fbpx
Wikipedia

Quantum nonlocality

In theoretical physics, quantum nonlocality refers to the phenomenon by which the measurement statistics of a multipartite quantum system do not allow an interpretation with local realism. Quantum nonlocality has been experimentally verified under a variety of physical assumptions.[1][2][3][4][5] Any physical theory that aims at superseding or replacing quantum theory should account for such experiments and therefore cannot fulfill local realism; quantum nonlocality is a property of the universe that is independent of our description of nature.

Quantum nonlocality does not allow for faster-than-light communication,[6] and hence is compatible with special relativity and its universal speed limit of objects. Thus, quantum theory is local in the strict sense defined by special relativity and, as such, the term "quantum nonlocality" is sometimes considered a misnomer.[citation needed] Still, it prompts many of the foundational discussions concerning quantum theory.[citation needed]

History edit

Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen edit

In the 1935 EPR paper,[7] Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen described "two spatially separated particles which have both perfectly correlated positions and momenta"[8] as a direct consequence of quantum theory. They intended to use the classical principle of locality to challenge the idea that the quantum wavefunction was a complete description of reality, but instead they sparked a debate on the nature of reality.[9] Afterwards, Einstein presented a variant of these ideas in a letter to Erwin Schrödinger,[10] which is the version that is presented here. The state and notation used here are more modern, and akin to David Bohm's take on EPR.[11] The quantum state of the two particles prior to measurement can be written as

 
where  .[12]

Here, subscripts “A” and “B” distinguish the two particles, though it is more convenient and usual to refer to these particles as being in the possession of two experimentalists called Alice and Bob. The rules of quantum theory give predictions for the outcomes of measurements performed by the experimentalists. Alice, for example, will measure her particle to be spin-up in an average of fifty percent of measurements. However, according to the Copenhagen interpretation, Alice's measurement causes the state of the two particles to collapse, so that if Alice performs a measurement of spin in the z-direction, that is with respect to the basis  , then Bob's system will be left in one of the states  . Likewise, if Alice performs a measurement of spin in the x-direction, that is, with respect to the basis  , then Bob's system will be left in one of the states  . Schrödinger referred to this phenomenon as "steering".[13] This steering occurs in such a way that no signal can be sent by performing such a state update; quantum nonlocality cannot be used to send messages instantaneously and is therefore not in direct conflict with causality concerns in special relativity.[12]

In the Copenhagen view of this experiment, Alice's measurement—and particularly her measurement choice—has a direct effect on Bob's state. However, under the assumption of locality, actions on Alice's system do not affect the "true", or "ontic" state of Bob's system. We see that the ontic state of Bob's system must be compatible with one of the quantum states   or  , since Alice can make a measurement that concludes with one of those states being the quantum description of his system. At the same time, it must also be compatible with one of the quantum states   or   for the same reason. Therefore, the ontic state of Bob's system must be compatible with at least two quantum states; the quantum state is therefore not a complete descriptor of his system. Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen saw this as evidence of the incompleteness of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory, since the wavefunction is explicitly not a complete description of a quantum system under this assumption of locality. Their paper concludes:[7]

While we have thus shown that the wave function does not provide a complete description of the physical reality, we left open the question of whether or not such a description exists. We believe, however, that such a theory is possible.

Although various authors (most notably Niels Bohr) criticised the ambiguous terminology of the EPR paper,[14][15] the thought experiment nevertheless generated a great deal of interest. Their notion of a "complete description" was later formalised by the suggestion of hidden variables that determine the statistics of measurement results, but to which an observer does not have access.[16] Bohmian mechanics provides such a completion of quantum mechanics, with the introduction of hidden variables; however the theory is explicitly nonlocal.[17] The interpretation therefore does not give an answer to Einstein's question, which was whether or not a complete description of quantum mechanics could be given in terms of local hidden variables in keeping with the "Principle of Local Action".[18]

Bell inequality edit

In 1964 John Bell answered Einstein's question by showing that such local hidden variables can never reproduce the full range of statistical outcomes predicted by quantum theory.[19] Bell showed that a local hidden variable hypothesis leads to restrictions on the strength of correlations of measurement results. If the Bell inequalities are violated experimentally as predicted by quantum mechanics, then reality cannot be described by local hidden variables and the mystery of quantum nonlocal causation remains. However, Bell notes that the non-local hidden variable model of Bohm are different:[19]

This [grossly nonlocal structure] is characteristic ... of any such theory which reproduces exactly the quantum mechanical predictions.

Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt (CHSH) reformulated these inequalities in a manner that was more conducive to experimental testing (see CHSH inequality).[20]

In the scenario proposed by Bell (a Bell scenario), two experimentalists, Alice and Bob, conduct experiments in separate labs. At each run, Alice (Bob) conducts an experiment     in her (his) lab, obtaining outcome    . If Alice and Bob repeat their experiments several times, then they can estimate the probabilities  , namely, the probability that Alice and Bob respectively observe the results   when they respectively conduct the experiments x,y. In the following, each such set of probabilities   will be denoted by just  . In the quantum nonlocality slang,   is termed a box.[21]

Bell formalized the idea of a hidden variable by introducing the parameter   to locally characterize measurement results on each system:[19] "It is a matter of indifference ... whether λ denotes a single variable or a set ... and whether the variables are discrete or continuous". However, it is equivalent (and more intuitive) to think of   as a local "strategy" or "message" that occurs with some probability   when Alice and Bob reboot their experimental setup. Bell's assumption of local causality then stipulates that each local strategy defines the distributions of independent outcomes if Alice conducts experiment x and Bob conducts experiment  :

 

Here   ( ) denotes the probability that Alice (Bob) obtains the result     when she (he) conducts experiment     and the local variable describing her (his) experiment has value   ( ).

Suppose that   can take values from some set  . If each pair of values   has an associated probability   of being selected (shared randomness is allowed, i.e.,   can be correlated), then one can average over this distribution to obtain a formula for the joint probability of each measurement result:

 

A box admitting such a decomposition is called a Bell local or a classical box. Fixing the number of possible values which   can each take, one can represent each box   as a finite vector with entries  . In that representation, the set of all classical boxes forms a convex polytope. In the Bell scenario studied by CHSH, where   can take values within  , any Bell local box   must satisfy the CHSH inequality:

 

where

 

The above considerations apply to model a quantum experiment. Consider two parties conducting local polarization measurements on a bipartite photonic state. The measurement result for the polarization of a photon can take one of two values (informally, whether the photon is polarized in that direction, or in the orthogonal direction). If each party is allowed to choose between just two different polarization directions, the experiment fits within the CHSH scenario. As noted by CHSH, there exist a quantum state and polarization directions which generate a box   with   equal to  . This demonstrates an explicit way in which a theory with ontological states that are local, with local measurements and only local actions cannot match the probabilistic predictions of quantum theory, disproving Einstein's hypothesis. Experimentalists such as Alain Aspect have verified the quantum violation of the CHSH inequality [1] as well as other formulations of Bell's inequality, to invalidate the local hidden variables hypothesis and confirm that reality is indeed nonlocal in the EPR sense.

Possibilistic nonlocality edit

Bell's demonstration is probabilistic in the sense that it shows that the precise probabilities predicted by quantum mechanics for some entangled scenarios cannot be met by a local hidden variable theory. (For short, here and henceforth "local theory" means "local hidden variables theory".) However, quantum mechanics permits an even stronger violation of local theories: a possibilistic one, in which local theories cannot even agree with quantum mechanics on which events are possible or impossible in an entangled scenario. The first proof of this kind was due to Daniel Greenberger, Michael Horne, and Anton Zeilinger in 1993[22] The state involved is often called the GHZ state.

In 1993, Lucien Hardy demonstrated a logical proof of quantum nonlocality that, like the GHZ proof is a possibilistic proof.[23][24][25] It starts with the observation that the state   defined below can be written in a few suggestive ways:

 
where, as above,  .

The experiment consists of this entangled state being shared between two experimenters, each of whom has the ability to measure either with respect to the basis   or  . We see that if they each measure with respect to  , then they never see the outcome  . If one measures with respect to   and the other  , they never see the outcomes     However, sometimes they see the outcome   when measuring with respect to  , since  

This leads to the paradox: having the outcome   we conclude that if one of the experimenters had measured with respect to the   basis instead, the outcome must have been   or  , since   and   are impossible. But then, if they had both measured with respect to the   basis, by locality the result must have been  , which is also impossible.

Nonlocal hidden variable models with a finite propagation speed edit

The work of Bancal et al.[26] generalizes Bell's result by proving that correlations achievable in quantum theory are also incompatible with a large class of superluminal hidden variable models. In this framework, faster-than-light signaling is precluded. However, the choice of settings of one party can influence hidden variables at another party's distant location, if there is enough time for a superluminal influence (of finite, but otherwise unknown speed) to propagate from one point to the other. In this scenario, any bipartite experiment revealing Bell nonlocality can just provide lower bounds on the hidden influence's propagation speed. Quantum experiments with three or more parties can, nonetheless, disprove all such non-local hidden variable models.[26]

Analogs of Bell’s theorem in more complicated causal structures edit

 
A simple Bayesian network. Rain influences whether the sprinkler is activated, and both rain and the sprinkler influence whether the grass is wet.

The random variables measured in a general experiment can depend on each other in complicated ways. In the field of causal inference, such dependencies are represented via Bayesian networks: directed acyclic graphs where each node represents a variable and an edge from a variable to another signifies that the former influences the latter and not otherwise, see the figure. In a standard bipartite Bell experiment, Alice's (Bob's) setting   ( ), together with her (his) local variable   ( ), influence her (his) local outcome   ( ). Bell's theorem can thus be interpreted as a separation between the quantum and classical predictions in a type of causal structures with just one hidden node  . Similar separations have been established in other types of causal structures.[27] The characterization of the boundaries for classical correlations in such extended Bell scenarios is challenging, but there exist complete practical computational methods to achieve it.[28][29]

Entanglement and nonlocality edit

Quantum nonlocality is sometimes understood as being equivalent to entanglement. However, this is not the case. Quantum entanglement can be defined only within the formalism of quantum mechanics, i.e., it is a model-dependent property. In contrast, nonlocality refers to the impossibility of a description of observed statistics in terms of a local hidden variable model, so it is independent of the physical model used to describe the experiment.

It is true that for any pure entangled state there exists a choice of measurements that produce Bell nonlocal correlations, but the situation is more complex for mixed states. While any Bell nonlocal state must be entangled, there exist (mixed) entangled states which do not produce Bell nonlocal correlations[30] (although, operating on several copies of some of such states,[31] or carrying out local post-selections,[32] it is possible to witness nonlocal effects). Moreover, while there are catalysts for entanglement,[33] there are none for nonlocality.[34] Finally, reasonably simple examples of Bell inequalities have been found for which the quantum state giving the largest violation is never a maximally entangled state, showing that entanglement is, in some sense, not even proportional to nonlocality.[35][36][37]

Quantum correlations edit

As shown, the statistics achievable by two or more parties conducting experiments in a classical system are constrained in a non-trivial way. Analogously, the statistics achievable by separate observers in a quantum theory also happen to be restricted. The first derivation of a non-trivial statistical limit on the set of quantum correlations, due to B. Tsirelson,[38] is known as Tsirelson's bound. Consider the CHSH Bell scenario detailed before, but this time assume that, in their experiments, Alice and Bob are preparing and measuring quantum systems. In that case, the CHSH parameter can be shown to be bounded by

 

The sets of quantum correlations and Tsirelson’s problem edit

Mathematically, a box   admits a quantum realization if and only if there exists a pair of Hilbert spaces  , a normalized vector   and projection operators   such that

  1. For all  , the sets   represent complete measurements. Namely,  .
  2.  , for all  .

In the following, the set of such boxes will be called  . Contrary to the classical set of correlations, when viewed in probability space,   is not a polytope. On the contrary, it contains both straight and curved boundaries.[39] In addition,   is not closed:[40] this means that there exist boxes   which can be arbitrarily well approximated by quantum systems but are themselves not quantum.

