fbpx
Wikipedia

Continuum hypothesis

In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that

there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers,

or equivalently, that

any subset of the real numbers is finite, is countably infinite, or has the same cardinality as the real numbers.

In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to the following equation in aleph numbers: , or even shorter with beth numbers: .

The continuum hypothesis was advanced by Georg Cantor in 1878,[1] and establishing its truth or falsehood is the first of Hilbert's 23 problems presented in 1900. The answer to this problem is independent of ZFC, so that either the continuum hypothesis or its negation can be added as an axiom to ZFC set theory, with the resulting theory being consistent if and only if ZFC is consistent. This independence was proved in 1963 by Paul Cohen, complementing earlier work by Kurt Gödel in 1940.[2]

The name of the hypothesis comes from the term the continuum for the real numbers.

History edit

Cantor believed the continuum hypothesis to be true and for many years tried in vain to prove it.[3] It became the first on David Hilbert's list of important open questions that was presented at the International Congress of Mathematicians in the year 1900 in Paris. Axiomatic set theory was at that point not yet formulated. Kurt Gödel proved in 1940 that the negation of the continuum hypothesis, i.e., the existence of a set with intermediate cardinality, could not be proved in standard set theory.[2] The second half of the independence of the continuum hypothesis – i.e., unprovability of the nonexistence of an intermediate-sized set – was proved in 1963 by Paul Cohen.[4]

Cardinality of infinite sets edit

Two sets are said to have the same cardinality or cardinal number if there exists a bijection (a one-to-one correspondence) between them. Intuitively, for two sets S and T to have the same cardinality means that it is possible to "pair off" elements of S with elements of T in such a fashion that every element of S is paired off with exactly one element of T and vice versa. Hence, the set {banana, apple, pear} has the same cardinality as {yellow, red, green}.

With infinite sets such as the set of integers or rational numbers, the existence of a bijection between two sets becomes more difficult to demonstrate. The rational numbers seemingly form a counterexample to the continuum hypothesis: the integers form a proper subset of the rationals, which themselves form a proper subset of the reals, so intuitively, there are more rational numbers than integers and more real numbers than rational numbers. However, this intuitive analysis is flawed; it does not take proper account of the fact that all three sets are infinite. It turns out the rational numbers can actually be placed in one-to-one correspondence with the integers, and therefore the set of rational numbers is the same size (cardinality) as the set of integers: they are both countable sets.

Cantor gave two proofs that the cardinality of the set of integers is strictly smaller than that of the set of real numbers (see Cantor's first uncountability proof and Cantor's diagonal argument). His proofs, however, give no indication of the extent to which the cardinality of the integers is less than that of the real numbers. Cantor proposed the continuum hypothesis as a possible solution to this question.

The continuum hypothesis states that the set of real numbers has minimal possible cardinality which is greater than the cardinality of the set of integers. That is, every set, S, of real numbers can either be mapped one-to-one into the integers or the real numbers can be mapped one-to-one into S. As the real numbers are equinumerous with the powerset of the integers, i.e.  , the continuum hypothesis can be restated as follows:

Continuum hypothesis —   .

Assuming the axiom of choice, there is a unique smallest cardinal number   greater than  , and the continuum hypothesis is in turn equivalent to the equality  .[5]

Independence from ZFC edit

The independence of the continuum hypothesis (CH) from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) follows from combined work of Kurt Gödel and Paul Cohen.

Gödel[6][2] showed that CH cannot be disproved from ZF, even if the axiom of choice (AC) is adopted (making ZFC). Gödel's proof shows that CH and AC both hold in the constructible universe L, an inner model of ZF set theory, assuming only the axioms of ZF. The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are consistent with ZF, provided ZF itself is consistent. The latter condition cannot be proved in ZF itself, due to Gödel's incompleteness theorems, but is widely believed to be true and can be proved in stronger set theories.

Cohen[4][7] showed that CH cannot be proven from the ZFC axioms, completing the overall independence proof. To prove his result, Cohen developed the method of forcing, which has become a standard tool in set theory. Essentially, this method begins with a model of ZF in which CH holds, and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original, in a way that CH does not hold in the new model. Cohen was awarded the Fields Medal in 1966 for his proof.

The independence proof just described shows that CH is independent of ZFC. Further research has shown that CH is independent of all known large cardinal axioms in the context of ZFC.[8] Moreover, it has been shown that the cardinality of the continuum can be any cardinal consistent with König's theorem. A result of Solovay, proved shortly after Cohen's result on the independence of the continuum hypothesis, shows that in any model of ZFC, if   is a cardinal of uncountable cofinality, then there is a forcing extension in which  . However, per König's theorem, it is not consistent to assume   is   or   or any cardinal with cofinality  .

The continuum hypothesis is closely related to many statements in analysis, point set topology and measure theory. As a result of its independence, many substantial conjectures in those fields have subsequently been shown to be independent as well.

