosophers became misanthropes. In the case of Thomas Hobbes, he discusses the politically unstable environment and the frequent wars which Hobbes had to live through. For Arthur Schopenhauer, he cites the fact that Schopenhauer was forced to flee from his home at the age of five and never found a place to call home afterward.[24][64] Another psychological factor is associated with negative attitudes toward the human body, especially in the form of general revulsion from sexuality.[65][24]

Besides the psychological causes, some wider social circumstances may also play a role. Generally speaking, the more negative the circumstances are, the more likely misanthropy becomes.[66][24] For example, it has been argued that socio-economic inequality in the form of unfair distribution of wealth increases the tendency to adopt a misanthropic perspective. This has to do with the fact that inequality tends to undermine trust in the government and others. It may be possible to overcome or reduce this source of misanthropy by implementing policies that build trust and promote a more equal distribution of wealth.[24][67] The political regime is another relevant factor. This specifically concerns authoritarian regimes using all means available to repress their population and stay in power.[68][69] For example, it has been argued that the severe forms of repression of the Ancien Régime in the late 17th century made it more likely for people to adopt a misanthropic outlook because their freedom was denied.[24][70] Democracy, on the other hand, may have the opposite effect since it allows more personal freedom due to its more optimistic outlook on human nature. [68][69]

Empirical studies often use questions related to trust in other people to measure misanthropy. This concerns specifically whether the individual believes that others would be fair and helpful.[71][72] In an empirical study on misanthropy in American society, Tom W. Smith concludes that factors associated with an increased misanthropic outlook are low socioeconomic status, being from racial and ethnic minorities, and having experienced recent negative events in one's life. In regard to religion, misanthropy is higher for people who do not attend church and for fundamentalists. Certain factors seem to play no significant role, like gender, having undergone a divorce, and never having been married.[71] Another study by Morris Rosenberg finds that misanthropy is associated with certain political outlooks, like being skeptical about free speech and a tendency to support authoritarian policies, for example, to suppress certain political and religious liberties. However, there seems to be no clear link to many of the broader political outlooks, like being a Democrat rather than a Republican or being a liberal rather than a conservative.[71][72]

Arguments for and against

Various discussions in the academic literature concern the question of whether misanthropy is an accurate assessment of humanity and what the consequences of adopting it are. Many proponents of misanthropy focus on the different forms of human flaws together with examples of when they exercise their negative influences. They argue that these flaws are so severe that misanthropy is an appropriate response.[73] Special importance in this regard is usually given to moral faults.[74][75][4] This is based on the idea that humans do not merely cause a great deal of suffering and destruction but are also morally responsible for them. The reason is that they are intelligent enough to understand the consequences of their actions and could potentially make balanced long-term decisions instead of focusing on personal short-term gains.[50] Opponents of misanthropy often respond to the different examples by claiming that they are extreme individual manifestations of human flaws, either by mentally ill perpetrators or by normal people under extreme circumstances. In this regard, the negative cases do not reflect on humanity at large and therefore are unable to justify the misanthropic attitude. So while there are cases of extreme human brutality, like the mass killings committed by dictators and their forces, listing such cases is not sufficient for condemning humanity at large.[4][76] Misanthropes have responded to this type of argument in various ways. Some hold that the underlying flaws are there in everyone, even if they reach their most extreme manifestation only in a few.[4] Others claim that many ordinary people are complicit in their manifestation, for example, by supporting the political leaders committing them, even if they did not directly commit them.[77] Another approach is to focus not on the grand extreme cases but on the ordinary small-scale manifestations of human flaws in everyday life, such as lying, cheating, breaking promises, and being ungrateful.[78][79]

A closely related defense of misanthropy is based on the actual damage caused by humans in the past.[49][80][81] In this regard, Svoboda presents a thought experiment involving the discovery of a fully established ecosystem on another planet. This ecosystem is in harmony except for a single species that dominates it and causes one ecological catastrophe after another resulting in mass extinctions of other species. Svoboda argues that having a negative attitude toward this species is the appropriate response and that this case accurately reflects the role of human beings on Earth.[82] An objection to this line of thought is that the negative assessment should not be directed at humanity but at certain social forces, like capitalism, fascism, religious fundamentalism, or imperialism, which are seen as the main cause of many tragedies.[83] On this view, the proper attitude would be anti-capitalism or a similar outlook but not misanthropy. Svoboda rejects this argument by claiming that these forces do not have a life of their own but depend on human beings to manifest them. In this regard, these forces are just different ways in which the negative value of humanity is enacted.[84]

 
Misanthropes often focus on the harm done by humans to animals on a large scale, as in factory farming.

A different problem for arguments based on human flaws is that they present just one side of humanity while evaluative attitudes should take all sides into account. So it may be the case that despite having very serious vices, humans may also possess equally important virtues that make up for their shortcomings.[85] For example, accounts that focus only on the great wars, cruelties, and tragedies in human history ignore its positive achievements in the sciences, arts, and humanities. And the focus on negative exemplars, like Stalin or Hitler, should be contrasted with positive exemplars, like Mother Teresa or Gandhi.[86] While it is difficult to make such comparisons on a large scale, misanthropes have argued that at least for important subfields, like man's treatment of animals, the scales are tipped against man.[87][88] Misanthropes often argue that positive achievements are rare exceptions while negative consequences are much more widespread.[89] Another argument favoring misanthropy, sometimes referred to as the asymmetry thesis, holds that morally bad actions carry more weight on an ethical level than their good counterparts. In this regard, a person cannot simply make up for the cold murders they committed by saving a few lives.[90]

Some objections to misanthropy are based not on whether this attitude appropriately reflects the negative value of humanity but on the costs of accepting such a position, for the individual and for society at large. This is especially relevant if misanthropy is associated with hatred, which may turn easily into violence against social institutions and other humans and may result in a lot of harm.[91] Misanthropy may also deprive the individual of most pleasures by making them miserable and friendless.[92] Defenders have argued that misanthropy is not necessarily connected to hatred, violence, and friendlessness. So these criticisms may be valid for forms of misanthropy focused on hatred and destruction but miss their target for other forms based on a peaceful and theoretical outlook.[93][4][6] A closely related criticism holds that misanthropy is morally objectable.[93] This argument may be valid for many individual misanthropes but it has been argued that misanthropy is not necessarily in conflict with obeying the demands of morality. An example of this would be Kant's "cold-hearted benefactor", who fulfills all their moral requirements toward other people despite lacking real sympathy.[94][95]

Another form of criticism focuses more on the theoretical level and claims that misanthropy is an inconsistent and self-contradictory position that amounts at best to a "proto-philosophy or sub-philosophy".[96][24] This inconsistency shows itself, for example, in the misanthrope's tendency to denounce the social world while still being engaged in it and being unable to fully leave it behind.[97] This criticism applies specifically to misanthropes who exclude themselves from the negative evaluation and look down on others with contempt from an arrogant position of inflated ego. But it may not apply to all types of misanthropy.[28][98][26] A closely related objection is based on the claim that misanthropy is an unnatural attitude and should therefore be seen as an aberration or a pathological case.[99]

In various disciplines

Philosophy

Misanthropy has been discussed and exemplified by philosophers throughout history. One of the earliest cases was the pre-Socratic philosopher Heraclitus. He is often characterized as a loner who had little patience for human society. A central factor to his negative outlook on human beings was their lack of comprehension of the true nature of reality. This concerns especially cases in which they remain in a state of ignorance despite having received a thorough explanation of the issue in question.[100][101][102] Another early discussion is found in Plato's Phaedo, where misanthropy is characterized as the result of frustrated expectations and excessively naïve optimism.[103][62][63]

 
The cynic philosopher Diogenes had a very negative image of the people around him and cared little for social conventions. For example, he used to walk around with a lamp in full daylight in his unsuccessful attempt to find an honest or worthy man.[104][105]

Various strands of misanthropy are also found in the cynic school of philosophy. There it is argued, for example, that humans keep on reproducing and multiplying the evils they are attempting to flee. For example, they move to cities to defend themselves against outsiders. But this process thwarts their initial goal by leading to even more violence due to high crime rates within the city. Diogenes is a well-known cynic misanthrope. He saw other people as hypocritical and superficial. He openly rejected all kinds of societal norms and values, often provoking others by consciously breaking conventions and behaving rudely.[106][24][107]

Thomas Hobbes is an example of misanthropy in early modern philosophy. His negative outlook on humanity is reflected in many of his works. For him, humans are egoistic and violent: they act according to their self-interest and are willing to pursue their goals at the expense of others. In their natural state, this leads to a never-ending war in which "every man to every man ... is an enemy". He saw the establishment of an authoritative state characterized by the strict enforcement of laws to maintain order as the only way to tame the violent human nature and avoid perpetual war.[108][109][110]

A different type of misanthropy is found in Jean-Jacques Rousseau. He idealizes the harmony and simplicity found in nature and contrasts them with the confusion and disorder found in humanity, especially in the form of society and institutions.[111][112][113] For example, in a famous statement, he claims that "Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains".[114][115] This negative outlook was also reflected in his lifestyle: he lived solitary and preferred to be with plants rather than humans.[116]

Arthur Schopenhauer is often mentioned as a prime example of misanthropy.[117][118] According to him, everything in the world, including humans and their activities, is an expression of one underlying will. However, this will is blind, which causes it to continuously engage in futile struggles. On the level of human life, this "presents itself as a continual deception" since it is driven by pointless desires. They are mostly egoistic and often result in injustice and suffering to others. Once they are satisfied, they only give rise to new pointless desires and more suffering.[119][120][121] In this regard, Schopenhauer dismisses most things that are typically considered precious or meaningful in human life, like romantic love, individuality, and liberty.[122] He holds that the best response to the human condition is a form of asceticism by denying the expression of the will. However, this is only found in very rare humans and "the dull majority of men" does not live up to this ideal.[123]

Friedrich Nietzsche, who was strongly influenced by Schopenhauer, is also often cited as an example of misanthropy. He saw man as a decadent and "sick animal" that constitutes no progress over other animals.[124][125][126] He even had a negative image of apes since they are more similar to human beings than other animals, for example, in regard to cruelty.[127] For Nietzsche, a noteworthy flaw of human beings is their tendency to create and enforce systems of moral rules that favor weak people and suppress true greatness.[125][128] He held that the human being is something to be overcome and replaced by what he calls the Übermensch.[129][130]

Religion

 
Focus on the sinful nature of human beings is one form of misanthropy, as in the Christian doctrine of original sin tainting every human being.