In the above definition, the space-like separation of the two parties conducting the Bell experiment was modeled by imposing that their associated operator algebras act on different factors   of the overall Hilbert space   describing the experiment. Alternatively, one could model space-like separation by imposing that these two algebras commute. This leads to a different definition:

  admits a field quantum realization if and only if there exists a Hilbert space  , a normalized vector   and projection operators   such that

  1. For all  , the sets   represent complete measurements. Namely,  .
  2.  , for all  .
  3.  , for all  .

Call   the set of all such correlations  .

How does this new set relate to the more conventional   defined above? It can be proven that   is closed. Moreover,  , where   denotes the closure of  . Tsirelson's problem[41] consists in deciding whether the inclusion relation   is strict, i.e., whether or not  . This problem only appears in infinite dimensions: when the Hilbert space   in the definition of   is constrained to be finite-dimensional, the closure of the corresponding set equals  .[41]

In January 2020, Ji, Natarajan, Vidick, Wright, and Yuen claimed a result in quantum complexity theory[42] that would imply that  , thus solving Tsirelson's problem.[43][44][45][46][47][48][49]

Tsirelson's problem can be shown equivalent to Connes embedding problem,[50][51][52] a famous conjecture in the theory of operator algebras.

Characterization of quantum correlations edit

Since the dimensions of   and   are, in principle, unbounded, determining whether a given box   admits a quantum realization is a complicated problem. In fact, the dual problem of establishing whether a quantum box can have a perfect score at a non-local game is known to be undecidable.[40] Moreover, the problem of deciding whether   can be approximated by a quantum system with precision   is NP-hard.[53] Characterizing quantum boxes is equivalent to characterizing the cone of completely positive semidefinite matrices under a set of linear constraints.[54]

For small fixed dimensions  , one can explore, using variational methods, whether   can be realized in a bipartite quantum system  , with  ,  . That method, however, can just be used to prove the realizability of  , and not its unrealizability with quantum systems.

To prove unrealizability, the most known method is the Navascués–Pironio–Acín (NPA) hierarchy.[55] This is an infinite decreasing sequence of sets of correlations   with the properties:

  1. If  , then   for all  .
  2. If  , then there exists   such that  .
  3. For any  , deciding whether   can be cast as a semidefinite program.

The NPA hierarchy thus provides a computational characterization, not of  , but of  . If Tsirelson's problem is solved in the affirmative, namely,  , then the above two methods would provide a practical characterization of  . If, on the contrary,  , then a new method to detect the non-realizability of the correlations in   is needed.

The physics of supra-quantum correlations edit

The works listed above describe what the quantum set of correlations looks like, but they do not explain why. Are quantum correlations unavoidable, even in post-quantum physical theories, or on the contrary, could there exist correlations outside   which nonetheless do not lead to any unphysical operational behavior?

In their seminal 1994 paper, Popescu and Rohrlich explore whether quantum correlations can be explained by appealing to relativistic causality alone.[56] Namely, whether any hypothetical box   would allow building a device capable of transmitting information faster than the speed of light. At the level of correlations between two parties, Einstein's causality translates in the requirement that Alice's measurement choice should not affect Bob's statistics, and vice versa. Otherwise, Alice (Bob) could signal Bob (Alice) instantaneously by choosing her (his) measurement setting     appropriately. Mathematically, Popescu and Rohrlich's no-signalling conditions are:

 
 

Like the set of classical boxes, when represented in probability space, the set of no-signalling boxes forms a polytope. Popescu and Rohrlich identified a box   that, while complying with the no-signalling conditions, violates Tsirelson's bound, and is thus unrealizable in quantum physics. Dubbed the PR-box, it can be written as:

 

Here   take values in  , and   denotes the sum modulo two. It can be verified that the CHSH value of this box is 4 (as opposed to the Tsirelson bound of  ). This box had been identified earlier, by Rastall[57] and Khalfin and Tsirelson.[58]

In view of this mismatch, Popescu and Rohrlich pose the problem of identifying a physical principle, stronger than the no-signalling conditions, that allows deriving the set of quantum correlations. Several proposals followed:

  1. Non-trivial communication complexity (NTCC).[59] This principle stipulates that nonlocal correlations should not be so strong as to allow two parties to solve all 1-way communication problems with some probability   using just one bit of communication. It can be proven that any box violating Tsirelson's bound by more than   is incompatible with NTCC.
  2. No Advantage for Nonlocal Computation (NANLC).[60] The following scenario is considered: given a function  , two parties are distributed the strings of   bits   and asked to output the bits   so that   is a good guess for  . The principle of NANLC states that non-local boxes should not give the two parties any advantage to play this game. It is proven that any box violating Tsirelson's bound would provide such an advantage.
  3. Information Causality (IC).[61] The starting point is a bipartite communication scenario where one of the parts (Alice) is handed a random string   of   bits. The second part, Bob, receives a random number  . Their goal is to transmit Bob the bit  , for which purpose Alice is allowed to transmit Bob   bits. The principle of IC states that the sum over   of the mutual information between Alice's bit and Bob's guess cannot exceed the number   of bits transmitted by Alice. It is shown that any box violating Tsirelson's bound would allow two parties to violate IC.
  4. Macroscopic Locality (ML).[62] In the considered setup, two separate parties conduct extensive low-resolution measurements over a large number of independently prepared pairs of correlated particles. ML states that any such “macroscopic” experiment must admit a local hidden variable model. It is proven that any microscopic experiment capable of violating Tsirelson's bound would also violate standard Bell nonlocality when brought to the macroscopic scale. Besides Tsirelson's bound, the principle of ML fully recovers the set of all two-point quantum correlators.
  5. Local Orthogonality (LO).[63] This principle applies to multipartite Bell scenarios, where   parties respectively conduct experiments   in their local labs. They respectively obtain the outcomes  . The pair of vectors   is called an event. Two events  ,   are said to be locally orthogonal if there exists   such that   and  . The principle of LO states that, for any multipartite box, the sum of the probabilities of any set of pair-wise locally orthogonal events cannot exceed 1. It is proven that any bipartite box violating Tsirelson's bound by an amount of   violates LO.

All these principles can be experimentally falsified under the assumption that we can decide if two or more events are space-like separated. This sets this research program aside from the axiomatic reconstruction of quantum mechanics via Generalized Probabilistic Theories.

The works above rely on the implicit assumption that any physical set of correlations must be closed under wirings.[64] This means that any effective box built by combining the inputs and outputs of a number of boxes within the considered set must also belong to the set. Closure under wirings does not seem to enforce any limit on the maximum value of CHSH. However, it is not a void principle: on the contrary, in [64] it is shown that many simple, intuitive families of sets of correlations in probability space happen to violate it.

Originally, it was unknown whether any of these principles (or a subset thereof) was strong enough to derive all the constraints defining  . This state of affairs continued for some years until the construction of the almost quantum set  .[65]   is a set of correlations that is closed under wirings and can be characterized via semidefinite programming. It contains all correlations in  , but also some non-quantum boxes  . Remarkably, all boxes within the almost quantum set are shown to be compatible with the principles of NTCC, NANLC, ML and LO. There is also numerical evidence that almost-quantum boxes also comply with IC. It seems, therefore, that, even when the above principles are taken together, they do not suffice to single out the quantum set in the simplest Bell scenario of two parties, two inputs and two outputs.[65]

Device independent protocols edit

Nonlocality can be exploited to conduct quantum information tasks which do not rely on the knowledge of the inner workings of the prepare-and-measurement apparatuses involved in the experiment. The security or reliability of any such protocol just depends on the strength of the experimentally measured correlations  . These protocols are termed device-independent.

Device-independent quantum key distribution edit

The first device-independent protocol proposed was device-independent quantum key distribution (QKD).[66] In this primitive, two distant parties, Alice and Bob, are distributed an entangled quantum state, that they probe, thus obtaining the statistics  . Based on how non-local the box   happens to be, Alice and Bob estimate how much knowledge an external quantum adversary Eve (the eavesdropper) could possess on the value of Alice and Bob's outputs. This estimation allows them to devise a reconciliation protocol at the end of which Alice and Bob share a perfectly correlated one-time pad of which Eve has no information whatsoever. The one-time pad can then be used to transmit a secret message through a public channel. Although the first security analyses on device-independent QKD relied on Eve carrying out a specific family of attacks,[67] all such protocols have been recently proven unconditionally secure.[68]

Device-independent randomness certification, expansion and amplification edit

Nonlocality can be used to certify that the outcomes of one of the parties in a Bell experiment are partially unknown to an external adversary. By feeding a partially random seed to several non-local boxes, and, after processing the outputs, one can end up with a longer (potentially unbounded) string of comparable randomness[69] or with a shorter but more random string.[70] This last primitive can be proven impossible in a classical setting.[71]

Device-independent (DI) randomness certification, expansion, and amplification are techniques used to generate high-quality random numbers that are secure against any potential attacks on the underlying devices used to generate random numbers. These techniques have critical applications in cryptography, where high-quality random numbers are essential for ensuring the security of cryptographic protocols. Randomness certification is the process of verifying that the output of a random number generator is truly random and has not been tampered with by an adversary. DI randomness certification does this verification without making assumptions about the underlying devices that generate random numbers. Instead, randomness is certified by observing correlations between the outputs of different devices that are generated using the same physical process. Recent research has demonstrated the feasibility of DI randomness certification using entangled quantum systems, such as photons or electrons. Randomness expansion is taking a small amount of initial random seed and expanding it into a much larger sequence of random numbers. In DI randomness expansion, the expansion is done using measurements of quantum systems that are prepared in a highly entangled state. The security of the expansion is guaranteed by the laws of quantum mechanics, which make it impossible for an adversary to predict the expansion output. Recent research has shown that DI randomness expansion can be achieved using entangled photon pairs and measurement devices that violate a Bell inequality.[72] Randomness amplification is the process of taking a small amount of initial random seed and increasing its randomness by using a cryptographic algorithm. In DI randomness amplification, this process is done using entanglement properties and quantum mechanics. The security of the amplification is guaranteed by the fact that any attempt by an adversary to manipulate the algorithm's output will inevitably introduce errors that can be detected and corrected. Recent research has demonstrated the feasibility of DI randomness amplification using quantum entanglement and the violation of a Bell inequality.[73]

DI randomness certification, expansion, and amplification are powerful techniques for generating high-quality random numbers that are secure against any potential attacks on the underlying devices used to generate random numbers. These techniques have critical applications in cryptography and are likely to become increasingly crucial as quantum computing technology advances. In addition, a milder approach called semi-DI exists where random numbers can be generated with some assumptions on the working principle of the devices, environment, dimension, energy, etc., in which it benefits from ease-of-implementation and high generation rate.[74]

Self-testing edit

Sometimes, the box   shared by Alice and Bob is such that it only admits a unique quantum realization. This means that there exist measurement operators   and a quantum state   giving rise to   such that any other physical realization   of   is connected to   via local unitary transformations. This phenomenon, that can be interpreted as an instance of device-independent quantum tomography, was first pointed out by Tsirelson[39] and named self-testing by Mayers and Yao.[66] Self-testing is known to be robust against systematic noise, i.e., if the experimentally measured statistics are close enough to  , one can still determine the underlying state and measurement operators up to error bars.[66]

