fbpx
Wikipedia

Reductio ad absurdum

In logic, reductio ad absurdum (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as argumentum ad absurdum (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or apagogical arguments, is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absurdity or contradiction.[1][2][3][4]

Reductio ad absurdum, painting by John Pettie exhibited at the Royal Academy in 1884

This argument form traces back to Ancient Greek philosophy and has been used throughout history in both formal mathematical and philosophical reasoning, as well as in debate. Formally, the proof technique is captured by an axiom for "Reductio ad Absurdum", normally given the abbreviation RAA, which is expressible in propositional logic. This axiom is the introduction rule for negation (see negation introduction) and it is sometimes named to make this connection clear. It is a consequence of the related mathematical proof technique called proof by contradiction.

Examples edit

The "absurd" conclusion of a reductio ad absurdum argument can take a range of forms, as these examples show:

  • The Earth cannot be flat; otherwise, since the Earth is assumed to be finite in extent, we would find people falling off the edge.
  • There is no smallest positive rational number because, if there were, then it could be divided by two to get a smaller one.

The first example argues that denial of the premise would result in a ridiculous conclusion, against the evidence of our senses.[5] The second example is a mathematical proof by contradiction (also known as an indirect proof[6]), which argues that the denial of the premise would result in a logical contradiction (there is a "smallest" number and yet there is a number smaller than it).[7]

Greek philosophy edit

Reductio ad absurdum was used throughout Greek philosophy. The earliest example of a reductio argument can be found in a satirical poem attributed to Xenophanes of Colophon (c. 570 – c. 475 BCE).[8] Criticizing Homer's attribution of human faults to the gods, Xenophanes states that humans also believe that the gods' bodies have human form. But if horses and oxen could draw, they would draw the gods with horse and ox bodies.[9] The gods cannot have both forms, so this is a contradiction. Therefore, the attribution of other human characteristics to the gods, such as human faults, is also false.

Greek mathematicians proved fundamental propositions using reductio ad absurdum. Euclid of Alexandria (mid-4th – mid-3rd centuries BCE) and Archimedes of Syracuse (c. 287 – c. 212 BCE) are two very early examples.[10]

The earlier dialogues of Plato (424–348 BCE), relating the discourses of Socrates, raised the use of reductio arguments to a formal dialectical method (elenchus), also called the Socratic method.[11] Typically, Socrates' opponent would make what would seem to be an innocuous assertion. In response, Socrates, via a step-by-step train of reasoning, bringing in other background assumptions, would make the person admit that the assertion resulted in an absurd or contradictory conclusion, forcing him to abandon his assertion and adopt a position of aporia.[6]

The technique was also a focus of the work of Aristotle (384–322 BCE), particularly in his Prior Analytics where he referred to it as demonstration to the impossible (Greek: ἡ εἰς τὸ ἀδύνατον ἀπόδειξις, lit. "demonstration to the impossible", 62b).[4]

Another example of this technique is found in the sorites paradox, where it was argued that if 1,000,000 grains of sand formed a heap, and removing one grain from a heap left it a heap, then a single grain of sand (or even no grains) forms a heap.[12]

Buddhist philosophy edit

Much of Madhyamaka Buddhist philosophy centers on showing how various essentialist ideas have absurd conclusions through reductio ad absurdum arguments (known as prasaṅga, "consequence" in Sanskrit). In the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, Nāgārjuna's reductio ad absurdum arguments are used to show that any theory of substance or essence was unsustainable and therefore, phenomena (dharmas) such as change, causality, and sense perception were empty (sunya) of any essential existence. Nāgārjuna's main goal is often seen by scholars as refuting the essentialism of certain Buddhist Abhidharma schools (mainly Vaibhasika) which posited theories of svabhava (essential nature) and also the Hindu Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika schools which posited a theory of ontological substances (dravyatas).[13]

Example from Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā edit

In 13.5, Nagarjuna wishes to demonstrate consequences of the presumption that things essentially, or inherently, exist, pointing out that if a "young man" exists in himself then it follows he cannot grow old (because he would no longer be a "young man"). As we attempt to separate the man from his properties (youth), we find that everything is subject to momentary change, and are left with nothing beyond the merely arbitrary convention that such entities as "young man" depend upon.

13:5 edit

A thing itself does not change.
Something different does not change.
Because a young man does not grow old.
And because an old man does not grow old either.[14]

Principle of non-contradiction edit

Aristotle clarified the connection between contradiction and falsity in his principle of non-contradiction, which states that a proposition cannot be both true and false.[15][16] That is, a proposition   and its negation   (not-Q) cannot both be true. Therefore, if a proposition and its negation can both be derived logically from a premise, it can be concluded that the premise is false. This technique, known as indirect proof or proof by contradiction,[6] has formed the basis of reductio ad absurdum arguments in formal fields such as logic and mathematics.