Some misanthropic views are also found in religious teachings. In Christianity, for example, this is associated with the sinful nature of humans and the widespread manifestation of sin in everyday life.[131] Common forms of sin are discussed in terms of the seven deadly sins, such as an excessive sense of self-importance in the form of pride, strong sexual cravings constituting lust, and following greed for material possessions as well as being envious of the possessions of others.[132] According to the doctrine of original sin, this flaw is found in every human being since human nature is already tainted by sin from birth by inheriting it from Adam and Eve's rebellion against God's authority.[131][133]

Misanthropic perspectives can also be discerned in various Buddhist teachings. For example, Buddha had a very negative outlook on the widespread flaws of human beings, including lust, hatred, delusion, sorrow, and despair.[134] These flaws are identified with some form of craving or attachment (taṇhā) and cause suffering (dukkha).[135][136] Buddhists hold that it is possible to overcome these failings in the process of achieving Buddhahood or enlightenment. However, this is seen as an extremely difficult and rare achievement. In this regard, most human beings carry these deep flaws with them throughout their life.[137]

However, there are also many religious teachings opposed to misanthropy, such as the emphasis on kindness and helping others. In Christianity, this is found in the concept of agape, which involves selfless and unconditional love in the form of compassion and a willingness to help others.[138] Buddhists see the practice of loving kindness (metta) as a central aspect that implies a positive attitude of compassion toward humans and all other sentient beings.[139][140]

Literature and popular culture

Many examples of misanthropy are also found in literature and popular culture. Timon of Athens by William Shakespeare is a famous portrayal of the life of the Ancient Greek Timon, who is widely known for his extreme misanthropic attitude. Shakespeare depicts him as a wealthy and generous gentleman. However, he becomes disillusioned with his ungrateful friends and humanity at large. This way, his initial philanthropy turns into an unrestrained hatred of humanity, which prompts him to leave society in order to live in a forest.[141][142] Molière's play The Misanthrope is another famous example. Its protagonist, Alceste, has a very low opinion of the people around him. He tends to focus on their flaws and openly criticizes them for their superficiality, insincerity, and hypocrisy. He rejects most social conventions and thereby often offends others, for example, by refusing to engage in social niceties like polite small talk.[143][144][145]

 
Jonathan Swift is well-known for his often explicit pronouncements of misanthropy.

The author Jonathan Swift had a reputation for being misanthropic. In some statements, he openly declares that he hates and detests "that animal called man".[146] Misanthropy is also found in many of his works. For example, Gulliver's Travels tells the adventures of the protagonist Gulliver, who journeys to various places, like an island inhabited by tiny people and a land ruled by intelligent horses. Through these experiences of the contrast between humans and other species, he comes to see more and more the deep flaws of humanity, leading him to develop a revulsion toward other human beings.[147][148] Ebenezer Scrooge from Charles Dickens's A Christmas Carol is an often-cited example of misanthropy. He is described as a cold-hearted, solitary miser who detests Christmas. He is greedy, selfish, and has no regard for the well-being of others.[149][150][151] Other writers associated with misanthropy include Gustave Flaubert and Philip Larkin.[152][153]

Mr. Burns from the TV show The Simpsons is a more recent example of misanthropy. He is one of the main antagonists and his main desire is to increase his already enormous wealth and power. He is ruthless in pursuing this goal and has no regard for the safety and well-being of others in the process.[154][155][156] An even darker form of misanthropy is found in the character the Joker from the DC Universe. He is one of the main antagonists of Batman and acts as an agent of chaos. He believes that people are selfish, cruel, irrational, and hypocritical. He is usually portrayed as a sociopath with a twisted sense of humor who uses violent means to expose and bring down organized society.[157][158][159]

Related concepts

Philosophical pessimism

Misanthropy is closely related to but not identical with philosophical pessimism. Philosophical pessimism is the view that life as a whole is not worth living or that the world in general is a bad place, for example, because it is meaningless and full of suffering.[160][161] This view is perhaps best exemplified by Arthur Schopenhauer, or in its most extreme form, Philipp Mainländer.[162] Philosophical pessimism is often accompanied by misanthropy by holding that humanity is also bad and maybe partially responsible for the badness of the world. But the two views do not entail each other and can be held separately.[4][163] A non-misanthropic pessimist may hold, for example, that humans are just victims of a terrible world but not to blame for it. Eco-misanthropists, on the other hand, may claim that the world and its nature are valuable but for the negative, destructive influence of humanity.[4][164]

Antinatalism and human extinction

Humanity is a moral disaster. There would have been much less destruction had we never evolved. The fewer humans there are in the future, the less destruction there will still be.

David Benatar, "The Misanthropic Argument for Anti-natalism"[75]

Antinatalism is the view that coming into existence is bad and that humans, therefore, have a duty to abstain from procreation.[165][166] A central argument for antinatalism is the so-called misanthropic argument. It sees the deep flaws of humans and their tendency to cause harm as a reason for avoiding to create more humans.[167][168] These harms include wars, genocides, factory farming, and damages done to the environment.[169] This argument contrasts with philanthropic arguments, which focus on the future suffering of the human about to come into existence. They argue that the only way to avoid their future suffering is to prevent them from being born.[167][168][38] The Voluntary Human Extinction Movement and the Church of Euthanasia are well-known examples of social movements in favor of antinatalism and human extinction.[170][171]

 
Some misanthropes hope for the extinction of the human species, which could happen, for example, due to a worldwide nuclear war.

Antinatalism is commonly endorsed by misanthropic thinkers.[38] But there are also many other ways that could lead to the extinction of the human species. This field is still relatively speculative but various suggestions have been made about threats to the long-term survival of the human species. An often-discussed scenario involves the outbreak of a worldwide nuclear war leaving Earth uninhabitable. Another threat is posed by advances in nano-technology, which may at some point lead to the development of self-replicating nanorobots that could get out of control. In the field of medicine, scientific advances could be used to create a deadly super-pathogen that could spread rapidly.[172][173][174] While such cases are usually seen as terrible scenarios and dangerous threats, misanthropes may instead interpret them as reasons for hope that the abhorrent age of humanity in history may soon come to an end.[175] A similar sentiment is expressed by Bertrand Russell, who states in relation to the existence of human life on earth and its misdeeds that they are "a passing nightmare; in time the earth will become again incapable of supporting life, and peace will return."[176]

Human exceptionalism and deep ecology

Human exceptionalism is the claim that human beings have unique importance and are exceptional compared to all other species. It is often based on the claim that they stand out because of their special capacities, like intelligence, rationality, and autonomy.[177] In religious contexts, it is frequently explained in relation to a unique role that God foresaw for them or that they were created in God's image.[178] Human exceptionalism is usually combined with the claim that human well-being matters more than the well-being of other species. This line of thought can be used to draw various ethical conclusions, for example, that humans have the right to rule the planet and impose their will on other species or that inflicting harm on other species may be morally acceptable if it is done with the purpose of promoting human well-being and excellence.[177][179] Generally speaking, the position of human exceptionalism is at odds with misanthropy since their outlooks on the value of humanity are in many ways diametrically opposed. [179] Nonetheless, it has been argued that this is not necessarily the case and it is possible to hold both positions at the same time. One way to do this is to claim that humanity is exceptional mainly due to a few rare individuals while maintaining a negative perspective toward the average person.[180] Another approach is to turn human exceptionalism on its head by claiming that human beings are exceptional in a negative sense, i.e. that, given their destructive and harmful history, they are much worse than any other species.[179]

Theorists in the field of deep ecology are also often critical of human exceptionalism and tend to favor a misanthropic perspective.[181][182] Deep ecology is a philosophical and social movement that emphasizes the inherent value of nature and advocates a radical change in human behavior toward nature.[183] Various theorists have criticized deep ecology based on the claim that it is misanthropic by privileging other species over humans.[182] For example, the deep ecology movement Earth First! has faced severe criticism when they praised the AIDS epidemic in Africa as a solution to the problem of human overpopulation in their newsletter.[184][185]

