fbpx
Wikipedia

Knowledge

Knowledge is an awareness of facts, a familiarity with individuals and situations, or a practical skill. Knowledge of facts, also called propositional knowledge, is often characterized as true belief that is distinct from opinion or guesswork by virtue of justification. While there is wide agreement among philosophers that propositional knowledge is a form of true belief, many controversies focus on justification. This includes questions like how to understand justification, whether it is needed at all, and whether something else besides it is needed. These controversies intensified in the latter half of the 20th century due to a series of thought experiments called Gettier cases that provoked alternative definitions.

The owl of Athena, a symbol of knowledge in the Western world

Knowledge can be produced in many ways. The main source of empirical knowledge is perception, which involves the usage of the senses to learn about the external world. Introspection allows people to learn about their internal mental states and processes. Other sources of knowledge include memory, rational intuition, inference, and testimony.[a] According to foundationalism, some of these sources are basic in that they can justify beliefs, without depending on other mental states. Coherentists reject this claim and contend that a sufficient degree of coherence among all the mental states of the believer is necessary for knowledge. According to infinitism, an infinite chain of beliefs is needed.

The main discipline investigating knowledge is epistemology, which studies what people know, how they come to know it, and what it means to know something. It discusses the value of knowledge and the thesis of philosophical skepticism, which questions the possibility of knowledge. Knowledge is relevant to many fields like the sciences, which aim to acquire knowledge using the scientific method based on repeatable experimentation, observation, and measurement. Various religions hold that humans should seek knowledge and that God or the divine is the source of knowledge. The anthropology of knowledge studies how knowledge is acquired, stored, retrieved, and communicated in different cultures. The sociology of knowledge examines under what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises, and what sociological consequences it has. The history of knowledge investigates how knowledge in different fields has developed, and evolved, in the course of history.

Definitions

Knowledge is a form of familiarity, awareness, understanding, or acquaintance. It often involves the possession of information learned through experience[1] and can be understood as a cognitive success or an epistemic contact with reality, like making a discovery.[2] Many academic definitions focus on propositional knowledge in the form of believing certain facts, as in "I know that Dave is at home".[3] Other types of knowledge include knowledge-how in the form of practical competence, as in "she knows how to swim", and knowledge by acquaintance as a familiarity with the known object based on previous direct experience, like knowing someone personally.[4]

Knowledge is often understood as a state of an individual person, but it can also refer to a characteristic of a group of people as group knowledge, social knowledge, or collective knowledge.[5] Some social sciences understand knowledge as a broad social phenomenon that is similar to culture.[6] The term may further denote knowledge stored in documents like the "knowledge housed in the library"[7] or the knowledge base of an expert system.[8] Knowledge is closely related to intelligence, but intelligence is more about the ability to acquire, process, and apply information, while knowledge concerns information and skills that a person already possesses.[9]

The word knowledge has its roots in the 12th-century Old English word cnawan, which comes from the Old High German word gecnawan.[10] The English word includes various meanings that some other languages distinguish using several words.[11] In ancient Greek, for example, four important terms for knowledge were used: epistēmē (unchanging theoretical knowledge), technē (expert technical knowledge), mētis (strategic knowledge), and gnōsis (personal intellectual knowledge).[12] The main discipline studying knowledge is called epistemology or the theory of knowledge. It examines the nature of knowledge and justification, how knowledge arises, and what value it has. Further topics include the different types of knowledge and the limits of what can be known.[13]

Despite agreements about the general characteristics of knowledge, its exact definition is disputed. Some definitions only focus on the most salient features of knowledge to give a practically useful characterization.[14] Another approach, termed analysis of knowledge, tries to provide a theoretically precise definition by listing the conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient,[15] similar to how chemists analyze a sample by seeking a list of all the chemical elements composing it.[16] According to a different view, knowledge is a unique state that cannot be analyzed in terms of other phenomena.[17] Some scholars base their definition on abstract intuitions while others focus on concrete cases[18] or rely on how the term is used in ordinary language.[19] There is also disagreement about whether knowledge is a rare phenomenon that requires high standards or a common phenomenon found in many everyday situations.[20]

Analysis of knowledge

 
The definition of knowledge as justified true belief is often discussed in the academic literature.

An often-discussed definition characterizes knowledge as justified true belief. This definition identifies three essential features: it is (1) a belief that is (2) true and (3) justified.[21][b] Truth is a widely accepted feature of knowledge. It implies that, while it may be possible to believe something false, one cannot know something false.[23][c] That knowledge is a form of belief implies that one cannot know something if one does not believe it. Some everyday expressions seem to violate this principle, like the claim that "I do not believe it, I know it!" But the point of such expressions is usually to emphasize one's confidence rather than denying that a belief is involved.[25]

The main controversy surrounding this definition concerns its third feature: justification.[26] This component is often included because of the impression that some true beliefs are not forms of knowledge, such as beliefs based on superstition, lucky guesses, or erroneous reasoning. For example, a person who guesses that a coin flip will land heads usually does not know that even if their belief turns out to be true. This indicates that there is more to knowledge than just being right about something.[27] These cases are excluded by requiring that beliefs have justification for them to count as knowledge.[28] Some philosophers hold that a belief is justified if it is based on evidence, which can take the form of mental states like experience, memory, and other beliefs. Others state that beliefs are justified if they are produced by reliable processes, like sensory perception or logical reasoning.[29]

 
The Gettier problem is grounded in the idea that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge.

The definition of knowledge as justified true belief came under severe criticism in the 20th century, when epistemologist Edmund Gettier formulated a series of counterexamples.[30] They purport to present concrete cases of justified true beliefs that fail to constitute knowledge. The reason for their failure is usually a form of epistemic luck: the beliefs are justified but their justification is not relevant to the truth.[31] In a well-known example, someone drives along a country road with many barn facades and only one real barn. The person is not aware of this, stops in front of the real barn by a lucky coincidence, and forms the justified true belief that they are in front of a barn. This example aims to establish that the person does not know that they are in front of a real barn, since they would not have been able to tell the difference.[32] This means that it is a lucky coincidence that this justified belief is also true.[33]

According to some philosophers, these counterexamples show that justification is not required for knowledge[34] and that knowledge should instead be characterized in terms of reliability or the manifestation of cognitive virtues. Another approach defines knowledge in regard to the function it plays in cognitive processes as that which provides reasons for thinking or doing something.[35] A different response accepts justification as an aspect of knowledge and include additional criteria.[36] Many candidates have been suggested, like the requirements that the justified true belief does not depend on any false beliefs, that no defeaters[d] are present, or that the person would not have the belief if it was false.[38] Another view states that beliefs have to be infallible to amount to knowledge.[39] A further approach, associated with pragmatism, focuses on the aspect of inquiry and characterizes knowledge in terms of what works as a practice that aims to produce habits of action.[40] There is still very little consensus in the academic discourse as to which of the proposed modifications or reconceptualizations is correct, and there are various alternative definitions of knowledge.[41]

Types

A common distinction among types of knowledge is between propositional knowledge, or knowledge-that, and non-propositional knowledge in the form of practical skills or acquaintance.[42][e] Other distinctions focus on how the knowledge is acquired and on the content of the known information.[44]

Propositional

 
Declarative knowledge can be stored in books.

Propositional knowledge, also referred to as declarative and descriptive knowledge, is a form of theoretical knowledge about facts, like knowing that "2 + 2 = 4". It is the paradigmatic type of knowledge in analytic philosophy.[45] Propositional knowledge is propositional in the sense that it involves a relation to a proposition. Since propositions are often expressed through that-clauses, it is also referred to as knowledge-that, as in "Akari knows that kangaroos hop".[46] In this case, Akari stands in the relation of knowing to the proposition "kangaroos hop". Closely related types of knowledge are know-wh, for example, knowing who is coming to dinner and knowing why they are coming.[47] These expressions are normally understood as types of propositional knowledge since they can be paraphrased using a that-clause.[48][f]

Propositional knowledge takes the form of mental representations involving concepts, ideas, theories, and general rules. These representations connect the knower to certain parts of reality by showing what they are like. They are often context-independent, meaning that they are not restricted to a specific use or purpose.[50] Propositional knowledge encompasses both knowledge of specific facts, like that the atomic mass of gold is 196.97 u, and generalities, like that the color of leaves of some trees changes in autumn.[51] Because of the dependence on mental representations, it is often held that the capacity for propositional knowledge is exclusive to relatively sophisticated creatures, such as humans. This is based on the claim that advanced intellectual capacities are needed to believe a proposition that expresses what the world is like.[52]

Non-propositional

 
Knowing how to ride a bicycle is one form of non-propositional knowledge.

Non-propositional knowledge is knowledge in which no essential relation to a proposition is involved. The two most well-known forms are knowledge-how (know-how or procedural knowledge) and knowledge by acquaintance.[53] To possess knowledge-how means to have some form of practical ability, skill, or competence,[54] like knowing how to ride a bicycle or knowing how to swim. Some of the abilities responsible for knowledge-how involve forms of knowledge-that, as in knowing how to prove a mathematical theorem, but this is not generally the case.[55] Some types of knowledge-how do not require a highly developed mind, in contrast to propositional knowledge, and are more common in the animal kingdom. For example, an ant knows how to walk even though it presumably lacks a mind sufficiently developed to represent the corresponding proposition.[52][g]

Knowledge by acquaintance is familiarity with something that results from direct experiential contact.[57] The object of knowledge can be a person, a thing, or a place. For example, by eating chocolate, one becomes acquainted with the taste of chocolate, and visiting Lake Taupō leads to the formation of knowledge by acquaintance of Lake Taupō. In these cases, the person forms non-inferential knowledge based on first-hand experience without necessarily acquiring factual information about the object. By contrast, it is also possible to indirectly learn a lot of propositional knowledge about chocolate or Lake Taupō by reading books without having the direct experiential contact required for knowledge by acquaintance.[58] The concept of knowledge by acquaintance was first introduced by Bertrand Russell. He holds that knowledge by acquaintance is more basic than propositional knowledge since to understand a proposition, one has to be acquainted with its constituents.[59]

A priori and a posteriori

The distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge depends on the role of experience in the processes of formation and justification.[60] To know something a posteriori means to know it based on experience.[61] For example, by seeing that it rains outside or hearing that the baby is crying, one acquires a posteriori knowledge of these facts.[62] A priori knowledge is possible without any experience to justify or support the known proposition.[63] Mathematical knowledge, such as that 2 + 2 = 4, is traditionally taken to be a priori knowledge since no empirical investigation is necessary to confirm this fact. In this regard, a posteriori knowledge is empirical knowledge while a priori knowledge is non-empirical knowledge.[64]

The relevant experience in question is primarily identified with sensory experience. Some non-sensory experiences, like memory and introspection, are often included as well. Some conscious phenomena are excluded from the relevant experience, like rational insight. For example, conscious thought processes may be required to arrive at a priori knowledge regarding the solution of mathematical problems, like when performing mental arithmetic to multiply two numbers.[65] The same is the case for the experience needed to learn the words through which the claim is expressed. For example, knowing that "all bachelors are unmarried" is a priori knowledge because no sensory experience is necessary to confirm this fact even though experience was needed to learn the meanings of the words "bachelor" and "unmarried".[66]

It is difficult to explain how a priori knowledge is possible and some empiricists deny it exists. It is usually seen as unproblematic that one can come to know things through experience, but it is not clear how knowledge is possible without experience. One of the earliest solutions to this problem comes from Plato, who argues that the soul already possesses the knowledge and just needs to recollect, or remember, it to access it again.[67] A similar explanation is given by Descartes, who holds that a priori knowledge exists as innate knowledge present in the mind of each human.[68] A further approach posits a special mental faculty responsible for this type of knowledge, often referred to as rational intuition or rational insight.[69]

Others

Various other types of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature. In philosophy, "self-knowledge" refers to a person's knowledge of their own sensations, thoughts, beliefs, and other mental states. A common view is that self-knowledge is more direct than knowledge of the external world, which relies on the interpretation of sense data. Because of this, it is traditionally claimed that self-knowledge is indubitable, like the claim that a person cannot be wrong about whether they are in pain. However, this position is not universally accepted in the contemporary discourse and an alternative view states that self-knowledge also depends on interpretations that could be false.[70] In a slightly different sense, self-knowledge can also refer to knowledge of the self as a persisting entity with certain personality traits, preferences, physical attributes, relationships, goals, and social identities.[71][h]

Metaknowledge is knowledge about knowledge. It can arise in the form of self-knowledge but includes other types as well, such as knowing what someone else knows or what information is contained in a scientific article. Other aspects of metaknowledge include knowing how knowledge can be acquired, stored, distributed, and used.[73]