See also edit

Sources edit

  • Hyde, Dominic; Raffman, Diana (2018). "Sorites Paradox". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.).
  • Garfield, Jay L. (1995), The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way, Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Pasti, Mary. Reductio Ad Absurdum: An Exercise in the Study of Population Change. United States, Cornell University, Jan., 1977.
  • Daigle, Robert W.. The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument Prior to Aristotle. N.p., San Jose State University, 1991.

References edit

  1. ^ "Reductio ad absurdum | logic". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2019-11-27.
  2. ^ "Definition of REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2019-11-27.
  3. ^ "reductio ad absurdum", Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged (12th ed.), 2014 [1991], retrieved October 29, 2016
  4. ^ a b Nicholas Rescher. "Reductio ad absurdum". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 July 2009.
  5. ^ DeLancey, Craig (2017-03-27), "8. Reductio ad Absurdum", A Concise Introduction to Logic, Open SUNY Textbooks, retrieved 2021-08-31
  6. ^ a b c Nordquist, Richard. "Reductio Ad Absurdum in Argument". ThoughtCo. Retrieved 2019-11-27.
  7. ^ Howard-Snyder, Frances; Howard-Snyder, Daniel; Wasserman, Ryan (30 March 2012). The Power of Logic (5th ed.). McGraw-Hill Higher Education. ISBN 978-0078038198.
  8. ^ Daigle, Robert W. (1991). "The reductio ad absurdum argument prior to Aristotle". Master's Thesis. San Jose State Univ. Retrieved August 22, 2012.
  9. ^ "Reductio ad Absurdum - Definition & Examples". Literary Devices. 2014-05-18. Retrieved 2021-08-31.
  10. ^ Joyce, David (1996). "Euclid's Elements: Book I". Euclid's Elements. Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Clark University. Retrieved December 23, 2017.
  11. ^ Bobzien, Susanne (2006). "Ancient Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved August 22, 2012.
  12. ^ Hyde & Raffman 2018.
  13. ^ Wasler, Joseph. Nagarjuna in Context. New York: Columibia University Press. 2005, pgs. 225-263.
  14. ^ Garfield 1995, p. 210.
  15. ^ Ziembiński, Zygmunt (2013). Practical Logic. Springer. p. 95. ISBN 978-9401756044.
  16. ^ Ferguson, Thomas Macaulay; Priest, Graham (2016). A Dictionary of Logic. Oxford University Press. p. 146. ISBN 978-0192511553.