The independence from ZFC means that proving or disproving the CH within ZFC is impossible. However, Gödel and Cohen's negative results are not universally accepted as disposing of all interest in the continuum hypothesis. The continuum hypothesis remains an active topic of research; see Woodin[9][10] and Peter Koellner[11] for an overview of the current research status.

The continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice were among the first genuinely mathematical statements shown to be independent of ZF set theory. Although the existence of some statements independent of ZFC had already been known more than two decades prior: for example, assuming good soundness properties and the consistency ZFC, Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which were published in 1931, establish that there is a formal statement (one for each appropriate Gödel numbering scheme) expressing the consistency of ZFC, that is also independent of it. The latter independence result indeed holds for many theories.

Arguments for and against the continuum hypothesis edit

Gödel believed that CH is false, and that his proof that CH is consistent with ZFC only shows that the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms do not adequately characterize the universe of sets. Gödel was a platonist and therefore had no problems with asserting the truth and falsehood of statements independent of their provability. Cohen, though a formalist,[12] also tended towards rejecting CH.

Historically, mathematicians who favored a "rich" and "large" universe of sets were against CH, while those favoring a "neat" and "controllable" universe favored CH. Parallel arguments were made for and against the axiom of constructibility, which implies CH. More recently, Matthew Foreman has pointed out that ontological maximalism can actually be used to argue in favor of CH, because among models that have the same reals, models with "more" sets of reals have a better chance of satisfying CH.[13]

Another viewpoint is that the conception of set is not specific enough to determine whether CH is true or false. This viewpoint was advanced as early as 1923 by Skolem, even before Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. Skolem argued on the basis of what is now known as Skolem's paradox, and it was later supported by the independence of CH from the axioms of ZFC since these axioms are enough to establish the elementary properties of sets and cardinalities. In order to argue against this viewpoint, it would be sufficient to demonstrate new axioms that are supported by intuition and resolve CH in one direction or another. Although the axiom of constructibility does resolve CH, it is not generally considered to be intuitively true any more than CH is generally considered to be false.[14]

At least two other axioms have been proposed that have implications for the continuum hypothesis, although these axioms have not currently found wide acceptance in the mathematical community. In 1986, Chris Freiling[15] presented an argument against CH by showing that the negation of CH is equivalent to Freiling's axiom of symmetry, a statement derived by arguing from particular intuitions about probabilities. Freiling believes this axiom is "intuitively true" but others have disagreed.

A difficult argument against CH developed by W. Hugh Woodin has attracted considerable attention since the year 2000.[9][10] Foreman does not reject Woodin's argument outright but urges caution.[16] Woodin proposed a new hypothesis that he labeled the (*)-axiom", or "Star axiom". The Star axiom would imply that   is  , thus falsifying CH. The Star axiom was bolstered by an independent May 2021 proof showing the Star axiom can be derived from a variation of Martin's maximum. However, Woodin stated in the 2010s that he now instead believes CH to be true, based on his belief in his new "ultimate L" conjecture.[17][18]

Solomon Feferman argued that CH is not a definite mathematical problem.[19] He proposed a theory of "definiteness" using a semi-intuitionistic subsystem of ZF that accepts classical logic for bounded quantifiers but uses intuitionistic logic for unbounded ones, and suggested that a proposition   is mathematically "definite" if the semi-intuitionistic theory can prove  . He conjectured that CH is not definite according to this notion, and proposed that CH should, therefore, be considered not to have a truth value. Peter Koellner wrote a critical commentary on Feferman's article.[20]

Joel David Hamkins proposes a multiverse approach to set theory and argues that "the continuum hypothesis is settled on the multiverse view by our extensive knowledge about how it behaves in the multiverse, and, as a result, it can no longer be settled in the manner formerly hoped for".[21] In a related vein, Saharon Shelah wrote that he does "not agree with the pure Platonic view that the interesting problems in set theory can be decided, that we just have to discover the additional axiom. My mental picture is that we have many possible set theories, all conforming to ZFC".[22]

Generalized continuum hypothesis edit

The generalized continuum hypothesis (GCH) states that if an infinite set's cardinality lies between that of an infinite set S and that of the power set   of S, then it has the same cardinality as either S or  . That is, for any infinite cardinal   there is no cardinal   such that  . GCH is equivalent to:

  for every ordinal  [5] (occasionally called Cantor's aleph hypothesis).

The beth numbers provide an alternate notation for this condition:   for every ordinal  . The continuum hypothesis is the special case for the ordinal  . GCH was first suggested by Philip Jourdain.[23] For the early history of GCH, see Moore.[24]

Like CH, GCH is also independent of ZFC, but Sierpiński proved that ZF + GCH implies the axiom of choice (AC) (and therefore the negation of the axiom of determinacy, AD), so choice and GCH are not independent in ZF; there are no models of ZF in which GCH holds and AC fails. To prove this, Sierpiński showed GCH implies that every cardinality n is smaller than some aleph number, and thus can be ordered. This is done by showing that n is smaller than   which is smaller than its own Hartogs number—this uses the equality  ; for the full proof, see Gillman.[25]

