fbpx
Wikipedia

R. G. Collingwood

Robin George Collingwood FBA (/ˈkɒlɪŋwʊd/; 22 February 1889 – 9 January 1943) was an English philosopher, historian and archaeologist. He is best known for his philosophical works, including The Principles of Art (1938) and the posthumously published The Idea of History (1946).

R. G. Collingwood

Born
Robin George Collingwood

22 February 1889
Gillhead, Cartmel Fell, Lancashire (now Cumbria), England
Died9 January 1943(1943-01-09) (aged 53)
Coniston, Lancashire, England
Alma materUniversity College, Oxford
Notable workThe Principles of Art (1938)
The Idea of History (1946)
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolBritish idealism
Historism[1]
InstitutionsPembroke College, Oxford
Main interests
Metaphysics
Philosophy of history
Aesthetics
Notable ideas
Historical imagination
Coining the English term historicism[1][2]
Aesthetic expressivism

Biography Edit

Collingwood was born 22 February 1889 in Cartmel, Grange-over-Sands, then in Lancashire (now Cumbria), the son of the artist and archaeologist W.G. Collingwood, who acted as John Ruskin's private secretary in the final years of Ruskin's life. Collingwood's mother was also an artist and a talented pianist. He was educated at Rugby School and University College, Oxford, where he gained a First in Classical Moderations (Greek and Latin) in 1910 and a congratulatory First in Greats (Ancient History and Philosophy) in 1912.[4] Prior to graduation, he was elected a fellow of Pembroke College, Oxford.

Collingwood was a fellow of Pembroke College, Oxford, for some 15 years until becoming the Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy at Magdalen College, Oxford. He was taught by the historian and archaeologist F. J. Haverfield, at the time Camden Professor of Ancient History. Important influences on Collingwood were the Italian Idealists Benedetto Croce, Giovanni Gentile and Guido de Ruggiero, the last of whom was also a close friend. Other important influences were Hegel, Kant, Giambattista Vico, F. H. Bradley and J. A. Smith.

After several years of increasingly debilitating strokes, Collingwood died at Coniston, Lancashire, on 9 January 1943. He was a practising Anglican throughout his life.

Philosopher Edit

Philosophy of history Edit

Collingwood is widely noted for The Idea of History (1946), which was collated from various sources soon after his death by a student, T. M. Knox. It came to be a major inspiration for philosophy of history in the English-speaking world and is extensively cited, leading to an ironic remark by commentator Louis Mink that Collingwood is coming to be "the best known neglected thinker of our time".[5]

Collingwood categorized history as a science, defining a science as "any organized body of knowledge."[6] However, he distinguished history from natural sciences because the concerns of these two branches are different: natural sciences are concerned with the physical world, while history, in its most common usage, is concerned with social sciences and human affairs.[7] Collingwood pointed out a fundamental difference between knowing things in the present (or in the natural sciences) and knowing history. To come to know things in the present or about things in the natural sciences, "real" things can be observed, as they are in existence or that have substance right now.

Since the internal thought processes of historical persons cannot be perceived with the physical senses and past historical events cannot be directly observed, history must be methodologically different from natural sciences. History, being a study of the human mind, is interested in the thoughts and motivations of the actors in history, this insight being encapsulated in his epigram "All history is the history of thought."[8] Therefore, Collingwood suggested that a historian must "reconstruct" history by using "historical imagination" to "re-enact" the thought processes of historical persons based on information and evidence from historical sources. Re-enactment of thought refers to the idea that the historian can access not only a thought process similar to that of the historical actor, but the actual thought process itself. Consider Collingwood's words regarding the study of Plato:

In its immediacy, as an actual experience of his own, Plato's argument must undoubtedly have grown up out of a discussion of some sort, though I do not know what it was, and been closely connected with such a discussion. Yet if I not only read his argument but understand it, follow it in my own mind by re-arguing it with and for myself, the process of argument which I go through is not a process resembling Plato's, it actually is Plato's, so far as I understand him rightly.[9]

In Collingwood's understanding, a thought is a single entity accessible to the public and therefore, regardless of how many people have the same thought, it is still a singular thought. "Thoughts, in other words, are to be distinguished on the basis of purely qualitative criteria, and if there are two people entertaining the (qualitatively) same thought, there is (numerically) only one thought since there is only one propositional content."[10] Therefore, if historians follow the correct line of inquiry in response to a historical source and reason correctly, they can arrive at the same thought the author of their source had and, in so doing, "re-enact" that thought.