See also

References

  1. ^ "misanthropy". www.etymonline.com. Retrieved 21 July 2021.
  2. ^ "Definition of Misanthropy". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 5 July 2021.
  3. ^ Company, Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: misanthropy". www.ahdictionary.com. Retrieved 5 July 2021.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q Kidd, Ian James (2020). "Philosophical Misanthropy". philosophynow.org (139).
  5. ^ a b Cooper 2018, p. 7.
  6. ^ a b c d e Edyvane, Derek (2013). "Rejecting Society: Misanthropy, Friendship and Montaigne". Res Publica. 19 (1): 53–65. doi:10.1007/s11158-012-9206-2. S2CID 144666876.
  7. ^ "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: philanthropy". www.ahdictionary.com. HarperCollins.
  8. ^ Lim, Song Hwee (31 August 2006). Celluloid Comrades: Representations of Male Homosexuality in Contemporary Chinese Cinemas. University of Hawaii Press. p. 167. ISBN 9780824830779.
  9. ^ Sawaya, Francesca (15 July 2014). The Difficult Art of Giving: Patronage, Philanthropy, and the American Literary Market. University of Pennsylvania Press. p. 207. ISBN 9780812290035.
  10. ^ a b Svoboda 2022, p. 6-7.
  11. ^ a b Cooper 2018, p. 54-6.
  12. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 38, 41.
  13. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 190.
  14. ^ Gilmore, David D. (3 August 2010). Misogyny: The Male Malady. University of Pennsylvania Press. p. 12. ISBN 9780812200324.
  15. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 145.
  16. ^ a b Kidd, Ian James. "Review of David E. Cooper, "Animals and Misanthropy" (Routledge, 2018)". Philosophy.
  17. ^ Harris 2022, p. 118.
  18. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 7, 13, 54-8.
  19. ^ a b c d e Kidd, Ian James (16 February 2022). "4. Misanthropy and the Hatred of Humanity". In Birondo, Noell (ed.). The Moral Psychology of Hate. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 75–99. ISBN 9781538160862.
  20. ^ a b Tsakalakis, Thomas (15 October 2020). Political Correctness: A Sociocultural Black Hole. Routledge. p. 144. ISBN 9781000205084.
  21. ^ a b Harris 2022, p. 21.
  22. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 6-9.
  23. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 6, 9, 29.
  24. ^ a b c d e f g h i Querido, Pedro (February 2020). "Andrew Gibson, Misanthropy: The Critique of Humanity". Comparative Critical Studies. 17 (1): 152–7. doi:10.3366/ccs.2020.0349. ISSN 1744-1854.
  25. ^ Wilford, Paul T.; Stoner, Samuel A. (4 June 2021). Kant and the Possibility of Progress: From Modern Hopes to Postmodern Anxieties. University of Pennsylvania Press. pp. 42–3. ISBN 9780812297799.
  26. ^ a b Svoboda 2022, p. 8.
  27. ^ Harris 2022, p. 22.
  28. ^ a b Harris 2022, p. 20-2.
  29. ^ King 1993, p. 57-8.
  30. ^ Babbitt, Irving (2015). "Chapter VII: Romantic Irony". Rousseau and Romanticism. Project Gutenberg.
  31. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 7.
  32. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 7-8.
  33. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 8-9.
  34. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 8-9, 40.
  35. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 110-1.
  36. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 115-6.
  37. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 14, 115.
  38. ^ a b c Svoboda 2022, p. 14.
  39. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 118-9.
  40. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 117-8.
  41. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 7, 47-8.
  42. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 3, 8, 48.
  43. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 39-42.
  44. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 34-6, 55.
  45. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 7, 13, 48.
  46. ^ a b Hurka, Thomas (2020). "Virtues and vices". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
  47. ^ Hurka, Thomas (2001). "Vices as Higher-Level Evils". Utilitas. 13 (2): 195–212. doi:10.1017/s0953820800003137. S2CID 145225191.
  48. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 39-48.
  49. ^ a b Svoboda 2022, p. 4-5.
  50. ^ a b Svoboda 2022, p. 3, 5.
  51. ^ Madison, B. J. C. (2017). "On the Nature of Intellectual Vice". Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective. 6 (12): 1–6.
  52. ^ Litvak, P.; Lerner, J. S. (2009). "cognitive bias". In Sander, David; Scherer, Klaus (eds.). The Oxford companion to emotion and the affective sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 89–90. ISBN 9780198569633.
  53. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 50-1.
  54. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 18.
  55. ^ Hackforth, R. (1946). "Moral Evil and Ignorance in Plato's Ethics". Classical Quarterly. 40 (3–4): 118–. doi:10.1017/S0009838800023442. S2CID 145412342.
  56. ^ Menon, Sangeetha. "Vedanta, Advaita". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 3 July 2021.
  57. ^ Mahathera, Nyanatiloka (1964). "II. Kamma and Rebirth". Karma and Rebirth. Buddhist Publication Society.
  58. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 56-8.
  59. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 7, 48.
  60. ^ a b c Harris 2022, p. 195.
  61. ^ Chambers, Robert (1847). Essays moral and economic. W. & R. Chambers. p. 191.
  62. ^ a b Shakespeare, William (3 April 2001). Timon of Athens. Cambridge University Press. p. 208. ISBN 9781139835114.
  63. ^ a b White, David A. (1989). Myth and Metaphysics in Plato's Phaedo. Susquehanna University Press. p. 134. ISBN 9780945636014.
  64. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 98-9, 107-8.
  65. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 13, 119, 207.
  66. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 119.
  67. ^ Hooghe, M.; Stolle, D. (15 May 2003). Generating Social Capital: Civil Society and Institutions in Comparative Perspective. Springer. p. 185. ISBN 9781403979544.
  68. ^ a b Gibson 2017, p. 13, 62, 207.
  69. ^ a b Tsakalakis, Thomas (15 October 2020). Political Correctness: A Sociocultural Black Hole. Routledge. p. 142. ISBN 9781000205084.
  70. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 61, 207.
  71. ^ a b c Smith, Tom W. (June 1997). "Factors Relating to Misanthropy in Contemporary American Society". Social Science Research. 26 (2): 170–196. doi:10.1006/ssre.1997.0592.
  72. ^ a b Rosenberg, Morris (December 1956). "Misanthropy and Political Ideology". American Sociological Review. 21 (6): 690. doi:10.2307/2088419.
  73. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 4, 7, 54
    Benatar 2015, p. 55
    Querido, Pedro (February 2020). "Andrew Gibson, Misanthropy: The Critique of Humanity". Comparative Critical Studies. 17 (1): 152–7. doi:10.3366/ccs.2020.0349. ISSN 1744-1854.
    Gibson 2017, p. 13

  74. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 3, 13.
  75. ^ a b Benatar 2015, p. 55.
  76. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 39-41.
  77. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 37, 41-2.
  78. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 43.
  79. ^ Kidd, Ian James (2020). "Humankind, Human Nature, and Misanthropy". Metascience. 29 (3): 505–508. doi:10.1007/s11016-020-00562-8. S2CID 225274682.
  80. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 80.
  81. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 38-9.
  82. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 1, 5.
  83. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 13, 69.
  84. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 69-70.
  85. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 51-52.
  86. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 64.
  87. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 52.
  88. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 77-8.
  89. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 5.
  90. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 13.
  91. ^ McGraw, Shannon (2014). "1. Introduction". Misanthropy and Criminal Behavior (PDF). pp. 1–2. (PDF) from the original on 2021-07-09.
  92. ^ Shklar, Judith N. (1984). "5. Misanthropy". Ordinary Vices. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. p. 192.
  93. ^ a b Svoboda 2022, p. 12, 29.
  94. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 29.
  95. ^ Stohr, Karen E. (2002). "Virtue Ethics and Kant's Cold-Hearted Benefactor". The Journal of Value Inquiry. 36 (2/3): 187–204. doi:10.1023/A:1016192117676.
  96. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 4-5.
  97. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 4, 60.
  98. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 63.
  99. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 65.
  100. ^ Moyal, Georges J.D. (1989). "On Heraclitus's Misanthropy". Revue de Philosophie Ancienne. 7 (2): 131–148. ISSN 0771-5420.
  101. ^ Mark, Joshua J. (2010-07-14). "Heraclitus of Ephesus". World History Encyclopedia. Retrieved 2017-12-08.
  102. ^ Ava, Chitwood (2004). Death by philosophy : the biographical tradition in the life and death of the archaic philosophers Empedocles, Heraclitus, and Democritus. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. p. 80. ISBN 0472113887. OCLC 54988783.
  103. ^ Stern, Paul (1993). Socratic Rationalism and Political Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato's Phaedo. SUNY Press. p. 95. ISBN 9780791415733.
  104. ^ Yeroulanos, Marinos (30 June 2016). A Dictionary of Classical Greek Quotations. Bloomsbury Publishing. p. 203. ISBN 9781786730497.
  105. ^ Navia, Luis E. (1996). Classical Cynicism: A Critical Study. Greenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 9780313300158.