Dimension witnesses edit

The degree of non-locality of a quantum box   can also provide lower bounds on the Hilbert space dimension of the local systems accessible to Alice and Bob.[75] This problem is equivalent to deciding the existence of a matrix with low completely positive semidefinite rank.[76] Finding lower bounds on the Hilbert space dimension based on statistics happens to be a hard task, and current general methods only provide very low estimates.[77] However, a Bell scenario with five inputs and three outputs suffices to provide arbitrarily high lower bounds on the underlying Hilbert space dimension.[78] Quantum communication protocols which assume a knowledge of the local dimension of Alice and Bob's systems, but otherwise do not make claims on the mathematical description of the preparation and measuring devices involved are termed semi-device independent protocols. Currently, there exist semi-device independent protocols for quantum key distribution [79] and randomness expansion.[80]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Aspect, Alain; Dalibard, Jean; Roger, Gérard (1982-12-20). "Experimental Test of Bell's Inequalities Using Time- Varying Analyzers". Physical Review Letters. 49 (25): 1804–1807. Bibcode:1982PhRvL..49.1804A. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.49.1804.
  2. ^ Rowe MA, et al. (February 2001). "Experimental violation of a Bell's Inequality with efficient detection". Nature. 409 (6822): 791–794. Bibcode:2001Natur.409..791R. doi:10.1038/35057215. hdl:2027.42/62731. PMID 11236986. S2CID 205014115.
  3. ^ Hensen, B, et al. (October 2015). "Loophole-free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1.3 kilometres". Nature. 526 (7575): 682–686. arXiv:1508.05949. Bibcode:2015Natur.526..682H. doi:10.1038/nature15759. PMID 26503041. S2CID 205246446.
  4. ^ Giustina, M, et al. (December 2015). "Significant-Loophole-Free Test of Bell's Theorem with Entangled Photons". Physical Review Letters. 115 (25): 250401. arXiv:1511.03190. Bibcode:2015PhRvL.115y0401G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.115.250401. PMID 26722905. S2CID 13789503.
  5. ^ Shalm, LK, et al. (December 2015). "Strong Loophole-Free Test of Local Realism". Physical Review Letters. 115 (25): 250402. arXiv:1511.03189. Bibcode:2015PhRvL.115y0402S. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.115.250402. PMC 5815856. PMID 26722906.
  6. ^ Ghirardi, G.C.; Rimini, A.; Weber, T. (March 1980). "A general argument against superluminal transmission through the quantum mechanical measurement process". Lettere al Nuovo Cimento. 27 (10): 293–298. doi:10.1007/BF02817189. S2CID 121145494.
  7. ^ a b Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935-05-15). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777. ISSN 0031-899X.
  8. ^ Reid, M. D.; Drummond, P. D.; Bowen, W. P.; Cavalcanti, E. G.; Lam, P. K.; Bachor, H. A.; Andersen, U. L.; Leuchs, G. (2009-12-10). "Colloquium : The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox: From concepts to applications". Reviews of Modern Physics. 81 (4): 1727–1751. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.81.1727. hdl:10072/37941. ISSN 0034-6861.
  9. ^ Clauser, John F., and Abner Shimony. "Bell's theorem. Experimental tests and implications." Reports on Progress in Physics 41.12 (1978): 1881.
  10. ^ Einstein, Albert. "Letter to E. Schrödinger" [Letter]. Einstein Archives, ID: Call Number 22-47. Hebrew University of Jerusalem.
  11. ^ Jevtic, S.; Rudolph, T (2015). "How Einstein and/or Schrödinger should have discovered Bell's theorem in 1936". Journal of the Optical Society of America B. 32 (4): 50–55. arXiv:1411.4387. Bibcode:2015JOSAB..32A..50J. doi:10.1364/JOSAB.32.000A50. S2CID 55579565.
  12. ^ a b Nielsen, Michael A.; Chuang, Isaac L. (2000). Quantum Computation and Quantum Information. Cambridge University Press. pp. 112–113. ISBN 978-0-521-63503-5.
  13. ^ Wiseman, H.M.; Jones, S.J.; Doherty, A.C. (April 2007). "Steering, Entanglement, Nonlocality, and the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox". Physical Review Letters. 98 (14): 140402. arXiv:quant-ph/0612147. Bibcode:2007PhRvL..98n0402W. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.98.140402. PMID 17501251. S2CID 30078867.
  14. ^ Bohr, N (July 1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 48 (8): 696–702. Bibcode:1935PhRv...48..696B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.48.696.
  15. ^ Furry, W.H. (March 1936). "Remarks on Measurements in Quantum Theory". Physical Review. 49 (6): 476. Bibcode:1936PhRv...49..476F. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.49.476.
  16. ^ von Neumann, J. (1932/1955). In Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik, Springer, Berlin, translated into English by Beyer, R.T., Princeton University Press, Princeton, cited by Baggott, J. (2004) Beyond Measure: Modern physics, philosophy, and the meaning of quantum theory, Oxford University Press, Oxford, ISBN 0-19-852927-9, pages 144–145.
  17. ^ Maudlin, Tim (2011). Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity : Metaphysical Intimations of Modern Physics (3rd ed.). John Wiley & Sons. p. 111. ISBN 9781444331264.
  18. ^ Fine, Arthur (Winter 2017). "The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in Quantum Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 6 December 2018.
  19. ^ a b c Bell, John (1964). "On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox". Physics Physique Физика. 1 (3): 195–200. doi:10.1103/PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.195.
  20. ^ Clauser, John F.; Horne, Michael A.; Shimony, Abner; Holt, Richard A. (October 1969). "Proposed Experiment to Test Local Hidden-Variable Theories". Physical Review Letters. 23 (15): 880–884. Bibcode:1969PhRvL..23..880C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.23.880. S2CID 18467053.
  21. ^ Barrett, J.; Linden, N.; Massar, S.; Pironio, S.; Popescu, S.; Roberts, D. (2005). "Non-local correlations as an information theoretic resource". Physical Review A. 71 (2): 022101. arXiv:quant-ph/0404097. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71b2101B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.71.022101. S2CID 13373771.
  22. ^ Daniel M. Greenberger; Michael A. Horne; Anton Zeilinger (2007), Going beyond Bell's Theorem, arXiv:0712.0921, Bibcode:2007arXiv0712.0921G
  23. ^ Hardy, Lucien (1993). "Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states". Physical Review Letters. 71 (11): 1665–1668. Bibcode:1993PhRvL..71.1665H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.71.1665. PMID 10054467. S2CID 11839894.
  24. ^ Braun, D.; Choi, M.-S. (2008). "Hardy's test versus the Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt test of quantum nonlocality: Fundamental and practical aspects". Physical Review A. 78 (3): 032114. arXiv:0808.0052. Bibcode:2008PhRvA..78c2114B. doi:10.1103/physreva.78.032114. S2CID 119267461.
  25. ^ Nikolić, Hrvoje (2007). "Quantum Mechanics: Myths and Facts". Foundations of Physics. 37 (11): 1563–1611. arXiv:quant-ph/0609163. Bibcode:2007FoPh...37.1563N. doi:10.1007/s10701-007-9176-y. S2CID 9613836.
  26. ^ a b Bancal, Jean-Daniel; Pironio, Stefano; Acin, Antonio; Liang, Yeong-Cherng; Scarani, Valerio; Gisin, Nicolas (2012). "Quantum nonlocality based on finite-speed causal influences leads to superluminal signaling". Nature Physics. 8 (867): 867–870. arXiv:1110.3795. Bibcode:2012NatPh...8..867B. doi:10.1038/nphys2460. S2CID 13922531.
  27. ^ Fritz, Tobias (2012). "Beyond Bell's Theorem: Correlation Scenarios". New J. Phys. 14 (10): 103001. arXiv:1206.5115. Bibcode:2012NJPh...14j3001F. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/14/10/103001. S2CID 4847110.
  28. ^ Wolfe, Elie; Spekkens, R. W.; Fritz, T (2019). "The Inflation Technique for Causal Inference with Latent Variables". Causal Inference. 7 (2). arXiv:1609.00672. doi:10.1515/jci-2017-0020. S2CID 52476882.
  29. ^ Navascués, Miguel; Wolfe, Elie (2020). "The Inflation Technique Completely Solves the Causal Compatibility Problem". Journal of Causal Inference. 8: 70–91. arXiv:1707.06476. doi:10.1515/jci-2018-0008. S2CID 155100141.
  30. ^ Werner, R.F. (1989). "Quantum States with Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen correlations admitting a hidden-variable model". Physical Review A. 40 (8): 4277–4281. Bibcode:1989PhRvA..40.4277W. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.40.4277. PMID 9902666.
  31. ^ Palazuelos, Carlos (2012). "Super-activation of quantum non-locality". Physical Review Letters. 109 (19): 190401. arXiv:1205.3118. Bibcode:2012PhRvL.109s0401P. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.109.190401. PMID 23215363. S2CID 4613963.
  32. ^ Popescu, Sandu (1995). "Bell's Inequalities and Density Matrices: Revealing "Hidden" Nonlocality". Physical Review Letters. 74 (14): 2619–2622. arXiv:quant-ph/9502005. Bibcode:1995PhRvL..74.2619P. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.74.2619. PMID 10057976. S2CID 35478562.
  33. ^ Jonathan, Daniel; Plenio, Martin B. (1999-10-25). "Entanglement-Assisted Local Manipulation of Pure Quantum States". Physical Review Letters. 83 (17): 3566–3569. arXiv:quant-ph/9905071. Bibcode:1999PhRvL..83.3566J. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.83.3566. hdl:10044/1/245. ISSN 0031-9007. S2CID 392419.
  34. ^ Karvonen, Martti (2021-10-13). "Neither Contextuality nor Nonlocality Admits Catalysts". Physical Review Letters. 127 (16): 160402. arXiv:2102.07637. Bibcode:2021PhRvL.127p0402K. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.127.160402. ISSN 0031-9007. PMID 34723585. S2CID 231924967.
  35. ^ Junge, Marius; Palazuelos, C (2011). "Large violation of Bell inequalities with low entanglement". Communications in Mathematical Physics. 306 (3): 695–746. arXiv:1007.3043. Bibcode:2011CMaPh.306..695J. doi:10.1007/s00220-011-1296-8. S2CID 673737.
  36. ^ Thomas Vidick; Stephanie Wehner (2011). "More Non-locality with less Entanglement". Physical Review A. 83 (5): 052310. arXiv:1011.5206. Bibcode:2011PhRvA..83e2310V. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.83.052310. S2CID 6589783.