Kurt Gödel showed that GCH is a consequence of ZF + V=L (the axiom that every set is constructible relative to the ordinals), and is therefore consistent with ZFC. As GCH implies CH, Cohen's model in which CH fails is a model in which GCH fails, and thus GCH is not provable from ZFC. W. B. Easton used the method of forcing developed by Cohen to prove Easton's theorem, which shows it is consistent with ZFC for arbitrarily large cardinals   to fail to satisfy  . Much later, Foreman and Woodin proved that (assuming the consistency of very large cardinals) it is consistent that   holds for every infinite cardinal  . Later Woodin extended this by showing the consistency of   for every  . Carmi Merimovich[26] showed that, for each n ≥ 1, it is consistent with ZFC that for each κ, 2κ is the nth successor of κ. On the other hand, László Patai[27] proved that if γ is an ordinal and for each infinite cardinal κ, 2κ is the γth successor of κ, then γ is finite.

For any infinite sets A and B, if there is an injection from A to B then there is an injection from subsets of A to subsets of B. Thus for any infinite cardinals A and B,   . If A and B are finite, the stronger inequality   holds. GCH implies that this strict, stronger inequality holds for infinite cardinals as well as finite cardinals.

Implications of GCH for cardinal exponentiation edit

Although the generalized continuum hypothesis refers directly only to cardinal exponentiation with 2 as the base, one can deduce from it the values of cardinal exponentiation   in all cases. GCH implies that:[28]

  when αβ+1;
  when β+1 < α and  , where cf is the cofinality operation; and
  when β+1 < α and  .

The first equality (when αβ+1) follows from:

  , while:
  ;

The third equality (when β+1 < α and  ) follows from:

 , by König's theorem, while:
 

Where, for every γ, GCH is used for equating   and  ;   is used as it is equivalent to the axiom of choice.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Cantor, Georg (1878). "Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre". Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik. 1878 (84): 242–258. doi:10.1515/crll.1878.84.242 (inactive 2023-12-09).{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of December 2023 (link)
  2. ^ a b c Gödel, Kurt (1940). The Consistency of the Continuum-Hypothesis. Princeton University Press.
  3. ^ Dauben, Joseph Warren (1990). Georg Cantor: His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite. Princeton University Press. pp. 134–137. ISBN 9780691024479.
  4. ^ a b Cohen, Paul J. (15 December 1963). "The independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, [part I]". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 50 (6): 1143–1148. Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C. doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143. JSTOR 71858. PMC 221287. PMID 16578557.
  5. ^ a b Goldrei, Derek (1996). Classic Set Theory. Chapman & Hall.
  6. ^ Gödel, Kurt (1938). "The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 24 (12): 556–557. Bibcode:1938PNAS...24..556G. doi:10.1073/pnas.24.12.556. PMC 1077160. PMID 16577857.
  7. ^ Cohen, Paul J. (15 January 1964). "The independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, [part] II". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 51 (1): 105–110. Bibcode:1964PNAS...51..105C. doi:10.1073/pnas.51.1.105. JSTOR 72252. PMC 300611. PMID 16591132.
  8. ^ Feferman, Solomon (February 1999). "Does mathematics need new axioms?". American Mathematical Monthly. 106 (2): 99–111. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.37.295. doi:10.2307/2589047. JSTOR 2589047.
  9. ^ a b Woodin, W. Hugh (2001). "The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 48 (6): 567–576. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-10.
  10. ^ a b Woodin, W. Hugh (2001). "The Continuum Hypothesis, Part II" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 48 (7): 681–690. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-10.
  11. ^ Koellner, Peter (2011). "The Continuum Hypothesis" (PDF). Exploring the Frontiers of Independence. Harvard lecture series. (PDF) from the original on 2012-01-24.
  12. ^ Goodman, Nicolas D. (1979). "Mathematics as an objective science". The American Mathematical Monthly. 86 (7): 540–551. doi:10.2307/2320581. JSTOR 2320581. MR 0542765. This view is often called formalism. Positions more or less like this may be found in Haskell Curry [5], Abraham Robinson [17], and Paul Cohen [4].
  13. ^ Maddy 1988, p. 500.
  14. ^ Kunen, Kenneth (1980). Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Amsterdam, NL: North-Holland. p. 171. ISBN 978-0-444-85401-8.
  15. ^ Freiling, Chris (1986). "Axioms of Symmetry: Throwing darts at the real number line". Journal of Symbolic Logic. Association for Symbolic Logic. 51 (1): 190–200. doi:10.2307/2273955. JSTOR 2273955. S2CID 38174418.
  16. ^ Foreman, Matt (2003). "Has the Continuum Hypothesis been settled?" (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-10. Retrieved 25 February 2006.
  17. ^ Wolchover, Natalie (15 July 2021). "How Many Numbers Exist? Infinity Proof Moves Math Closer to an Answer". Quanta Magazine. Retrieved 30 December 2021.
  18. ^ Rittberg, Colin J. (March 2015). "How Woodin changed his mind: new thoughts on the Continuum Hypothesis". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 69 (2): 125–151. doi:10.1007/s00407-014-0142-8. S2CID 122205863.
  19. ^ Feferman, Solomon (2011). "Is the Continuum Hypothesis a definite mathematical problem?" (PDF). Exploring the Frontiers of Independence. Harvard lecture series. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-10.
  20. ^ Koellner, Peter (2011). "Feferman on the indefiniteness of CH" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2012-03-19.
  21. ^ Hamkins, Joel David (2012). "The set-theoretic multiverse". The Review of Symbolic Logic. 5 (3): 416–449. arXiv:1108.4223. doi:10.1017/S1755020311000359. S2CID 33807508.
  22. ^ Shelah, Saharon (2003). "Logical dreams". Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. New Series. 40 (2): 203–228. arXiv:math/0211398. doi:10.1090/s0273-0979-03-00981-9. S2CID 1510438.
  23. ^ Jourdain, Philip E.B. (1905). "On transfinite cardinal numbers of the exponential form". Philosophical Magazine. Series 6. 9 (49): 42–56. doi:10.1080/14786440509463254.
  24. ^ Moore, Gregory H. (2011). "Early history of the generalized continuum hypothesis: 1878–1938". Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 17 (4): 489–532. doi:10.2178/bsl/1318855631. MR 2896574.
  25. ^ Gillman, Leonard (2002). "Two classical surprises concerning the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis" (PDF). American Mathematical Monthly. 109 (6): 544–553. doi:10.2307/2695444. JSTOR 2695444. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-10.
  26. ^ Merimovich, Carmi (2007). "A power function with a fixed finite gap everywhere". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 72 (2): 361–417. arXiv:math/0005179. doi:10.2178/jsl/1185803615. MR 2320282. S2CID 15577499.
  27. ^ Patai, L. (1930). "Untersuchungen über die א-reihe". Mathematische und naturwissenschaftliche Berichte aus Ungarn (in German). 37: 127–142.
  28. ^ Hayden, Seymour; Kennison, John F. (1968). Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory. Columbus, Ohio: Charles E. Merrill. p. 147, exercise 76.
  • Maddy, Penelope (June 1988). "Believing the axioms, [part I]". Journal of Symbolic Logic. Association for Symbolic Logic. 53 (2): 481–511. doi:10.2307/2274520. JSTOR 2274520.