  106. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 14-6.
  107. ^ Arruzza, Cinzia; Nikulin, Dmitri (21 November 2016). Philosophy and Political Power in Antiquity. Brill. p. 119. ISBN 9789004324626.
  108. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 93, 95, 98.
  109. ^ Williams, Garrath. "Hobbes, Thomas: Moral and Political Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 January 2023.
  110. ^ Byrne, James M. (1 January 1997). Religion and the Enlightenment: From Descartes to Kant. Westminster John Knox Press. p. 112. ISBN 9780664257606.
  111. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 110-1.
  112. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 19.
  113. ^ King 1993, p. 58-9.
  114. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 112.
  115. ^ Williams, David Lay (1 November 2010). Rousseau's Platonic Enlightenment. Penn State Press. p. 147. ISBN 9780271045511.
  116. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 111.
  117. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 12, 15.
  118. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 101.
  119. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 101-3.
  120. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 15-6.
  121. ^ Troxell, Mary. "Schopenhauer, Arthur". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 January 2023.
  122. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 104-5.
  123. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 105-6.
  124. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 2.
  125. ^ a b Villa, Dana (1 September 2020). Socratic Citizenship. Princeton University Press. p. 127. ISBN 9780691218175.
  126. ^ Wilkerson, Dale. "Nietzsche, Friedrich: 1. Life". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 January 2023.
  127. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 62.
  128. ^ Solomon, Robert C. (26 August 2004). In Defense of Sentimentality. Oxford University Press. p. 67. ISBN 9780198033288.
  129. ^ Shaw, George Bernard (2021). Man and Superman, John Bull's Other Island, and Major Barbara. Oxford University Press. p. xxxii. ISBN 9780198828853.
  130. ^ Grillaert, Nel (2008). What the God-seekers Found in Nietzsche: The Reception of Neitzche's Übermensch by the Philosophers of the Russian Religious Renaissance. Rodopi. p. 245. ISBN 9789042024809.
  131. ^ a b Gibson 2017, p. 28-9.
  132. ^ Kastenbaum, Robert (2003). "Seven Deadly Sins". Encyclopedia of Death and Dying. New York: Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 9780028656908.
  133. ^ Hale, Tom; Thorson, Stephen (2007). The Applied Old Testament Commentary. David C Cook. p. 46. ISBN 9780781448642.
  134. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 4.
  135. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 6-7.
  136. ^ Morgan, Diane (2010). Essential Buddhism: A Comprehensive Guide to Belief and Practice. ABC-CLIO. p. 91. ISBN 9780313384523.
  137. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 56.
  138. ^ Catholic University of America (1967). "Agape". New Catholic Encyclopedia. McGraw-Hill. ISBN 9780787639990.
  139. ^ Aung, SK (April 1996). "Loving kindness: the essential Buddhist contribution to primary care". Humane health care international. 12 (2). PMID 14986605.
  140. ^ Morgan, Diane (2010). Essential Buddhism: A Comprehensive Guide to Belief and Practice. ABC-CLIO. p. 138. ISBN 9780313384523.
  141. ^ Harris 2022, p. 27-30.
  142. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 1-2.
  143. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 2-4.
  144. ^ Harris 2022, p. 58.
  145. ^ Hawcroft, Michael (27 September 2007). Molière: Reasoning With Fools. Oxford University Press. p. 132. ISBN 9780191527937.
  146. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 14.
  147. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 84-5.
  148. ^ Jan, K. M.; Firdaus, Shabnam (2004). Perspectives on Gulliver’s Travels. Atlantic Publishers & Dist. p. 115. ISBN 9788126903450.
  149. ^ Moore, Grace (2011). A Christmas Carol: Insight Text Guides. Insight Publications. p. 16. ISBN 9781921411915.
  150. ^ Pirson, Michael (14 September 2017). Humanistic Management: Protecting Dignity and Promoting Well-Being. Cambridge University Press. p. 58. ISBN 9781107160729.
  151. ^ Cornog, Mary W. (1998). Merriam-Webster's Vocabulary Builder. Merriam-Webster. p. 357. ISBN 9780877799108.
  152. ^ The Letters of Gustave Flaubert: 1857-1880. Harvard University Press. 1982. p. xiv. ISBN 0674526406.
  153. ^ Raban, Jonathan (October 17, 1992). "Books: Mr Miseryguts: Philip Larkin's letters show all the grim humor that was a hallmark of his great poems, but, as the years pass, they also chart the true depths of his misanthropy and despair". The Independent. Archived from the original on 2022-05-15. Retrieved June 18, 2017.
  154. ^ Goertz, Allie; Prescott, Julia; Oakley, Bill; Weinstein, Josh (18 September 2018). 100 Things The Simpsons Fans Should Know & Do Before They Die (in Arabic). Triumph Books. p. 72. ISBN 9781641251099.
  155. ^ Fink, Moritz (19 June 2019). The Simpsons: A Cultural History. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 82. ISBN 9781538116173.
  156. ^ Brown, Alan S.; Logan, Chris (22 June 2009). The Psychology of the Simpsons: D'oh!. BenBella Books, Inc. p. 229. ISBN 9781935251392.
  157. ^ Lee, Judith Yaross; Bird, John (16 November 2020). Seeing MAD: Essays on MAD Magazine's Humor and Legacy. University of Missouri Press. p. 164. ISBN 9780826274489.
  158. ^ Donohoo, Timothy (6 January 2023). "The Joker Has a Morbidly Hilarious Reason For Not Killing Red Hood". CBR.
  159. ^ Bolus, Michael Peter (26 August 2019). Aesthetics and the Cinematic Narrative: An Introduction. Anthem Press. p. 24. ISBN 9781783089826.
  160. ^ Smith, Cameron (2014). "Introduction". Philosophical Pessimism: A Study In The Philosophy Of Arthur Schopenhauer. pp. 1–3.
  161. ^ Jenkins, Scott (2020). "The Pessimistic Origin of Nietzsche's Thought of Eternal Recurrence". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 63 (1): 20–41. doi:10.1080/0020174x.2019.1669976. S2CID 211969776.
  162. ^ Fernández, Jordi (2006). "Schopenhauer's Pessimism". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 73 (3): 646–664. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00552.x.
  163. ^ Cooper 2018, p. 5-6.
  164. ^ Gerber, Lisa (2002). "What is So Bad About Misanthropy?". Environmental Ethics. 24 (1): 41–55. doi:10.5840/enviroethics200224140.
  165. ^ Metz, Thaddeus (2012). "Contemporary Anti-Natalism, Featuring Benatar's Better Never to Have Been". South African Journal of Philosophy. 31 (1): 1–9. doi:10.1080/02580136.2012.10751763. S2CID 143091736.
  166. ^ Benatar 2015, p. 34-5.
  167. ^ a b Benatar 2015, p. 55-6.
  168. ^ a b Benatar, David (15 July 2015a). "'We Are Creatures That Should Not Exist': The Theory Of Anti-Natalism". The Critique. Retrieved 4 July 2021.
  169. ^ May, Todd (December 17, 2018). "Would Human Extinction Be a Tragedy?". The New York Times. Human beings are destroying large parts of the inhabitable earth and causing unimaginable suffering to many of the animals that inhabit it. This is happening through at least three means. First, human contribution to climate change is devastating ecosystems . . . Second, the increasing human population is encroaching on ecosystems that would otherwise be intact. Third, factory farming fosters the creation of millions upon millions of animals for whom it offers nothing but suffering and misery before slaughtering them in often barbaric ways. There is no reason to think that those practices are going to diminish any time soon. Quite the opposite.
  170. ^ Stibbe, Arran (1 May 2015). Ecolinguistics: Language, Ecology and the Stories We Live By. Routledge. p. 13. ISBN 9781317511908.
  171. ^ MacCormack, Patricia (2020). The Ahuman Manifesto: Activism for the End of the Anthropocene. Bloomsbury Academic. p. 143. ISBN 978-1350081093.
  172. ^ Bostrom, Nick (2003). "Extinction, Human". In Demeny, Paul George; McNicoll, Geoffrey (eds.). Encyclopedia of Population. Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 9780028656779.
  173. ^ Leslie, John (1998). The end of the world: the science and ethics of human extinction. New York: Routledge. pp. 25–6. ISBN 0203007727.
  174. ^ Gordijn, Bert; Cutter, Anthony Mark (30 September 2013). In Pursuit of Nanoethics. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 123. ISBN 9781402068171.
  175. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 107.
  176. ^ Svoboda 2022, p. 107-8.
  177. ^ a b Srinivasan, Krithika; Kasturirangan, Rajesh (October 2016). "Political ecology, development, and human exceptionalism". Geoforum. 75: 126–7. doi:10.1016/j.geoforum.2016.07.011.
  178. ^ Durst, Dennis L. (2022). The Perils of Human Exceptionalism: Elements of a Nineteenth-Century Theological Anthropology. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 1. ISBN 9781666900194.
  179. ^ a b c Svoboda 2022, p. 9.
  180. ^ Gibson 2017, p. 64-5.
  181. ^ Malone, Karen; Truong, Son; Gray, Tonia (17 January 2017). Reimagining Sustainability in Precarious Times. Springer. ISBN 9789811025501.
  182. ^ a b Sale, Kirkpatrick (14 May 1988). "Deep Ecology And Its Critics" (PDF). The Nation. (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-06.
  183. ^ Ball, Terence (June 2011). Blanchfield, Deirdre S. (ed.). Environmental Encyclopedia. Gale / Cengage Learning. ISBN 9781414487366.
  184. ^ Hay, P. R. (2002). Main currents in western environmental thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. p. 66. ISBN 0253340535.
  185. ^ Taylor, Bron (2005). Jones, Lindsay (ed.). Encyclopedia of Religion. Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 9780028657349.