Collingwood rejected what he deemed "scissors-and-paste history" in which the historian rejects a statement recorded by their subject either because it contradicts another historical statement or because it contradicts the historian's own understanding of the world. As he states in Principles of History, sometimes a historian will encounter "a story which he simply cannot believe, a story characteristic, perhaps, of the superstitions or prejudices of the author's time or the circle in which he lived, but not credible to a more enlightened age, and therefore to be omitted."[11] This, Collingwood argues, is an unacceptable way to do history. Sources which make claims that do not align with current understandings of the world were still created by rational humans who had reason for creating them. Therefore, these sources are valuable and ought to be investigated further in order to get at the historical context in which they were created and for what reason.

Philosophy of art Edit

The Principles of Art (1938) comprises Collingwood's most developed treatment of aesthetic questions. Collingwood held (following Benedetto Croce) that works of art are essentially expressions of emotion. For Collingwood, an important social role for artists is to clarify and articulate emotions from their community.

Collingwood developed a position later known as aesthetic expressivism (not to be confused with various other views typically called expressivism), a thesis first developed by Croce.[12]

Political philosophy Edit

In politics Collingwood defended the ideals of what he called liberalism "in its Continental sense":

The essence of this conception is ... the idea of a community as governing itself by fostering the free expression of all political opinions that take shape within it, and finding some means of reducing this multiplicity of opinions to a unity.[13]

In his Autobiography, Collingwood confessed that his politics had always been "democratic" and "liberal", and shared Guido de Ruggiero's opinion that socialism had rendered a great service to liberalism by pointing out the shortcomings of laissez-faire economics.[14]

Archaeologist Edit

Collingwood was not just a philosopher of history but also a practising historian and archaeologist. He was, during his time, a leading authority on Roman Britain: he spent his term time at Oxford teaching philosophy but devoted his long vacations to archaeology.

He began work along Hadrian's Wall. The family home was at Coniston in the Lake District and his father was a leading figure in the Cumberland and Westmorland Archaeological Society. Collingwood was drawn in on a number of excavations and put forward the theory that Hadrian's Wall was not so much a fighting platform but an elevated sentry walk.[15] He also put forward the suggestion that Hadrian's defensive system also included a number of forts along the Cumberland coast.

He was very active in the 1930 Wall Pilgrimage for which he prepared the ninth edition of Bruce's Handbook.

His final and most controversial excavation in Cumbria was that of a circular ring ditch near Penrith known as King Arthur's Round Table in 1937. It appeared to be a Neolithic henge monument, and Collingwood's excavations, failing to find conclusive evidence of Neolithic activity, nevertheless found the base of two stone pillars, a possible cremation trench and some post holes. Sadly, his subsequent ill health prevented him undertaking a second season so the work was handed over to the German prehistorian Gerhard Bersu, who queried some of Collingwood's findings. However, recently, Grace Simpson, the daughter of the excavator F. G. Simpson, has queried Bersu's work and largely rehabilitated Collingwood as an excavator.[16]

He also began what was to be the major work of his archaeological career, preparing a corpus of the Roman Inscriptions of Britain, which involved travelling all over Britain to see the inscriptions and draw them; he eventually prepared drawings of nearly 900 inscriptions. It was finally published in 1965 by his student R. P. Wright.

He also published two major archaeological works. The first was The Archaeology of Roman Britain, a handbook in sixteen chapters covering first the archaeological sites (fortresses, towns and temples and portable antiquities) inscriptions, coins, pottery and brooches. Mortimer Wheeler in a review,[17] remarked that "it seemed at first a trifle off beat that he should immerse himself in so much museum-like detail ... but I felt sure that this was incidental to his primary mission to organise his own thinking".

However, his most important work was his contribution to the first volume of the Oxford History of England, Roman Britain and the English Settlements, of which he wrote the major part, Nowell Myres adding the second smaller part on English settlements. The book was in many ways revolutionary for it set out to write the story of Roman Britain from an archaeological rather than a historical viewpoint, putting into practice his own belief in 'Question and Answer' archaeology.