External links edit

reductio, absurdum, logic, reductio, absurdum, latin, reduction, absurdity, also, known, argumentum, absurdum, latin, argument, absurdity, apagogical, arguments, form, argument, that, attempts, establish, claim, showing, that, opposite, scenario, would, lead, . In logic reductio ad absurdum Latin for reduction to absurdity also known as argumentum ad absurdum Latin for argument to absurdity or apagogical arguments is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absurdity or contradiction 1 2 3 4 Reductio ad absurdum painting by John Pettie exhibited at the Royal Academy in 1884 This argument form traces back to Ancient Greek philosophy and has been used throughout history in both formal mathematical and philosophical reasoning as well as in debate Formally the proof technique is captured by an axiom for Reductio ad Absurdum normally given the abbreviation RAA which is expressible in propositional logic This axiom is the introduction rule for negation see negation introduction and it is sometimes named to make this connection clear It is a consequence of the related mathematical proof technique called proof by contradiction Contents 1 Examples 2 Greek philosophy 3 Buddhist philosophy 3 1 Example from Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika 3 1 1 13 5 4 Principle of non contradiction 5 See also 6 Sources 7 References 8 External linksExamples editThe absurd conclusion of a reductio ad absurdum argument can take a range of forms as these examples show The Earth cannot be flat otherwise since the Earth is assumed to be finite in extent we would find people falling off the edge There is no smallest positive rational number because if there were then it could be divided by two to get a smaller one The first example argues that denial of the premise would result in a ridiculous conclusion against the evidence of our senses 5 The second example is a mathematical proof by contradiction also known as an indirect proof 6 which argues that the denial of the premise would result in a logical contradiction there is a smallest number and yet there is a number smaller than it 7 Greek philosophy editReductio ad absurdum was used throughout Greek philosophy The earliest example of a reductio argument can be found in a satirical poem attributed to Xenophanes of Colophon c 570 c 475 BCE 8 Criticizing Homer s attribution of human faults to the gods Xenophanes states that humans also believe that the gods bodies have human form But if horses and oxen could draw they would draw the gods with horse and ox bodies 9 The gods cannot have both forms so this is a contradiction Therefore the attribution of other human characteristics to the gods such as human faults is also false Greek mathematicians proved fundamental propositions using reductio ad absurdum Euclid of Alexandria mid 4th mid 3rd centuries BCE and Archimedes of Syracuse c 287 c 212 BCE are two very early examples 10 The earlier dialogues of Plato 424 348 BCE relating the discourses of Socrates raised the use of reductio arguments to a formal dialectical method elenchus also called the Socratic method 11 Typically Socrates opponent would make what would seem to be an innocuous assertion In response Socrates via a step by step train of reasoning bringing in other background assumptions would make the person admit that the assertion resulted in an absurd or contradictory conclusion forcing him to abandon his assertion and adopt a position of aporia 6 The technique was also a focus of the work of Aristotle 384 322 BCE particularly in his Prior Analytics where he referred to it as demonstration to the impossible Greek ἡ eἰs tὸ ἀdynaton ἀpodei3is lit demonstration to the impossible 62b 4 Another example of this technique is found in the sorites paradox where it was argued that if 1 000 000 grains of sand formed a heap and removing one grain from a heap left it a heap then a single grain of sand or even no grains forms a heap 12 Buddhist philosophy editMuch of Madhyamaka Buddhist philosophy centers on showing how various essentialist ideas have absurd conclusions through reductio ad absurdum arguments known as prasaṅga consequence in Sanskrit In the Mulamadhyamakakarika Nagarjuna s reductio ad absurdum arguments are used to show that any theory of substance or essence was unsustainable and therefore phenomena dharmas such as change causality and sense perception were empty sunya of any essential existence Nagarjuna s main goal is often seen by scholars as refuting the essentialism of certain Buddhist Abhidharma schools mainly Vaibhasika which posited theories of svabhava essential nature and also the Hindu Nyaya and Vaiseṣika schools which posited a theory of ontological substances dravyatas 13 Example from Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika edit In 13 5 Nagarjuna wishes to demonstrate consequences of the presumption that things essentially or inherently exist pointing out that if a young man exists in himself then it follows he cannot grow old because he would no longer be a young man As we attempt to separate the man from his properties youth we find that everything is subject to momentary change and are left with nothing beyond the merely arbitrary convention that such entities as young man depend upon 13 5 edit A thing itself does not change Something different does not change Because a young man does not grow old And because an old man does not grow old either 14 Principle of non contradiction editAristotle clarified the connection between contradiction and falsity in his principle of non contradiction which states that a proposition cannot be both true and false 15 16 That is a proposition Q displaystyle Q nbsp and its negation Q displaystyle lnot Q nbsp not Q cannot both be true Therefore if a proposition and its negation can both be derived logically from a premise it can be concluded that the premise is false This technique known as indirect proof or proof by contradiction 6 has formed the basis of reductio ad absurdum arguments in formal fields such as logic and mathematics See also editAppeal to ridicule Argument from fallacy Contraposition List of Latin phrases Mathematical proof Prasangika Slippery slope StrawmanSources editHyde Dominic Raffman Diana 2018 Sorites Paradox In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 ed Garfield Jay L 1995 The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way Oxford Oxford University Press Pasti Mary Reductio Ad Absurdum An Exercise in the Study of Population Change United States Cornell University Jan 1977 Daigle Robert W The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument Prior to Aristotle N p San Jose State University 1991 References edit Reductio ad absurdum logic Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 2019 11 27 Definition of REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM www merriam webster com Retrieved 2019 11 27 reductio ad absurdum Collins English Dictionary Complete and Unabridged 12th ed 2014 1991 retrieved October 29 2016 a b Nicholas Rescher Reductio ad absurdum The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 21 July 2009 DeLancey Craig 2017 03 27 8 Reductio ad Absurdum A Concise Introduction to Logic Open SUNY Textbooks retrieved 2021 08 31 a b c Nordquist Richard Reductio Ad Absurdum in Argument ThoughtCo Retrieved 2019 11 27 Howard Snyder Frances Howard Snyder Daniel Wasserman Ryan 30 March 2012 The Power of Logic 5th ed McGraw Hill Higher Education ISBN 978 0078038198 Daigle Robert W 1991 The reductio ad absurdum argument prior to Aristotle Master s Thesis San Jose State Univ Retrieved August 22 2012 Reductio ad Absurdum Definition amp Examples Literary Devices 2014 05 18 Retrieved 2021 08 31 Joyce David 1996 Euclid s Elements Book I Euclid s Elements Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Clark University Retrieved December 23 2017 Bobzien Susanne 2006 Ancient Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved August 22 2012 Hyde amp Raffman 2018 Wasler Joseph Nagarjuna in Context New York Columibia University Press 2005 pgs 225 263 Garfield 1995 p 210 Ziembinski Zygmunt 2013 Practical Logic Springer p 95 ISBN 978 9401756044 Ferguson Thomas Macaulay Priest Graham 2016 A Dictionary of Logic Oxford University Press p 146 ISBN 978 0192511553 External links edit nbsp The dictionary definition of per impossibile at Wiktionary Reductio ad absurdum Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Reductio ad absurdum amp oldid 1221015787, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.