Works cited

  • Benatar, David (2015). "The Misanthropic Argument for Anti-natalism". In S. Hannan; S. Brennan; R. Vernon (eds.). Permissible Progeny?: The Morality of Procreation and Parenting. Oxford University Press. pp. 34–64. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199378111.003.0002. ISBN 9780199378142.
  • Cooper, David E. (2 February 2018). Animals and Misanthropy. Routledge. ISBN 9781351583770.
  • Gibson, Andrew (15 June 2017). Misanthropy: The Critique of Humanity. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 9781474293181.
  • Harris, Joseph (November 2022). Misanthropy in the Age of Reason. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780192867575.
  • King, Florence (15 March 1993). With Charity Toward None: A Fond Look At Misanthropy. St. Martin's Press. ISBN 9780312094140.
  • Svoboda, Toby (29 April 2022). A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy. Taylor & Francis Limited. ISBN 9781032029986.

External links

  •   The dictionary definition of misanthropy at Wiktionary
  •   Quotations related to Misanthropy at Wikiquote

misanthropy, misanthrope, redirects, here, molière, comedy, misanthrope, french, metal, band, misanthrope, band, album, american, hard, rock, band, thrope, general, hatred, dislike, distrust, contempt, human, species, human, behavior, human, nature, misanthrop. Misanthrope redirects here For the Moliere comedy see Le Misanthrope For the French metal band see Misanthrope band For the album by American hard rock band DED see Mis an thrope Misanthropy is the general hatred dislike distrust or contempt of the human species human behavior or human nature A misanthrope or misanthropist is someone who holds such views or feelings The word originates from the Greek words mῖsos misos hatred and ἄn8rwpos anthropos man human Misanthropy involves a negative evaluative attitude toward humanity that is based on mankind s flaws Misanthropes hold that these flaws characterize all or at least the great majority of human beings and that there is no easy way to rectify them short of a complete transformation of the dominant way of life Various types of misanthropy are distinguished in the academic literature based on what attitude is involved at whom it is directed and how it is expressed Either emotions or theoretical judgments can serve as the foundation of the attitude It can be directed at all humans without exception or exclude a few idealized people In this regard some misanthropes condemn themselves while others consider themselves superior to everyone else Misanthropy is typically associated with either a destructive outlook aiming to hurt other people or an attempt to flee society Other types of misanthropic responses include activism by trying to improve humanity quietism in the form of resignation and humor mocking the absurdity of the human condition Engraving depicting the play Le Misanthrope by Moliere The negative misanthropic outlook is based on different types of human flaws Moral flaws are often seen as the main factor They include cruelty indifference to the suffering of others selfishness injustice and greed They may result in harm to humans and animals like genocides and factory farming of livestock Other flaws include intellectual flaws like dogmatism and cognitive biases as well as aesthetic flaws concerning ugliness and lack of sensitivity to beauty Many debates in the academic literature discuss whether misanthropy is a valid viewpoint and what its implications are Proponents of misanthropy usually point to human flaws and the harm they have caused as a sufficient reason for condemning humanity Critics have responded to this line of thought by claiming that severe flaws concern only a few extreme cases like mentally ill perpetrators but not humanity at large Another objection is based on the claim that humans also have virtues besides their flaws and that a balanced evaluation might be overall positive A further criticism rejects misanthropy because of its association with hatred which may lead to violence and because it may make people friendless and unhappy Defenders of misanthropy have responded by claiming that this applies only to some forms of misanthropy but not to misanthropy in general A related issue concerns the question of the psychological and social factors that cause people to become misanthropes They include becoming disillusioned with someone that was adored before socio economic inequality and living under an authoritarian regime Misanthropy is relevant in various disciplines It has been discussed and exemplified by philosophers throughout history Examples include Heraclitus Diogenes Thomas Hobbes Jean Jacques Rousseau Arthur Schopenhauer and Friedrich Nietzsche Misanthropic outlooks form part of some religious teachings discussing the deep flaws of human beings like the Christian doctrine of original sin Misanthropic perspectives and characters are also found in literature and popular culture They include William Shakespeare s portrayal of Timon of Athens Moliere s play The Misanthrope and Gulliver s Travels by Jonathan Swift Misanthropy is closely related to but not identical to philosophical pessimism Many misanthropes promote antinatalism the view that humans should abstain from procreation Contents 1 Definition 2 Types 2 1 Misanthropic forms of life 3 Forms of human flaws 4 Psychological and social causes 5 Arguments for and against 6 In various disciplines 6 1 Philosophy 6 2 Religion 6 3 Literature and popular culture 7 Related concepts 7 1 Philosophical pessimism 7 2 Antinatalism and human extinction 7 3 Human exceptionalism and deep ecology 8 See also 9 References 9 1 Works cited 10 External linksDefinition EditMisanthropy a word of 17th century origin from the Greek misanthrōpos 1 is traditionally defined as hatred or dislike of humankind 2 3 In contemporary philosophy the term is usually understood in a wider sense as a negative evaluation of humanity as a whole based on humanity s vices and flaws 4 5 This negative evaluation can express itself in various forms hatred being only one of them In this sense misanthropy has a cognitive component based on a negative assessment of humanity and is not just a blind rejection 4 5 6 Misanthropy is usually contrasted with philanthropy which refers to the love of humankind and is associated with efforts to increase human well being for example through charitable aid or donations However the two terms do not contradict each other and the same person may be a misanthrope in one sense and a philanthrope in another sense 7 8 9 One central aspect of all forms of misanthropy is that their target is not local but ubiquitous So the negative attitude is not just directed at some individual persons or groups of people but at humanity as a whole 10 11 12 This distinguishes misanthropes from racists misogynists and misandrists which hold a negative attitude toward certain races or genders 6 13 14 So these forms of discrimination and intolerance are not general characteristics of misanthropes 6 It has been argued that misanthropy does not need to be universal in the sense that a person literally dislikes every human being Instead it depends on the person s horizon For example a villager who loathes every other villager without exception is a misanthrope if their horizon is limited to only this village 15 Both misanthropes and their critics agree that negative features and failings are not equally distributed i e that the vices and bad traits are exemplified much more strongly in some than in others But for misanthropy the negative assessment of humanity is not based on a few extreme and outstanding cases it is a condemnation of humanity as a whole including the more ordinary cases 4 11 Because of this focus on the ordinary it is sometimes held that these flaws are obvious and open to see for everyone but people tend to ignore them or even praise them as virtues due to their intellectual flaws 16 Some see the flaws as part of human nature as such 17 16 Others also base their view on non essential flaws i e what humanity has come to be This includes flaws seen as symptoms of modern civilization in general Nevertheless both groups agree that the relevant flaws are entrenched This means that there is either no or no easy way to rectify them and nothing short of a complete transformation of the dominant way of life would be required if that is possible at all 18 19 Types EditVarious types of misanthropy are distinguished in the academic literature They are based on what attitude is involved how it is expressed and whether the misanthrope includes themselves in their negative assessment 20 21 22 The differences between them often matter for assessing whether misanthropy is a faulty and self contradictory outlook or a respectable philosophical position 23 24 An early categorization is due to Immanuel Kant who distinguishes between positive and negative misanthropes Positive misanthropes are active enemies of humanity They wish harm to other people and undertake attempts to hurt them in one form or another Negative misanthropy on the other hand is a form of peaceful anthropophobia that leads people to isolate themselves They wish others well despite seeing serious flaws in them Kant associates negative misanthropy with moral disappointment due to previous negative experiences with others 20 25 Another distinction focuses on whether the misanthropic condemnation of humanity is only directed at other people or at everyone including oneself In this regard self inclusive misanthropes are consistent in their attitude by including themselves in their negative assessment This type is contrasted with self aggrandizing misanthropes who either implicitly or explicitly exclude themselves from the general condemnation and see themselves instead as superior to everyone else 21 26 In this regard it may be accompanied by an exaggerated sense of self worth and self importance 27 According to Joseph Harris the self aggrandizing type is more common even though this outlook seems to undermine its own position by constituting a form of hypocrisy 28 A closely related categorization is due to Irving Babbitt who distinguishes misanthropes based on whether they allow exceptions in their negative assessment In this regard misanthropes of the naked intellect regard humanity as a whole as hopeless Tender misanthropes on the other hand exclude a few idealized people from their negative evaluation Babbitt cites Rousseau and his fondness for natural uncivilized man as an example of tender misanthropy and contrasts it with Swift s thorough dismissal of all of humanity 29 30 A further way to categorize forms of misanthropy is in relation to the type of attitude involved toward humanity In this regard Toby Svoboda distinguishes the attitudes of dislike hate contempt and judgment A misanthrope based on dislike harbors a distaste in the form of negative feelings toward other people 10 Misanthropy focusing on hatred involves an intensive form of dislike that includes the additional component of wishing ill upon others and at times of trying to realize this wish 31 In the case of contempt the attitude is not based on feelings and emotions but on a more theoretical outlook It leads misanthropes to see other people as worthless and look down on them while excluding themselves from this assessment 32 If the misanthropic attitude has its foundation in judgment it is also theoretical but does not distinguish between self and others It is the view that humanity is in general bad without implying that the misanthrope is in any way better than the rest 33 According to Svoboda only misanthropy based on judgment constitutes a serious philosophical position Misanthropy focusing on contempt is biased against other people while misanthropy in the form of dislike and hate is difficult to assess since these emotional attitudes often do not respond to objective evidence 34 Misanthropic forms of life Edit Misanthropy is often associated with the tendency to avoid social contacts as portrayed in painting The Misanthrope by Pieter Bruegel the Elder Misanthropes can also be distinguished based on the form of life they use to respond to the misanthropic outlook In this regard misanthropy is usually not restricted to a theoretical opinion but involves an evaluative attitude that calls for a practical response This is realized in different forms of life that come with different dominant emotions and various practical consequences for how to lead one s life 4 35 These responses to misanthropy are sometimes presented through simplified prototypes that may be too crude to accurately capture the mental life of any single person but instead aim to portray common attitudes among groups of misanthropes The two responses most commonly associated with misanthropy involve either destruction or fleeing from society The destructive misanthrope is said to be driven by a hatred of humankind and aims at tearing it down with violence if necessary 4 36 For the fugitive misanthrope fear is the dominant emotion and leads the misanthrope to seek a secluded place in order to avoid the corrupting contact with civilization and humanity as much as possible 4 6 The contemporary misanthropic literature has also identified further less known types of misanthropic lifestyles 4 The activist misanthrope is driven by hope despite their negative appraisal of humanity This hope is a form of meliorism based on the idea that it is possible and feasible for humanity to transform itself and the activist tries to realize this ideal 4 37 A weaker version of this approach is to try to improve the world incrementally to avoid some of the worst outcomes without the hope of fully solving the fundamental problem 38 The quietist misanthrope on the other hand takes a pessimistic approach toward what the individual can do for bringing about a transformation or significant improvements In contrast to the more drastic reactions of the other responses mentioned they resign themselves to quiet acceptance and small scale avoidance 39 4 A further approach is focused on humor based on mockery and ridicule at the absurdity of the human condition for example because humans hurt each other and risk future self destruction for trivial concerns like a marginal increase in profit This way humor can act both as a mirror to portray the terrible truth of the situation and as its palliative at the same time 40 Forms of human flaws