The result was alluring and influential. However, as Ian Richmond wrote, 'The general reader may discover too late that it has one major defect. It does not sufficiently distinguish between objective and subjective and combines both in a subtle and apparently objective presentation'.[18]

The most notorious passage is that on Romano-British art: "the impression that constantly haunts the archaeologist, like a bad smell, is that of an ugliness that plagues the place like a London fog".[19]

Collingwood's most important contribution to British archaeology was his insistence on Question and Answer archaeology: excavations should not take place unless there is a question to be answered. It is a philosophy which, as Anthony Birley points out,[20] has been incorporated by English Heritage into the conditions for Scheduled Monuments Consent. Still, it has always been surprising that the proponents of the "new" archaeology in the 1960s and the 70s have entirely ignored the work of Collingwood, the one major archaeologist who was also a major professional philosopher. He has been described as an early proponent of archaeological theory.[21]

Author Edit

Outside archaeology and philosophy, he also published the travel book The First Mate's Log of a Voyage to Greece (1940), an account of a yachting voyage in the Mediterranean, in the company of several of his students.

Arthur Ransome was a family friend, and learned to sail in their boat, subsequently teaching his sibling's children to sail. Ransome loosely based the Swallows in Swallows and Amazons series on his sibling's children.

Works Edit

Main works published in his lifetime Edit

  • Religion and Philosophy (1916) ISBN 1-85506-317-4[22]
  • Roman Britain (1923; 2nd ed., 1932) ISBN 0-8196-1160-3[23][24]
  • Speculum Mentis; or The Map of Knowledge (1924) ISBN 978-1-897406-42-7[25]
  • Outlines of a Philosophy of Art (1925)[26]
  • The Archaeology of Roman Britain (1930) ISBN 978-0-09-185045-6[27]
  • An Essay on Philosophical Method (1933, rev. ed. 2005). ISBN 1-85506-392-1[28]
  • Roman Britain and the English Settlements (with J. N. L. Myres, 1936, 2nd ed. 1937)[19]
  • The Principles of Art (1938) ISBN 0-19-500209-1[29]
  • An Autobiography (1939) ISBN 0-19-824694-3[30]
  • The First Mate's Log (1940)[31]
  • An Essay on Metaphysics (1940, revised edition 1998). ISBN 0-8191-3315-9[32]
  • The New Leviathan (1942, rev. ed. 1992) ISBN 0-19-823880-0[33]

Main articles published in his lifetime Edit

  • 'A Philosophy of Progress', The Realist, 1:1, April 1929, 64-77

Published posthumously Edit

All 'revised' editions comprise the original text plus a new introduction and extensive additional material.