Common knowledge is knowledge that is publicly known and shared by most individuals within a community. It establishes a common ground for communication, understanding, social cohesion, and cooperation.[74] General knowledge encompasses common knowledge but also includes knowledge that many people have been exposed to but may not be able to immediately recall.[75] Common knowledge contrasts with domain knowledge or specialized knowledge, which belongs to a specific domain and is only possessed by experts.[76]

Situated knowledge is knowledge specific to a particular situation.[77] It is closely related to practical or tacit knowledge, which is learned and applied in specific circumstances. This especially concerns certain forms of acquiring knowledge, such as trial and error or learning from experience.[78] In this regard, situated knowledge usually lacks a more explicit structure and is not articulated in terms of universal ideas.[79] The term is often used in feminism and postmodernism to argue that many forms of knowledge are not absolute but depend on the concrete historical, cultural, and linguistic context.[77]

Explicit knowledge is knowledge that can be fully articulated, shared, and explained, like the knowledge of historical dates and mathematical formulas. It can be acquired through traditional learning methods, such as reading books and attending lectures. It contrasts with tacit knowledge, which is not easily articulated or explained to others, like the ability to recognize someone's face and the practical expertise of a master craftsman. Tacit knowledge is often learned through first-hand experience or direct practice.[80]

Cognitive load theory distinguishes between biologically primary and secondary knowledge. Biologically primary knowledge is knowledge that humans have as part of their evolutionary heritage, such as knowing how to recognize faces and speech and many general problem-solving capacities. Biologically secondary knowledge is knowledge acquired because of specific social and cultural circumstances, such as knowing how to read and write.[81]

Knowledge can be occurrent or dispositional. Occurrent knowledge is knowledge that is actively involved in cognitive processes. Dispositional knowledge, by contrast, lies dormant in the back of a person's mind and is given by the mere ability to access the relevant information. For example, if a person knows that cats have whiskers then this knowledge is dispositional most of the time and becomes occurrent while they are thinking about it.[82]

Many forms of Eastern spirituality and religion distinguish between higher and lower knowledge. They are also referred to as para vidya and apara vidya in Hinduism or the two truths doctrine in Buddhism. Lower knowledge is based on the senses and the intellect. It encompasses both mundane or conventional truths as well as discoveries of the empirical sciences.[83] Higher knowledge is understood as knowledge of God, the absolute, the true self, or the ultimate reality. It belongs neither to the external world of physical objects nor to the internal world of the experience of emotions and concepts. Many spiritual teachings stress the importance of higher knowledge to progress on the spiritual path and to see reality as it truly is beyond the veil of appearances.[84]

Sources

 
Perception relies on the senses to acquire knowledge.

Sources of knowledge are ways in which people come to know things. They can be understood as cognitive capacities that are exercised when a person acquires new knowledge.[85] Various sources of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature, often in terms of the mental faculties responsible. They include perception, introspection, memory, inference, and testimony. However, not everyone agrees that all of them actually lead to knowledge. Usually, perception or observation, i.e. using one of the senses, is identified as the most important source of empirical knowledge.[86] Knowing that a baby is sleeping is observational knowledge if it was caused by a perception of the snoring baby. However, this would not be the case if one learned about this fact through a telephone conversation with one's spouse. Perception comes in different modalities, including vision, sound, touch, smell, and taste, which correspond to different physical stimuli.[87] It is an active process in which sensory signals are selected, organized, and interpreted to form a representation of the environment. This leads in some cases to illusions that misrepresent certain aspects of reality, like the Müller-Lyer illusion and the Ponzo illusion.[88]

Introspection is often seen in analogy to perception as a source of knowledge, not of external physical objects, but of internal mental states. A traditionally common view is that introspection has a special epistemic status by being infallible. According to this position, it is not possible to be mistaken about introspective facts, like whether one is in pain, because there is no difference between appearance and reality. However, this claim has been contested in the contemporary discourse and critics argue that it may be possible, for example, to mistake an unpleasant itch for a pain or to confuse the experience of a slight ellipse for the experience of a circle.[89] Perceptual and introspective knowledge often act as a form of fundamental or basic knowledge. According to some empiricists, they are the only sources of basic knowledge and provide the foundation for all other knowledge.[90]

Memory differs from perception and introspection in that it is not as independent or basic as they are since it depends on other previous experiences.[91] The faculty of memory retains knowledge acquired in the past and makes it accessible in the present, as when remembering a past event or a friend's phone number.[92] It is generally seen as a reliable source of knowledge. However, it can be deceptive at times nonetheless, either because the original experience was unreliable or because the memory degraded and does not accurately represent the original experience anymore.[93][i]

Knowledge based on perception, introspection, and memory may give rise to inferential knowledge, which comes about when reasoning is applied to draw inferences from other known facts.[95] For example, the perceptual knowledge of a Czech stamp on a postcard may give rise to the inferential knowledge that one's friend is visiting the Czech Republic. This type of knowledge depends on other sources of knowledge responsible for the premises. Some rationalists argue for rational intuition as a further source of knowledge that does not rely on observation and introspection. They hold for example that some beliefs, like the mathematical belief that 2 + 2 = 4, are justified through pure reason alone.[96]

 
Knowledge by testimony relies on statements given by other people, like the testimony given at a trial.

Testimony is often included as an additional source of knowledge that, unlike the other sources, is not tied to one specific cognitive faculty. Instead, it is based on the idea that one person can come to know a fact because another person talks about this fact. Testimony can happen in numerous ways, like regular speech, a letter, a newspaper, or a blog. The problem of testimony consists in clarifying why and under what circumstances testimony can lead to knowledge. A common response is that it depends on the reliability of the person pronouncing the testimony: only testimony from reliable sources can lead to knowledge.[97]

Limits

The problem of the limits of knowledge concerns the question of which facts are unknowable.[98] These limits constitute a form of inevitable ignorance that can affect both what is knowable about the external world as well as what one can know about oneself and about what is good.[99] Some limits of knowledge only apply to particular people in specific situations while others pertain to humanity at large.[100] A fact is unknowable to a person if this person lacks access to the relevant information, like facts in the past that did not leave any significant traces. For example, it may be unknowable to people today what Caesar's breakfast was the day he was assassinated but it was knowable to him and some contemporaries.[101] Another factor restricting knowledge is given by the limitations of the human cognitive faculties. Some people may lack the cognitive ability to understand highly abstract mathematical truths and some facts cannot be known by any human because they are too complex for the human mind to conceive.[102] A further limit of knowledge arises due to certain logical paradoxes. For instance, there are some ideas that will never occur to anyone. It is not possible to know them because if a person knew about such an idea then this idea would have occurred at least to them.[103][j]

There are many disputes about what can or cannot be known in certain fields. Religious skepticism is the view that beliefs about God or other religious doctrines do not amount to knowledge.[105] Moral skepticism encompasses a variety of views, including the claim that moral knowledge is impossible, meaning that one cannot know what is morally good or whether a certain behavior is morally right.[106] An influential theory about the limits of metaphysical knowledge was proposed by Immanuel Kant. For him, knowledge is restricted to the field of appearances and does not reach the things in themselves, which exist independently of humans and lie beyond the realm of appearances. Based on the observation that metaphysics aims to characterize the things in themselves, he concludes that no metaphysical knowledge is possible, like knowing whether the world has a beginning or is infinite.[107]

There are also limits to knowledge in the empirical sciences, such as the uncertainty principle, which states that it is impossible to know the exact magnitudes of certain certain pairs of physical properties, like the position and momentum of a particle, at the same time.[108] Other examples are physical systems studied by chaos theory, for which it is not practically possible to predict how they will behave since they are so sensitive to initial conditions that even the slightest of variations may produce a completely different behavior. This phenomenon is known as the butterfly effect.[109]

 
Pyrrho was one of the first philosophical skeptics.

The strongest position about the limits of knowledge is radical or global skepticism, which holds that humans lack any form of knowledge or that knowledge is impossible. For example, the dream argument states that perceptual experience is not a source of knowledge since dreaming provides unreliable information and a person could be dreaming without knowing it. Because of this inability to discriminate between dream and perception, it is argued that there is no perceptual knowledge of the external world.[110][k] This thought experiment is based on the problem of underdetermination, which arises when the available evidence is not sufficient to make a rational decision between competing theories. In such cases, a person is not justified in believing one theory rather than the other. If this is always the case then global skepticism follows.[111] Another skeptical argument assumes that knowledge requires absolute certainty and aims to show that all human cognition is fallible since it fails to meet this standard.[112]

An influential argument against radical skepticism states that radical skepticism is self-contradictory since denying the existence of knowledge is itself a knowledge-claim.[113] Other arguments rely on common sense[114] or deny that infallibility is required for knowledge.[115] Very few philosophers have explicitly defended radical skepticism but this position has been influential nonetheless, usually in a negative sense: many see it as a serious challenge to any epistemological theory and often try to show how their preferred theory overcomes it.[116] Another form of philosophical skepticism advocates the suspension of judgment as a form of attaining tranquility while remaining humble and open-minded.[117]

A less radical limit of knowledge is identified by falliblists, who argue that the possibility of error can never be fully excluded. This means that even the best-researched scientific theories and the most fundamental commonsense views could still be subject to error. Further research may reduce the possibility of being wrong, but it can never fully exclude it. Some fallibilists reach the skeptical conclusion from this observation that there is no knowledge but the more common view is that knowledge exists but is fallible.[118] Pragmatists argue that one consequence of fallibilism is that inquiry should not aim for truth or absolute certainty but for well-supported and justified beliefs while remaining open to the possibility that one's beliefs may need to be revised later.[119]

Structure

The structure of knowledge is the way in which the mental states of a person need to be related to each other for knowledge to arise.[120] A common view is that a person has to have good reasons for holding a belief if this belief is to amount to knowledge. When the belief is challenged, the person may justify it by referring to their reason for holding it. In many cases, this reason depends itself on another belief that may as well be challenged. An example is a person who believes that Ford cars are cheaper than BMWs. When their belief is challenged, they may justify it by claiming that they heard it from a reliable source. This justification depends on the assumption that their source is reliable, which may itself be challenged. The same may apply to any subsequent reason they cite.[121] This threatens to lead to an infinite regress since the epistemic status at each step depends on the epistemic status of the previous step.[122] Theories of the structure of knowledge offer responses for how to solve this problem.[121]

 
Foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism are theories of the structure of knowledge. The black arrows symbolize how one belief supports another belief.

Three traditional theories are foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism. Foundationalists and coherentists deny the existence of an infinite regress, in contrast to infinitists.[121] According to foundationalists, some basic reasons have their epistemic status independent of other reasons and thereby constitute the endpoint of the regress.[123] Some foundationalists hold that certain sources of knowledge, like perception, provide basic reasons. Another view is that this role is played by certain self-evident truths, like the knowledge of one's own existence and the content of one's ideas.[124] The view that basic reasons exist is not universally accepted. One criticism states that there should be a reason why some reasons are basic while others are not. According to this view, the putative basic reasons are not actually basic since their status would depend on other reasons. Another criticism is based on hermeneutics and argues that all understanding is circular and requires interpretation, which implies that knowledge does not need a secure foundation.[125]

Coherentists and infinitists avoid these problems by denying the contrast between basic and non-basic reasons. Coherentists argue that there is only a finite number of reasons, which mutually support and justify one another. This is based on the intuition that beliefs do not exist in isolation but form a complex web of interconnected ideas that is justified by its coherence rather than by a few privileged foundational beliefs.[126] One difficulty for this view is how to demonstrate that it does not involve the fallacy of circular reasoning.[127] If two beliefs mutually support each other then a person has a reason for accepting one belief if they already have the other. However, mutual support alone is not a good reason for newly accepting both beliefs at once. A closely related issue is that there can be distinct sets of coherent beliefs. Coherentists face the problem of explaining why someone should accept one coherent set rather than another.[126] For infinitists, in contrast to foundationalists and coherentists, there is an infinite number of reasons. This view embraces the idea that there is a regress since each reason depends on another reason. One difficulty for this view is that the human mind is limited and may not be able to possess an infinite number of reasons. This raises the question of whether, according to infinitism, human knowledge is possible at all.[128]

Value

 
Los portadores de la antorcha (The Torch-Bearers) – sculpture by Anna Hyatt Huntington symbolizing the transmission of knowledge from one generation to the next (Ciudad Universitaria, Madrid, Spain)

Knowledge may be valuable either because it is useful or because it is good in itself. Knowledge can be useful by helping a person achieve their goals. For example, if one knows the answers to questions in an exam one is able to pass that exam or by knowing which horse is the fastest, one can earn money from bets. In these cases, knowledge has instrumental value.[129] Not all forms of knowledge are useful and many beliefs about trivial matters have no instrumental value. This concerns, for example, knowing how many grains of sand are on a specific beach or memorizing phone numbers one never intends to call. In a few cases, knowledge may even have a negative value. For example, if a person's life depends on gathering the courage to jump over a ravine, then having a true belief about the involved dangers may hinder them from doing so.[130]

 
The value of knowledge plays a key role in education for deciding which knowledge to pass on to the students.