Sources edit

Further reading edit

  • Cohen, Paul Joseph (2008) [1966]. Set theory and the continuum hypothesis. Mineola, New York City: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-46921-8.
  • Dales, H.G.; Woodin, W.H. (1987). An Introduction to Independence for Analysts. Cambridge.
  • Enderton, Herbert (1977). Elements of Set Theory. Academic Press.
  • Gödel, K.: What is Cantor's Continuum Problem?, reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam's collection Philosophy of Mathematics, 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press, 1983. An outline of Gödel's arguments against CH.
  • Martin, D. (1976). "Hilbert's first problem: the continuum hypothesis," in Mathematical Developments Arising from Hilbert's Problems, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics XXVIII, F. Browder, editor. American Mathematical Society, 1976, pp. 81–92. ISBN 0-8218-1428-1
  • McGough, Nancy. "The Continuum Hypothesis".
  • Wolchover, Natalie (15 July 2021). "How Many Numbers Exist? Infinity Proof Moves Math Closer to an Answer".

External links edit

  Quotations related to Continuum hypothesis at Wikiquote

continuum, hypothesis, this, article, about, hypothesis, theory, assumption, fluid, mechanics, continuum, assumption, mathematics, specifically, theory, continuum, hypothesis, abbreviated, hypothesis, about, possible, sizes, infinite, sets, states, that, there. This article is about the hypothesis in set theory For the assumption in fluid mechanics see Continuum assumption In mathematics specifically set theory the continuum hypothesis abbreviated CH is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets It states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers or equivalently that any subset of the real numbers is finite is countably infinite or has the same cardinality as the real numbers In Zermelo Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice ZFC this is equivalent to the following equation in aleph numbers 2 ℵ 0 ℵ 1 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 aleph 1 or even shorter with beth numbers ℶ 1 ℵ 1 displaystyle beth 1 aleph 1 The continuum hypothesis was advanced by Georg Cantor in 1878 1 and establishing its truth or falsehood is the first of Hilbert s 23 problems presented in 1900 The answer to this problem is independent of ZFC so that either the continuum hypothesis or its negation can be added as an axiom to ZFC set theory with the resulting theory being consistent if and only if ZFC is consistent This independence was proved in 1963 by Paul Cohen complementing earlier work by Kurt Godel in 1940 2 The name of the hypothesis comes from the term the continuum for the real numbers Contents 1 History 2 Cardinality of infinite sets 3 Independence from ZFC 4 Arguments for and against the continuum hypothesis 5 Generalized continuum hypothesis 5 1 Implications of GCH for cardinal exponentiation 6 See also 7 References 8 Sources 9 Further reading 10 External linksHistory editCantor believed the continuum hypothesis to be true and for many years tried in vain to prove it 3 It became the first on David Hilbert s list of important open questions that was presented at the International Congress of Mathematicians in the year 1900 in Paris Axiomatic set theory was at that point not yet formulated Kurt Godel proved in 1940 that the negation of the continuum hypothesis i e the existence of a set with intermediate cardinality could not be proved in standard set theory 2 The second half of the independence of the continuum hypothesis i e unprovability of the nonexistence of an intermediate sized set was proved in 1963 by Paul Cohen 4 Cardinality of infinite sets editMain article Cardinal number Two sets are said to have the same cardinality or cardinal number if there exists a bijection a one to one correspondence between them Intuitively for two sets S and T to have the same cardinality means that it is possible to pair off elements of S with elements of T in such a fashion that every element of S is paired off with exactly one element of T and vice versa Hence the set banana apple pear has the same cardinality as yellow red green With infinite sets such as the set of integers or rational numbers the existence of a bijection between two sets becomes more difficult to demonstrate The rational numbers seemingly form a counterexample to the continuum hypothesis the integers form a proper subset of the rationals which themselves form a proper subset of the reals so intuitively there are more rational numbers than integers and more real numbers than rational numbers However this intuitive analysis is flawed it does not take proper account of the fact that all three sets are infinite It turns out the rational numbers can actually be placed in one to one correspondence with the integers and therefore the set of rational numbers is the same size cardinality as the set of integers they are both countable sets Cantor gave two proofs that the cardinality of the set of integers is strictly smaller than that of the set of real numbers see