  37. ^ Yeong-Cherng Liang; Tamás Vértesi; Nicolas Brunner (2010). "Semi-device-independent bounds on entanglement". Physical Review A. 83 (2): 022108. arXiv:1012.1513. Bibcode:2011PhRvA..83b2108L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.83.022108. S2CID 73571969.
  38. ^ Cirel'son, BS (1980). "Quantum generalizations of Bell's inequality". Letters in Mathematical Physics. 4 (2): 93–100. Bibcode:1980LMaPh...4...93C. doi:10.1007/bf00417500. S2CID 120680226.
  39. ^ a b Tsirel'son, B.S. (1987). "Quantum analogues of the Bell inequalities. The case of two spatially separated domains". Journal of Soviet Mathematics. 36 (4): 557–570. doi:10.1007/BF01663472. S2CID 119363229.
  40. ^ a b Slofstra, William (2017). "The set of quantum correlations is not closed". arXiv:1703.08618 [quant-ph].
  41. ^ a b "Bell inequalities and operator algebras". Open quantum problems.
  42. ^ Ji, Zhengfeng; Natarajan, Anand; Vidick, Thomas; Wright, John; Yuen, Henry (2020). "MIP*=RE". arXiv:2001.04383. Bibcode:2020arXiv200104383J. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  43. ^ Castelvecchi, Davide (2020). "How 'spooky' is quantum physics? The answer could be incalculable". Nature. 577 (7791): 461–462. Bibcode:2020Natur.577..461C. doi:10.1038/d41586-020-00120-6. PMID 31965099.
  44. ^ Kalai, Gil (2020-01-17). "Amazing: Zhengfeng Ji, Anand Natarajan, Thomas Vidick, John Wright, and Henry Yuen proved that MIP* = RE and thus disproved Connes 1976 Embedding Conjecture, and provided a negative answer to Tsirelson's problem". Combinatorics and more. Retrieved 2020-03-06.
  45. ^ Barak, Boaz (2020-01-14). "MIP*=RE, disproving Connes embedding conjecture". Windows On Theory. Retrieved 2020-03-06.
  46. ^ Aaronson, Scott (16 January 2020). "MIP*=RE". Shtetl-Optimized. Retrieved 2020-03-06.
  47. ^ Regan, Kenneth W. (2020-01-15). "Halting Is Poly-Time Quantum Provable". Gödel's Lost Letter and P=NP. Retrieved 2020-03-06.
  48. ^ Vidick, Thomas (2020-01-14). "A Masters project". MyCQstate. Retrieved 2020-03-06.
  49. ^ Hartnett, Kevin (4 March 2020). "Landmark Computer Science Proof Cascades Through Physics and Math". Quanta Magazine. Retrieved 2020-03-09.
  50. ^ Junge, M; Navascués, M; Palazuelos, C; Pérez-García, D; Scholz, VB; Werner, RF (2011). "Connes' embedding problem and Tsirelson's problem". J. Math. Phys. 52 (1): 012102. arXiv:1008.1142. Bibcode:2011JMP....52a2102J. doi:10.1063/1.3514538. S2CID 12321570.
  51. ^ Fritz, Tobias (2012). "Tsirelson's problem and Kirchberg's conjecture". Rev. Math. Phys. 24 (5): 1250012. arXiv:1008.1168. Bibcode:2012RvMaP..2450012F. doi:10.1142/S0129055X12500122. S2CID 17162262.
  52. ^ Ozawa, Narutaka (2013). "About the Connes Embedding Conjecture---Algebraic approaches---". Jpn. J. Math. 8: 147–183. doi:10.1007/s11537-013-1280-5. hdl:2433/173118. S2CID 121154563.
  53. ^ Ito, T.; Kobayashi, H.; Matsumoto, K. (2008). "Oracularization and two-prover one-round interactive proofs against nonlocal strategies". arXiv:0810.0693 [quant-ph].
  54. ^ Sikora, Jamie; Varvitsiotis, Antonios (2017). "Linear conic formulations for two-party correlations and values of nonlocal games". Mathematical Programming. 162 (1–2): 431–463. arXiv:1506.07297. doi:10.1007/s10107-016-1049-8. S2CID 8234910.
  55. ^ Navascués, Miguel; Pironio, S; Acín, A (2007). "Bounding the Set of Quantum Correlations". Physical Review Letters. 98 (1): 010401. arXiv:quant-ph/0607119. Bibcode:2007PhRvL..98a0401N. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.98.010401. PMID 17358458. S2CID 41742170.
  56. ^ Popescu, Sandu; Rohrlich, Daniel (1994). "Nonlocality as an axiom". Foundations of Physics. 24 (3): 379–385. Bibcode:1994FoPh...24..379P. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.508.4193. doi:10.1007/BF02058098. S2CID 120333148.
  57. ^ Rastall, Peter (1985). "Locality, Bell's theorem, and quantum mechanics". Foundations of Physics. 15 (9): 963–972. Bibcode:1985FoPh...15..963R. doi:10.1007/bf00739036. S2CID 122298281.
  58. ^ Khalfin, L.A.; Tsirelson, B.S. (1985). Lahti; et al. (eds.). Quantum and quasi-classical analogs of Bell inequalities. Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics. World Sci. Publ. pp. 441–460.
  59. ^ Brassard, G; Buhrman, H; Linden, N; Methot, AA; Tapp, A; Unger, F (2006). "Limit on Nonlocality in Any World in Which Communication Complexity Is Not Trivial". Physical Review Letters. 96 (25): 250401. arXiv:quant-ph/0508042. Bibcode:2006PhRvL..96y0401B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.96.250401. PMID 16907289. S2CID 6135971.
  60. ^ Linden, N.; Popescu, S.; Short, A. J.; Winter, A. (2007). "Quantum Nonlocality and Beyond: Limits from Nonlocal Computation". Physical Review Letters. 99 (18): 180502. arXiv:quant-ph/0610097. Bibcode:2007PhRvL..99r0502L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.99.180502. PMID 17995388.
  61. ^ Pawlowski, M.; Paterek, T.; Kaszlikowski, D.; Scarani, V.; Winter, A.; Zukowski, M. (October 2009). "Information Causality as a Physical Principle". Nature. 461 (7267): 1101–1104. arXiv:0905.2292. Bibcode:2009Natur.461.1101P. doi:10.1038/nature08400. PMID 19847260. S2CID 4428663.
  62. ^ Navascués, M.; H. Wunderlich (2009). "A Glance Beyond the Quantum Model". Proc. R. Soc. A. 466 (2115): 881–890. arXiv:0907.0372. doi:10.1098/rspa.2009.0453.
  63. ^ Fritz, T.; A. B. Sainz; R. Augusiak; J. B. Brask; R. Chaves; A. Leverrier; A. Acín (2013). "Local orthogonality as a multipartite principle for quantum correlations". Nature Communications. 4: 2263. arXiv:1210.3018. Bibcode:2013NatCo...4.2263F. doi:10.1038/ncomms3263. PMID 23948952. S2CID 14759956.
  64. ^ a b Allcock, Jonathan; Nicolas Brunner; Noah Linden; Sandu Popescu; Paul Skrzypczyk; Tamás Vértesi (2009). "Closed sets of non-local correlations". Physical Review A. 80 (6): 062107. arXiv:0908.1496. Bibcode:2009PhRvA..80f2107A. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.80.062107. S2CID 118677048.
  65. ^ a b Navascués, M.; Y. Guryanova; M. J. Hoban; A. Acín (2015). "Almost Quantum Correlations". Nature Communications. 6: 6288. arXiv:1403.4621. Bibcode:2015NatCo...6.6288N. doi:10.1038/ncomms7288. PMID 25697645. S2CID 12810715.
  66. ^ a b c Mayers, Dominic; Yao, Andrew C.-C. (1998). Quantum Cryptography with Imperfect Apparatus. IEEE Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science (FOCS).
  67. ^ Acín, Antonio; Nicolas Gisin; Lluis Masanes (2006). "From Bell's Theorem to Secure Quantum Key Distribution". Physical Review Letters. 97 (12): 120405. arXiv:quant-ph/0510094. Bibcode:2006PhRvL..97l0405A. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.97.120405. PMID 17025944. S2CID 3315286.
  68. ^ Vazirani, Umesh; Vidick, Thomas (2014). "Fully Device-Independent Quantum Key Distribution". Physical Review Letters. 113 (14): 140501. arXiv:1210.1810. Bibcode:2014PhRvL.113n0501V. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.113.140501. PMID 25325625. S2CID 119299119.
  69. ^ Colbeck, Roger (December 2006). Chapter 5. Quantum And Relativistic Protocols For Secure Multi-Party Computation (Thesis), University of Cambridge. arXiv:0911.3814.
  70. ^ Colbeck, Roger; Renner, Renato (2012). "Free randomness can be amplified". Nature Physics. 8 (6): 450–453. arXiv:1105.3195. Bibcode:2012NatPh...8..450C. doi:10.1038/nphys2300. S2CID 118309394.
  71. ^ Santha, Miklos; Vazirani, Umesh V. (1984-10-24). Generating quasi-random sequences from slightly-random sources. Proceedings of the 25th IEEE Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science. University of California. pp. 434–440.
  72. ^ Colbeck, R. & Kent, A. (2011). Private randomness expansion with untrusted devices. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical, 44(9), 095305. doi: 10.1088/1751-8113/44/9/095305
  73. ^ Pironio, S, et al. (2010). "Random numbers certified by Bell's theorem". Nature. 464 (7291): 1021–1024. arXiv:0911.3427. Bibcode:2010Natur.464.1021P. doi:10.1038/nature09008. PMID 20393558. S2CID 4300790.
  74. ^ Tebyanian, H., Zahidy, M., Avesani, M., Stanco, A., Villoresi, P., & Vallone, G. (2021). Semi-device independent randomness generation based on quantum state's indistinguishability. Quantum Science and Technology, 6(4), 045026. doi: 10.1088/2058-9565/ac2047. URL: https://iopscience.iop.org/article/10.1088/2058-9565/ac2047 }
  75. ^ Brunner, Nicolas; Pironio, Stefano; Acín, Antonio; Gisin, Nicolas; Methot, Andre Allan; Scarani, Valerio (2008). "Testing the Hilbert space dimension". Physical Review Letters. 100 (21): 210503. arXiv:0802.0760. Bibcode:2008arXiv0802.0760B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.100.210503. PMID 18518591. S2CID 119256543.
  76. ^ Prakash, Anupam; Sikora, Jamie; Varvitsiotis, Antonios; Wei Zhaohui (2018). "Completely positive semidefinite rank". Mathematical Programming. 171 (1–2): 397–431. arXiv:1604.07199. doi:10.1007/s10107-017-1198-4. S2CID 17885968.
  77. ^ Navascués, Miguel; Vértesi, Tamás (2015). "Bounding the set of finite dimensional quantum correlations". Physical Review Letters. 115 (2): 020501. arXiv:1412.0924. Bibcode:2015PhRvL.115b0501N. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.115.020501. PMID 26207454. S2CID 12226163.
  78. ^ Coladangelo, Andrea; Stark, Jalex (2018). "Unconditional separation of finite and infinite-dimensional quantum correlations". arXiv:1804.05116 [quant-ph].
  79. ^ Pawlowski, Marcin; Brunner, Nicolas (2011). "Semi-device-independent security of one-way quantum key distribution". Physical Review A. 84 (1): 010302(R). arXiv:1103.4105. Bibcode:2011PhRvA..84a0302P. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.84.010302. S2CID 119300029.
  80. ^ Li, Hong-Wei; Yin, Zhen-Qiang; Wu, Yu-Chun; Zou, Xu-Bo; Wang, Shuang; Chen, Wei; Guo, Guang-Can; Han, Zheng-Fu (2011). "Semi-device-independent random-number expansion without entanglement". Physical Review A. 84 (3): 034301. arXiv:1108.1480. Bibcode:2011PhRvA..84c4301L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.84.034301. S2CID 118407749.