Besides having instrumental value, knowledge may also have intrinsic value. This means that some forms of knowledge are good in themselves even if they do not provide any practical benefits. According to philosopher Duncan Pritchard, this applies to forms of knowledge linked to wisdom.[131] It is controversial whether all knowledge has intrinsic value, including knowledge about trivial facts like knowing whether the biggest apple tree had an even number of leaves yesterday morning. One view in favor of the intrinsic value of knowledge states that having no belief about a matter is a neutral state and knowledge is always better than this neutral state, even if the value difference is only minimal.[132]

A more specific issue in epistemology concerns the question of whether or why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief.[133] There is wide agreement that knowledge is usually good in some sense but the thesis that knowledge is better than true belief is controversial. An early discussion of this problem is found in Plato's Meno in relation to the claim that both knowledge and true belief can successfully guide action and, therefore, have apparently the same value. For example, it seems that mere true belief is as effective as knowledge when trying to find the way to Larissa.[134] According to Plato, knowledge is better because it is more stable.[135] Another suggestion is that knowledge gets its additional value from justification. One difficulty for this view is that while justification makes it more probable that a belief is true, it is not clear what additional value it provides in comparison to an unjustified belief that is already true.[136]

The problem of the value of knowledge is often discussed in relation to reliabilism and virtue epistemology.[137] Reliabilism can be defined as the thesis that knowledge is reliably formed true belief. This view has difficulties in explaining why knowledge is valuable or how a reliable belief-forming process adds additional value.[138] According to an analogy by philosopher Linda Zagzebski, a cup of coffee made by a reliable coffee machine has the same value as an equally good cup of coffee made by an unreliable coffee machine.[139] This difficulty in solving the value problem is sometimes used as an argument against reliabilism.[140] Virtue epistemology, by contrast, offers a unique solution to the value problem. Virtue epistemologists see knowledge as the manifestation of cognitive virtues. They hold that knowledge has additional value due to its association with virtue. This is based on the idea that cognitive success in the form of the manifestation of virtues is inherently valuable independent of whether the resulting states are instrumentally useful.[141]

Acquiring and transmitting knowledge often comes with certain costs, such as the material resources required to obtain new information and the time and energy needed to understand it. For this reason, an awareness of the value of knowledge is crucial to many fields that have to make decisions about whether to seek knowledge about a specific matter. On a political level, this concerns the problem of identifying the most promising research programs to allocate funds.[142] Similar concerns affect businesses, where stakeholders have to decide whether the cost of acquiring knowledge is justified by the economic benefits that this knowledge may provide, and the military, which relies on intelligence to identify and prevent threats.[143] In the field of education, the value of knowledge can be used to choose which knowledge should be passed on to the students.[144]

Science

The scientific approach is usually regarded as an exemplary process of how to gain knowledge about empirical facts.[145] Scientific knowledge includes mundane knowledge about easily observable facts, for example, chemical knowledge that certain reactants become hot when mixed together. It also encompasses knowledge of less tangible issues, like claims about the behavior of genes, neutrinos, and black holes.[146]

A key aspect of most forms of science is that they seek natural laws that explain empirical observations.[145] Scientific knowledge is discovered and tested using the scientific method.[l] This method aims to arrive at reliable knowledge by formulating the problem in a clear way and by ensuring that the evidence used to support or refute a specific theory is public, reliable, and replicable. This way, other researchers can repeat the experiments and observations in the initial study to confirm or disconfirm it.[148] The scientific method is often analyzed as a series of steps that begins with regular observation and data collection. Based on these insights, scientists then try to find a hypothesis that explains the observations. The hypothesis is then tested using a controlled experiment to compare whether predictions based on the hypothesis match the observed results. As a last step, the results are interpreted and a conclusion is reached whether and to what degree the findings confirm or disconfirm the hypothesis.[149]

The empirical sciences are usually divided into natural and social sciences. The natural sciences, like physics, biology, and chemistry, focus on quantitative research methods to arrive at knowledge about natural phenomena.[150] Quantitative research happens by making precise numerical measurements and the natural sciences often rely on advanced technological instruments to perform these measurements and to setup experiments. Another common feature of their approach is to use mathematical tools to analyze the measured data and formulate exact and general laws to describe the observed phenomena.[151]

The social sciences, like sociology, anthropology, and communication studies, examine social phenomena on the level of human behavior, relationships, and society at large.[152] While they also make use of quantitative research, they usually give more emphasis to qualitative methods. Qualitative research gathers non-numerical data, often with the goal of arriving at a deeper understanding of the meaning and interpretation of social phenomena from the perspective of those involved.[153] This approach can take various forms, such as interviews, focus groups, and case studies.[154] Mixed-method research combines quantitative and qualitative methods to explore the same phenomena from a variety of perspectives to get a more comprehensive understanding.[155]

The progress of scientific knowledge is traditionally seen as a gradual and continuous process in which the existing body of knowledge is increased at each step. This view has been challenged by some philosophers of science, such as Thomas Kuhn, who holds that between phases of incremental progress, there are so-called scientific revolutions in which a paradigm shift occurs. According to this view, some basic assumptions are changed due to the paradigm shift, resulting in a radically new perspective on the body of scientific knowledge that is incommensurable with the previous outlook.[156][m]

Scientism refers to a group of views that privilege the sciences and the scientific method over other forms of inquiry and knowledge acquisition. In its strongest formulation, it is the claim that there is no other knowledge besides scientific knowledge.[158] A common critique of scientism, made by philosophers such as Hans-Georg Gadamer and Paul Feyerabend, is that the fixed requirement of following the scientific method is too rigid and results in a misleading picture of reality by excluding various relevant phenomena from the scope of knowledge.[159]

History

The history of knowledge is the field of inquiry that studies how knowledge in different fields has developed and evolved in the course of history. It is closely related to the history of science, but covers a wider area that includes knowledge from fields like philosophy, mathematics, education, literature, art, and religion. It further covers practical knowledge of specific crafts, medicine, and everyday practices. It investigates not only how knowledge is created and employed, but also how it is disseminated and preserved.[160]

Before the ancient period, knowledge about social conduct and survival skills was passed down orally and in the form of customs from one generation to the next.[161] The ancient period saw the rise of major civilizations starting about 3000 BCE in Mesopotamia, Egypt, India, and China. The invention of writing in this period significantly increased the amount of stable knowledge within society since it could be stored and shared without being limited by imperfect human memory.[162] During this time, the first developments in scientific fields like mathematics, astronomy, and medicine were made. They were later formalized and greatly expanded by the ancient Greeks starting in the 6th century BCE. Other ancient advancements concerned knowledge in the fields of agriculture, law, and politics.[163]

 
The invention of the printing press in the 15th century greatly expanded access to written materials.

In the medieval period, religious knowledge was a central concern, and religious institutions, like the Catholic Church in Europe, influenced intellectual activity.[164] Jewish communities set up yeshivas as centers for studying religious texts and Jewish law.[165] In the Muslim world, madrasa schools were established and focused on Islamic law and Islamic philosophy.[166] Many intellectual achievements of the ancient period were preserved, refined, and expanded during the Islamic Golden Age from the 8th to 13th centuries.[167] Centers of higher learning were established in this period in various regions, like Al-Qarawiyyin University in Morocco,[168] the Al-Azhar University in Egypt,[169] the House of Wisdom in Iraq,[170] and the first universities in Europe.[171] This period also saw the formation of guilds, which preserved and advanced technical and craft knowledge.[172]

In the Renaissance period, starting in the 14th century, there was a renewed interest in the humanities and sciences.[173] The printing press was invented in the 15th century and significantly increased the availability of written media and general literacy of the population.[174] These developments served as the foundation of the Scientific Revolution in the Age of Enlightenment starting in the 16th and 17th centuries. It led to an explosion of knowledge in fields such as physics, chemistry, biology, and the social sciences.[175] The technological advancements that accompanied this development made possible the Industrial Revolution in the 18th and 19th centuries.[176] In the 20th century, the development of computers and the Internet led to a vast expansion of knowledge by revolutionizing how knowledge is stored, shared, and created.[177][n]

In various disciplines

Religion

Knowledge plays a central role in many religions. Knowledge claims about the existence of God or religious doctrines about how each one should live their lives are found in almost every culture.[179] However, such knowledge claims are often controversial and are commonly rejected by religious skeptics and atheists.[180] The epistemology of religion is the field of inquiry studying whether belief in God and in other religious doctrines is rational and amounts to knowledge.[181] One important view in this field is evidentialism, which states that belief in religious doctrines is justified if it is supported by sufficient evidence. Suggested examples of evidence for religious doctrines include religious experiences such as direct contact with the divine or inner testimony when hearing God's voice.[182] Evidentialists often reject that belief in religious doctrines amounts to knowledge based on the claim that there is not sufficient evidence.[183] A famous saying in this regard is due to Bertrand Russell. When asked how he would justify his lack of belief in God when facing his judgment after death, he replied "Not enough evidence, God! Not enough evidence."[184]

However, religious teachings about the existence and nature of God are not always seen as knowledge claims by their defenders. Some explicitly state that the proper attitude towards such doctrines is not knowledge but faith. This is often combined with the assumption that these doctrines are true but cannot be fully understood by reason or verified through rational inquiry. For this reason, it is claimed that one should accept them even though they do not amount to knowledge.[180] Such a view is reflected in a famous saying by Immanuel Kant where he claims that he "had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith."[185]

Distinct religions often differ from each other concerning the doctrines they proclaim as well as their understanding of the role of knowledge in religious practice.[186] In both the Jewish and the Christian traditions, knowledge plays a role in the fall of man, in which Adam and Eve were expelled from the Garden of Eden. Responsible for this fall was that they ignored God's command and ate from the tree of knowledge, which gave them the knowledge of good and evil. This is seen as a rebellion against God since this knowledge belongs to God and it is not for humans to decide what is right or wrong.[187] In the Christian literature, knowledge is seen as one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit.[188] In Islam, "the Knowing" (al-ʿAlīm) is one of the 99 names reflecting distinct attributes of God. The Qur'an asserts that knowledge comes from Allah and the acquisition of knowledge is encouraged in the teachings of Muhammad.[189]

 
Saraswati is the goddess of knowledge and the arts in Hinduism.