Cantor s first uncountability proof and Cantor s diagonal argument His proofs however give no indication of the extent to which the cardinality of the integers is less than that of the real numbers Cantor proposed the continuum hypothesis as a possible solution to this question The continuum hypothesis states that the set of real numbers has minimal possible cardinality which is greater than the cardinality of the set of integers That is every set S of real numbers can either be mapped one to one into the integers or the real numbers can be mapped one to one into S As the real numbers are equinumerous with the powerset of the integers i e R 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle mathbb R 2 aleph 0 nbsp the continuum hypothesis can be restated as follows Continuum hypothesis S ℵ 0 lt S lt 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle nexists S aleph 0 lt S lt 2 aleph 0 nbsp Assuming the axiom of choice there is a unique smallest cardinal number ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 nbsp greater than ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 nbsp and the continuum hypothesis is in turn equivalent to the equality 2 ℵ 0 ℵ 1 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 aleph 1 nbsp 5 Independence from ZFC editThe independence of the continuum hypothesis CH from Zermelo Fraenkel set theory ZF follows from combined work of Kurt Godel and Paul Cohen Godel 6 2 showed that CH cannot be disproved from ZF even if the axiom of choice AC is adopted making ZFC Godel s proof shows that CH and AC both hold in the constructible universe L an inner model of ZF set theory assuming only the axioms of ZF The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are consistent with ZF provided ZF itself is consistent The latter condition cannot be proved in ZF itself due to Godel s incompleteness theorems but is widely believed to be true and can be proved in stronger set theories Cohen 4 7 showed that CH cannot be proven from the ZFC axioms completing the overall independence proof To prove his result Cohen developed the method of forcing which has become a standard tool in set theory Essentially this method begins with a model of ZF in which CH holds and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original in a way that CH does not hold in the new model Cohen was awarded the Fields Medal in 1966 for his proof The independence proof just described shows that CH is independent of ZFC Further research has shown that CH is independent of all known large cardinal axioms in the context of ZFC 8 Moreover it has been shown that the cardinality of the continuum can be any cardinal consistent with Konig s theorem A result of Solovay proved shortly after Cohen s result on the independence of the continuum hypothesis shows that in any model of ZFC if k displaystyle kappa nbsp is a cardinal of uncountable cofinality then there is a forcing extension in which 2 ℵ 0 k displaystyle 2 aleph 0 kappa nbsp However per Konig s theorem it is not consistent to assume 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 nbsp is ℵ w displaystyle aleph omega nbsp or ℵ w 1 w displaystyle aleph omega 1 omega nbsp or any cardinal with cofinality w displaystyle omega nbsp The continuum hypothesis is closely related to many statements in analysis point set topology and measure theory As a result of its independence many substantial conjectures in those fields have subsequently been shown to be independent as well The independence from ZFC means that proving or disproving the CH within ZFC is impossible However Godel and Cohen s negative results are not universally accepted as disposing of all interest in the continuum hypothesis The continuum hypothesis remains an active topic of research see Woodin 9 10 and Peter Koellner 11 for an overview of the current research status The continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice were among the first genuinely mathematical statements shown to be independent of ZF set theory Although the existence of some statements independent of ZFC had already been known more than two decades prior for example assuming good soundness properties and the consistency ZFC Godel s incompleteness theorems which were published in 1931 establish that there is a formal statement one for each appropriate Godel numbering scheme expressing the consistency of ZFC that is also independent of it The latter independence result indeed holds for many theories Arguments for and against the continuum hypothesis editGodel believed that CH is false and that his proof that CH is consistent with ZFC only shows that the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms do not adequately characterize the universe of sets Godel was a platonist and therefore had no problems with asserting the truth and falsehood of statements independent of their provability Cohen though a formalist 12 also tended towards rejecting CH Historically mathematicians who favored a rich and large universe of sets were against CH while those favoring a neat and controllable universe