Further reading edit

quantum, nonlocality, theoretical, physics, quantum, nonlocality, refers, phenomenon, which, measurement, statistics, multipartite, quantum, system, allow, interpretation, with, local, realism, been, experimentally, verified, under, variety, physical, assumpti. In theoretical physics quantum nonlocality refers to the phenomenon by which the measurement statistics of a multipartite quantum system do not allow an interpretation with local realism Quantum nonlocality has been experimentally verified under a variety of physical assumptions 1 2 3 4 5 Any physical theory that aims at superseding or replacing quantum theory should account for such experiments and therefore cannot fulfill local realism quantum nonlocality is a property of the universe that is independent of our description of nature Quantum nonlocality does not allow for faster than light communication 6 and hence is compatible with special relativity and its universal speed limit of objects Thus quantum theory is local in the strict sense defined by special relativity and as such the term quantum nonlocality is sometimes considered a misnomer citation needed Still it prompts many of the foundational discussions concerning quantum theory citation needed Contents 1 History 1 1 Einstein Podolsky and Rosen 1 2 Bell inequality 2 Possibilistic nonlocality 3 Nonlocal hidden variable models with a finite propagation speed 4 Analogs of Bell s theorem in more complicated causal structures 5 Entanglement and nonlocality 6 Quantum correlations 6 1 The sets of quantum correlations and Tsirelson s problem 6 2 Characterization of quantum correlations 6 3 The physics of supra quantum correlations 7 Device independent protocols 7 1 Device independent quantum key distribution 7 2 Device independent randomness certification expansion and amplification 7 3 Self testing 7 4 Dimension witnesses 8 See also 9 References 10 Further readingHistory editEinstein Podolsky and Rosen edit Main article EPR paradox In the 1935 EPR paper 7 Albert Einstein Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen described two spatially separated particles which have both perfectly correlated positions and momenta 8 as a direct consequence of quantum theory They intended to use the classical principle of locality to challenge the idea that the quantum wavefunction was a complete description of reality but instead they sparked a debate on the nature of reality 9 Afterwards Einstein presented a variant of these ideas in a letter to Erwin Schrodinger 10 which is the version that is presented here The state and notation used here are more modern and akin to David Bohm s take on EPR 11 The quantum state of the two particles prior to measurement can be written as ps A B 1 2 0 A 1 B 1 A 0 B 1 2 A B A B displaystyle left psi AB right rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 left left 0 right rangle A left 1 right rangle B left 1 right rangle A left 0 right rangle B right frac 1 sqrt 2 left left right rangle A left right rangle B left right rangle A left right rangle B right nbsp where 1 2 0 1 textstyle left pm right rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 left left 0 right rangle pm left 1 right rangle right nbsp 12 Here subscripts A and B distinguish the two particles though it is more convenient and usual to refer to these particles as being in the possession of two experimentalists called Alice and Bob The rules of quantum theory give predictions for the outcomes of measurements performed by the experimentalists Alice for example will measure her particle to be spin up in an average of fifty percent of measurements However according to the Copenhagen interpretation Alice s measurement causes the state of the two particles to collapse so that if Alice performs a measurement of spin in the z direction that is with respect to the basis 0 A 1 A displaystyle left 0 right rangle A left 1 right rangle A nbsp then Bob s system will be left in one of the states 0 B 1 B displaystyle left 0 right rangle B left 1 right rangle B nbsp Likewise if Alice performs a measurement of spin in the x direction that is with respect to the basis A A displaystyle left right rangle A left right rangle A nbsp then Bob s system will be left in one of the states B B displaystyle left right rangle B left right rangle B nbsp Schrodinger referred to this phenomenon as steering 13 This steering occurs in such a way that no signal can be sent by performing such a state update quantum nonlocality cannot be used to send messages instantaneously and is therefore not in direct conflict with causality concerns in special relativity 12 In the Copenhagen view of this experiment Alice s measurement and particularly her measurement choice has a direct effect on Bob s state However under the assumption of locality actions on Alice s system do not affect the true or ontic state of Bob s system We see that the ontic state of Bob s system must be compatible with one of the quantum states B displaystyle left uparrow right rangle B nbsp or B displaystyle left downarrow right rangle B nbsp since Alice can make a measurement that concludes with one of those states being the quantum description of his system At the same time it must also be compatible with one of the quantum states B displaystyle left leftarrow right rangle B nbsp or B displaystyle left rightarrow right rangle B nbsp for the same reason Therefore the ontic state of Bob s system must be compatible with at least two quantum states the quantum state is therefore not a complete descriptor of his system Einstein Podolsky and Rosen saw this as evidence of the incompleteness of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory since the wavefunction is explicitly not a complete description of a quantum system under this assumption of locality Their paper concludes 7 While we have thus shown that the wave function does not provide a complete description of the physical reality we left open the question of whether or not such a description exists We believe however that such a theory is possible Although various authors most notably Niels Bohr criticised the ambiguous terminology of the EPR paper 14 15 the thought experiment nevertheless generated a great deal of interest Their notion of a complete description was later formalised by the suggestion of hidden variables that determine the statistics of measurement results but to which an observer does not have access 16 Bohmian mechanics provides such a completion of quantum mechanics with the introduction of hidden variables however the theory is explicitly nonlocal 17 The interpretation therefore does not give an answer to Einstein s question which was whether or not a complete description of quantum mechanics could be given in terms of local hidden variables in keeping with the Principle of Local Action 18 Bell inequality edit See also Bell s theorem and Bell test experiments In 1964 John Bell answered Einstein s question by showing that such local hidden variables can never reproduce the full range of statistical outcomes predicted by quantum theory 19 Bell showed that a local hidden variable hypothesis leads to restrictions on the strength of correlations of measurement results If the Bell inequalities are violated experimentally as predicted by quantum mechanics then reality cannot be described by local hidden variables and the mystery of quantum nonlocal causation remains However Bell notes that the non local hidden variable model of Bohm are different 19 This grossly nonlocal structure is characteristic of any such theory which reproduces exactly the quantum mechanical predictions Clauser Horne Shimony and Holt CHSH reformulated these inequalities in a manner that was more conducive to experimental testing see CHSH inequality 20 In the scenario proposed by Bell a Bell scenario two experimentalists Alice and Bob conduct experiments in separate labs At each run Alice Bob conducts an experiment x displaystyle x nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp in her his lab obtaining outcome a displaystyle a nbsp b displaystyle b nbsp If Alice and Bob repeat their experiments several times then they can estimate the probabilities P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp namely the probability that Alice and Bob respectively observe the results a b displaystyle a b nbsp when they respectively conduct the experiments x y In the following each such set of probabilities P a b x y a b x y displaystyle P a b x y a b x y nbsp will be denoted by just P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp In the quantum nonlocality slang P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp is termed a box 21 Bell formalized the idea of a hidden variable by introducing the parameter l displaystyle lambda nbsp to locally characterize measurement results on each system 19 It is a matter of indifference whether l denotes a single variable or a set and whether the variables are discrete or continuous However it is equivalent and more intuitive to think of l displaystyle lambda nbsp as a local strategy or message that occurs with some probability r l displaystyle rho lambda nbsp when Alice and Bob reboot their experimental setup Bell s assumption of local causality then stipulates that each local strategy defines the distributions of independent outcomes if Alice conducts experiment x and Bob conducts experiment y displaystyle y nbsp P a b x y l A l B P A a x l A P B b y l B displaystyle P a b x y lambda A lambda B P A a x lambda A P B b y lambda B nbsp Here P A a x l A displaystyle P A a x lambda A nbsp P B b y l B displaystyle P B b y lambda B nbsp denotes the probability that Alice Bob obtains the result a displaystyle a nbsp b displaystyle b nbsp when she he conducts experiment x displaystyle x nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp and the local variable describing her his experiment has value l A displaystyle lambda A nbsp l B displaystyle lambda B nbsp Suppose that l A l B displaystyle lambda A lambda B nbsp can take values from some set L displaystyle Lambda nbsp If each pair of values l A l B L displaystyle lambda A lambda B in Lambda nbsp has an associated probability r l A l B displaystyle rho lambda A lambda B nbsp of being selected shared randomness is allowed i e l A l B displaystyle lambda A lambda B nbsp can be correlated then one can average over this distribution to obtain a formula for the joint probability of each measurement result P a b x y l A l B L r l A l B P A a x l A P B b y l B displaystyle P a b x y sum lambda A lambda B in Lambda rho lambda A lambda B P A a x lambda A P B b y lambda B nbsp A box admitting such a decomposition is called a Bell local or a classical box Fixing the number of possible values which a b x y displaystyle a b x y nbsp can each take one can represent each box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp as a finite vector with entries P a b x y a b x y displaystyle left P a b x y right a b x y nbsp In that representation the set of all classical boxes forms a convex polytope In the Bell scenario studied by CHSH where a b x y displaystyle a b x y nbsp can take values within 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 nbsp any Bell local box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp must satisfy the CHSH inequality S C H S H E 0 0 E 1 0 E 0 1 E 1 1 2 displaystyle S rm CHSH equiv E 0 0 E 1 0 E 0 1 E 1 1 leq 2 nbsp whereE x y a b 0 1 1 a b P a b x y displaystyle E x y equiv sum a b 0 1 1 a b P a b x y nbsp The above considerations apply to model a quantum experiment Consider two parties conducting local polarization measurements on a bipartite photonic state The measurement result for the polarization of a photon can take one of two values informally whether the photon is polarized in that direction or in the orthogonal direction If each party is allowed to choose between just two different polarization directions the experiment fits within the CHSH scenario As noted by CHSH there exist a quantum state and polarization directions which generate a box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp with S C H S H displaystyle S rm CHSH nbsp equal to 2 2 2 828 displaystyle 2 sqrt 2 approx 2 828 nbsp This demonstrates an explicit way in which a theory with ontological states that are local with local measurements and only local actions cannot match the probabilistic predictions of quantum theory disproving Einstein s hypothesis Experimentalists such as Alain Aspect have verified the quantum violation of the CHSH inequality 1 as well as other formulations of Bell s inequality to invalidate the local hidden variables hypothesis and confirm that reality is indeed nonlocal in the EPR sense Possibilistic nonlocality editBell s demonstration is probabilistic in the sense that it shows that the precise probabilities predicted by quantum mechanics for some entangled scenarios cannot be met by a local hidden variable theory For short here and henceforth local theory means local hidden variables theory However quantum mechanics permits an even stronger violation of local theories a possibilistic one in which local theories cannot even agree with quantum mechanics on which events are possible or impossible in an entangled scenario The first proof of this kind was due to Daniel Greenberger Michael Horne and Anton Zeilinger in 1993 22 The state involved is often called the GHZ state In 1993 Lucien Hardy demonstrated a logical proof of quantum nonlocality that like the GHZ proof is a possibilistic proof 23 24 25 It starts with the observation that the state ps displaystyle left psi right rangle nbsp defined below can be written in a few suggestive ways ps 1 3 00 01 10 1 3 2 0 1 2 1 1 1 3 2 0 1 2 1 1 displaystyle left psi right rangle frac 1 sqrt 3 left left 00 right rangle left 01 right rangle left 10 right rangle right frac 1 sqrt 3 left sqrt 2 left 0 right rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 left left 1 right rangle left 1 right rangle right right frac 1 sqrt 3 left sqrt 2 left 0 right rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 left left 1 right rangle left 1 right rangle right right nbsp where as above 1 2 0 1 displaystyle pm rangle tfrac 1 sqrt 2 left 0 right rangle pm left 1 right rangle nbsp The experiment consists of this entangled state being shared between two experimenters each of whom has the ability to measure either with respect to the basis 0 1 displaystyle left 0 right rangle left 1 right rangle nbsp or displaystyle