Notes Edit

  1. ^ a b Collingwood himself used the term historicism, a term that he apparently coined, to describe his approach (for example, in his lecture "Ruskin's Philosophy" lecture, delivered to the Ruskin Centenary Conference Exhibition, Coniston, Cumbria (see Jan van der Dussen, History as a Science: The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, Springer, 2012, p. 49)), but some later historiographers describe him as a proponent of "historism" in accordance with the current English meaning of the term (F. R. Ankersmit, Sublime Historical Experience, Stanford University Press, 2005, p. 404).
  2. ^ A translation of the German Historismus first coined by Karl Wilhelm Friedrich Schlegel (see Brian Leiter, Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2007, p. 175: "[The word 'historicism'] appears as early as the late eighteenth century in the writings of the German romantics, who used it in a neutral sense. In 1797 Friedrich Schlegel used 'historicism' to refer to a philosophy that stresses the importance of history ...").
  3. ^ David Naugle, "R. G. Collingwood and the Hermeneutic Tradition", 1993.
  4. ^ Oxford University Calendar 1913, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1913, pp. 196, 222
  5. ^ Mink, Louis O. (1969). Mind, History, and Dialectic. Indiana University Press, 1.
  6. ^ Collingwood, R. G.; Dray, William H.; van der Dussen, W. J. (1999). The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-19-823703-7.
  7. ^ D'Oro, Giuseppina; Connelly, James. "Robin George Collingwood". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2019.
  8. ^ "historiography – Intellectual history | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 18 July 2022.
  9. ^ Collingwood, R. G. (1993). The Idea of History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 301.
  10. ^ D'Oro, Giuseppina; Connelly, James. "Robin George Collingwood". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 April 2019.
  11. ^ Collingwood, R. G.; Dray, William H; van der Dussen, W. J. (1999). The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-823703-7.
  12. ^ Gaut, Berys Nigel; Lopes, Dominic, eds. (2013). "Expressivism: Croce and Collingwood". The Routledge companion to aesthetics. Routledge philosophy companions (3 ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 106–115. ISBN 978-0-415-78286-9.
  13. ^ R. G. Collingwood (2005). "Man Goes Mad" in The Philosophy of Enchantment. Oxford University Press, 318.
  14. ^ Boucher, David (2003). The Social and Political Thought of R. G. Collingwood. Cambridge University Press. p. 152.
  15. ^ The Vasculum 8:4–9.
  16. ^ Collingwood Studies 5, 1998, 109-119
  17. ^ Antiquity 43
  18. ^ Richmond, I.A., 1944. 'Appreciation of R. G. Collingwood as an archaeologist', Proceedings of the British Academy 29:478
  19. ^ a b Collingwood, R. G. (Robin George), 1889-1943. (1937). Roman Britain and the English settlements. Myres, J. N. L. (John Nowell Linton) (Second ed.). Oxford: The Clarendon Press. pp. 250. ISBN 019821703X. OCLC 398748 – via Internet Archive.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  20. ^ Introductory essay in R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography, Oxford University Press.
  21. ^ Leach, Stephen (2012). "R.G. Collingwood – An Early Archaeological Theorist?". In Duggan, M.; McIntosh, F.; Rohl, D. J. (eds.). TRAC 2011: Proceedings of the Twenty First Theoretical Roman Archaeology Conference, Newcastle 2011. Theoretical Roman Archaeology Conference & Oxbow Books. pp. 10–18. doi:10.16995/TRAC2011_10_18. S2CID 194526654. 
  22. ^ Collingwood, R. G. (Robin George) (1916). Religion and Philosophy. Robarts - University of Toronto. London, Macmillan. ISBN 1-85506-317-4 – via Internet Archive.
  23. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1923). Roman Britain. Clarendon Press.
  24. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1932). Roman Britain. Clarendon Press.
  25. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1924). Speculum Mentis: Or, The Map of Knowledge. Clarendon Press.
  26. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1925). Outlines of a philosophy of art. Thoemmes. ISBN 9781855063167.
  27. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1930). The archaeology of Roman Britain. Methuen & Co. Ltd. ISBN 9780416275803.
  28. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1933). An essay on philosophical method. The Clarendon Press.
  29. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1938). The Principles of Art. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-500209-6.
  30. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1939). An autobiography. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-281247-6.
  31. ^ Collingwood, R. G. (15 April 2003). The First Mates Log. A&C Black. ISBN 9781855063280.
  32. ^ Collingwood, R. G.; Collingwood, Robin George (24 May 2001). An Essay on Metaphysics. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780199241415.
  33. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1999). The New Leviathan: Or Man, Society, Civilization, and Barbarism. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198238805.
  34. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (31 December 1960). The Idea of Nature. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198020011.
  35. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1956). The idea of history. Oxford University Press.
  36. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1964). Essays in the philosophy of art. Indiana University Press.
  37. ^ Collingwood, Robin George (1965). Essays in the Philosophy of History. University of Texas Press. ISBN 9780292732292.
  38. ^ Collingwood, Robin George; Boucher, David (1989). Essays in Political Philosophy. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198248231.
  39. ^ Collingwood, Robin George; Collingwood, R. G. (1999). The Principles of History: And Other Writings in Philosophy of History. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198237037.
  40. ^ Collingwood, R. G. (2005). The Philosophy of Enchantment: Studies in Folktale, Cultural Criticism, and Anthropology. Oxford University Press.

Sources Edit

  • William M. Johnston, The Formative Years of R. G. Collingwood (Harvard University Archives, 1965)
  • Jan van der Dussen: History as a Science: The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. Springer, 2012. ISBN 978-94-007-4311-3 [Print]; ISBN 978-94-007-4312-0 [eBook]
  • David Boucher. The Social and Political Thought of R. G. Collingwood. Cambridge University Press. 1989. 300pp.
  • Alan Donagan. The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. University of Chicago Press. 1986.
  • William H. Dray. History as Re-enactment: R. G. Collingwood's Idea of History. Oxford University Press. 1995. 347pp.