favored CH Parallel arguments were made for and against the axiom of constructibility which implies CH More recently Matthew Foreman has pointed out that ontological maximalism can actually be used to argue in favor of CH because among models that have the same reals models with more sets of reals have a better chance of satisfying CH 13 Another viewpoint is that the conception of set is not specific enough to determine whether CH is true or false This viewpoint was advanced as early as 1923 by Skolem even before Godel s first incompleteness theorem Skolem argued on the basis of what is now known as Skolem s paradox and it was later supported by the independence of CH from the axioms of ZFC since these axioms are enough to establish the elementary properties of sets and cardinalities In order to argue against this viewpoint it would be sufficient to demonstrate new axioms that are supported by intuition and resolve CH in one direction or another Although the axiom of constructibility does resolve CH it is not generally considered to be intuitively true any more than CH is generally considered to be false 14 At least two other axioms have been proposed that have implications for the continuum hypothesis although these axioms have not currently found wide acceptance in the mathematical community In 1986 Chris Freiling 15 presented an argument against CH by showing that the negation of CH is equivalent to Freiling s axiom of symmetry a statement derived by arguing from particular intuitions about probabilities Freiling believes this axiom is intuitively true but others have disagreed A difficult argument against CH developed by W Hugh Woodin has attracted considerable attention since the year 2000 9 10 Foreman does not reject Woodin s argument outright but urges caution 16 Woodin proposed a new hypothesis that he labeled the axiom or Star axiom The Star axiom would imply that 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 nbsp is ℵ 2 displaystyle aleph 2 nbsp thus falsifying CH The Star axiom was bolstered by an independent May 2021 proof showing the Star axiom can be derived from a variation of Martin s maximum However Woodin stated in the 2010s that he now instead believes CH to be true based on his belief in his new ultimate L conjecture 17 18 Solomon Feferman argued that CH is not a definite mathematical problem 19 He proposed a theory of definiteness using a semi intuitionistic subsystem of ZF that accepts classical logic for bounded quantifiers but uses intuitionistic logic for unbounded ones and suggested that a proposition ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp is mathematically definite if the semi intuitionistic theory can prove ϕ ϕ displaystyle phi lor neg phi nbsp He conjectured that CH is not definite according to this notion and proposed that CH should therefore be considered not to have a truth value Peter Koellner wrote a critical commentary on Feferman s article 20 Joel David Hamkins proposes a multiverse approach to set theory and argues that the continuum hypothesis is settled on the multiverse view by our extensive knowledge about how it behaves in the multiverse and as a result it can no longer be settled in the manner formerly hoped for 21 In a related vein Saharon Shelah wrote that he does not agree with the pure Platonic view that the interesting problems in set theory can be decided that we just have to discover the additional axiom My mental picture is that we have many possible set theories all conforming to ZFC 22 Generalized continuum hypothesis editThe generalized continuum hypothesis GCH states that if an infinite set s cardinality lies between that of an infinite set S and that of the power set P S displaystyle mathcal P S nbsp of S then it has the same cardinality as either S or P S displaystyle mathcal P S nbsp That is for any infinite cardinal l displaystyle lambda nbsp there is no cardinal k displaystyle kappa nbsp such that l lt k lt 2 l displaystyle lambda lt kappa lt 2 lambda nbsp GCH is equivalent to ℵ a 1 2 ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha 1 2 aleph alpha nbsp for every ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp 5 occasionally called Cantor s aleph hypothesis The beth numbers provide an alternate notation for this condition ℵ a ℶ a displaystyle aleph alpha beth alpha nbsp for every ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp The continuum hypothesis is the special case for the ordinal a 1 displaystyle alpha 1 nbsp GCH was first suggested by Philip Jourdain 23 For the early history of GCH see Moore 24 Like CH GCH is also independent of ZFC but Sierpinski proved that ZF GCH implies the axiom of choice AC and therefore the negation of the axiom of determinacy AD so choice and GCH are not independent in ZF there are no models of ZF in which GCH holds and AC fails To prove this Sierpinski showed GCH implies that every cardinality n is smaller than some aleph number and thus can be ordered This is done by showing that n is smaller than 2 ℵ 0 n displaystyle 2 aleph 0 n nbsp which is smaller than its