EditA core aspect of misanthropy is that its negative attitude toward humanity is based on human flaws 41 4 Various misanthropes have provided extensive lists of flaws including cruelty greed selfishness wastefulness dogmatism self deception and insensitivity to beauty 42 43 4 These flaws can be categorized in many ways It is often held that moral flaws constitute the most serious case 19 44 Other flaws discussed in the contemporary literature include intellectual flaws aesthetic flaws and spiritual flaws 45 19 Moral flaws of human beings are exemplified in harm done to humans by other humans like the mass killings during the Holocaust Moral flaws are often identified with tendencies to promote what is bad or with inappropriate attitudes toward values 46 47 They include cruelty indifference to the suffering of others selfishness moral laziness cowardice injustice greed and ingratitude The harm done because of these flaws can be divided into three categories harm done directly to humans harm done directly to other animals and harm done indirectly to both humans and animals by harming the environment Examples of these categories include the Holocaust factory farming of livestock and pollution causing climate change 48 19 49 In this regard it is not just relevant that human beings cause these forms of harm but also that they are morally responsible for them This is based on the idea that they can understand the consequences of their actions and could act differently However they decide not to for example because they ignore the long term well being of others in order to get short term personal benefits 50 Intellectual flaws concern cognitive capacities They can be defined as what leads to false beliefs what obstructs knowledge or what violates the demands of rationality They include intellectual vices like arrogance wishful thinking dogmatism stupidity and gullibility as well as cognitive biases like the confirmation bias the self serving bias the hindsight bias and the anchoring bias 51 52 46 Intellectual flaws can work in tandem with all kinds of vices they may deceive someone about having a certain vice and thereby prevent them from addressing it and improving themself for example by being mindless and failing to recognize their flaws They also include forms of self deceit wilful ignorance and being in denial about something 53 54 Similar considerations have prompted some traditions to see intellectual failings like ignorance as the root of all evil 55 56 57 Aesthetic flaws are usually not given the same importance as moral and intellectual flaws but they also carry some weight for misanthropic considerations These flaws relate to beauty and ugliness They concern ugly aspects of human life itself like defecation and aging ugliness caused by human activities like pollution and litter and inappropriate attitudes toward aesthetic aspects like being insensitive to beauty 58 59 19 Psychological and social causes EditVarious psychological and social factors have been identified in the academic literature as possible causes of misanthropic sentiments The individual factors by themselves may not be able to fully explain misanthropy but can show instead how it becomes more likely 24 For example it is often argued that undergoing disappointments and disillusionments in life increases the tendency to adopt a misanthropic outlook 60 61 In this regard the more idealistic and optimistic the person initially was the stronger this reversal and the following negative outlook tend to be 60 This type of psychological explanation is already found in Plato s Phaedo In it Socrates explains that misanthropy arises when a person trusts and admires someone without knowing them sufficiently well If it is then discovered later that the admired person has serious flaws the initial attitude may be reversed and universalized to apply to all others This leads to general distrust and contempt toward other humans It becomes more likely if the admired person is a close friend and if it happens more than once 62 63 This form of misanthropy may be accompanied by a feeling of moral superiority in which the misanthrope considers themselves to be better than everyone else 60 Other types of negative personal experiences in life may have a similar effect Andrew Gibson uses this line of thought to explain why some philosophers became misanthropes In the case of Thomas Hobbes he discusses the politically unstable environment and the frequent wars which Hobbes had to live through For Arthur Schopenhauer he cites the fact that Schopenhauer was forced to flee from his home at the age of five and never found a place to call home afterward 24 64 Another psychological factor is associated with negative attitudes toward the human body especially in the form of general revulsion from sexuality 65 24 Besides the psychological causes some wider social circumstances may also play a role Generally speaking the more negative the circumstances are the more likely misanthropy becomes 66 24 For example it has been argued that socio economic inequality in the form of unfair distribution of wealth increases the tendency to adopt a misanthropic perspective This has to do with the fact that inequality tends to undermine trust in the government and others It may be possible to overcome or reduce this source of misanthropy by implementing policies that build trust and promote a more equal distribution of wealth 24 67 The political regime is another relevant factor This specifically concerns authoritarian regimes using all means available to repress their population and stay in power 68 69 For example it has been argued that the severe forms of repression of the Ancien Regime in the late 17th century made it more likely for people to adopt a misanthropic outlook because their freedom was denied 24 70 Democracy on the other hand may have the opposite effect since it allows more personal freedom due to its more optimistic outlook on human nature 68 69 Empirical studies often use questions related to trust in other people to measure misanthropy This concerns specifically whether the individual believes that others would be fair and helpful 71 72 In an empirical study on misanthropy in American society Tom W Smith concludes that factors associated with an increased misanthropic outlook are low socioeconomic status being from racial and ethnic minorities and having experienced recent negative events in one s life In regard to religion misanthropy is higher for people who do not attend church and for fundamentalists Certain factors seem to play no significant role like gender having undergone a divorce and never having been married 71 Another study by Morris Rosenberg finds that misanthropy is associated with certain political outlooks like being skeptical about free speech and a tendency to support authoritarian policies for example to suppress certain political and religious liberties However there seems to be no clear link to many of the broader political outlooks like being a Democrat rather than a Republican or being a liberal rather than a conservative 71 72 Arguments for and against EditVarious discussions in the academic literature concern the question of whether misanthropy is an accurate assessment of humanity and what the consequences of adopting it are Many proponents of misanthropy focus on the different forms of human flaws together with examples of when they exercise their negative influences They argue that these flaws are so severe that misanthropy is an appropriate response 73 Special importance in this regard is usually given to moral faults 74 75 4 This is based on the idea that humans do not merely cause a great deal of suffering and destruction but are also morally responsible for them The reason is that they are intelligent enough to understand the consequences of their actions and could potentially make balanced long term decisions instead of focusing on personal short term gains 50 Opponents of misanthropy often respond to the different examples by claiming that they are extreme individual manifestations of human flaws either by mentally ill perpetrators or by normal people under extreme circumstances In this regard the negative cases do not reflect on humanity at large and therefore are unable to justify the misanthropic attitude So while there are cases of extreme human brutality like the mass killings committed by dictators and their forces listing such cases is not sufficient for condemning humanity at large 4 76 Misanthropes have responded to this type of argument in various ways Some hold that the underlying flaws are there in everyone even if they reach their most extreme manifestation only in a few 4 Others claim that many ordinary people are complicit in their manifestation for example by supporting the political leaders committing them even if they did not directly commit them 77 Another approach is to focus not on the grand extreme cases but on the ordinary small scale manifestations of human flaws in everyday life such as lying cheating breaking promises and being ungrateful 78 79 A closely related defense of misanthropy is based on the actual damage caused by humans in the past 49 80 81 In this regard Svoboda presents a thought experiment involving the discovery of a fully established ecosystem on another planet This ecosystem is in harmony except for a single species that dominates it and causes one ecological catastrophe after another resulting in mass extinctions of other species Svoboda argues that having a negative attitude toward this species is the appropriate response and that this case accurately reflects the role of human beings on Earth 82 An objection to this line of thought is that the negative assessment should not be directed at humanity but at certain social forces like capitalism fascism religious fundamentalism or imperialism which are seen as the main cause of many tragedies 83 On this view the proper attitude would be anti capitalism or a similar outlook but not misanthropy Svoboda rejects this argument by claiming that these forces do not have a life of their own but depend on human beings to manifest them In this regard these forces are just different ways in which the negative value of humanity is enacted 84 Misanthropes often focus on the harm done by humans to animals on a large scale as in factory farming A different problem for arguments based on human flaws is that they present just one side of humanity while evaluative attitudes should take all sides into account So it may be the case that despite having very serious vices humans may also possess equally important virtues that make up for their shortcomings 85 For example accounts that focus only on the great wars cruelties and tragedies in human history ignore its positive achievements in the sciences arts and humanities And the focus on negative exemplars like Stalin or Hitler should be contrasted with positive exemplars like Mother Teresa or Gandhi 86 While it is difficult to make such comparisons on a large scale misanthropes have argued that at least for important subfields like man s treatment of animals the scales are tipped against man 87 88 Misanthropes often argue that positive achievements are rare exceptions while negative consequences are much more widespread 89 Another argument favoring misanthropy sometimes referred to as the asymmetry thesis holds that morally bad actions carry more weight on an ethical level than their good counterparts In this regard a person cannot simply make up for the cold murders they committed by saving a few lives 90 Some objections to misanthropy are based not on whether this attitude appropriately reflects the negative value of humanity but on the costs of accepting such a position for the individual and for society at large This is especially relevant if misanthropy is associated with hatred which may turn easily into violence against social institutions and other humans and may result in a lot of harm 91 Misanthropy may also deprive the individual of most pleasures by making them miserable and friendless 92 Defenders have argued that misanthropy is not necessarily connected to hatred violence and friendlessness So these criticisms may be valid for forms of misanthropy focused on hatred and destruction but miss their target for other forms based on a peaceful and theoretical outlook 93 4 6 A closely related criticism holds that misanthropy is morally objectable 93 This argument may be valid for many individual misanthropes but it has been argued that misanthropy is not necessarily in conflict with obeying the demands of morality An example of this would be Kant s cold hearted benefactor who fulfills all their moral requirements toward other people despite lacking real sympathy 94 95 Another form of criticism focuses more on the theoretical level and claims that misanthropy is an inconsistent and self contradictory position that amounts at best to a proto philosophy or sub philosophy 96 24 This inconsistency shows itself for example in the misanthrope s tendency to denounce the social world while still being engaged in it and being unable to fully leave it behind 97 This criticism applies specifically to misanthropes who exclude themselves from the negative evaluation and look down on others with contempt from an arrogant position of inflated ego But it may not apply to all types of misanthropy 28 98 26 A closely related objection is based on the claim that misanthropy is an unnatural attitude and should therefore be seen as an aberration or a pathological case 99 In various disciplines EditPhilosophy Edit Misanthropy has been discussed and exemplified by philosophers throughout history One of the earliest cases was the pre Socratic philosopher Heraclitus He is often characterized as a loner who had little patience for human society A central factor to his negative outlook on human beings was their lack of comprehension of the true nature of reality This concerns especially cases in which they remain in a state of ignorance despite having received a thorough explanation of the issue in question 100 101 102 Another early discussion is found in Plato s Phaedo where misanthropy is characterized as the result of frustrated expectations and excessively naive optimism 103 62 63 The cynic philosopher Diogenes had a very negative image of the people around him and cared little for social conventions For example he used to walk around with a lamp in full