In Buddhism, knowledge that leads to liberation is called vijjā. It contrasts with avijjā or ignorance, which is understood as the root of all suffering. This is often explained in relation to the claim that humans suffer because they crave things that are impermanent. The ignorance of the impermanent nature of things is seen as the factor responsible for this craving.[190] The central goal of Buddhist practice is to stop suffering. This aim is to be achieved by understanding and practicing the teaching known as the Four Noble Truths and thereby overcoming ignorance.[191] Knowledge plays a key role in the classical path of Hinduism known as jñāna yoga or "path of knowledge". It aims to achieve oneness with the divine by fostering an understanding of the self and its relation to Brahman or ultimate reality.[192]

Anthropology

The anthropology of knowledge is a multi-disciplinary field of inquiry.[193] It studies how knowledge is acquired, stored, retrieved, and communicated.[194] Special interest is given to how knowledge is reproduced and changes in relation to social and cultural circumstances.[195] In this context, the term knowledge is used in a very broad sense, roughly equivalent to terms like understanding and culture.[196] This means that the forms and reproduction of understanding are studied irrespective of their truth value. In epistemology, by contrast, knowledge is usually restricted to forms of true belief. The main focus in anthropology is on empirical observations of how people ascribe truth values to meaning contents, like when affirming an assertion, even if these contents are false.[195] This also includes practical components: knowledge is what is employed when interpreting and acting on the world and involves diverse phenomena, such as feelings, embodied skills, information, and concepts. It is used to understand and anticipate events to prepare and react accordingly.[197]

The reproduction of knowledge and its changes often happen through some form of communication used to transfer knowledge.[198] This includes face-to-face discussions and online communications as well as seminars and rituals. An important role in this context falls to institutions, like university departments or scientific journals in the academic context.[195] Anthropologists of knowledge understand traditions as knowledge that has been reproduced within a society or geographic region over several generations. They are interested in how this reproduction is affected by external influences. For example, societies tend to interpret knowledge claims found in other societies and incorporate them in a modified form.[199]

Within a society, people belonging to the same social group usually understand things and organize knowledge in similar ways to one another. In this regard, social identities play a significant role: people who associate themselves with similar identities, like age-influenced, professional, religious, and ethnic identities, tend to embody similar forms of knowledge. Such identities concern both how a person sees themselves, for example, in terms of the ideals they pursue, as well as how other people see them, such as the expectations they have toward the person.[200]

Sociology

The sociology of knowledge is the subfield of sociology that studies how thought and society are related to each other.[201] Like the anthropology of knowledge, it understands "knowledge" in a wide sense that encompasses philosophical and political ideas, religious and ideological doctrines, folklore, law, and technology. The sociology of knowledge studies in what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises, what consequences it has, and on what existential conditions it depends. The examined conditions include physical, demographic, economic, and sociocultural factors. For instance, philosopher Karl Marx claimed that the dominant ideology in a society is a product of and changes with the underlying socioeconomic conditions.[201] Another example is found in forms of decolonial scholarship that claim that colonial powers are responsible for the hegemony of Western knowledge systems. They seek a decolonization of knowledge to undermine this hegemony.[202] A related issue concerns the link between knowledge and power, in particular, the extent to which knowledge is power. The philosopher Michel Foucault explored this issue and examined how knowledge and the institutions responsible for it control people through what he termed biopower by shaping societal norms, values, and regulatory mechanisms in fields like psychiatry, medicine, and the penal system.[203]

A central subfield is the sociology of scientific knowledge, which investigates the social factors involved in the production and validation of scientific knowledge. This encompasses examining the impact of the distribution of resources and rewards on the scientific process, which leads some areas of research to flourish while others languish. Further topics focus on selection processes, such as how academic journals decide whether to publish an article and how academic institutions recruit researchers, and the general values and norms characteristic of the scientific profession.[204]

Others

Formal epistemology studies knowledge using formal tools found in mathematics and logic.[205] An important issue in this field concerns the epistemic principles of knowledge. These are rules governing how knowledge and related states behave and in what relations they stand to each other. The transparency principle, also referred to as the luminosity of knowledge, states that it is impossible for someone to know something without knowing that they know it.[o][206] According to the conjunction principle, if a person has justified beliefs in two separate propositions, then they are also justified in believing the conjunction of these two propositions. In this regard, if Bob has a justified belief that dogs are animals and another justified belief that cats are animals, then he is justified to believe the conjunction that both dogs and cats are animals. Other commonly discussed principles are the closure principle and the evidence transfer principle.[207]

Knowledge management is the process of creating, gathering, storing, and sharing knowledge. It involves the management of information assets that can take the form of documents, databases, policies, and procedures. It is of particular interest in the field of business and organizational development, as it directly impacts decision-making and strategic planning. Knowledge management efforts are often employed to increase operational efficiency in attempts to gain a competitive advantage.[208] Key processes in the field of knowledge management are knowledge creation, knowledge storage, knowledge sharing, and knowledge application. Knowledge creation is the first step and involves the production of new information. Knowledge storage can happen through media like books, audio recordings, film, and digital databases. Secure storage facilitates knowledge sharing, which involves the transmission of information from one person to another. For the knowledge to be beneficial, it has to be put into practice, meaning that its insights should be used to either improve existing practices or implement new ones.[209]

Knowledge representation is the process of storing organized information, which may happen using various forms of media and also includes information stored in the mind.[210] It plays a key role in the artificial intelligence, where the term is used for the field of inquiry that studies how computer systems can efficiently represent information. This field investigates how different data structures and interpretative procedures can be combined to achieve this goal and which formal languages can be used to express knowledge items. Some efforts in this field are directed at developing general languages and systems that can be employed in a great variety of domains while others focus on an optimized representation method within one specific domain. Knowledge representation is closely linked to automatic reasoning because the purpose of knowledge representation formalisms is usually to construct a knowledge base from which inferences are drawn.[211] Influential knowledge base formalisms include logic-based systems, rule-based systems, semantic networks, and frames. Logic-based systems rely on formal languages employed in logic to represent knowledge. They use linguistic devices like individual terms, predicates, and quantifiers. For rule-based systems, each unit of information is expressed using a conditional production rule of the form "if A then B". Semantic nets model knowledge as a graph consisting of vertices to represent facts or concepts and edges to represent the relations between them. Frames provide complex taxonomies to group items into classes, subclasses, and instances.[212]

Pedagogy is the study of teaching methods or the art of teaching.[p] It explores how learning takes place and which techniques teachers may employ to transmit knowledge to students and improve their learning experience while keeping them motivated.[214] There is a great variety of teaching methods and the most effective approach often depends on factors like the subject matter and the age and proficiency level of the learner.[215] In teacher-centered education, the teacher acts as the authority figure imparting information and directing the learning process. Student-centered approaches give a more active role to students with the teacher acting as a coach to facilitate the process.[216] Further methodological considerations encompass the difference between group work and individual learning and the use of instructional media and other forms of educational technology.[217]

See also

  • Epistemic modal logic – subfield of modal logic that is concerned with reasoning about knowledge
  • Ignorance – Lack of knowledge and understanding
  • Knowledge falsification – Deliberate misrepresentation of knowledge
  • Omniscience – Capacity to know everything
  • Outline of knowledge – Knowledge: what is known, understood, proven; information and products of learning

References

Notes

  1. ^ In this context, testimony is what other people report, both in spoken and written form.
  2. ^ A similar approach was already discussed in Ancient Greek philosophy in Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, where Socrates pondered the distinction between knowledge and true belief but rejected this definition.[22]
  3. ^ Truth is usually associated with objectivity. This view is rejected by relativism about truth, which argues that what is true depends on one's perspective.[24]
  4. ^ A defeater of a belief is evidence that this belief is false.[37]
  5. ^ A distinction similar to the one between knowledge-that and knowledge-how was already discussed in ancient Greece as the contrast between epistēmē (unchanging theoretical knowledge) and technē (expert technical knowledge).[43]
  6. ^ For instance, to know whether Ben is rich can be understood as knowing that Ben is rich, in case he is, and knowing that Ben is not rich, in case he is not.[49]
  7. ^ However, it is controversial to what extent goal-directed behavior in lower animals is comparable to human knowledge-how.[56]
  8. ^ Individuals may lack a deeper understanding of their character and feelings and attaining self-knowledge is one step in psychoanalysis.[72]
  9. ^ Confabulation is a special type of memory error that consists remembering events that did not happen, often provoked by an attempt to fill memory gaps.[94]
  10. ^ An often-cited paradox from the field of formal epistemology is Fitch's paradox of knowability, which states that knowledge has limits because denying this claim leads to the absurd conclusion that every truth is known.[104]
  11. ^ A similar often-cited thought experiment assumes that a person is not a regular human being but a brain in a vat that receives electrical stimuli. These stimuli give the brain the false impression of having a body and interacting with the external world. Since the person is unable to tell the difference, it is argued that they do not know that they have a body responsible for reliable perceptions.[111]
  12. ^ It is controversial to what extent there is a single scientific method that applies equally to all sciences rather than a group of related approaches.[147]
  13. ^ It is controversial how radical the difference between paradigms is and whether they truly are incommensurable.[157]
  14. ^ The internet also reduced the cost of accessing knowledge with a lot of information being freely available.[178]
  15. ^ This principle implies that if Heike knows that today is Monday, then she also knows that she knows that today is Monday.
  16. ^ The exact definition of the term is disputed.[213]

Citations

  1. ^
  2. ^
  3. ^
  4. ^
  5. ^
  6. ^
  7. ^
  8. ^
  9. ^
  10. ^
  11. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 2. What Is Knowledge?
  12. ^ Allen 2005
  13. ^
  14. ^
  15. ^
  16. ^
  17. ^ Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 7. Is Knowledge Analyzable?
  18. ^
  19. ^
  20. ^
  21. ^
  22. ^
  23. ^
  24. ^
  25. ^
  26. ^
  27. ^
  28. ^
  29. ^
    • Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 1.3 The Justification Condition, § 6.1 Reliabilist Theories of Knowledge
    • Klein 1998, § 4. Foundationalism and Coherentism, § 6. Externalism
    • Hetherington 2022a, § 5a. The Justified-True-Belief Conception of Knowledge, § 7. Knowing’s Point
  30. ^ Hetherington 2022, Lead Section, § Introduction
  31. ^
  32. ^
  33. ^ Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 3. The Gettier Problem, § 10.2 Fake Barn Cases
  34. ^ Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 3. The Gettier Problem, § 4. No False Lemmas, § 5. Modal Conditions, § 6. Doing Without Justification?
  35. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 2.3 Knowing Facts
  36. ^
  37. ^ McCain, Stapleford & Steup 2021, p. 111
  38. ^
  39. ^
  40. ^
  41. ^
  42. ^
  43. ^ Allen 2005, Lead Section
  44. ^
  45. ^
  46. ^
  47. ^ Hetherington 2022a, § 1b. Knowledge-That, § 1c. Knowledge-Wh
  48. ^
  49. ^ Hetherington 2022a, § 1c. Knowledge-Wh
  50. ^
  51. ^ Woolfolk & Margetts 2012, p. 251
  52. ^ a b Pritchard 2013, 1 Some preliminaries
  53. ^
  54. ^
  55. ^
  56. ^ Pavese 2022, § 7.4 Knowledge-How in Preverbal Children and Nonhuman Animals.
  57. ^
  58. ^
  59. ^
  60. ^
  61. ^
  62. ^ Baehr 2022, Lead Section
  63. ^
  64. ^ Moser 2016, Lead Section
  65. ^
    • Baehr 2022, § 1. An Initial Characterization, § 4. The Relevant Sense of 'Experience'
    • Russell 2020, § 4.1 A Priori Justification Is Justification That Is Independent of Experience
  66. ^
  67. ^
  68. ^
  69. ^ Baehr 2022, § 1. An Initial Characterization, § 6. Positive Characterizations of the A Priori
  70. ^
  71. ^
  72. ^
  73. ^
  74. ^
  75. ^ Schneider & McGrew 2022, pp. 115–116
  76. ^
  77. ^ a b
  78. ^ Barnett 2006, pp. 146–147
  79. ^ Hunter 2009, pp. 151–153
  80. ^
  81. ^
  82. ^
  83. ^
  84. ^
  85. ^
  86. ^
  87. ^
  88. ^
  89. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 5.2 Introspection
  90. ^
  91. ^
  92. ^
  93. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 5.3 Memory
  94. ^
  95. ^
  96. ^
  97. ^
  98. ^
  99. ^
  100. ^ Rescher 2009, p. 6
  101. ^
  102. ^
  103. ^
  104. ^ Weisberg 2021, § 4.2 The Knowability Paradox (a.k.a. the Church-Fitch Paradox)
  105. ^ Kreeft & Tacelli 2009, p. 371
  106. ^
  107. ^
  108. ^
  109. ^ Yanofsky 2013, pp. 161–164
  110. ^
  111. ^ a b Steup & Neta 2020, § 6.1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism
  112. ^
  113. ^ Stroll 2023, § Skepticism
  114. ^
  115. ^
  116. ^
  117. ^
  118. ^
  119. ^
  120. ^
  121. ^ a b c
  122. ^
  123. ^
  124. ^
  125. ^
  126. ^ a b
  127. ^
  128. ^ Klein 1998, § 4. Foundationalism and Coherentism
  129. ^
  130. ^ Pritchard 2013, 2 The value of knowledge
  131. ^
  132. ^
  133. ^
  134. ^
  135. ^ Olsson 2011, p. 875
  136. ^ Pritchard, Turri & Carter 2022, Lead Section, § 6. Other Accounts of the Value of Knowledge
  137. ^
  138. ^ Pritchard, Turri & Carter 2022, § 2. Reliabilism and the Meno Problem, § 3. Virtue Epistemology and the Value Problem
  139. ^ Turri, Alfano & Greco 2021
  140. ^ Pritchard, Turri & Carter 2022, § 2. Reliabilism and the Meno Problem
  141. ^
  142. ^
  143. ^
  144. ^ Degenhardt 2019, pp. 1–6
  145. ^ a b
  146. ^ Moser 2005, p. 386
  147. ^ Hepburn & Andersen 2021, Lead Section, § 1. Overview and organizing themes
  148. ^
  149. ^
  150. ^
  151. ^
  152. ^
  153. ^
  154. ^
  155. ^
  156. ^
  157. ^ Bird 2022, § 6.2 Incommensurability
  158. ^ Plantinga 2018, pp. 222–223
  159. ^
  160. ^
    • Burke 2015, 1. Knowledges and Their Histories: § History and Its Neighbours, 3. Processes: § Four Stages, 3. Processes: § Oral Transmission
    • Doren 1992, pp. xvi–xviii
    • Daston 2017, pp. 142–143
    • Mulsow 2018, p. 159
  161. ^
  162. ^
  163. ^
  164. ^
  165. ^
  166. ^
  167. ^ Trefil 2012, pp. 49–51
  168. ^ Aqil, Babekri & Nadmi 2020, p. 156
  169. ^ Cosman & Jones 2009, p. 148
  170. ^ Gilliot 2018, p. 81
  171. ^
  172. ^ Power 1970, pp. 243–244
  173. ^
  174. ^
  175. ^
  176. ^
  177. ^
  178. ^
  179. ^ Clark 2022, Lead Section, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
  180. ^ a b Penelhum 1971, 1. Faith, Scepticism and Philosophy
  181. ^
  182. ^
    • Clark 2022, Lead Section, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
    • Forrest 2021, Lead Section, § 2. The Rejection of Enlightenment Evidentialism
    • Dougherty 2014, pp. 97–98
  183. ^
    • Clark 2022, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
    • Forrest 2021, Lead Section, 2. The Rejection of Enlightenment Evidentialism
  184. ^ Clark 2022, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
  185. ^ Stevenson 2003, pp. 72–73
  186. ^
  187. ^
  188. ^
  189. ^
  190. ^
  191. ^
  192. ^
  193. ^
    • Allwood 2013, pp. 69–72
    • Boyer 2007, 1. Of Dialectical Germans and Dialectical Ethnographers: Notes from an Engagement with Philosophy
  194. ^ Cohen 2010, pp. S193–S202
  195. ^ a b c Allwood 2013, pp. 69–72
  196. ^
  197. ^ Barth 2002, pp. 1–2
  198. ^
  199. ^
  200. ^
  201. ^ a b
  202. ^
  203. ^
  204. ^
  205. ^ Weisberg 2021
  206. ^
  207. ^ Klein 1998, § 7. Epistemic Principles
  208. ^
  209. ^
  210. ^
  211. ^
  212. ^
  213. ^ Watkins & Mortimore 1999, pp. 1–3
  214. ^
  215. ^
  216. ^ Emaliana 2017, pp. 59–61
  217. ^