own Hartogs number this uses the equality 2 ℵ 0 n 2 2 ℵ 0 n displaystyle 2 aleph 0 n 2 cdot 2 aleph 0 n nbsp for the full proof see Gillman 25 Kurt Godel showed that GCH is a consequence of ZF V L the axiom that every set is constructible relative to the ordinals and is therefore consistent with ZFC As GCH implies CH Cohen s model in which CH fails is a model in which GCH fails and thus GCH is not provable from ZFC W B Easton used the method of forcing developed by Cohen to prove Easton s theorem which shows it is consistent with ZFC for arbitrarily large cardinals ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha nbsp to fail to satisfy 2 ℵ a ℵ a 1 displaystyle 2 aleph alpha aleph alpha 1 nbsp Much later Foreman and Woodin proved that assuming the consistency of very large cardinals it is consistent that 2 k gt k displaystyle 2 kappa gt kappa nbsp holds for every infinite cardinal k displaystyle kappa nbsp Later Woodin extended this by showing the consistency of 2 k k displaystyle 2 kappa kappa nbsp for every k displaystyle kappa nbsp Carmi Merimovich 26 showed that for each n 1 it is consistent with ZFC that for each k 2k is the nth successor of k On the other hand Laszlo Patai 27 proved that if g is an ordinal and for each infinite cardinal k 2k is the gth successor of k then g is finite For any infinite sets A and B if there is an injection from A to B then there is an injection from subsets of A to subsets of B Thus for any infinite cardinals A and B A lt B 2 A 2 B displaystyle A lt B to 2 A leq 2 B nbsp If A and B are finite the stronger inequality A lt B 2 A lt 2 B displaystyle A lt B to 2 A lt 2 B nbsp holds GCH implies that this strict stronger inequality holds for infinite cardinals as well as finite cardinals Implications of GCH for cardinal exponentiation edit Although the generalized continuum hypothesis refers directly only to cardinal exponentiation with 2 as the base one can deduce from it the values of cardinal exponentiation ℵ a ℵ b displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta nbsp in all cases GCH implies that 28 ℵ a ℵ b ℵ b 1 displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta aleph beta 1 nbsp when a b 1 ℵ a ℵ b ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta aleph alpha nbsp when b 1 lt a and ℵ b lt cf ℵ a displaystyle aleph beta lt operatorname cf aleph alpha nbsp where cf is the cofinality operation and ℵ a ℵ b ℵ a 1 displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta aleph alpha 1 nbsp when b 1 lt a and ℵ b cf ℵ a displaystyle aleph beta geq operatorname cf aleph alpha nbsp The first equality when a b 1 follows from ℵ a ℵ b ℵ b 1 ℵ b 2 ℵ b ℵ b 2 ℵ b ℵ b 2 ℵ b ℵ b 1 displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta leq aleph beta 1 aleph beta 2 aleph beta aleph beta 2 aleph beta cdot aleph beta 2 aleph beta aleph beta 1 nbsp while ℵ b 1 2 ℵ b ℵ a ℵ b displaystyle aleph beta 1 2 aleph beta leq aleph alpha aleph beta nbsp The third equality when b 1 lt a and ℵ b cf ℵ a displaystyle aleph beta geq operatorname cf aleph alpha nbsp follows from ℵ a ℵ b ℵ a cf ℵ a gt ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta geq aleph alpha operatorname cf aleph alpha gt aleph alpha nbsp by Konig s theorem while ℵ a ℵ b ℵ a ℵ a 2 ℵ a ℵ a 2 ℵ a ℵ a 2 ℵ a ℵ a 1 displaystyle aleph alpha aleph beta leq aleph alpha aleph alpha leq 2 aleph alpha aleph alpha 2 aleph alpha cdot aleph alpha 2 aleph alpha aleph alpha 1 nbsp Where for every g GCH is used for equating 2 ℵ g displaystyle 2 aleph gamma nbsp and ℵ g 1 displaystyle aleph gamma 1 nbsp ℵ g 2 ℵ g displaystyle aleph gamma 2 aleph gamma nbsp is used as it is equivalent to the axiom of choice See also editAbsolute Infinite Beth number Cardinality W logic Second continuum hypothesis Wetzel s problemReferences edit Cantor Georg 1878 Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre Journal fur die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik 1878 84 242 258 doi 10 1515 crll 1878 84 242 inactive 2023 12 09 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint DOI inactive as of December 2023 link a b c Godel Kurt 1940 The Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis Princeton University Press Dauben Joseph Warren 1990 Georg Cantor His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite Princeton University Press pp 134 137 ISBN 9780691024479 a b Cohen Paul J 15 December 1963 The independence of the Continuum Hypothesis part I Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 50 6 1143 1148 Bibcode 1963PNAS 50 1143C doi 10 1073 pnas 50 6 1143 JSTOR 71858 PMC 221287 PMID 16578557 a b Goldrei Derek 1996 Classic Set Theory Chapman amp Hall Godel Kurt 1938 The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 24 12 556 557 Bibcode 1938PNAS 24 556G doi 10 1073 pnas 24 12 556 PMC 1077160 PMID 16577857 Cohen Paul J 15 January 1964 The independence of the Continuum Hypothesis part II Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 51 1 105 110 Bibcode 1964PNAS 51 105C doi 10 1073 pnas 51 1 105 JSTOR 72252 PMC 300611 PMID 16591132 Feferman Solomon