daylight in his unsuccessful attempt to find an honest or worthy man 104 105 Various strands of misanthropy are also found in the cynic school of philosophy There it is argued for example that humans keep on reproducing and multiplying the evils they are attempting to flee For example they move to cities to defend themselves against outsiders But this process thwarts their initial goal by leading to even more violence due to high crime rates within the city Diogenes is a well known cynic misanthrope He saw other people as hypocritical and superficial He openly rejected all kinds of societal norms and values often provoking others by consciously breaking conventions and behaving rudely 106 24 107 Thomas Hobbes is an example of misanthropy in early modern philosophy His negative outlook on humanity is reflected in many of his works For him humans are egoistic and violent they act according to their self interest and are willing to pursue their goals at the expense of others In their natural state this leads to a never ending war in which every man to every man is an enemy He saw the establishment of an authoritative state characterized by the strict enforcement of laws to maintain order as the only way to tame the violent human nature and avoid perpetual war 108 109 110 A different type of misanthropy is found in Jean Jacques Rousseau He idealizes the harmony and simplicity found in nature and contrasts them with the confusion and disorder found in humanity especially in the form of society and institutions 111 112 113 For example in a famous statement he claims that Man is born free and everywhere he is in chains 114 115 This negative outlook was also reflected in his lifestyle he lived solitary and preferred to be with plants rather than humans 116 Arthur Schopenhauer is often mentioned as a prime example of misanthropy 117 118 According to him everything in the world including humans and their activities is an expression of one underlying will However this will is blind which causes it to continuously engage in futile struggles On the level of human life this presents itself as a continual deception since it is driven by pointless desires They are mostly egoistic and often result in injustice and suffering to others Once they are satisfied they only give rise to new pointless desires and more suffering 119 120 121 In this regard Schopenhauer dismisses most things that are typically considered precious or meaningful in human life like romantic love individuality and liberty 122 He holds that the best response to the human condition is a form of asceticism by denying the expression of the will However this is only found in very rare humans and the dull majority of men does not live up to this ideal 123 Friedrich Nietzsche who was strongly influenced by Schopenhauer is also often cited as an example of misanthropy He saw man as a decadent and sick animal that constitutes no progress over other animals 124 125 126 He even had a negative image of apes since they are more similar to human beings than other animals for example in regard to cruelty 127 For Nietzsche a noteworthy flaw of human beings is their tendency to create and enforce systems of moral rules that favor weak people and suppress true greatness 125 128 He held that the human being is something to be overcome and replaced by what he calls the Ubermensch 129 130 Religion Edit Focus on the sinful nature of human beings is one form of misanthropy as in the Christian doctrine of original sin tainting every human being Some misanthropic views are also found in religious teachings In Christianity for example this is associated with the sinful nature of humans and the widespread manifestation of sin in everyday life 131 Common forms of sin are discussed in terms of the seven deadly sins such as an excessive sense of self importance in the form of pride strong sexual cravings constituting lust and following greed for material possessions as well as being envious of the possessions of others 132 According to the doctrine of original sin this flaw is found in every human being since human nature is already tainted by sin from birth by inheriting it from Adam and Eve s rebellion against God s authority 131 133 Misanthropic perspectives can also be discerned in various Buddhist teachings For example Buddha had a very negative outlook on the widespread flaws of human beings including lust hatred delusion sorrow and despair 134 These flaws are identified with some form of craving or attachment taṇha and cause suffering dukkha 135 136 Buddhists hold that it is possible to overcome these failings in the process of achieving Buddhahood or enlightenment However this is seen as an extremely difficult and rare achievement In this regard most human beings carry these deep flaws with them throughout their life 137 However there are also many religious teachings opposed to misanthropy such as the emphasis on kindness and helping others In Christianity this is found in the concept of agape which involves selfless and unconditional love in the form of compassion and a willingness to help others 138 Buddhists see the practice of loving kindness metta as a central aspect that implies a positive attitude of compassion toward humans and all other sentient beings 139 140 Literature and popular culture Edit Many examples of misanthropy are also found in literature and popular culture Timon of Athens by William Shakespeare is a famous portrayal of the life of the Ancient Greek Timon who is widely known for his extreme misanthropic attitude Shakespeare depicts him as a wealthy and generous gentleman However he becomes disillusioned with his ungrateful friends and humanity at large This way his initial philanthropy turns into an unrestrained hatred of humanity which prompts him to leave society in order to live in a forest 141 142 Moliere s play The Misanthrope is another famous example Its protagonist Alceste has a very low opinion of the people around him He tends to focus on their flaws and openly criticizes them for their superficiality insincerity and hypocrisy He rejects most social conventions and thereby often offends others for example by refusing to engage in social niceties like polite small talk 143 144 145 Jonathan Swift is well known for his often explicit pronouncements of misanthropy The author Jonathan Swift had a reputation for being misanthropic In some statements he openly declares that he hates and detests that animal called man 146 Misanthropy is also found in many of his works For example Gulliver s Travels tells the adventures of the protagonist Gulliver who journeys to various places like an island inhabited by tiny people and a land ruled by intelligent horses Through these experiences of the contrast between humans and other species he comes to see more and more the deep flaws of humanity leading him to develop a revulsion toward other human beings 147 148 Ebenezer Scrooge from Charles Dickens s A Christmas Carol is an often cited example of misanthropy He is described as a cold hearted solitary miser who detests Christmas He is greedy selfish and has no regard for the well being of others 149 150 151 Other writers associated with misanthropy include Gustave Flaubert and Philip Larkin 152 153 Mr Burns from the TV show The Simpsons is a more recent example of misanthropy He is one of the main antagonists and his main desire is to increase his already enormous wealth and power He is ruthless in pursuing this goal and has no regard for the safety and well being of others in the process 154 155 156 An even darker form of misanthropy is found in the character the Joker from the DC Universe He is one of the main antagonists of Batman and acts as an agent of chaos He believes that people are selfish cruel irrational and hypocritical He is usually portrayed as a sociopath with a twisted sense of humor who uses violent means to expose and bring down organized society 157 158 159 Related concepts EditPhilosophical pessimism Edit Misanthropy is closely related to but not identical with philosophical pessimism Philosophical pessimism is the view that life as a whole is not worth living or that the world in general is a bad place for example because it is meaningless and full of suffering 160 161 This view is perhaps best exemplified by Arthur Schopenhauer or in its most extreme form Philipp Mainlander 162 Philosophical pessimism is often accompanied by misanthropy by holding that humanity is also bad and maybe partially responsible for the badness of the world But the two views do not entail each other and can be held separately 4 163 A non misanthropic pessimist may hold for example that humans are just victims of a terrible world but not to blame for it Eco misanthropists on the other hand may claim that the world and its nature are valuable but for the negative destructive influence of humanity 4 164 Antinatalism and human extinction Edit Humanity is a moral disaster There would have been much less destruction had we never evolved The fewer humans there are in the future the less destruction there will still be David Benatar The Misanthropic Argument for Anti natalism 75 Antinatalism is the view that coming into existence is bad and that humans therefore have a duty to abstain from procreation 165 166 A central argument for antinatalism is the so called misanthropic argument It sees the deep flaws of humans and their tendency to cause harm as a reason for avoiding to create more humans 167 168 These harms include wars genocides factory farming and damages done to the environment 169 This argument contrasts with philanthropic arguments which focus on the future suffering of the human about to come into existence They argue that the only way to avoid their future suffering is to prevent them from being born 167 168 38 The Voluntary Human Extinction Movement and the Church of Euthanasia are well known examples of social movements in favor of antinatalism and human extinction 170 171 Some misanthropes hope for the extinction of the human species which could happen for example due to a worldwide nuclear war Antinatalism is commonly endorsed by misanthropic thinkers 38 But there are also many other ways that could lead to the extinction of the human species This field is still relatively speculative but various suggestions have been made about threats to the long term survival of the human species An often discussed scenario involves the outbreak of a worldwide nuclear war leaving Earth uninhabitable Another threat is posed by advances in nano technology which may at some point lead to the development of self replicating nanorobots that could get out of control In the field of medicine scientific advances could be used to create a deadly super pathogen that could spread rapidly 172 173 174 While such cases are usually seen as terrible scenarios and dangerous threats misanthropes may instead interpret them as reasons for hope that the abhorrent age of humanity in history may soon come to an end 175 A similar sentiment is expressed by Bertrand Russell who states in relation to the existence of human life on earth and its misdeeds that they are a passing nightmare in time the earth will become again incapable of supporting life and peace will return 176 Human exceptionalism and deep ecology Edit Human exceptionalism is the claim that human beings have unique importance and are exceptional compared to all other species It is often based on the claim that they stand out because of their special capacities like intelligence rationality and autonomy 177 In religious contexts it is frequently explained in relation to a unique role that God foresaw for them or that they were created in God s image 178 Human exceptionalism is usually combined with the claim that human well being matters more than the well being of other species This line of thought can be used to draw various ethical conclusions for example that humans have the right to rule the planet and impose their will on other species or that inflicting harm on other species may be morally acceptable if it is done with the purpose of promoting human well being and excellence 177 179 Generally speaking the position of human exceptionalism is at odds with misanthropy since their outlooks on the value of humanity are in many ways diametrically opposed 179 Nonetheless it has been argued that this is not necessarily the case and it is possible to hold both positions at the same time One way to do this is to claim that humanity is exceptional mainly due to a few rare individuals while maintaining a negative perspective toward the average person 180 Another approach is to turn human exceptionalism on its head by claiming that human beings are exceptional in a negative sense i e that given their destructive and harmful history they are much worse than any other species 179 Theorists in the field of deep ecology are also often critical of human exceptionalism and tend to favor a misanthropic perspective 181 182 Deep ecology is a philosophical and social movement that emphasizes the inherent value of nature and advocates a radical change in human behavior toward nature 183 Various theorists have criticized deep ecology based on the claim that it is misanthropic by privileging other species over humans 182 For example the deep ecology movement Earth First has faced severe criticism when they praised the AIDS epidemic in Africa as a solution to the problem of human overpopulation in their newsletter 184 185 See also EditAsociality lack of motivation to engage in social interaction Antisocial disregard for and violation of the rights of others Antihumanism rejection of humanism Cosmicism Emotional isolation Hatred video game Machiavellianism psychology Nihilism Social alienationReferences Edit misanthropy www etymonline com Retrieved 21 July 2021 Definition of Misanthropy www merriam webster com Retrieved 5 July 2021 Company Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing The American Heritage Dictionary entry misanthropy www ahdictionary com Retrieved 5 July 2021 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q Kidd Ian James 2020 Philosophical Misanthropy philosophynow org 139 a b Cooper 2018 p 7 a b c d e Edyvane Derek 2013 Rejecting Society Misanthropy Friendship and Montaigne Res Publica 19 1 53 65 doi 10 1007 s11158 012 9206 2 S2CID 144666876 The American Heritage Dictionary entry philanthropy www ahdictionary com HarperCollins Lim Song Hwee 31 August 