Sources

  • AHD staff (2022a). "Knowledge". The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins. from the original on 29 November 2022. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  • AHD staff (2022b). "Knowledge Base". The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins. from the original on 19 March 2022. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  • AHD staff (2022c). "Intelligence". The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins. from the original on 8 January 2024. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • AHD Staff (2022d). "Social Science". The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins.
  • AHD Staff (2022e). "Confabulate". The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins.
  • Ames, Roger T.; Yajun, Chen; Hershock, Peter D. (2021). Confucianism and Deweyan Pragmatism: Resources for a New Geopolitics of Interdependence. University of Hawaii Press. ISBN 978-0-8248-8857-2.
  • Akerkar, Rajendra; Sajja, Priti (2010). Knowledge-Based Systems. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-0-7637-7647-3. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 2 December 2023.
  • Allen, Barry (2005). . In Horowitz, Maryanne Cline (ed.). New Dictionary of the History of Ideas. Vol. 3. Charles Scribner's Sons. pp. 1199–1204. ISBN 978-0-684-31377-1. OCLC 55800981. Archived from the original on 22 August 2017.
  • Allwood, Carl Martin (2013). "Anthropology of Knowledge". The Encyclopedia of Cross-Cultural Psychology. John Wiley & Sons, Inc. pp. 69–72. doi:10.1002/9781118339893.wbeccp025. ISBN 978-1-118-33989-3. from the original on 26 September 2022. Retrieved 26 September 2022.
  • Alter, Torin; Nagasawa, Yujin (2015). Consciousness in the Physical World: Perspectives on Russellian Monism. Oxford University Press. pp. 93–94. ISBN 978-0-19-992736-4. from the original on 1 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Antonio, Cartelli (2008). "Higher Education's New Frontier for the E-University and Virtual Campus". In Antonio, Cartelli; Marco, Palma (eds.). Encyclopedia of Information Communication Technology. IGI Global. ISBN 978-1-59904-846-8.
  • APA staff (2022). "Situated Knowledge". APA Dictionary of Psychology. American Psychological Association. from the original on 20 September 2022. Retrieved 18 September 2022.
  • Appelrouth, Scott; Edles, Laura Desfor (2008). Classical and Contemporary Sociological Theory: Text and Readings. Pine Forge Press. ISBN 978-0-7619-2793-8.
  • Aqil, Moulay Driss; Babekri, El Hassane; Nadmi, Mustapha (2020). "Morocco: Contributions to Mathematics Education From Morocco". In Vogeli, Bruce R.; Tom, Mohamed E. A. El (eds.). Mathematics And Its Teaching In The Muslim World. World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-314-679-2. from the original on 10 December 2023. Retrieved 15 December 2023.
  • Attie-Picker, Mario (2020). "Does Skepticism Lead to Tranquility? Exploring a Pyrrhonian Theme". In Lombrozo, Tania; Knobe, Joshua; Nichols, Shaun (eds.). Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy. Vol. 3. Oxford University Press. pp. 97–125. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198852407.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-885240-7.
  • Audi, Robert (2002). "The Sources of Knowledge". The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 71–94. ISBN 978-0-19-513005-8. from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Awad, Elias M.; Ghaziri, Hassan (2003). Knowledge Management. Pearson Education India. ISBN 978-93-325-0619-0. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 2 December 2023.
  • Baehr, Jason S. (2022). "A Priori and A Posteriori". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 4 October 2019. Retrieved 17 September 2022.
  • Baggini, J.; Southwell, G. (2016). Philosophy: Key Themes. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-00887-9.
  • Baird, Tess; Maskill, Linda (2017). "Memory". In Maskill, Linda; Tempest, Stephanie (eds.). Neuropsychology for Occupational Therapists: Cognition in Occupational Performance. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-71132-3.
  • Barnett, Michael (2006). "Vocational Knowledge and Vocational Pedagogy". In Young, Michael; Gamble, Jeanne (eds.). Knowledge, Curriculum and Qualifications for South African Further Education. HSRC Press. ISBN 978-0-7969-2154-3. from the original on 14 December 2023. Retrieved 14 December 2023.
  • Barth, Fredrik (2002). "An Anthropology of Knowledge". Current Anthropology. 43 (1): 1–18. doi:10.1086/324131. hdl:1956/4191. ISSN 0011-3204.
  • Bartlett, Steve; Burton, Diana (2007). Introduction to Education Studies (2nd ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-4129-2193-0.
  • Bartlett, Gary (2018). "Occurrent States". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 48 (1): 1–17. doi:10.1080/00455091.2017.1323531. S2CID 220316213. from the original on 4 May 2021. Retrieved 3 April 2021.
  • Beins, Bernard C. (2017). Research Method: A Tool for Life. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-43623-6. from the original on 8 January 2024. Retrieved 8 January 2024.
  • Bergström, Lars (1987). "On the Value of Scientific Knowledge". In Lehrer, Keith (ed.). Science and Ethics. Rodopi. ISBN 978-90-6203-670-7.
  • Bertelson, Paul; Gelder, BéAtrice De (2004). "The Psychology of Multimodal Perception". Crossmodal Space and Crossmodal Attention. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198524861.003.0007. ISBN 9780191689260.
  • Bird, Alexander (2022). "Thomas Kuhn". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March 2024.
  • Black, Charlene Villaseñor; Álvarez, Mari-Tere (2019). Renaissance Futurities: Science, Art, Invention. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-96951-3.
  • Black, Tim (2002). "Relevant Alternatives and the Shifting Standards of Knowledge". Southwest Philosophy Review. 18 (1): 23–32. doi:10.5840/swphilreview20021813. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Blackburn, Simon (2008). "Ding an sich". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954143-0.
  • Blayney, Benjamin, ed. (1769). "Genesis". The King James Bible. Oxford University Press. OCLC 745260506. Archived from the original on 30 January 2023. Retrieved 30 January 2023.
  • Bloor, David (2004). "Sociology of Scientific Knowledge". Handbook of Epistemology. Springer Netherlands. pp. 919–962. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-1986-9_25. ISBN 978-1-4020-1986-9.
  • Bosančić, Saša (2018). "Self-positioning of Semi-skilled Workers: Analysing Subjectification Processes with SKAD". The Sociology of Knowledge Approach to Discourse: Investigating the Politics of Knowledge and Meaning-making. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-04872-0.
  • Bowen, James; Gelpi, Ettore; Anweiler, Oskar (2023). "Education". Encyclopedia Britannica. from the original on 12 December 2007. Retrieved 30 April 2023.
  • Bowker, John (2003). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of World Religions. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-280094-7.
  • Boyer, Dominic (2007). "1. Of Dialectical Germans and Dialectical Ethnographers: Notes from an Engagement with Philosophy". In Harris, Mark (ed.). Ways of Knowing: Anthropological Approaches to Crafting Experience and Knowledge. Berghahn Books. ISBN 978-1-84545-364-0.
  • Bukoye, Roseline Olufunke (2019). "Utilization of Instruction Materials as Tools for Effective Academic Performance of Students: Implications for Counselling". The 2nd Innovative and Creative Education and Teaching International Conference. ICETIC. p. 1395. doi:10.3390/proceedings2211395.
  • Burke, Peter (2015). What Is the History of Knowledge?. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-5095-0306-3. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Burton, David (2002). "Knowledge and Liberation: Philosophical Ruminations on a Buddhist Conundrum". Philosophy East and West. 52 (3): 326–345. doi:10.1353/pew.2002.0011. ISSN 0031-8221. JSTOR 1400322. S2CID 145257341. from the original on 17 February 2023. Retrieved 17 February 2023.
  • Cai, Zixing; Liu, Lijue; Chen, Baifan; Wang, Yong (2021). Artificial Intelligence: From Beginning To Date. World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-12-2371-6. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 2 December 2023.
  • Cameron, Ross (2018). "Infinite Regress Arguments". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 2 January 2020. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Campo, Juan Eduardo (2009). Encyclopedia of Islam. Infobase Publishing. p. 515. ISBN 978-1-4381-2696-8. from the original on 4 March 2023. Retrieved 4 March 2023.
  • Carson, Thomas; Cerrito, Joann, eds. (2003). New Catholic Encyclopedia Vol. 14: Thi–Zwi (2nd ed.). Thomson/Gale. p. 164. ISBN 978-0-7876-4018-7.
  • Castilho, Luciana V.; Lopes, Heitor S. (2009). "An Ontology-Based System for Knowledge Management and Learning in Neuropediatric Physiotherapy". In Szczerbicki, Edward; Nguyen, Ngoc Thanh (eds.). Smart Information and Knowledge Management: Advances, Challenges, and Critical Issues. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-3-642-04583-7. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 2 December 2023.
  • CD staff. "Knowledge". Cambridge Advanced Learner's Dictionary & Thesaurus. Cambridge University Press. from the original on 16 November 2023. Retrieved 3 December 2023.
  • Celenza, Christopher S. (2021). The Italian Renaissance and the Origin of the Humanities: An Intellectual History, 1400–1800. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-83340-0.
  • Chappell, Sophie-Grace (2019). "Plato on Knowledge in the Theaetetus". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Chaudhary, Angraj (2017). "Avijjā". In Sarao, K.T.S.; Long, Jeffery D. (eds.). Buddhism and Jainism. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-94-024-0851-5.
  • Chaudhary, Angraj (2017a). "Wisdom (Buddhism)". In Sarao, K.T.S.; Long, Jeffery D. (eds.). Buddhism and Jainism. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-94-024-0851-5.
  • Choo, Chun Wei (2002). "Knowledge Management". In Schement, Jorge Reina (ed.). Encyclopedia of Communication and Information. Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 978-0-02-865385-3. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 1 December 2023.
  • Christopher, Jabez; Prasath, Rajendra; Vanga, Odelu (2018). "Expert Intelligence: Theory of the Missing Facet". In Groza, Adrian; Prasath, Rajendra (eds.). Mining Intelligence and Knowledge Exploration: 6th International Conference. Springer. ISBN 978-3-030-05918-7.
  • Clark, Romane (1988). "Vicious Infinite Regress Arguments". Philosophical Perspectives. 2: 369–380. doi:10.2307/2214081. JSTOR 2214081. from the original on 26 March 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Clark, Kelly James (2022). "Religious Epistemology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 21 September 2022. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  • Clegg, Joshua W. (2022). Good Science: Psychological Inquiry as Everyday Moral Practice. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-009-02181-4.
  • Cohen, Emma (2010). "Anthropology of Knowledge". The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute. 16: S193–S202. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9655.2010.01617.x. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0012-9B72-7. JSTOR 40606072. from the original on 26 September 2022. Retrieved 26 September 2022.
  • Cohen, Robert S. (2013). The Natural Sciences and the Social Sciences: Some Critical and Historical Perspectives. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-017-3391-5.
  • Colander, David C. (2016). Social Science: An Introduction to the Study of Society. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-22573-7.
  • Conner, Clifford D. (2009). A People's History of Science: Miners, Midwives, and Low Mechanicks. Bold Type Books. ISBN 978-0-7867-3786-4. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Coser, Lewis A. (2009) [1968]. "Knowledge, Sociology of". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. Gale. ISBN 978-0-02-928751-4. from the original on 7 March 2023. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • Cosman, Madeleine Pelner; Jones, Linda Gale (2009). Handbook to Life in the Medieval World, 3-Volume Set. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4381-0907-7.
  • Cox, Michael T.; Raja, Anita (2011). Metareasoning: Thinking About Thinking. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-01480-9. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Danesi, Marcel (2013). Encyclopedia of Media and Communication. University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-1-4426-9553-5. from the original on 13 November 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Das, Nilanjan; Salow, Bernhard (2018). "Transparency and the KK Principle". Noûs. 52 (1): 3–23. doi:10.1111/nous.12158. from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Daston, Lorraine (2017). "The History of Science and the History of Knowledge". KNOW: A Journal on the Formation of Knowledge. 1 (1): 131–154. doi:10.1086/691678. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-002C-EDB1-5. S2CID 164680540.
  • Degenhardt, M. A. B. (2019). Education and the Value of Knowledge. Routledge. pp. 1–6. ISBN 978-1-000-62799-2. from the original on 5 April 2023. Retrieved 9 March 2023.
  • Delahunty, Andrew; Dignen, Sheila (2012). "Tree of Knowledge". Oxford Dictionary of Reference and Allusion. Oxford University Press. p. 365. ISBN 978-0-19-956746-1. from the original on 17 February 2023. Retrieved 17 February 2023.