February 1999 Does mathematics need new axioms American Mathematical Monthly 106 2 99 111 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 37 295 doi 10 2307 2589047 JSTOR 2589047 a b Woodin W Hugh 2001 The Continuum Hypothesis Part I PDF Notices of the AMS 48 6 567 576 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 10 a b Woodin W Hugh 2001 The Continuum Hypothesis Part II PDF Notices of the AMS 48 7 681 690 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 10 Koellner Peter 2011 The Continuum Hypothesis PDF Exploring the Frontiers of Independence Harvard lecture series Archived PDF from the original on 2012 01 24 Goodman Nicolas D 1979 Mathematics as an objective science The American Mathematical Monthly 86 7 540 551 doi 10 2307 2320581 JSTOR 2320581 MR 0542765 This view is often called formalism Positions more or less like this may be found in Haskell Curry 5 Abraham Robinson 17 and Paul Cohen 4 Maddy 1988 p 500 Kunen Kenneth 1980 Set Theory An Introduction to Independence Proofs Amsterdam NL North Holland p 171 ISBN 978 0 444 85401 8 Freiling Chris 1986 Axioms of Symmetry Throwing darts at the real number line Journal of Symbolic Logic Association for Symbolic Logic 51 1 190 200 doi 10 2307 2273955 JSTOR 2273955 S2CID 38174418 Foreman Matt 2003 Has the Continuum Hypothesis been settled PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 10 Retrieved 25 February 2006 Wolchover Natalie 15 July 2021 How Many Numbers Exist Infinity Proof Moves Math Closer to an Answer Quanta Magazine Retrieved 30 December 2021 Rittberg Colin J March 2015 How Woodin changed his mind new thoughts on the Continuum Hypothesis Archive for History of Exact Sciences 69 2 125 151 doi 10 1007 s00407 014 0142 8 S2CID 122205863 Feferman Solomon 2011 Is the Continuum Hypothesis a definite mathematical problem PDF Exploring the Frontiers of Independence Harvard lecture series Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 10 Koellner Peter 2011 Feferman on the indefiniteness of CH PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2012 03 19 Hamkins Joel David 2012 The set theoretic multiverse The Review of Symbolic Logic 5 3 416 449 arXiv 1108 4223 doi 10 1017 S1755020311000359 S2CID 33807508 Shelah Saharon 2003 Logical dreams Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society New Series 40 2 203 228 arXiv math 0211398 doi 10 1090 s0273 0979 03 00981 9 S2CID 1510438 Jourdain Philip E B 1905 On transfinite cardinal numbers of the exponential form Philosophical Magazine Series 6 9 49 42 56 doi 10 1080 14786440509463254 Moore Gregory H 2011 Early history of the generalized continuum hypothesis 1878 1938 Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 4 489 532 doi 10 2178 bsl 1318855631 MR 2896574 Gillman Leonard 2002 Two classical surprises concerning the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis PDF American Mathematical Monthly 109 6 544 553 doi 10 2307 2695444 JSTOR 2695444 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 10 Merimovich Carmi 2007 A power function with a fixed finite gap everywhere Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 2 361 417 arXiv math 0005179 doi 10 2178 jsl 1185803615 MR 2320282 S2CID 15577499 Patai L 1930 Untersuchungen uber die א reihe Mathematische und naturwissenschaftliche Berichte aus Ungarn in German 37 127 142 Hayden Seymour Kennison John F 1968 Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory Columbus Ohio Charles E Merrill p 147 exercise 76 Maddy Penelope June 1988 Believing the axioms part I Journal of Symbolic Logic Association for Symbolic Logic 53 2 481 511 doi 10 2307 2274520 JSTOR 2274520 Sources editThis article incorporates material from Generalized continuum hypothesis on PlanetMath which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution Share Alike License Archived 2017 02 08 at the Wayback MachineFurther reading editCohen Paul Joseph 2008 1966 Set theory and the continuum hypothesis Mineola New York City Dover Publications ISBN 978 0 486 46921 8 Dales H G Woodin W H 1987 An Introduction to Independence for Analysts Cambridge Enderton Herbert 1977 Elements of Set Theory Academic Press Godel K What is Cantor s Continuum Problem reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam s collection Philosophy of Mathematics 2nd ed Cambridge University Press 1983 An outline of Godel s arguments against CH Martin D 1976 Hilbert s first problem the continuum hypothesis in Mathematical Developments Arising from Hilbert s Problems Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics XXVIII F Browder editor American Mathematical Society 1976 pp 81 92 ISBN 0 8218 1428 1 McGough Nancy The Continuum Hypothesis Wolchover Natalie 15 July 2021 How Many Numbers Exist Infinity Proof Moves Math Closer to an Answer External links edit nbsp Quotations related to Continuum hypothesis at Wikiquote Szudzik Matthew amp Weisstein Eric W Continuum Hypothesis MathWorld Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Continuum hypothesis amp oldid 1190897116, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.