Further reading Edit

External links Edit

collingwood, this, article, includes, list, general, references, lacks, sufficient, corresponding, inline, citations, please, help, improve, this, article, introducing, more, precise, citations, june, 2023, learn, when, remove, this, template, message, robin, . This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations June 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Robin George Collingwood FBA ˈ k ɒ l ɪ ŋ w ʊ d 22 February 1889 9 January 1943 was an English philosopher historian and archaeologist He is best known for his philosophical works including The Principles of Art 1938 and the posthumously published The Idea of History 1946 R G CollingwoodFBABornRobin George Collingwood22 February 1889Gillhead Cartmel Fell Lancashire now Cumbria EnglandDied9 January 1943 1943 01 09 aged 53 Coniston Lancashire EnglandAlma materUniversity College OxfordNotable workThe Principles of Art 1938 The Idea of History 1946 Era20th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolBritish idealismHistorism 1 InstitutionsPembroke College OxfordMain interestsMetaphysicsPhilosophy of historyAestheticsNotable ideasHistorical imaginationCoining the English term historicism 1 2 Aesthetic expressivism Contents 1 Biography 2 Philosopher 2 1 Philosophy of history 2 2 Philosophy of art 2 3 Political philosophy 3 Archaeologist 4 Author 5 Works 5 1 Main works published in his lifetime 5 2 Main articles published in his lifetime 5 3 Published posthumously 6 Notes 7 Sources 8 Further reading 9 External linksBiography EditCollingwood was born 22 February 1889 in Cartmel Grange over Sands then in Lancashire now Cumbria the son of the artist and archaeologist W G Collingwood who acted as John Ruskin s private secretary in the final years of Ruskin s life Collingwood s mother was also an artist and a talented pianist He was educated at Rugby School and University College Oxford where he gained a First in Classical Moderations Greek and Latin in 1910 and a congratulatory First in Greats Ancient History and Philosophy in 1912 4 Prior to graduation he was elected a fellow of Pembroke College Oxford Collingwood was a fellow of Pembroke College Oxford for some 15 years until becoming the Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy at Magdalen College Oxford He was taught by the historian and archaeologist F J Haverfield at the time Camden Professor of Ancient History Important influences on Collingwood were the Italian Idealists Benedetto Croce Giovanni Gentile and Guido de Ruggiero the last of whom was also a close friend Other important influences were Hegel Kant Giambattista Vico F H Bradley and J A Smith After several years of increasingly debilitating strokes Collingwood died at Coniston Lancashire on 9 January 1943 He was a practising Anglican throughout his life Philosopher EditPhilosophy of history Edit Collingwood is widely noted for The Idea of History 1946 which was collated from various sources soon after his death by a student T M Knox It came to be a major inspiration for philosophy of history in the English speaking world and is extensively cited leading to an ironic remark by commentator Louis Mink that Collingwood is coming to be the best known neglected thinker of our time 5 Collingwood categorized history as a science defining a science as any organized body of knowledge 6 However he distinguished history from natural sciences because the concerns of these two branches are different natural sciences are concerned with the physical world while history in its most common usage is concerned with social sciences and human affairs 7 Collingwood pointed out a fundamental difference between knowing things in the present or in the natural sciences and knowing history To come to know things in the present or about things in the natural sciences real things can be observed as they are in existence or that have substance right now Since the internal thought processes of historical persons cannot be perceived with the physical senses and past historical events cannot be directly observed history must be methodologically different from natural sciences History being a study of the human mind is interested in the thoughts and motivations of the actors in history this insight being encapsulated in his epigram All history is the history of thought 8 Therefore Collingwood suggested that a historian must reconstruct history by using historical imagination to re enact the thought processes of historical persons based on information and evidence from historical sources Re enactment of thought refers to the idea that the historian can access not only a thought process similar to that of the historical actor but the actual thought process itself Consider Collingwood s words regarding the study of Plato In its immediacy as an actual experience of his own Plato s argument must undoubtedly have grown up out of a discussion of some sort though I do not know what it was and been closely connected with such a discussion Yet if I not only read his argument but understand it follow it in my own mind by re arguing it with and for myself the process of argument which I go through is not a process resembling