  • DePoe, John M. (2022). "Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  • Desouza, K.; Awazu, Y. (2005). Engaged Knowledge Management: Engagement with New Realities. Springer. ISBN 978-0-230-00607-2. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Dika, Tarek (2023). Descartes's Method: The Formation of the Subject of Science. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-286986-9.
  • Dodd, Ashley C.; Zambetti, Benjamin R.; Deneve, Jeremiah (2023). "Scientific Method". Translational Surgery. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-323-90630-2.
  • Dokic, Jérôme; Égré, Paul (2009). "Margin for Error and the Transparency of Knowledge". Synthese. 166 (1): 1–20. doi:10.1007/s11229-007-9245-y. S2CID 14221986. from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Doren, Charles Van (1992). A History of Knowledge: Past, Present, and Future. Random House Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-345-37316-8. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Dougherty, Trent (2014). "Faith, Trust, and Testimony". Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue: 97–123. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672158.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-967215-8.
  • Dreyer, Jaco S. (2017). "Practical Theology and the Call for the Decolonisation of Higher Education in South Africa: Reflections and Proposals". HTS Teologiese Studies / Theological Studies. 73 (4): 1–7. doi:10.4102/hts.v73i4.4805.
  • Durán, Juan M.; Formanek, Nico (2018). "Grounds for Trust: Essential Epistemic Opacity and Computational Reliabilism". Minds and Machines. 28 (4): 645–666. arXiv:1904.01052. doi:10.1007/s11023-018-9481-6. ISSN 1572-8641. S2CID 53102940.
  • Emaliana, Ive (2017). "Teacher-Centered or Student-Centered Learning Approach To Promote Learning?". Jurnal Sosial Humaniora. 10 (2): 59. doi:10.12962/j24433527.v10i2.2161. S2CID 148796695.
  • Esposito, John L., ed. (2003). "Madrasa". The Oxford Dictionary of Islam. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-512558-0. from the original on 9 December 2023. Retrieved 15 December 2023.
  • Evans, James A.; Foster, Jacob G. (2011). "Metaknowledge". Science. 331 (6018): 721–725. Bibcode:2011Sci...331..721E. doi:10.1126/science.1201765. PMID 21311014. S2CID 220090552.
  • Faber, Niels R.; Maruster, Laura; Jorna, René J. (2017). "Assessing and Determining Social Sustainability". In Jorna, René (ed.). Sustainable Innovation: The Organisational, Human and Knowledge Dimension. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-28034-1. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Fagan, Brian M.; Durrani, Nadia (2016). World Prehistory: A Brief Introduction. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-27910-5. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Flynn, Mark (2000). "A Critique of Scientism Not Science per se". Interchange. 31 (1): 83–86. doi:10.1023/a:1007695016458. S2CID 141495171.
  • Forrest, Peter (2021). "The Epistemology of Religion". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  • Foxall, Gordon (2017). Context and Cognition in Consumer Psychology: How Perception and Emotion Guide Action. Routledge. p. 75. ISBN 978-1-317-67738-3. from the original on 1 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Friesen, Norm (2017). The Textbook and the Lecture: Education in the Age of New Media. JHU Press. ISBN 978-1-4214-2434-7. from the original on 13 May 2023. Retrieved 3 May 2023.
  • Fumerton, Richard (2008). "The Problem of the Criterion". The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism. Oxford University Press. pp. 34–52. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195183214.003.0003. ISBN 978-0-19-518321-4. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Fumerton, Richard (2022). Foundationalism. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781009028868. ISBN 978-1-009-02886-8. from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Gabriel, Cle-Anne (2022). Why Teach with Cases?: Reflections on Philosophy and Practice. Emerald Group Publishing. ISBN 978-1-80382-399-7.
  • García-Arnaldos, María Dolores (2020). "An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, Written by O'Brien, D." History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis. 23 (2): 508. doi:10.30965/26664275-20210003. ISSN 2666-4275. S2CID 228985437. from the original on 4 March 2023. Retrieved 4 March 2023.
  • Gardiner, J. M. (2001). "Episodic Memory and Autonoetic Consciousness: A First-person Approach". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences. 356 (1413): 1351–1361. doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.0955. ISSN 0962-8436. PMC 1088519. PMID 11571027.
  • Gascoigne, Neil; Thornton, Tim (2014). Tacit Knowledge. Routledge. pp. 8, 37, 81, 108. ISBN 978-1-317-54726-6. from the original on 6 March 2023. Retrieved 6 March 2023.
  • Gauch, Hugh G. (2003). Scientific Method in Practice. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-01708-4.
  • George, Theodore (2021). "Hermeneutics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 6 March 2024.
  • Gertler, Brie (2010). "1. Introduction". Self-Knowledge. Routledge. p. 1. ISBN 978-1-136-85811-6. from the original on 8 April 2023. Retrieved 24 October 2022.
  • Gertler, Brie (2021). "Self-Knowledge". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 11 November 2021. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  • Gertler, Brie (2021a). "Self-Knowledge > Knowledge of the Self". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 3 July 2022. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  • Ghose, Aurobindo (1998). "Political Writings and Speeches. 1890–1908: The Glory of God in Man". Bande Mataram II. Sri Aurobindo Ashram Publication Department. ISBN 978-81-7058-416-2. from the original on 9 March 2023. Retrieved 9 March 2023.
  • Gilliot, Claude (2018). "Libraries". In Meri, Josef (ed.). Routledge Revivals: Medieval Islamic Civilization (2006): An Encyclopedia - Volume II. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-66813-2.
  • Goldman, Alvin I. (1976). "Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge". The Journal of Philosophy. 73 (20): 771–791. doi:10.2307/2025679. JSTOR 2025679.
  • Green, Christopher R. (2022). "Epistemology of Testimony". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  • Gupta, Anil (2021). "Definitions: 1.1 Real and Nominal Definitions". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 1 May 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  • Gutting, Gary; Oksala, Johanna (2022). "Michel Foucault". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March 2024.
  • Hamner, M. Gail (2003). American Pragmatism: A Religious Genealogy. Oxford University Press. p. 87. ISBN 978-0-19-515547-1. from the original on 7 March 2023. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • Hannon, Michael (2021). "Knowledge, Concept of". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-P031-2. ISBN 978-0-415-07310-3. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Hansen, Judith Friedman (1982). "From Background to Foreground: Toward an Anthropology of Learning". Anthropology & Education Quarterly. 13 (2): 193. doi:10.1525/aeq.1982.13.2.05x1833m. ISSN 0161-7761. JSTOR 3216630.
  • Hasan, Ali; Fumerton, Richard (2018). "Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 6 June 2022.
  • Hasan, Ali; Fumerton, Richard (2020). "Knowledge by Acquaintance Vs. Description: 1. The Distinction". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 31 May 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  • Hasan, Ali; Fumerton, Richard (2022). "Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 11 December 2023.
  • Hatfield, Gary (1998). "Scientific Method". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-07310-3.
  • Haymes, Brian; Özdalga, Elisabeth (2016). Concept Of The Knowledge Of God. Springer. pp. 26–28. ISBN 978-1-349-19066-9. from the original on 1 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Hepburn, Brian; Andersen, Hanne (2021). "Scientific Method". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 26 February 2020. Retrieved 23 July 2022.
  • Hetherington, Stephen. Fallibilism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 18 August 2020. Retrieved 13 December 2023.
  • Hetherington, Stephen (2022). "Gettier Problems". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 19 February 2009. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  • Hetherington, Stephen (2022a). "Knowledge". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 18 May 2022.
  • Heydorn, Wendy; Jesudason, Susan (2013). Decoding Theory of Knowledge for the IB Diploma. Cambridge University Press. p. 10. ISBN 978-1-107-62842-7. from the original on 1 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Hill, Sonya D., ed. (2009). "Knowledge–Based View Of The Firm". Encyclopedia of Management. Gale. ISBN 978-1-4144-0691-6. from the original on 6 March 2023. Retrieved 6 March 2023.
  • Hirschberger, Johannes (2019). A Short History Western Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-31145-7. from the original on 8 January 2024. Retrieved 8 January 2024.
  • Hoad, T. F. (1993). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.
  • Hookway, Christopher (8 November 2012). The Pragmatic Maxim: Essays on Peirce and Pragmatism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-958838-1.
  • Howell, Kerry E. (2013). An Introduction to the Philosophy of Methodology. Sage. ISBN 978-1-4462-0298-2.
  • Hunter, Lynette (2009). "Situated Knowledge". Mapping Landscapes for Performance as Research: Scholarly Acts and Creative Cartographies. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 151–153. doi:10.1057/9780230244481_23. ISBN 978-0-230-24448-1. from the original on 20 September 2022. Retrieved 19 September 2022.
  • Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins; Steup, Matthias (2018). "The Analysis of Knowledge". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 2 May 2022. Retrieved 24 May 2022.
  • Johnson, Mark S.; Stearns, Peter N. (2023). Education in World History. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-81337-8. from the original on 9 December 2023. Retrieved 3 May 2023.
  • Jones, Constance; Ryan, James D. (2006). Encyclopedia of Hinduism. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-0-8160-7564-5. from the original on 20 October 2022. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  • Jorna, René (2017). Sustainable Innovation: The Organisational, Human and Knowledge Dimension. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-28034-1. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Kandel, Abraham (1992). Fuzzy Expert Systems. CRC Press. ISBN 978-0-8493-4297-4. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 2 December 2023.
  • Kemmis, Stephen; Edwards-Groves, Christine (2017). Understanding Education: History, Politics and Practice. Springer. ISBN 978-981-10-6433-3. from the original on 13 May 2023. Retrieved 3 May 2023.
  • Kern, Andrea (2017). Sources of Knowledge: On the Concept of a Rational Capacity for Knowledge. Harvard University Press. pp. 8–10, 133. ISBN 978-0-674-41611-6. from the original on 28 October 2022. Retrieved 28 October 2022.
  • Kernis, Michael H. (2013). Self-Esteem Issues and Answers: A Sourcebook of Current Perspectives. Psychology Press. p. 209. ISBN 978-1-134-95270-0. from the original on 22 October 2022. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  • Khatoon, Naima (2012). General Psychology. Pearson Education India. ISBN 978-81-317-5999-8.
  • Kitchener, Richard F. (1996). "Genetic Epistemology and Cognitive Psychology of Science". In O'Donohue, William; Kitchener, Richard F. (eds.). The Philosophy of Psychology. Sage. ISBN 978-0-85702-612-5.
  • Klausen, Søren Harnow (2015). "Group Knowledge: A Real-world Approach". Synthese. 192 (3): 813–839. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0589-9. S2CID 207246817. from the original on 1 February 2024. Retrieved 13 November 2022.
  • Klein, Peter D. (1998). "Knowledge, Concept of". In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-P031-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. OCLC 38096851. from the original on 13 June 2022. Retrieved 13 June 2022.
  • Klenke, Karin (2014). "Sculpting the Contours of the Qualitative Landscape of Leadership Research". In Day, David (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Leadership and Organizations. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-021377-0.
  • Kraft, Tim (2012). "Scepticism, Infallibilism, Fallibilism". Discipline Filosofiche. 22 (2): 49–70. ISSN 2279-7343. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Kreeft, Peter; Tacelli, Ronald K. (2009). Handbook of Christian Apologetics. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-7544-3.
  • Kuhn, Thomas S. (1992). The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-41747-2. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Kuruk, Paul (2020). Traditional Knowledge, Genetic Resources, Customary Law and Intellectual Property: A Global Primer. Edward Elgar Publishing. p. 25. ISBN 978-1-78536-848-6. from the original on 7 March 2023. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • Lackey, Jennifer (2021). The Epistemology of Groups. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-965660-8. from the original on 25 October 2022. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  • Lammenranta, Markus (2022). "Epistemic Circularity". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 27 January 2021. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Landau, Iddo (2017). Finding Meaning in an Imperfect World. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-065768-0.