2006 Celluloid Comrades Representations of Male Homosexuality in Contemporary Chinese Cinemas University of Hawaii Press p 167 ISBN 9780824830779 Sawaya Francesca 15 July 2014 The Difficult Art of Giving Patronage Philanthropy and the American Literary Market University of Pennsylvania Press p 207 ISBN 9780812290035 a b Svoboda 2022 p 6 7 a b Cooper 2018 p 54 6 Benatar 2015 p 38 41 Gibson 2017 p 190 Gilmore David D 3 August 2010 Misogyny The Male Malady University of Pennsylvania Press p 12 ISBN 9780812200324 Gibson 2017 p 145 a b Kidd Ian James Review of David E Cooper Animals and Misanthropy Routledge 2018 Philosophy Harris 2022 p 118 Cooper 2018 p 7 13 54 8 a b c d e Kidd Ian James 16 February 2022 4 Misanthropy and the Hatred of Humanity In Birondo Noell ed The Moral Psychology of Hate Rowman amp Littlefield pp 75 99 ISBN 9781538160862 a b Tsakalakis Thomas 15 October 2020 Political Correctness A Sociocultural Black Hole Routledge p 144 ISBN 9781000205084 a b Harris 2022 p 21 Svoboda 2022 p 6 9 Svoboda 2022 p 6 9 29 a b c d e f g h i Querido Pedro February 2020 Andrew Gibson Misanthropy The Critique of Humanity Comparative Critical Studies 17 1 152 7 doi 10 3366 ccs 2020 0349 ISSN 1744 1854 Wilford Paul T Stoner Samuel A 4 June 2021 Kant and the Possibility of Progress From Modern Hopes to Postmodern Anxieties University of Pennsylvania Press pp 42 3 ISBN 9780812297799 a b Svoboda 2022 p 8 Harris 2022 p 22 a b Harris 2022 p 20 2 King 1993 p 57 8 Babbitt Irving 2015 Chapter VII Romantic Irony Rousseau and Romanticism Project Gutenberg Svoboda 2022 p 7 Svoboda 2022 p 7 8 Svoboda 2022 p 8 9 Svoboda 2022 p 8 9 40 Cooper 2018 p 110 1 Cooper 2018 p 115 6 Svoboda 2022 p 14 115 a b c Svoboda 2022 p 14 Cooper 2018 p 118 9 Svoboda 2022 p 117 8 Cooper 2018 p 7 47 8 Cooper 2018 p 3 8 48 Benatar 2015 p 39 42 Benatar 2015 p 34 6 55 Cooper 2018 p 7 13 48 a b Hurka Thomas 2020 Virtues and vices Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge Hurka Thomas 2001 Vices as Higher Level Evils Utilitas 13 2 195 212 doi 10 1017 s0953820800003137 S2CID 145225191 Benatar 2015 p 39 48 a b Svoboda 2022 p 4 5 a b Svoboda 2022 p 3 5 Madison B J C 2017 On the Nature of Intellectual Vice Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6 12 1 6 Litvak P Lerner J S 2009 cognitive bias In Sander David Scherer Klaus eds The Oxford companion to emotion and the affective sciences Oxford Oxford University Press pp 89 90 ISBN 9780198569633 Cooper 2018 p 50 1 Svoboda 2022 p 18 Hackforth R 1946 Moral Evil and Ignorance in Plato s Ethics Classical Quarterly 40 3 4 118 doi 10 1017 S0009838800023442 S2CID 145412342 Menon Sangeetha Vedanta Advaita Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 3 July 2021 Mahathera Nyanatiloka 1964 II Kamma and Rebirth Karma and Rebirth Buddhist Publication Society Benatar 2015 p 56 8 Cooper 2018 p 7 48 a b c Harris 2022 p 195 Chambers Robert 1847 Essays moral and economic W amp R Chambers p 191 a b Shakespeare William 3 April 2001 Timon of Athens Cambridge University Press p 208 ISBN 9781139835114 a b White David A 1989 Myth and Metaphysics in Plato s Phaedo Susquehanna University Press p 134 ISBN 9780945636014 Gibson 2017 p 98 9 107 8 Gibson 2017 p 13 119 207 Gibson 2017 p 119 Hooghe M Stolle D 15 May 2003 Generating Social Capital Civil Society and Institutions in Comparative Perspective Springer p 185 ISBN 9781403979544 a b Gibson 2017 p 13 62 207 a b Tsakalakis Thomas 15 October 2020 Political Correctness A Sociocultural Black Hole Routledge p 142 ISBN 9781000205084 Gibson 2017 p 61 207 a b c Smith Tom W June 1997 Factors Relating to Misanthropy in Contemporary American Society Social Science Research 26 2 170 196 doi 10 1006 ssre 1997 0592 a b Rosenberg Morris December 1956 Misanthropy and Political Ideology American Sociological Review 21 6 690 doi 10 2307 2088419 Cooper 2018 p 4 7 54Benatar 2015 p 55Querido Pedro February 2020 Andrew Gibson Misanthropy The Critique of Humanity Comparative Critical Studies 17 1 152 7 doi 10 3366 ccs 2020 0349 ISSN 1744 1854 Gibson 2017 p 13 Svoboda 2022 p 3 13 a b Benatar 2015 p 55 Benatar 2015 p 39 41 Benatar 2015 p 37 41 2 Benatar 2015 p 43 Kidd Ian James 2020 Humankind Human Nature and Misanthropy Metascience 29 3 505 508 doi 10 1007 s11016 020 00562 8 S2CID 225274682 Cooper 2018 p 80 Benatar 2015 p 38 9 Svoboda 2022 p 1 5 Svoboda 2022 p 13 69 Svoboda 2022 p 69 70 Benatar 2015 p 51 52 Gibson 2017 p 64 Benatar 2015 p 52 Cooper 2018 p 77 8 Svoboda 2022 p 5 Svoboda 2022 p 13 McGraw Shannon 2014 1 Introduction Misanthropy and Criminal Behavior PDF pp 1 2 Archived PDF from the original on 2021 07 09 Shklar Judith N 1984 5 Misanthropy Ordinary Vices Belknap Press of Harvard University Press p 192 a b Svoboda 2022 p 12 29 Svoboda 2022 p 29 Stohr Karen E 2002 Virtue Ethics and Kant s Cold Hearted Benefactor The Journal of Value Inquiry 36 2 3 187 204 doi 10 1023 A 1016192117676 Gibson 2017 p 4 5 Gibson 2017 p 4 60 Gibson 2017 p 63 Gibson 2017 p 65 Moyal Georges J D 1989 On Heraclitus s Misanthropy Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 7 2 131 148 ISSN 0771 5420 Mark Joshua J 2010 07 14 Heraclitus of Ephesus World History Encyclopedia Retrieved 2017 12 08 Ava Chitwood 2004 Death by philosophy the biographical tradition in the life and death of the archaic philosophers Empedocles Heraclitus and Democritus Ann Arbor University of Michigan Press p 80 ISBN 0472113887 OCLC 54988783 Stern Paul 1993 Socratic Rationalism and Political Philosophy An Interpretation of Plato s Phaedo SUNY Press p 95 ISBN 9780791415733 Yeroulanos Marinos 30 June 2016 A Dictionary of Classical Greek Quotations Bloomsbury Publishing p 203 ISBN 9781786730497 Navia Luis E 1996 Classical Cynicism A Critical Study Greenwood Publishing Group ISBN 9780313300158 Gibson 2017 p 14 6 Arruzza Cinzia Nikulin Dmitri 21 November 2016 Philosophy and Political Power in Antiquity Brill p 119 ISBN 9789004324626 Gibson 2017 p 93 95 98 Williams Garrath Hobbes Thomas Moral and Political Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 8 January 2023 Byrne James M 1 January 1997 Religion and the Enlightenment From Descartes to Kant Westminster John Knox Press p 112 ISBN 9780664257606 Gibson 2017 p 110 1 Cooper 2018 p 19 King 1993 p 58 9 Gibson 2017 p 112 Williams David Lay 1 November 2010 Rousseau s Platonic Enlightenment Penn State Press p 147 ISBN 9780271045511 Gibson 2017 p 111 Svoboda 2022 p 12 15 Gibson 2017 p 101 Gibson 2017 p 101 3 Svoboda 2022 p 15 6 Troxell Mary Schopenhauer Arthur Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 8 January 2023 Gibson 2017 p 104 5 Gibson 2017 p 105 6 Cooper 2018 p 2 a b Villa Dana 1 September 2020 Socratic Citizenship Princeton University Press p 127 ISBN 9780691218175 Wilkerson Dale Nietzsche Friedrich 1 Life Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 8 January 2023 Cooper 2018 p 62 Solomon Robert C 26 August 2004 In Defense of Sentimentality Oxford University Press p 67 ISBN 9780198033288 Shaw George Bernard 2021 Man and Superman John Bull s Other Island and Major Barbara Oxford University Press p xxxii ISBN 9780198828853 Grillaert Nel 2008 What the God seekers Found in Nietzsche The Reception of Neitzche s Ubermensch by the Philosophers of the Russian Religious Renaissance Rodopi p 245 ISBN 9789042024809 a b Gibson 2017 p 28 9 Kastenbaum Robert 2003 Seven Deadly Sins Encyclopedia of Death and Dying New York Macmillan Reference USA ISBN 9780028656908 Hale Tom Thorson Stephen 2007 The Applied Old Testament Commentary David C Cook p 46 ISBN 9780781448642 Cooper 2018 p 4 Cooper 2018 p 6 7 Morgan Diane 2010 Essential Buddhism A Comprehensive Guide to Belief and Practice ABC CLIO p 91 ISBN 9780313384523 Cooper 2018 p 56 Catholic University of America 1967 Agape New Catholic Encyclopedia McGraw Hill ISBN 9780787639990 Aung SK April 1996 Loving kindness the essential Buddhist contribution to primary care Humane health care international 12 2 PMID 14986605 Morgan Diane 2010 Essential Buddhism A Comprehensive Guide to Belief and Practice ABC CLIO p 138 ISBN 9780313384523 Harris 2022 p 27 30 Gibson 2017 p 1 2 Gibson 2017 p 2 4 Harris 2022 p 58 Hawcroft Michael 27 September 2007 Moliere Reasoning With Fools Oxford University Press p 132 ISBN 9780191527937 Gibson 2017 p 14 Gibson 2017 p 84 5 Jan K M Firdaus Shabnam 2004 Perspectives on Gulliver s Travels Atlantic Publishers amp Dist p 115 ISBN 9788126903450 Moore Grace 2011 A Christmas Carol Insight Text Guides Insight Publications p 16 ISBN 9781921411915 Pirson Michael 14 September 2017 Humanistic Management Protecting Dignity and Promoting Well Being Cambridge University Press p 58 ISBN 9781107160729 Cornog Mary W 1998 Merriam Webster s Vocabulary Builder Merriam Webster p 357 ISBN 9780877799108 The Letters of Gustave Flaubert 1857 1880 Harvard University Press 1982 p xiv ISBN 0674526406 Raban Jonathan October 17 1992 Books Mr Miseryguts Philip Larkin s letters show all the grim humor that was a hallmark of his great poems but as the years pass they also chart the true depths of his misanthropy and despair The Independent Archived from the original on 2022 05 15 Retrieved June 18 2017 Goertz Allie Prescott Julia Oakley Bill Weinstein Josh 18 September 2018 100 Things The Simpsons Fans Should Know amp Do Before They Die in Arabic Triumph Books p 72 ISBN 9781641251099 Fink Moritz 19 June 2019 The Simpsons A Cultural History Rowman amp Littlefield p 82 ISBN 9781538116173 Brown Alan S Logan Chris 22 June 2009 The Psychology of the Simpsons D oh BenBella Books Inc p 229 ISBN 9781935251392 Lee Judith Yaross Bird John 16 November 2020 Seeing MAD Essays on MAD Magazine s Humor and Legacy University of Missouri Press p 164 ISBN 9780826274489 Donohoo Timothy 6 January 2023 The Joker Has a Morbidly Hilarious Reason For Not Killing Red Hood CBR Bolus Michael Peter 26 August 2019 Aesthetics and the Cinematic Narrative An Introduction Anthem Press p 24 ISBN 9781783089826 Smith Cameron 2014 Introduction Philosophical Pessimism A Study In The Philosophy Of Arthur Schopenhauer pp 1 3 Jenkins Scott 2020 The Pessimistic Origin of Nietzsche s Thought of Eternal Recurrence Inquiry An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 63 1 20 41 doi 10 1080 0020174x 2019 1669976 S2CID 211969776 Fernandez Jordi 2006 Schopenhauer s Pessimism Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 3 646 664 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2006 tb00552 x Cooper 2018 p 5 6 Gerber Lisa 2002 What is So Bad About Misanthropy Environmental Ethics 24 1 41 55 doi 10 5840 enviroethics200224140 Metz Thaddeus 2012 Contemporary Anti Natalism Featuring Benatar s Better Never to Have Been South African Journal of Philosophy 31 1 1 9 doi 10 1080 02580136 2012 10751763 S2CID 143091736 Benatar 2015 p 34 5 a b Benatar 2015 p 55 6 a b Benatar David 15 July 2015a We Are Creatures That Should Not Exist The Theory Of Anti Natalism The Critique Retrieved 4 July 2021 May Todd December 17 2018 Would Human Extinction Be a Tragedy The New York Times Human beings are destroying large parts of the inhabitable earth and causing unimaginable suffering to many of the animals that inhabit it This is happening through at least three means First human contribution to climate change is devastating ecosystems Second the increasing human population is encroaching on ecosystems that would otherwise be intact Third factory farming fosters the creation of millions upon millions of animals for whom it offers nothing but suffering and misery before slaughtering them in often barbaric ways There is no reason to think that those practices are going to diminish any time soon Quite the opposite Stibbe Arran 1 May 2015 Ecolinguistics Language Ecology and the Stories We Live By Routledge p 13 ISBN 9781317511908 MacCormack Patricia 2020 The Ahuman Manifesto Activism for the End of the Anthropocene Bloomsbury Academic p 143 ISBN 978 1350081093 Bostrom Nick 2003 Extinction Human In Demeny Paul George McNicoll Geoffrey eds Encyclopedia of Population Macmillan Reference USA ISBN 9780028656779 Leslie John 1998 The end of the world the science and ethics of human extinction New York Routledge pp 25 6 ISBN 0203007727 Gordijn Bert Cutter Anthony Mark 30 September 2013 In Pursuit of Nanoethics Springer Science amp Business Media p 123 ISBN 9781402068171 Svoboda 2022 p 107 Svoboda 2022 p 107 8 a b Srinivasan Krithika Kasturirangan Rajesh October 2016 Political ecology development and human exceptionalism Geoforum 75 126 7 doi 10 1016 j geoforum 2016 07 011 Durst Dennis L 2022 The Perils of Human Exceptionalism Elements of a Nineteenth Century Theological Anthropology Rowman amp Littlefield p 1 ISBN 9781666900194 a b c Svoboda 2022 p 9 Gibson 2017 p 64 5 Malone Karen Truong Son Gray Tonia 17 January 2017 Reimagining Sustainability in Precarious Times Springer ISBN 9789811025501 a b Sale Kirkpatrick 14 May 1988 Deep Ecology And Its Critics PDF The Nation Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 06 Ball Terence June 2011 Blanchfield Deirdre S ed Environmental Encyclopedia Gale Cengage Learning ISBN 9781414487366 Hay P R 2002 Main currents in western environmental thought Bloomington Indiana University Press p 66 ISBN 0253340535 Taylor Bron 2005 Jones Lindsay ed Encyclopedia of Religion Macmillan Reference USA ISBN 9780028657349 Works cited Edit Benatar David 2015 The Misanthropic Argument for Anti natalism In S Hannan S Brennan R Vernon eds Permissible Progeny The Morality of Procreation and Parenting Oxford University Press pp 34 64 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199378111 003 0002 ISBN 9780199378142 Cooper David E 2 February 2018 Animals and Misanthropy Routledge ISBN 9781351583770 Gibson Andrew 15 June 2017 Misanthropy The Critique of Humanity Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 9781474293181 Harris Joseph November 2022 Misanthropy in the Age of Reason Oxford University Press ISBN 9780192867575 King Florence 15 March 1993 With Charity Toward None A Fond Look At Misanthropy St Martin s Press ISBN 9780312094140 Svoboda Toby 29 April 2022 A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy Taylor amp Francis Limited ISBN 9781032029986 External links Edit Wikimedia Commons has media related to Misanthropy The dictionary definition of misanthropy at Wiktionary Quotations related to Misanthropy at Wikiquote Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Misanthropy amp oldid 1145647898, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.