Plato s it actually is Plato s so far as I understand him rightly 9 In Collingwood s understanding a thought is a single entity accessible to the public and therefore regardless of how many people have the same thought it is still a singular thought Thoughts in other words are to be distinguished on the basis of purely qualitative criteria and if there are two people entertaining the qualitatively same thought there is numerically only one thought since there is only one propositional content 10 Therefore if historians follow the correct line of inquiry in response to a historical source and reason correctly they can arrive at the same thought the author of their source had and in so doing re enact that thought Collingwood rejected what he deemed scissors and paste history in which the historian rejects a statement recorded by their subject either because it contradicts another historical statement or because it contradicts the historian s own understanding of the world As he states in Principles of History sometimes a historian will encounter a story which he simply cannot believe a story characteristic perhaps of the superstitions or prejudices of the author s time or the circle in which he lived but not credible to a more enlightened age and therefore to be omitted 11 This Collingwood argues is an unacceptable way to do history Sources which make claims that do not align with current understandings of the world were still created by rational humans who had reason for creating them Therefore these sources are valuable and ought to be investigated further in order to get at the historical context in which they were created and for what reason Philosophy of art Edit The Principles of Art 1938 comprises Collingwood s most developed treatment of aesthetic questions Collingwood held following Benedetto Croce that works of art are essentially expressions of emotion For Collingwood an important social role for artists is to clarify and articulate emotions from their community Collingwood developed a position later known as aesthetic expressivism not to be confused with various other views typically called expressivism a thesis first developed by Croce 12 Political philosophy Edit In politics Collingwood defended the ideals of what he called liberalism in its Continental sense The essence of this conception is the idea of a community as governing itself by fostering the free expression of all political opinions that take shape within it and finding some means of reducing this multiplicity of opinions to a unity 13 In his Autobiography Collingwood confessed that his politics had always been democratic and liberal and shared Guido de Ruggiero s opinion that socialism had rendered a great service to liberalism by pointing out the shortcomings of laissez faire economics 14 Archaeologist EditCollingwood was not just a philosopher of history but also a practising historian and archaeologist He was during his time a leading authority on Roman Britain he spent his term time at Oxford teaching philosophy but devoted his long vacations to archaeology He began work along Hadrian s Wall The family home was at Coniston in the Lake District and his father was a leading figure in the Cumberland and Westmorland Archaeological Society Collingwood was drawn in on a number of excavations and put forward the theory that Hadrian s Wall was not so much a fighting platform but an elevated sentry walk 15 He also put forward the suggestion that Hadrian s defensive system also included a number of forts along the Cumberland coast He was very active in the 1930 Wall Pilgrimage for which he prepared the ninth edition of Bruce s Handbook His final and most controversial excavation in Cumbria was that of a circular ring ditch near Penrith known as King Arthur s Round Table in 1937 It appeared to be a Neolithic henge monument and Collingwood s excavations failing to find conclusive evidence of Neolithic activity nevertheless found the base of two stone pillars a possible cremation trench and some post holes Sadly his subsequent ill health prevented him undertaking a second season so the work was handed over to the German prehistorian Gerhard Bersu who queried some of Collingwood s findings However recently Grace Simpson the daughter of the excavator F G Simpson has queried Bersu s work and largely rehabilitated Collingwood as an excavator 16 He also began what was to be the major work of his archaeological career preparing a corpus of the Roman Inscriptions of Britain which involved travelling all over Britain to see the inscriptions and draw them he eventually prepared drawings of nearly 900 inscriptions It was finally published in 1965 by his student R P Wright He also published two major archaeological works The first was The Archaeology of Roman Britain a handbook in sixteen chapters covering first the archaeological sites fortresses towns and temples and portable antiquities inscriptions coins pottery and brooches Mortimer Wheeler in a review 17 remarked that it seemed at first a trifle off beat that he should immerse himself in so much museum like detail but I felt sure that this was incidental to his primary mission to organise his own thinking However