  • Thornton, Tim; Lanzer, Peter (2018). Lanzer, Peter (ed.). Textbook of Catheter-Based Cardiovascular Interventions: A Knowledge-Based Approach. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-319-55994-0. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Lee, Jerry Won (2017). The Politics of Translingualism: After Englishes. Routledge. p. 67. ISBN 978-1-315-31051-0. from the original on 8 March 2023. Retrieved 8 March 2023.
  • Legg, Catherine; Hookway, Christopher (2021). "Pragmatism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 March 2024.
  • Legge, Dominic (2017). The Trinitarian Christology of St Thomas Aquinas. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-879419-6.
  • Lehrer, Keith (2015). "1. The Analysis of Knowledge". Theory of Knowledge. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-19609-7. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Lemos, Noah M. (1994). Intrinsic Value: Concept and Warrant. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-46207-5.
  • Lengnick-Hall, Mark L.; Lengnick-Hall, Cynthia A. (2003). Human Resource Management in the Knowledge Economy: New Challenges, New Roles, New Capabilities. Berrett-Koehler Publishers. ISBN 978-1-57675-159-6. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 2 December 2023.
  • Leonard, Nick (2021). "Epistemological Problems of Testimony". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  • Leondes, Cornelius T. (2001). Expert Systems: The Technology of Knowledge Management and Decision Making for the 21st Century. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-08-053145-8. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Lilley, Simon; Lightfoot, Geoffrey; Amaral, Paulo (2004). Representing Organization: Knowledge, Management, and the Information Age. Oxford University Press. pp. 162–163. ISBN 978-0-19-877541-6. from the original on 10 March 2023. Retrieved 10 March 2023.
  • Low, Renae; Jin, Putai; Sweller, John (2008). "Cognitive Architecture and Instructional Design in a Multimedia Context". In Zheng, Robert (ed.). Cognitive Effects of Multimedia Learning. IGI Global. ISBN 978-1-60566-159-9.
  • Lycan, William G. (2019). "2. Moore Against the New Skeptics". On Evidence in Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 21–36. ISBN 978-0-19-256526-6. from the original on 6 March 2023. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • Magee, Bryan; Popper, Karl R. (1971). "Conversation with Karl Popper". In Magee, Bryan (ed.). Modern British Philosophy. St. Martin's Press. pp. 74–75. ISBN 978-0-19-283047-0. OCLC 314039. Popper: Putting our ideas into words, or better, writing them down, makes an important difference. ... It is what I call 'knowledge in the objective sense'. Scientific knowledge belongs to it. It is this knowledge which is stored in our libraries rather than our heads. Magee: And you regard the knowledge stored in our libraries as more important than the knowledge stored in our heads. Popper: Much more important, from every point of view
  • Mahadevan, Kanchana (2007). "Gadamerian Hermeneutics: Between Strangers and Friends". In Ghosh, Manjulika; Ghosh, Raghunath (eds.). Language and Interpretation: Hermeneutics from East-West Perspective. Northern Book Centre. ISBN 978-81-7211-230-1.
  • Markie, Peter J. (1998). "Rationalism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 24 June 2021. Retrieved 8 January 2024.
  • Markie, Peter; Folescu, M. (2023). "Rationalism vs. Empiricism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 February 2024.
  • Markman, Arthur B. (2006). "Knowledge Representation, Psychology of". Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Wiley. doi:10.1002/0470018860.s00558. ISBN 978-0-470-01619-0.
  • Martin, M. G. F. (1998). "Perception". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-V023-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Retrieved 26 March 2024.
  • McCain, Kevin (2022). "Problem of the Criterion". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 28 May 2022.
  • McCain, Kevin; Stapleford, Scott; Steup, Matthias (2021). Epistemic Dilemmas: New Arguments, New Angles. Routledge. p. 111. ISBN 978-1-000-46851-9. from the original on 21 October 2022. Retrieved 21 October 2022.
  • McCormick, Matt. "Kant, Immanuel: Metaphysics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 February 2024.
  • McDermid, Douglas (2023). "Pragmatism: 2b. Anti-Cartesianism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 23 May 2019. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • McGeer, V. (2001). "Self-knowledge: Philosophical Aspects". International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences. Elsevier: 13837–13841. doi:10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/01073-1. ISBN 978-0-08-043076-8.
  • Meirmans, Stephanie; Butlin, Roger K.; Charmantier, Anne; Engelstädter, Jan; Groot, Astrid T.; King, Kayla C.; Kokko, Hanna; Reid, Jane M.; Neiman, Maurine (2019). "Science policies: How should science funding be allocated? An evolutionary biologists' perspective". Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 32 (8): 754–768. doi:10.1111/jeb.13497. hdl:2164/12705. PMC 6771946. PMID 31215105.
  • Mertler, Craig A. (2021). Introduction to Educational Research. SAGE Publications. ISBN 978-1-5443-8834-2.
  • Miah, Sajahan (2006). Russell's Theory of Perception. Continuum. pp. 19–20. ISBN 978-1-84714-284-9. from the original on 1 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 3. Episodicity". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 5 October 2021. Retrieved 2 October 2021.
  • Misak, Cheryl (2002). Truth, Politics, Morality: Pragmatism and Deliberation. Routledge. p. 53. ISBN 978-1-134-82618-6. from the original on 7 March 2023. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • Mishra, T. K. (2021). The Power of Ethics: Some Lessons from the Bhagavad-Gita. K.K. Publications. p. 52. ISBN 978-81-7844-127-6. from the original on 30 July 2022. Retrieved 21 June 2022.
  • Morin, Alain; Racy, Famira (2021). "15. Dynamic Self-processes - Self-knowledge". The Handbook of Personality Dynamics and Processes. Academic Press. pp. 373–374. ISBN 978-0-12-813995-0. from the original on 22 October 2022. Retrieved 22 October 2022.
  • Morrison, Robert (2005). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. p. 371. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. from the original on 30 March 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Moser, Paul K. (1998). "A priori". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 9 May 2021. Retrieved 8 January 2024.
  • Moser, Paul K. (2005). "13. Scientific Knowledge". The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-020818-9. from the original on 19 May 2023. Retrieved 8 March 2023.
  • Moser, Paul K. (2016). "A Posteriori". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. from the original on 20 September 2022. Retrieved 18 September 2022.
  • Mulsow, Martin (2018). "6. History of Knowledge". In Tamm, Marek; Burke, Peter (eds.). Debating New Approaches to History. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4742-8193-5. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 29 November 2023.
  • Murphy, Patricia (2003). "1. Defining Pedagogy". In Gipps, Caroline V. (ed.). Equity in the Classroom: Towards Effective Pedagogy for Girls and Boys. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-71682-0. from the original on 25 January 2024. Retrieved 22 August 2022.
  • Murphy, Peter (2022). "Coherentism in Epistemology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 12 June 2022. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  • MW Staff (2023). "Definition of Knowledge". Merriam-Webster. from the original on 21 December 2023. Retrieved 3 December 2023.
  • Myers, Michael D. (2009). Qualitative Research in Business & Management. Sage Publications. ISBN 978-1-4129-2165-7.
  • Niiniluoto, Ilkka (2019). "Scientific Progress". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 6 March 2023. Retrieved 8 March 2023.
  • O'Brien, Dan (2006). An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. Polity. ISBN 978-0-7456-3316-9.
  • O'Brien, Daniel (2022). "The Epistemology of Perception". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 8 May 2009. Retrieved 25 October 2022.
  • O'Grady, Paul. "Relativism". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. Retrieved 6 March 2024.
  • Olsson, Erik J (2011). "The Value of Knowledge". Philosophy Compass. 6 (12): 874–883. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00425.x. S2CID 143034920.
  • Paden, William E. (2005). "Comparative Religion". Encyclopedia of Religion (2nd ed.). Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 978-0028657332.
  • Paden, William E. (2009). "Comparative Religion". The Routledge Companion to the Study of Religion. Routledge. pp. 239–256. doi:10.4324/9780203868768-19. ISBN 978-0-203-86876-8. from the original on 21 September 2022. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  • Parikh, Rohit; Renero, Adriana (2017). "Justified True Belief: Plato, Gettier, and Turing". Philosophical Explorations of the Legacy of Alan Turing. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. Vol. 324. Springer International Publishing. pp. 93–102. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-53280-6_4. ISBN 978-3-319-53280-6. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Pavese, Carlotta (2022). "Knowledge How". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 25 November 2023. Retrieved 12 December 2023.
  • Payne, William Harold (2003). "Contributions to the Science of Education and The Education of Teachers". In Salvatori, Mariolina Rizzi (ed.). Pedagogy: Disturbing History, 1820-1930. University of Pittsburgh Press. ISBN 978-0-8229-7246-4.
  • Peels, Rik (2023). Ignorance: A Philosophical Study. Oxford University Press. p. 28. ISBN 978-0-19-765451-4. from the original on 1 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Penelhum, Terence (1971). "1. Faith, Scepticism and Philosophy". Problems of Religious Knowledge. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-333-10633-4. from the original on 1 February 2024. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  • Perin, Casey (2020). "23. Tranquility as the Goal in Pyrrhonian Skepticism". In Arenson, Kelly (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 285–294. doi:10.4324/9781351168120-23. ISBN 978-1-351-16812-0. S2CID 225751581. from the original on 12 December 2023. Retrieved 12 December 2023.
  • Pinch, T. (2013). Confronting Nature: T́he Sociology of Solar-Neutrino Detection. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-015-7729-8.
  • Plantinga, Alvin (2018). "Scientism: Who Needs It?". In Ridder, Jeroen de; Peels, Rik; Woudenberg, Rene van (eds.). Scientism: Prospects and Problems. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-046276-5.
  • Plato (2002). Five Dialogues. Hackett Pub. Co. pp. 89–90, 97b–98a. ISBN 978-0-87220-633-5.
  • Poston, Ted. "Foundationalism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 3 November 2011. Retrieved 11 December 2023.
  • Powell, Timothy (2020). The Value of Knowledge: The Economics of Enterprise Knowledge and Intelligence. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-059304-4.
  • Power, Edward J. (1970). Main Currents in the History of Education. McGraw-Hill. ISBN 978-0-07-050581-0. from the original on 3 May 2023. Retrieved 3 May 2023.
  • Power, Richenda (2014). A Question of Knowledge. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-88375-3.
  • Pritchard, Duncan (2007). "Recent Work on Epistemic Value". American Philosophical Quarterly. 44 (2): 85–110. JSTOR 20464361.
  • Pritchard, Duncan (2013). What Is This Thing Called Knowledge?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-57367-7. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Pritchard, Duncan; Turri, John; Carter, J. Adam (2022). "The Value of Knowledge". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 19 September 2022.
  • Rambachan, Anantanand (2006). The Advaita Worldview: God, World, and Humanity. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-6851-7.
  • Reginster, Bernard (2017). "Self-knowledge as Freedom in Schopenhauer and Freud". In Renz, Ursula (ed.). Self-knowledge: A History. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022642-8.
  • Reif, Frederick (2008). Applying Cognitive Science to Education: Thinking and Learning in Scientific and Other Complex Domains. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-18263-8. from the original on 15 April 2023. Retrieved 16 April 2023.
  • Repko, Allen F. (2008). Interdisciplinary Research: Process and Theory. Sage. ISBN 978-1-4129-5915-5.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (1998). Fallibilism. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-P019-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Retrieved 23 March 2024. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  • Rescher, Nicholas (2005). Epistemic Logic: A Survey of the Logic of Knowledge. University of Pittsburgh Press. ISBN 978-0-8229-7092-7. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (2009). Unknowability: An Inquiry into the Limits of Knowledge. Lexington books. ISBN 978-0-7391-3615-7.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (2005a). "Knowledge, the Limits of". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (2009a). Ignorance: On the Wider Implications of Deficient Knowledge. University of Pittsburgh Press. ISBN 978-0-8229-6014-0.
  • Rodríguez, Ángel García (2018). "Fake Barns and Our Epistemological Theorizing". Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía. 50 (148): 29–54. doi:10.22201/iifs.18704905e.2018.02. ISSN 0011-1503. JSTOR 26767766. S2CID 171635198.
  • Barnett, Ronald (1990). The Idea Of Higher Education. Open University Press. p. 40. ISBN 978-0-335-09420-2. from the original on 5 March 2023. Retrieved 5 March 2023.