left right rangle left right rangle nbsp We see that if they each measure with respect to 0 1 displaystyle left 0 right rangle left 1 right rangle nbsp then they never see the outcome 11 displaystyle left 11 right rangle nbsp If one measures with respect to 0 1 displaystyle left 0 right rangle left 1 right rangle nbsp and the other displaystyle left right rangle left right rangle nbsp they never see the outcomes 0 displaystyle left 0 right rangle nbsp 0 displaystyle left 0 right rangle nbsp However sometimes they see the outcome displaystyle left right rangle nbsp when measuring with respect to displaystyle left right rangle left right rangle nbsp since ps 1 2 3 0 displaystyle langle psi rangle tfrac 1 2 sqrt 3 neq 0 nbsp This leads to the paradox having the outcome displaystyle rangle nbsp we conclude that if one of the experimenters had measured with respect to the 0 1 displaystyle left 0 right rangle left 1 right rangle nbsp basis instead the outcome must have been 1 displaystyle 1 rangle nbsp or 1 displaystyle 1 rangle nbsp since 0 displaystyle 0 rangle nbsp and 0 displaystyle 0 rangle nbsp are impossible But then if they had both measured with respect to the 0 1 displaystyle left 0 right rangle left 1 right rangle nbsp basis by locality the result must have been 11 displaystyle left 11 right rangle nbsp which is also impossible Nonlocal hidden variable models with a finite propagation speed editThe work of Bancal et al 26 generalizes Bell s result by proving that correlations achievable in quantum theory are also incompatible with a large class of superluminal hidden variable models In this framework faster than light signaling is precluded However the choice of settings of one party can influence hidden variables at another party s distant location if there is enough time for a superluminal influence of finite but otherwise unknown speed to propagate from one point to the other In this scenario any bipartite experiment revealing Bell nonlocality can just provide lower bounds on the hidden influence s propagation speed Quantum experiments with three or more parties can nonetheless disprove all such non local hidden variable models 26 Analogs of Bell s theorem in more complicated causal structures edit nbsp A simple Bayesian network Rain influences whether the sprinkler is activated and both rain and the sprinkler influence whether the grass is wet The random variables measured in a general experiment can depend on each other in complicated ways In the field of causal inference such dependencies are represented via Bayesian networks directed acyclic graphs where each node represents a variable and an edge from a variable to another signifies that the former influences the latter and not otherwise see the figure In a standard bipartite Bell experiment Alice s Bob s setting x displaystyle x nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp together with her his local variable l A displaystyle lambda A nbsp l B displaystyle lambda B nbsp influence her his local outcome a displaystyle a nbsp b displaystyle b nbsp Bell s theorem can thus be interpreted as a separation between the quantum and classical predictions in a type of causal structures with just one hidden node l A l B displaystyle lambda A lambda B nbsp Similar separations have been established in other types of causal structures 27 The characterization of the boundaries for classical correlations in such extended Bell scenarios is challenging but there exist complete practical computational methods to achieve it 28 29 Entanglement and nonlocality editSee also Quantum entanglement Quantum nonlocality is sometimes understood as being equivalent to entanglement However this is not the case Quantum entanglement can be defined only within the formalism of quantum mechanics i e it is a model dependent property In contrast nonlocality refers to the impossibility of a description of observed statistics in terms of a local hidden variable model so it is independent of the physical model used to describe the experiment It is true that for any pure entangled state there exists a choice of measurements that produce Bell nonlocal correlations but the situation is more complex for mixed states While any Bell nonlocal state must be entangled there exist mixed entangled states which do not produce Bell nonlocal correlations 30 although operating on several copies of some of such states 31 or carrying out local post selections 32 it is possible to witness nonlocal effects Moreover while there are catalysts for entanglement 33 there are none for nonlocality 34 Finally reasonably simple examples of Bell inequalities have been found for which the quantum state giving the largest violation is never a maximally entangled state showing that entanglement is in some sense not even proportional to nonlocality 35 36 37 Quantum correlations editAs shown the statistics achievable by two or more parties conducting experiments in a classical system are constrained in a non trivial way Analogously the statistics achievable by separate observers in a quantum theory also happen to be restricted The first derivation of a non trivial statistical limit on the set of quantum correlations due to B Tsirelson 38 is known as Tsirelson s bound Consider the CHSH Bell scenario detailed before but this time assume that in their experiments Alice and Bob are preparing and measuring quantum systems In that case the CHSH parameter can be shown to be bounded by 2 2 C H S H 2 2 displaystyle 2 sqrt 2 leq mathrm CHSH leq 2 sqrt 2 nbsp The sets of quantum correlations and Tsirelson s problem edit Mathematically a box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp admits a quantum realization if and only if there exists a pair of Hilbert spaces H A H B displaystyle H A H B nbsp a normalized vector ps H A H B displaystyle left psi right rangle in H A otimes H B nbsp and projection operators E a x H A H A F b y H B H B displaystyle E a x H A to H A F b y H B to H B nbsp such that For all x y displaystyle x y nbsp the sets E a x a F b y b displaystyle E a x a F b y b nbsp represent complete measurements Namely a E a x I A b F b y I B displaystyle sum a E a x mathbb I A sum b F b y mathbb I B nbsp P a b x y ps E a x F b y ps displaystyle P a b x y left langle psi right E a x otimes F b y left psi right rangle nbsp for all a b x y displaystyle a b x y nbsp In the following the set of such boxes will be called Q displaystyle Q nbsp Contrary to the classical set of correlations when viewed in probability space Q displaystyle Q nbsp is not a polytope On the contrary it contains both straight and curved boundaries 39 In addition Q displaystyle Q nbsp is not closed 40 this means that there exist boxes P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp which can be arbitrarily well approximated by quantum systems but are themselves not quantum In the above definition the space like separation of the two parties conducting the Bell experiment was modeled by imposing that their associated operator algebras act on different factors H A H B displaystyle H A H B nbsp of the overall Hilbert space H H A H B displaystyle H H A otimes H B nbsp describing the experiment Alternatively one could model space like separation by imposing that these two algebras commute This leads to a different definition P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp admits a field quantum realization if and only if there exists a Hilbert space H displaystyle H nbsp a normalized vector ps H displaystyle left psi right rangle in H nbsp and projection operators E a x H H F b y H H displaystyle E a x H to H F b y H to H nbsp such that For all x y displaystyle x y nbsp the sets E a x a F b y b displaystyle E a x a F b y b nbsp represent complete measurements Namely a E a x I b F b y I displaystyle sum a E a x mathbb I sum b F b y mathbb I nbsp P a b x y ps E a x F b y ps displaystyle P a b x y left langle psi right E a x F b y left psi right rangle nbsp for all a b x y displaystyle a b x y nbsp E a x F b y 0 displaystyle E a x F b y 0 nbsp for all a b x y displaystyle a b x y nbsp Call Q c displaystyle Q c nbsp the set of all such correlations P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp How does this new set relate to the more conventional Q displaystyle Q nbsp defined above It can be proven that Q c displaystyle Q c nbsp is closed Moreover Q Q c displaystyle bar Q subseteq Q c nbsp where Q displaystyle bar Q nbsp denotes the closure of Q displaystyle Q nbsp Tsirelson s problem 41 consists in deciding whether the inclusion relation Q Q c displaystyle bar Q subseteq Q c nbsp is strict i e whether or not Q Q c displaystyle bar Q Q c nbsp This problem only appears in infinite dimensions when the Hilbert space H displaystyle H nbsp in the definition of Q c displaystyle Q c nbsp is constrained to be finite dimensional the closure of the corresponding set equals Q displaystyle bar Q nbsp 41 In January 2020 Ji Natarajan Vidick Wright and Yuen claimed a result in quantum complexity theory 42 that would imply that Q Q c displaystyle bar Q neq Q c nbsp thus solving Tsirelson s problem 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 Tsirelson s problem can be shown equivalent to Connes embedding problem 50 51 52 a famous conjecture in the theory of operator algebras Characterization of quantum correlations edit Since the dimensions of H A displaystyle H A nbsp and H B displaystyle H B nbsp are in principle unbounded determining whether a given box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp admits a quantum realization is a complicated problem In fact the dual problem of establishing whether a quantum box can have a perfect score at a non local game is known to be undecidable 40 Moreover the problem of deciding whether P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp can be approximated by a quantum system with precision 1 poly X Y displaystyle 1 operatorname poly X Y nbsp is NP hard 53 Characterizing quantum boxes is equivalent to characterizing the cone of completely positive semidefinite matrices under a set of linear constraints 54 For small fixed dimensions d A d B displaystyle d A d B nbsp one can explore using variational methods whether P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp can be realized in a bipartite quantum system H A H B displaystyle H A otimes H B nbsp with dim H A d A displaystyle dim H A d A nbsp dim H B d B displaystyle dim H B d B nbsp That method however can just be used to prove the realizability of P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp and not its unrealizability with quantum systems To prove unrealizability the most known method is the Navascues Pironio Acin NPA hierarchy 55 This is an infinite decreasing sequence of sets of correlations Q 1 Q 2 Q 3 displaystyle Q 1 supset Q 2 supset Q 3 supset nbsp with the properties If P a b x y Q c displaystyle P a b x y in Q c nbsp then P a b x y Q k displaystyle P a b x y in Q k nbsp for all k displaystyle k nbsp If P a b x y Q c displaystyle P a b x y not in Q c nbsp then there exists k displaystyle k nbsp such that P a b x y Q k displaystyle P a b x y not in Q k nbsp For any k displaystyle k nbsp deciding whether P a b x y Q k displaystyle P a b x y in Q k nbsp can be cast as a semidefinite program The NPA hierarchy thus provides a computational characterization not of Q displaystyle Q nbsp but of Q c displaystyle Q c nbsp If Tsirelson s problem is solved in the affirmative namely Q Q c displaystyle bar Q Q c nbsp then the above two methods would provide a practical characterization of Q displaystyle bar Q nbsp If on the contrary Q Q c displaystyle bar Q not Q c nbsp then a new method to detect the non realizability of the correlations in Q c Q displaystyle Q c bar Q nbsp is needed The physics of supra quantum correlations edit The works listed above describe what the quantum set of correlations looks like but they do not explain why Are quantum correlations unavoidable even in post quantum physical theories or on the contrary could there exist correlations outside Q displaystyle bar Q nbsp which nonetheless do not lead to any unphysical operational behavior In their seminal 1994 paper Popescu and Rohrlich explore whether quantum correlations can be explained by appealing to relativistic causality alone 56 Namely whether any hypothetical box P a b x y Q displaystyle P a b x y not in bar Q nbsp would allow building a device capable of transmitting information faster than the speed of light At the level of correlations between two parties Einstein s causality translates in the requirement that Alice s measurement choice should not affect Bob s statistics and vice versa Otherwise Alice Bob could signal Bob Alice instantaneously by choosing her his measurement setting x displaystyle x nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp appropriately Mathematically Popescu and Rohrlich s no signalling conditions are a P a b x y a P a b x y P B b y displaystyle sum a P a b x y sum a P a b x prime y P B b y nbsp b P a b x y b P a b x y P A a x displaystyle sum b P a b x y sum b P a b x y prime P A a x nbsp Like the set of classical boxes when represented in probability space the set of no signalling boxes forms a polytope Popescu and Rohrlich identified a box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp that while complying with the no signalling conditions violates Tsirelson s bound and is thus unrealizable in quantum physics Dubbed the PR box it can be written as P a b x y 1 2 d x y a b displaystyle P a b x y frac 1 2 delta xy a oplus b nbsp Here a b x y displaystyle a b x y nbsp take values in 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 nbsp and a b displaystyle a oplus b nbsp denotes the sum modulo two It can be verified that the CHSH value of this box is 4 as opposed to the Tsirelson bound of 2 2 2 828 displaystyle 2 sqrt 2 approx 2 828 nbsp This box had been identified earlier by Rastall 57 and Khalfin and Tsirelson 58 In view of this mismatch Popescu and Rohrlich pose the problem of identifying a physical principle stronger than the no signalling conditions that allows deriving the set of quantum correlations Several proposals followed Non trivial communication complexity NTCC 59 This principle stipulates that nonlocal correlations should not be so strong as to allow two parties to solve all 1 way communication problems with some probability p gt 1 2 displaystyle p gt 1 2 nbsp using just one bit of communication It can be proven that any box violating Tsirelson