his most important work was his contribution to the first volume of the Oxford History of England Roman Britain and the English Settlements of which he wrote the major part Nowell Myres adding the second smaller part on English settlements The book was in many ways revolutionary for it set out to write the story of Roman Britain from an archaeological rather than a historical viewpoint putting into practice his own belief in Question and Answer archaeology The result was alluring and influential However as Ian Richmond wrote The general reader may discover too late that it has one major defect It does not sufficiently distinguish between objective and subjective and combines both in a subtle and apparently objective presentation 18 The most notorious passage is that on Romano British art the impression that constantly haunts the archaeologist like a bad smell is that of an ugliness that plagues the place like a London fog 19 Collingwood s most important contribution to British archaeology was his insistence on Question and Answer archaeology excavations should not take place unless there is a question to be answered It is a philosophy which as Anthony Birley points out 20 has been incorporated by English Heritage into the conditions for Scheduled Monuments Consent Still it has always been surprising that the proponents of the new archaeology in the 1960s and the 70s have entirely ignored the work of Collingwood the one major archaeologist who was also a major professional philosopher He has been described as an early proponent of archaeological theory 21 Author EditOutside archaeology and philosophy he also published the travel book The First Mate s Log of a Voyage to Greece 1940 an account of a yachting voyage in the Mediterranean in the company of several of his students Arthur Ransome was a family friend and learned to sail in their boat subsequently teaching his sibling s children to sail Ransome loosely based the Swallows in Swallows and Amazons series on his sibling s children Works EditMain works published in his lifetime Edit Religion and Philosophy 1916 ISBN 1 85506 317 4 22 Roman Britain 1923 2nd ed 1932 ISBN 0 8196 1160 3 23 24 Speculum Mentis or The Map of Knowledge 1924 ISBN 978 1 897406 42 7 25 Outlines of a Philosophy of Art 1925 26 The Archaeology of Roman Britain 1930 ISBN 978 0 09 185045 6 27 An Essay on Philosophical Method 1933 rev ed 2005 ISBN 1 85506 392 1 28 Roman Britain and the English Settlements with J N L Myres 1936 2nd ed 1937 19 The Principles of Art 1938 ISBN 0 19 500209 1 29 An Autobiography 1939 ISBN 0 19 824694 3 30 The First Mate s Log 1940 31 An Essay on Metaphysics 1940 revised edition 1998 ISBN 0 8191 3315 9 32 The New Leviathan 1942 rev ed 1992 ISBN 0 19 823880 0 33 Main articles published in his lifetime Edit A Philosophy of Progress The Realist 1 1 April 1929 64 77Published posthumously Edit The Idea of Nature 1945 ISBN 0 19 500217 2 34 The Idea of History 1946 revised edition 1993 ISBN 0 19 285306 6 35 Essays in the Philosophy of Art 1964 36 Essays in the Philosophy of History 1965 ISBN 0 8240 6355 4 37 Essays in Political Philosophy with David Boucher 1989 ISBN 0 19 823566 6 38 The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History ed William H Dray and W J van der Dussen 2001 ISBN 0 19 924315 8 39 The Philosophy of Enchantment Studies in Folktale Cultural Criticism and Anthropology 2005 ISBN 0 19 926253 5 40 All revised editions comprise the original text plus a new introduction and extensive additional material Notes Edit a b Collingwood himself used the term historicism a term that he apparently coined to describe his approach for example in his lecture Ruskin s Philosophy lecture delivered to the Ruskin Centenary Conference Exhibition Coniston Cumbria see Jan van der Dussen History as a Science The Philosophy of R G Collingwood Springer 2012 p 49 but some later historiographers describe him as a proponent of historism in accordance with the current English meaning of the term F R Ankersmit Sublime Historical Experience Stanford University Press 2005 p 404 A translation of the German Historismus first coined by Karl Wilhelm Friedrich Schlegel see Brian Leiter Michael Rosen eds The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy Oxford University Press 2007 p 175 The word historicism appears as early as the late eighteenth century in the writings of the German romantics who used it in a neutral sense In 1797 Friedrich Schlegel used historicism to refer to a philosophy that stresses the importance of history David Naugle R G Collingwood and the Hermeneutic Tradition 1993 Oxford University Calendar 1913 Oxford Oxford University Press 1913 pp 196 222 Mink Louis O 1969 Mind History and Dialectic Indiana University Press 1 Collingwood R G Dray William H van der Dussen W J 1999 The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History New York Oxford University Press p 1 ISBN 978 0 19 823703 7 D Oro Giuseppina Connelly James Robin George Collingwood The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 3 April 2019 historiography Intellectual history Britannica www britannica com Retrieved 18 July 2022 Collingwood R G 1993 The Idea of History New York Oxford University Press p 301 D Oro Giuseppina Connelly James Robin George Collingwood The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 3 April 2019 Collingwood R G Dray William H van der Dussen W J 1999 The Principles of History and Other Writings in Philosophy of History New York Oxford University Press p 13 ISBN 978 0 19 823703 7 Gaut Berys Nigel Lopes Dominic eds 2013 Expressivism Croce and Collingwood The Routledge companion to aesthetics Routledge philosophy companions 3 ed London Routledge pp 106 115 ISBN 978 0 415 78286 9 R G Collingwood 2005 Man Goes Mad in The Philosophy of Enchantment Oxford University Press 318 Boucher David 2003 The Social and Political Thought of R G Collingwood Cambridge University Press p 152 The Vasculum 8 4 9 Collingwood Studies 5 1998 109 119 Antiquity 43 Richmond I A 1944 Appreciation of R G Collingwood as an archaeologist Proceedings of the British Academy 29 478 a b Collingwood R G Robin George 1889 1943 1937 Roman Britain and the English settlements Myres J N L John Nowell Linton Second ed Oxford The Clarendon Press pp 250 ISBN 019821703X OCLC 398748 via Internet Archive a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Introductory essay in R G Collingwood An Autobiography Oxford University Press Leach Stephen 2012 R G Collingwood An Early Archaeological Theorist In Duggan M McIntosh F Rohl D J eds TRAC 2011 Proceedings of the Twenty First Theoretical Roman Archaeology Conference Newcastle 2011 Theoretical Roman Archaeology Conference amp Oxbow Books pp 10 18 doi 10 16995 TRAC2011 10 18 S2CID 194526654 nbsp Collingwood R G Robin George 1916 Religion and Philosophy Robarts University of Toronto London Macmillan ISBN 1 85506 317 4 via Internet Archive Collingwood Robin George 1923 Roman Britain Clarendon Press Collingwood Robin George 1932 Roman Britain Clarendon Press Collingwood Robin George 1924 Speculum Mentis Or The Map of Knowledge Clarendon Press Collingwood Robin George 1925 Outlines of a philosophy of art Thoemmes ISBN 9781855063167 Collingwood Robin George 1930 The archaeology of Roman Britain Methuen amp Co Ltd ISBN 9780416275803 Collingwood Robin George 1933 An essay on philosophical method The Clarendon Press Collingwood Robin George 1938 The Principles of Art Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 500209 6 Collingwood Robin George 1939 An autobiography Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 281247 6 Collingwood R G 15 April 2003 The First Mates Log A amp C Black ISBN 9781855063280 Collingwood R G Collingwood Robin George 24 May 2001 An Essay on Metaphysics Clarendon Press ISBN 9780199241415 Collingwood Robin George 1999 The New Leviathan Or Man Society Civilization and Barbarism Clarendon Press ISBN 9780198238805 Collingwood Robin George 31 December 1960 The Idea of Nature Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198020011 Collingwood Robin George 1956 The idea of history Oxford University Press Collingwood Robin George 1964 Essays in the philosophy of art Indiana University Press Collingwood Robin George 1965 Essays in the Philosophy of History University of Texas Press ISBN 9780292732292 Collingwood Robin George Boucher David 1989 Essays in Political Philosophy Clarendon Press ISBN 9780198248231 Collingwood Robin George Collingwood R G 1999 The Principles of History And Other Writings in Philosophy of History Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198237037 Collingwood R G 2005 The Philosophy of Enchantment Studies in Folktale Cultural Criticism and Anthropology Oxford University Press Sources EditWilliam M Johnston The Formative Years of R G Collingwood Harvard University Archives 1965 Jan van der Dussen History as a Science The Philosophy of R G Collingwood Springer 2012 ISBN 978 94 007 4311 3 Print ISBN 978 94 007 4312 0 eBook David Boucher The Social and Political Thought of R G Collingwood Cambridge University Press 1989 300pp Alan Donagan The Later Philosophy of R G Collingwood University of Chicago Press 1986 William H Dray History as Re enactment R G Collingwood s Idea of History Oxford University Press 1995 347pp Further reading EditMoran Sean Farrell R G Collingwood Encyclopedia of Historians and Historical Writing Vol I https plato stanford edu entries collingwood External links Edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Robin George Collingwood nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to R G Collingwood Additional Articles and Documents by R G Collingwood at the Wayback Machine archived 13 September 2005 D Oro Giuseppina Robin George Collingwood In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Kemp Gary Collingwood s Aesthetics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Voice in the wilderness RG Collingwood 2009 radio discussion with Marnie Hughes Warrington on The Philosopher s Zone How the untimely death of RG Collingwood changed the course of philosophy forever 2019 article by Ray Monk for Prospect Leach S 2009 An Appreciation of R G Collingwood as an Archaeologist Bulletin of the History of Archaeology 19 1 pp 14 20 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title R G Collingwood amp oldid 1179095207, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.