s bound by more than 2 2 2 3 1 0 4377 displaystyle 2 sqrt 2 left frac 2 sqrt 3 1 right approx 0 4377 nbsp is incompatible with NTCC No Advantage for Nonlocal Computation NANLC 60 The following scenario is considered given a function f 0 1 n 1 displaystyle f 0 1 n to 1 nbsp two parties are distributed the strings of n displaystyle n nbsp bits x y displaystyle x y nbsp and asked to output the bits a b displaystyle a b nbsp so that a b displaystyle a oplus b nbsp is a good guess for f x y displaystyle f x oplus y nbsp The principle of NANLC states that non local boxes should not give the two parties any advantage to play this game It is proven that any box violating Tsirelson s bound would provide such an advantage Information Causality IC 61 The starting point is a bipartite communication scenario where one of the parts Alice is handed a random string x displaystyle x nbsp of n displaystyle n nbsp bits The second part Bob receives a random number k 1 n displaystyle k in 1 n nbsp Their goal is to transmit Bob the bit x k displaystyle x k nbsp for which purpose Alice is allowed to transmit Bob s displaystyle s nbsp bits The principle of IC states that the sum over k displaystyle k nbsp of the mutual information between Alice s bit and Bob s guess cannot exceed the number s displaystyle s nbsp of bits transmitted by Alice It is shown that any box violating Tsirelson s bound would allow two parties to violate IC Macroscopic Locality ML 62 In the considered setup two separate parties conduct extensive low resolution measurements over a large number of independently prepared pairs of correlated particles ML states that any such macroscopic experiment must admit a local hidden variable model It is proven that any microscopic experiment capable of violating Tsirelson s bound would also violate standard Bell nonlocality when brought to the macroscopic scale Besides Tsirelson s bound the principle of ML fully recovers the set of all two point quantum correlators Local Orthogonality LO 63 This principle applies to multipartite Bell scenarios where n displaystyle n nbsp parties respectively conduct experiments x 1 x n displaystyle x 1 x n nbsp in their local labs They respectively obtain the outcomes a 1 a n displaystyle a 1 a n nbsp The pair of vectors a x displaystyle bar a bar x nbsp is called an event Two events a x displaystyle bar a bar x nbsp a x displaystyle bar a prime bar x prime nbsp are said to be locally orthogonal if there exists k displaystyle k nbsp such that x k x k displaystyle x k x k prime nbsp and a k a k displaystyle a k not a k prime nbsp The principle of LO states that for any multipartite box the sum of the probabilities of any set of pair wise locally orthogonal events cannot exceed 1 It is proven that any bipartite box violating Tsirelson s bound by an amount of 0 052 displaystyle 0 052 nbsp violates LO All these principles can be experimentally falsified under the assumption that we can decide if two or more events are space like separated This sets this research program aside from the axiomatic reconstruction of quantum mechanics via Generalized Probabilistic Theories The works above rely on the implicit assumption that any physical set of correlations must be closed under wirings 64 This means that any effective box built by combining the inputs and outputs of a number of boxes within the considered set must also belong to the set Closure under wirings does not seem to enforce any limit on the maximum value of CHSH However it is not a void principle on the contrary in 64 it is shown that many simple intuitive families of sets of correlations in probability space happen to violate it Originally it was unknown whether any of these principles or a subset thereof was strong enough to derive all the constraints defining Q displaystyle bar Q nbsp This state of affairs continued for some years until the construction of the almost quantum set Q displaystyle tilde Q nbsp 65 Q displaystyle tilde Q nbsp is a set of correlations that is closed under wirings and can be characterized via semidefinite programming It contains all correlations in Q c Q displaystyle Q c supset bar Q nbsp but also some non quantum boxes P a b x y Q c displaystyle P a b x y not in Q c nbsp Remarkably all boxes within the almost quantum set are shown to be compatible with the principles of NTCC NANLC ML and LO There is also numerical evidence that almost quantum boxes also comply with IC It seems therefore that even when the above principles are taken together they do not suffice to single out the quantum set in the simplest Bell scenario of two parties two inputs and two outputs 65 Device independent protocols editNonlocality can be exploited to conduct quantum information tasks which do not rely on the knowledge of the inner workings of the prepare and measurement apparatuses involved in the experiment The security or reliability of any such protocol just depends on the strength of the experimentally measured correlations P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp These protocols are termed device independent Device independent quantum key distribution edit Main article Device independent quantum cryptography The first device independent protocol proposed was device independent quantum key distribution QKD 66 In this primitive two distant parties Alice and Bob are distributed an entangled quantum state that they probe thus obtaining the statistics P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp Based on how non local the box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp happens to be Alice and Bob estimate how much knowledge an external quantum adversary Eve the eavesdropper could possess on the value of Alice and Bob s outputs This estimation allows them to devise a reconciliation protocol at the end of which Alice and Bob share a perfectly correlated one time pad of which Eve has no information whatsoever The one time pad can then be used to transmit a secret message through a public channel Although the first security analyses on device independent QKD relied on Eve carrying out a specific family of attacks 67 all such protocols have been recently proven unconditionally secure 68 Device independent randomness certification expansion and amplification edit Nonlocality can be used to certify that the outcomes of one of the parties in a Bell experiment are partially unknown to an external adversary By feeding a partially random seed to several non local boxes and after processing the outputs one can end up with a longer potentially unbounded string of comparable randomness 69 or with a shorter but more random string 70 This last primitive can be proven impossible in a classical setting 71 Device independent DI randomness certification expansion and amplification are techniques used to generate high quality random numbers that are secure against any potential attacks on the underlying devices used to generate random numbers These techniques have critical applications in cryptography where high quality random numbers are essential for ensuring the security of cryptographic protocols Randomness certification is the process of verifying that the output of a random number generator is truly random and has not been tampered with by an adversary DI randomness certification does this verification without making assumptions about the underlying devices that generate random numbers Instead randomness is certified by observing correlations between the outputs of different devices that are generated using the same physical process Recent research has demonstrated the feasibility of DI randomness certification using entangled quantum systems such as photons or electrons Randomness expansion is taking a small amount of initial random seed and expanding it into a much larger sequence of random numbers In DI randomness expansion the expansion is done using measurements of quantum systems that are prepared in a highly entangled state The security of the expansion is guaranteed by the laws of quantum mechanics which make it impossible for an adversary to predict the expansion output Recent research has shown that DI randomness expansion can be achieved using entangled photon pairs and measurement devices that violate a Bell inequality 72 Randomness amplification is the process of taking a small amount of initial random seed and increasing its randomness by using a cryptographic algorithm In DI randomness amplification this process is done using entanglement properties and quantum mechanics The security of the amplification is guaranteed by the fact that any attempt by an adversary to manipulate the algorithm s output will inevitably introduce errors that can be detected and corrected Recent research has demonstrated the feasibility of DI randomness amplification using quantum entanglement and the violation of a Bell inequality 73 DI randomness certification expansion and amplification are powerful techniques for generating high quality random numbers that are secure against any potential attacks on the underlying devices used to generate random numbers These techniques have critical applications in cryptography and are likely to become increasingly crucial as quantum computing technology advances In addition a milder approach called semi DI exists where random numbers can be generated with some assumptions on the working principle of the devices environment dimension energy etc in which it benefits from ease of implementation and high generation rate 74 Self testing edit Sometimes the box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp shared by Alice and Bob is such that it only admits a unique quantum realization This means that there exist measurement operators E a x F b y displaystyle E a x F b y nbsp and a quantum state ps displaystyle left psi right rangle nbsp giving rise to P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp such that any other physical realization E a x F b y ps displaystyle tilde E a x tilde F b y left tilde psi right rangle nbsp of P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp is connected to E a x F b y ps displaystyle E a x F b y left psi right rangle nbsp via local unitary transformations This phenomenon that can be interpreted as an instance of device independent quantum tomography was first pointed out by Tsirelson 39 and named self testing by Mayers and Yao 66 Self testing is known to be robust against systematic noise i e if the experimentally measured statistics are close enough to P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp one can still determine the underlying state and measurement operators up to error bars 66 Dimension witnesses edit The degree of non locality of a quantum box P a b x y displaystyle P a b x y nbsp can also provide lower bounds on the Hilbert space dimension of the local systems accessible to Alice and Bob 75 This problem is equivalent to deciding the existence of a matrix with low completely positive semidefinite rank 76 Finding lower bounds on the Hilbert space dimension based on statistics happens to be a hard task and current general methods only provide very low estimates 77 However a Bell scenario with five inputs and three outputs suffices to provide arbitrarily high lower bounds on the underlying Hilbert space dimension 78 Quantum communication protocols which assume a knowledge of the local dimension of Alice and Bob s systems but otherwise do not make claims on the mathematical description of the preparation and measuring devices involved are termed semi device independent protocols Currently there exist semi device independent protocols for quantum key distribution 79 and randomness expansion 80 See also editAction at a distance Popper s experiment Quantum pseudo telepathy Quantum contextuality Quantum foundationsReferences edit a b Aspect Alain Dalibard Jean Roger Gerard 1982 12 20 Experimental Test of Bell s Inequalities Using Time Varying Analyzers Physical Review Letters 49 25 1804 1807 Bibcode 1982PhRvL 49 1804A doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 49 1804 Rowe MA et al February 2001 Experimental violation of a Bell s Inequality with efficient detection Nature 409 6822 791 794 Bibcode 2001Natur 409 791R doi 10 1038 35057215 hdl 2027 42 62731 PMID 11236986 S2CID 205014115 Hensen B et al October 2015 Loophole free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1 3 kilometres Nature 526 7575 682 686 arXiv 1508 05949 Bibcode 2015Natur 526 682H doi 10 1038 nature15759 PMID 26503041 S2CID 205246446 Giustina M et al December 2015 Significant Loophole Free Test of Bell s Theorem with Entangled Photons Physical Review Letters 115 25 250401 arXiv 1511 03190 Bibcode 2015PhRvL 115y0401G doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 115 250401 PMID 26722905 S2CID 13789503 Shalm LK et al December 2015 Strong Loophole Free Test of Local Realism Physical Review Letters 115 25 250402 arXiv 1511 03189 Bibcode 2015PhRvL 115y0402S doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 115 250402 PMC 5815856 PMID 26722906 Ghirardi G C Rimini A Weber T March 1980 A general argument against superluminal transmission through the quantum mechanical measurement process Lettere al Nuovo Cimento 27 10 293 298 doi 10 1007 BF02817189 S2CID 121145494 a b Einstein A Podolsky B Rosen N 1935 05 15 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete Physical Review 47 10 777 780 doi 10 1103 PhysRev 47 777 ISSN 0031 899X Reid M D Drummond P D Bowen W P Cavalcanti E G Lam P K Bachor H A Andersen U L Leuchs G 2009 12 10 Colloquium The Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox From concepts to applications Reviews of Modern Physics 81 4 1727 1751 doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 81 1727 hdl 10072 37941 ISSN 0034 6861 Clauser John F and Abner Shimony Bell s theorem Experimental tests and implications Reports on Progress in Physics 41 12 1978 1881 Einstein Albert Letter to E Schrodinger Letter Einstein Archives ID Call Number 22 47 Hebrew University of Jerusalem Jevtic S Rudolph T 2015 How Einstein and or Schrodinger should have discovered Bell s theorem in 1936 Journal of the Optical Society of America B 32 4 50 55 arXiv 1411 4387 Bibcode 2015JOSAB 32A 50J doi 10 1364 JOSAB 32 000A50 S2CID 55579565 a b Nielsen Michael A Chuang Isaac L 2000 Quantum Computation and Quantum Information Cambridge University Press pp 112 113 ISBN 978 0 521 63503 5 Wiseman H M Jones S J Doherty A C April 2007 Steering Entanglement Nonlocality and the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox Physical Review Letters 98 14 140402 arXiv quant ph 0612147 Bibcode 2007PhRvL 98n0402W doi 10 1103 physrevlett 98 140402 PMID 17501251 S2CID 30078867 Bohr N July 1935 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete Physical Review 48 8 696 702 Bibcode 1935PhRv 48 696B doi 10 1103 PhysRev 48 696 Furry W H March 1936 Remarks on Measurements in Quantum Theory Physical Review 49 6 476 Bibcode 1936PhRv 49 476F doi 10 1103 PhysRev 49 476 von Neumann J 1932 1955 In Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik Springer Berlin translated into English by Beyer R T Princeton University Press Princeton cited by Baggott J 2004 Beyond Measure Modern physics philosophy and the meaning of quantum theory Oxford University Press Oxford ISBN 0 19 852927 9 pages 144 145 Maudlin Tim 2011 Quantum Non Locality and Relativity Metaphysical Intimations of Modern Physics 3rd ed John Wiley amp Sons p 111 ISBN 9781444331264 Fine Arthur Winter 2017 The Einstein Podolsky Rosen Argument in Quantum Theory In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 6 December 2018 a b c Bell John 1964 On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox Physics Physique Fizika 1 3 195 200 doi 10 1103 PhysicsPhysiqueFizika 1 195 Clauser John F Horne Michael A Shimony Abner Holt Richard A October 1969 Proposed Experiment to Test Local Hidden Variable Theories Physical Review Letters 23 15 880 884 Bibcode 1969PhRvL 23 880C doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 23 880 S2CID 18467053 Barrett J Linden N Massar S Pironio S Popescu S Roberts D 2005 Non local correlations as an information theoretic resource Physical Review A 71 2 022101 arXiv quant ph 0404097 Bibcode 2005PhRvA 71b2101B doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 71 022101 S2CID 13373771 Daniel M Greenberger Michael A Horne Anton Zeilinger 2007 Going beyond Bell s Theorem arXiv 0712 0921 Bibcode 2007arXiv0712 0921G Hardy Lucien 1993 Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states Physical Review Letters 71 11 1665 1668 Bibcode 1993PhRvL 71 1665H doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 71 1665 PMID 10054467 S2CID 11839894 Braun D Choi M S 2008 Hardy s test versus the Clauser Horne Shimony Holt test of quantum nonlocality Fundamental and practical aspects Physical Review A 78 3 032114 arXiv 0808 0052 Bibcode 2008PhRvA 78c2114B doi 10 1103 physreva 78 032114 S2CID 119267461 Nikolic Hrvoje 2007 Quantum Mechanics Myths and Facts Foundations of Physics 37 11 1563 1611 arXiv quant ph 0609163 Bibcode 2007FoPh 37 1563N doi 10 1007 s10701 007 9176 y S2CID 9613836 a b Bancal Jean Daniel Pironio Stefano Acin Antonio Liang Yeong Cherng Scarani Valerio Gisin Nicolas 2012 Quantum nonlocality based on finite speed causal influences leads to superluminal signaling Nature Physics 8 867 867 870 arXiv 1110 3795 Bibcode 2012NatPh 8 867B doi 10 1038 nphys2460 S2CID 13922531 Fritz Tobias 2012 Beyond Bell s Theorem Correlation Scenarios New J Phys 14 10 103001 arXiv 1206 5115 Bibcode 2012NJPh 14j3001F doi 10 1088 1367 2630 14 10 103001 S2CID 4847110 Wolfe Elie Spekkens R W Fritz T 2019 The Inflation Technique for Causal Inference with Latent Variables Causal Inference 7 2 arXiv 1609 00672 doi 10 1515 jci 2017 0020 S2CID 52476882 Navascues Miguel Wolfe Elie 2020 The Inflation Technique Completely Solves the Causal Compatibility Problem Journal of Causal Inference 8 70 91 arXiv 1707 06476 doi 10 1515 jci 2018 0008 S2CID 155100141 Werner R F 1989 Quantum States with Einstein Podolsky Rosen correlations admitting a hidden variable model Physical Review A 40 8 4277 4281 Bibcode 1989PhRvA 40 4277W doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 40 4277 PMID 9902666 Palazuelos Carlos 2012 Super activation of quantum non locality Physical Review Letters 109 19 190401 arXiv 1205 3118 Bibcode 2012PhRvL 109s0401P doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 109 190401 PMID 23215363 S2CID 4613963 Popescu Sandu 1995 Bell s Inequalities and Density Matrices Revealing Hidden Nonlocality Physical Review Letters 74 14 2619 2622 arXiv quant ph 9502005 Bibcode 1995PhRvL 74 2619P doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 74 2619 PMID 10057976 S2CID 35478562 Jonathan Daniel Plenio Martin B 1999 10 25 Entanglement Assisted Local Manipulation of Pure Quantum States Physical Review Letters 83 17 3566 3569 arXiv quant ph 9905071 Bibcode 1999PhRvL 83 3566J doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 83 3566 hdl 10044 1 245 ISSN 0031 9007 S2CID 392419 Karvonen Martti 2021 10 13 Neither Contextuality nor Nonlocality Admits Catalysts Physical Review Letters 127 16 160402 arXiv 2102 07637 Bibcode 2021PhRvL 127p0402K doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 127 160402 ISSN 0031 9007 PMID 34723585 S2CID 231924967 Junge Marius Palazuelos C 2011 Large violation of Bell inequalities with low entanglement Communications in Mathematical Physics 306 3 695 746 arXiv 1007 3043 Bibcode 2011CMaPh 306 695J doi 10 1007 s00220 011 1296 8 S2CID 673737 Thomas Vidick Stephanie Wehner 2011 More Non locality with less Entanglement Physical Review A 83 5 052310 arXiv 1011 5206 Bibcode 2011PhRvA 83e2310V doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 83 052310 S2CID 6589783 Yeong Cherng Liang Tamas Vertesi Nicolas Brunner 2010 Semi device independent bounds on entanglement Physical Review A 83 2 022108 arXiv 1012 1513 Bibcode 2011PhRvA 83b2108L doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 83 022108 S2CID 73571969 Cirel son BS 1980 Quantum generalizations of Bell s inequality Letters in Mathematical Physics 4 2 93 100 Bibcode 1980LMaPh 4 93C doi 10 1007 bf00417500 S2CID 120680226 a b Tsirel son B S 1987 Quantum analogues of the Bell inequalities The case of two spatially separated domains Journal of Soviet Mathematics 36 4 557 570 doi 10 1007 BF01663472 S2CID 119363229 a b Slofstra William 2017 The set of quantum correlations is not closed arXiv 1703 08618 quant ph a b Bell inequalities and operator algebras Open quantum problems Ji Zhengfeng Natarajan Anand Vidick Thomas Wright John Yuen Henry 2020 MIP RE arXiv 2001 04383 Bibcode 2020arXiv200104383J a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Castelvecchi Davide 2020 How spooky is quantum physics The answer could be incalculable Nature 577 7791 461 462 Bibcode 2020Natur 577 461C doi 10 1038 d41586 020 00120 6 PMID 31965099 Kalai Gil 2020 01 17 Amazing Zhengfeng Ji Anand Natarajan Thomas Vidick John Wright and Henry Yuen proved that MIP RE and thus disproved Connes 1976 Embedding Conjecture and provided a negative answer to Tsirelson s problem Combinatorics and more Retrieved 2020 03 06 Barak Boaz 2020 01 14 MIP RE disproving Connes embedding conjecture Windows On Theory Retrieved 2020 03 06 Aaronson Scott 16 January 2020 MIP RE Shtetl Optimized Retrieved 2020 03 06 Regan Kenneth W 2020 01 15 Halting Is Poly Time Quantum Provable Godel s Lost Letter and P NP Retrieved 2020 03 06 Vidick Thomas 2020 01 14 A Masters project MyCQstate Retrieved 2020 03 06 Hartnett Kevin 4 March 2020 Landmark Computer Science Proof Cascades Through Physics and Math Quanta Magazine Retrieved 2020 03 09 Junge M Navascues M Palazuelos C Perez Garcia D Scholz VB Werner RF 2011 Connes embedding problem and Tsirelson s problem J Math Phys 52 1 012102 arXiv 1008 1142 Bibcode 2011JMP 52a2102J doi 10 1063 1 3514538 S2CID 12321570 Fritz Tobias 2012 Tsirelson s problem and Kirchberg s conjecture Rev Math Phys 24 5 1250012 arXiv 1008 1168 Bibcode 2012RvMaP 2450012F doi 10 1142 S0129055X12500122 S2CID 17162262 Ozawa Narutaka 2013 About the Connes Embedding Conjecture Algebraic approaches Jpn J Math 8 147 183 doi 10 1007 s11537 013 1280 5 hdl 2433 173118 S2CID 121154563 Ito T Kobayashi H Matsumoto K 2008 Oracularization and two prover one round interactive proofs against nonlocal strategies arXiv 0810 0693 quant ph Sikora Jamie Varvitsiotis Antonios 2017 Linear conic formulations for two party correlations and values of nonlocal games Mathematical Programming 162 1 2 431 463 arXiv 1506 07297 doi 10 1007 s10107 016 1049 8 S2CID 8234910 Navascues Miguel Pironio S Acin A 2007 Bounding the Set of Quantum Correlations Physical Review Letters 98 1 010401 arXiv quant ph 0607119 Bibcode 2007PhRvL 98a0401N doi 10 1103 physrevlett 98 010401 PMID 17358458 S2CID 41742170 Popescu Sandu Rohrlich Daniel 1994 Nonlocality as an axiom Foundations of Physics 24 3 379 385 Bibcode 1994FoPh 24 379P CiteSeerX 10 1 1 508 4193 doi 10 1007 BF02058098 S2CID 120333148 Rastall Peter 1985 Locality Bell s theorem and quantum mechanics Foundations of Physics 15 9 963 972 Bibcode 1985FoPh 15 963R doi 10 1007 bf00739036 S2CID 122298281 Khalfin L A Tsirelson B S 1985 Lahti et al eds Quantum and quasi classical analogs of Bell inequalities Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics World Sci Publ pp 441 460 Brassard G Buhrman H Linden N Methot AA Tapp A Unger F 2006 Limit on Nonlocality in Any World in Which Communication Complexity Is Not Trivial Physical Review Letters 96 25 250401 arXiv quant ph 0508042 Bibcode 2006PhRvL 96y0401B doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 96 250401 PMID 16907289 S2CID 6135971 Linden N Popescu S Short A J Winter A 2007 Quantum Nonlocality and Beyond Limits from Nonlocal Computation Physical Review Letters 99 18 180502 arXiv quant ph 0610097 Bibcode 2007PhRvL 99r0502L doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 99 180502 PMID 17995388 Pawlowski M Paterek T Kaszlikowski D Scarani V Winter A Zukowski M October 2009 Information Causality as a Physical Principle Nature 461 7267 1101 1104 arXiv 0905 2292 Bibcode 2009Natur 461 1101P doi 10 1038 nature08400 PMID 19847260 S2CID 4428663 Navascues M H Wunderlich 2009 A Glance Beyond the Quantum Model Proc R Soc A 466 2115 881 890 arXiv 0907 0372 doi 10 1098 rspa 2009 0453 Fritz T A B Sainz R Augusiak J B Brask R Chaves A Leverrier A Acin 2013 Local orthogonality as a multipartite principle for quantum correlations Nature Communications 4 2263 arXiv 1210 3018 Bibcode 2013NatCo 4 2263F doi 10 1038 ncomms3263 PMID 23948952 S2CID 14759956 a b Allcock Jonathan Nicolas Brunner Noah Linden Sandu Popescu Paul Skrzypczyk Tamas Vertesi 2009 Closed sets of non local correlations Physical Review A 80 6 062107 arXiv 0908 1496 Bibcode 2009PhRvA 80f2107A doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 80 062107 S2CID 118677048 a b Navascues M Y Guryanova M J Hoban A Acin 2015 Almost Quantum Correlations Nature Communications 6 6288 arXiv 1403 4621 Bibcode 2015NatCo 6 6288N doi 10 1038 ncomms7288 PMID 25697645 S2CID 12810715 a b c Mayers Dominic Yao Andrew C C 1998 Quantum Cryptography with Imperfect Apparatus IEEE Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science FOCS Acin Antonio Nicolas Gisin Lluis Masanes 2006 From Bell s Theorem to Secure Quantum Key Distribution Physical Review Letters 97 12 120405 arXiv quant ph 0510094 Bibcode 2006PhRvL 97l0405A doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 97 120405 PMID 17025944 S2CID 3315286 Vazirani Umesh Vidick Thomas 2014 Fully Device Independent Quantum Key Distribution Physical Review Letters 113 14 140501 arXiv 1210 1810 Bibcode 2014PhRvL 113n0501V doi 10 1103 physrevlett 113 140501 PMID 25325625 S2CID 119299119 Colbeck Roger December 2006 Chapter 5 Quantum And Relativistic Protocols For Secure Multi Party Computation Thesis University of Cambridge arXiv 0911 3814 Colbeck Roger Renner Renato 2012 Free randomness can be amplified Nature Physics 8 6 450 453 arXiv 1105 3195 Bibcode 2012NatPh 8 450C doi 10 1038 nphys2300 S2CID 118309394 Santha Miklos Vazirani Umesh V 1984 10 24 Generating quasi random sequences from slightly random sources Proceedings of the 25th IEEE Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science University of California pp 434 440 Colbeck R amp Kent A 2011 Private randomness expansion with untrusted devices Journal of Physics A Mathematical and Theoretical 44 9 095305 doi 10 1088 1751 8113 44 9 095305 Pironio S et al 2010 Random numbers certified by Bell s theorem Nature 464 7291 1021 1024 arXiv 0911 3427 Bibcode 2010Natur 464 1021P doi 10 1038 nature09008 PMID 20393558 S2CID 4300790 Tebyanian H Zahidy M Avesani M Stanco A Villoresi P amp Vallone G 2021 Semi device independent randomness generation based on quantum state s indistinguishability Quantum Science and Technology 6 4 045026 doi 10 1088 2058 9565 ac2047 URL https iopscience iop org article 10 1088 2058 9565 ac2047 Brunner Nicolas Pironio Stefano Acin Antonio Gisin Nicolas Methot Andre Allan Scarani Valerio 2008 Testing the Hilbert space dimension Physical Review Letters 100 21 210503 arXiv 0802 0760 Bibcode 2008arXiv0802 0760B doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 100 210503 PMID 18518591 S2CID 119256543 Prakash Anupam Sikora Jamie Varvitsiotis Antonios Wei Zhaohui 2018 Completely positive semidefinite rank Mathematical Programming 171 1 2 397 431 arXiv 1604 07199 doi 10 1007 s10107 017 1198 4 S2CID 17885968 Navascues Miguel Vertesi Tamas 2015 Bounding the set of finite dimensional quantum correlations Physical Review Letters 115 2 020501 arXiv 1412 0924 Bibcode 2015PhRvL 115b0501N doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 115 020501 PMID 26207454 S2CID 12226163 Coladangelo Andrea Stark Jalex 2018 Unconditional separation of finite and infinite dimensional quantum correlations arXiv 1804 05116 quant ph Pawlowski Marcin Brunner Nicolas 2011 Semi device independent security of one way quantum key distribution Physical Review A 84 1 010302 R arXiv 1103 4105 Bibcode 2011PhRvA 84a0302P doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 84 010302 S2CID 119300029 Li Hong Wei Yin Zhen Qiang Wu Yu Chun Zou Xu Bo Wang Shuang Chen Wei Guo Guang Can Han Zheng Fu 2011 Semi device independent random number expansion without entanglement Physical Review A 84 3 034301 arXiv 1108 1480 Bibcode 2011PhRvA 84c4301L doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 84 034301 S2CID 118407749 Further reading editGrib AA Rodrigues WA 1999 Nonlocality in Quantum Physics Springer Verlag ISBN 978 0 306 46182 8 Cramer JG 2015 The Quantum Handshake Entanglement Nonlocality and Transactions Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 319 24642 0 Duarte FJ 2019 Fundamentals of Quantum Entanglement Institute of Physics UK ISBN 978 0 7503 2226 3 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Quantum nonlocality amp oldid 1196749871, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.