  • Rothberg, Helen N.; Erickson, G. Scott (2005). From Knowledge to Intelligence: Creating Competitive Advantage in the Next Economy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-7506-7762-2. from the original on 8 January 2024. Retrieved 8 January 2024.
  • Russell, Bruce (2020). "A Priori Justification and Knowledge". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 12 August 2021. Retrieved 18 September 2022.
  • Rutten, Emanuel (2012). A Critical Assessment of Contemporary Cosmological Arguments: Towards a Renewed Case for Theism. Vrije Universiteit. ISBN 978-90-819608-0-9.
  • Sayre-McCord, Geoff (2023). "Metaethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 12 July 2023. Retrieved 19 December 2023.
  • Scheler, Max; Stikkers, Kenneth W. (2012). Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge (Routledge Revivals). Routledge. p. 23. ISBN 978-0-415-62334-6. from the original on 7 March 2023. Retrieved 7 March 2023.
  • Schneider, W. Joel; McGrew, Kevin S. (2022). "The Cattell-Horn-Carroll Theory of Cognitive Abilities". In Flanagan, Dawn P.; McDonough, Erin M. (eds.). Contemporary Intellectual Assessment: Theories, Tests, and Issues. Guilford Publications. ISBN 978-1-4625-5203-0. from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 30 November 2023.
  • Schoonenboom, Judith; Johnson, R. Burke (2017). "How to Construct a Mixed Methods Research Design". KZFSS Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie. 69 (S2): 107–131. doi:10.1007/s11577-017-0454-1. PMC 5602001. PMID 28989188.
  • Schwitzgebel, Eric (2021). "Belief: 2.1 Occurrent Versus Dispositional Belief". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 15 November 2019. Retrieved 8 June 2022.
  • Shapiro, Stuart C. (2006). "Knowledge Representation". Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Wiley. doi:10.1002/0470018860.s00058. ISBN 978-0-470-01619-0.
  • Shorten, Allison; Smith, Joanna (2017). "Mixed methods research: expanding the evidence base". Evidence Based Nursing. 20 (3): 74–75. doi:10.1136/eb-2017-102699. PMID 28615184.
  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2019). "Moral Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 3 March 2024.
  • Sonneveld, Helmi B.; Loening, Kurt L. (1993). Terminology: Applications in interdisciplinary communication. John Benjamins Publishing. ISBN 978-90-272-7400-7.
  • Spaulding, Shannon (2016). "Imagination Through Knowledge". In Kind, Amy; Kung, Peter (eds.). Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-102619-5. from the original on 5 December 2023. Retrieved 5 December 2023.
  • Stanley, Jason; Willlamson, Timothy (2001). "Knowing How". Journal of Philosophy. 98 (8): 411–444. doi:10.2307/2678403. JSTOR 2678403. from the original on 2 June 2022. Retrieved 12 June 2022.
  • Stehr, Nico; Adolf, Marian T. (2016). "The Price of Knowledge". Social Epistemology. 30 (5–6): 483–512. doi:10.1080/02691728.2016.1172366.
  • Steinberg, Sheila (1995). Introduction to Communication Course Book 1: The Basics. Juta and Company Ltd. ISBN 978-0-7021-3649-8. from the original on 17 May 2023. Retrieved 28 November 2022.
  • Steup, Matthias; Neta, Ram (2020). "Epistemology". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 21 July 2020. Retrieved 22 May 2022.
  • Stevenson, Leslie (2003). "Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge". Kantian Review. 7: 72–101. doi:10.1017/S1369415400001746. ISSN 2044-2394. S2CID 143965507. from the original on 21 September 2022. Retrieved 21 September 2022.
  • Stoltz, Jonathan (2021). Illuminating the Mind: An Introduction to Buddhist Epistemology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-090756-3.
  • Stroll, Avrum (2023). "Epistemology". Encyclopædia Britannica. from the original on 10 July 2019. Retrieved 20 May 2022.
knowledge, other, uses, disambiguation, awareness, facts, familiarity, with, individuals, situations, practical, skill, facts, also, called, propositional, knowledge, often, characterized, true, belief, that, distinct, from, opinion, guesswork, virtue, justifi. For other uses see Knowledge disambiguation Knowledge is an awareness of facts a familiarity with individuals and situations or a practical skill Knowledge of facts also called propositional knowledge is often characterized as true belief that is distinct from opinion or guesswork by virtue of justification While there is wide agreement among philosophers that propositional knowledge is a form of true belief many controversies focus on justification This includes questions like how to understand justification whether it is needed at all and whether something else besides it is needed These controversies intensified in the latter half of the 20th century due to a series of thought experiments called Gettier cases that provoked alternative definitions The owl of Athena a symbol of knowledge in the Western worldKnowledge can be produced in many ways The main source of empirical knowledge is perception which involves the usage of the senses to learn about the external world Introspection allows people to learn about their internal mental states and processes Other sources of knowledge include memory rational intuition inference and testimony a According to foundationalism some of these sources are basic in that they can justify beliefs without depending on other mental states Coherentists reject this claim and contend that a sufficient degree of coherence among all the mental states of the believer is necessary for knowledge According to infinitism an infinite chain of beliefs is needed The main discipline investigating knowledge is epistemology which studies what people know how they come to know it and what it means to know something It discusses the value of knowledge and the thesis of philosophical skepticism which questions the possibility of knowledge Knowledge is relevant to many fields like the sciences which aim to acquire knowledge using the scientific method based on repeatable experimentation observation and measurement Various religions hold that humans should seek knowledge and that God or the divine is the source of knowledge The anthropology of knowledge studies how knowledge is acquired stored retrieved and communicated in different cultures The sociology of knowledge examines under what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises and what sociological consequences it has The history of knowledge investigates how knowledge in different fields has developed and evolved in the course of history Contents 1 Definitions 1 1 Analysis of knowledge 2 Types 2 1 Propositional 2 2 Non propositional 2 3 A priori and a posteriori 2 4 Others 3 Sources 4 Limits 5 Structure 6 Value 7 Science 8 History 9 In various disciplines 9 1 Religion 9 2 Anthropology 9 3 Sociology 9 4 Others 10 See also 11 References 11 1 Notes 11 2 Citations 11 3 Sources 12 External linksDefinitionsMain article Definitions of knowledge Knowledge is a form of familiarity awareness understanding or acquaintance It often involves the possession of information learned through experience 1 and can be understood as a cognitive success or an epistemic contact with reality like making a discovery 2 Many academic definitions focus on propositional knowledge in the form of believing certain facts as in I know that Dave is at home 3 Other types of knowledge include knowledge how in the form of practical competence as in she knows how to swim and knowledge by acquaintance as a familiarity with the known object based on previous direct experience like knowing someone personally 4 Knowledge is often understood as a state of an individual person but it can also refer to a characteristic of a group of people as group knowledge social knowledge or collective knowledge 5 Some social sciences understand knowledge as a broad social phenomenon that is similar to culture 6 The term may further denote knowledge stored in documents like the knowledge housed in the library 7 or the knowledge base of an expert system 8 Knowledge is closely related to intelligence but intelligence is more about the ability to acquire process and apply information while knowledge concerns information and skills that a person already possesses 9 The word knowledge has its roots in the 12th century Old English word cnawan which comes from the Old High German word gecnawan 10 The English word includes various meanings that some other languages distinguish using several words 11 In ancient Greek for example four important terms for knowledge were used episteme unchanging theoretical knowledge techne expert technical knowledge metis strategic knowledge and gnōsis personal intellectual knowledge 12 The main discipline studying knowledge is called epistemology or the theory of knowledge It examines the nature of knowledge and justification how knowledge arises and what value it has Further topics include the different types of knowledge and the limits of what can be known 13 Despite agreements about the general characteristics of knowledge its exact definition is disputed Some definitions only focus on the most salient features of knowledge to give a practically useful characterization 14 Another approach termed analysis of knowledge tries to provide a theoretically precise definition by listing the conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient 15 similar to how chemists analyze a sample by seeking a list of all the chemical elements composing it 16 According to a different view knowledge is a unique state that cannot be analyzed in terms of other phenomena 17 Some scholars base their definition on abstract intuitions while others focus on concrete cases 18 or rely on how the term is used in ordinary language 19 There is also disagreement about whether knowledge is a rare phenomenon that requires high standards or a common phenomenon found in many everyday situations 20 Analysis of knowledge See also Belief Justified true belief and Definitions of knowledge Justified true belief nbsp The definition of knowledge as justified true belief is often discussed in the academic literature An often discussed definition characterizes knowledge as justified true belief This definition identifies three essential features it is 1 a belief that is 2 true and 3 justified 21 b Truth is a widely accepted feature of knowledge It implies that while it may be possible to believe something false one cannot know something false 23 c That knowledge is a form of belief implies that one cannot know something if one does not believe it Some everyday expressions seem to violate this principle like the claim that I do not believe it I know it But the point of such expressions is usually to emphasize one s confidence rather than denying that a belief is involved 25 The main controversy surrounding this definition concerns its third feature justification 26 This component is often included because of the impression that some true beliefs are not forms of knowledge such as beliefs based on superstition lucky guesses or erroneous reasoning For example a person who guesses that a coin flip will land heads usually does not know that even if their belief turns out to be true This indicates that there is more to knowledge than just being right about something 27 These cases are excluded by requiring that beliefs have justification for them to count as knowledge 28 Some philosophers hold that a belief is justified if it is based on evidence which can take the form of mental states like experience memory and other beliefs Others state that beliefs are justified if they are produced by reliable processes like sensory perception or logical reasoning 29 nbsp The Gettier problem is grounded in the idea that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge The definition of knowledge as justified true belief came under severe criticism in the 20th century when epistemologist Edmund Gettier formulated a series of counterexamples 30 They purport to present concrete cases of justified true beliefs that fail to constitute knowledge The reason for their failure is usually a form of epistemic luck the beliefs are justified but their justification is not relevant to the truth 31 In a well known example someone drives along a country road with many barn facades and only one real barn The person is not aware of this stops in front of the real barn by a lucky coincidence and forms the justified true belief that they are in front of a barn This example aims to establish that the person does not know that they are in front of a real barn since they would not have been able to tell the difference 32 This means that it is a lucky coincidence that this justified belief is also true 33 According to some philosophers these counterexamples show that justification is not required for knowledge 34 and that knowledge should instead be characterized in terms of reliability or the manifestation of cognitive virtues Another approach defines knowledge in regard to the function it plays in cognitive processes as that which provides reasons for thinking or doing something 35 A different response accepts justification as an aspect of knowledge and include additional criteria 36 Many candidates have been suggested like the requirements that the justified true belief does not depend on any false beliefs that no defeaters d are present or that the person would not have the belief if it was false 38 Another view states that beliefs have to be infallible to amount to knowledge 39 A further approach associated with pragmatism focuses on the aspect of inquiry and characterizes knowledge in terms of what works as a practice that aims to produce habits of action 40 There is still very little consensus in the academic discourse as to which of the proposed modifications or reconceptualizations is correct and there are various alternative definitions of knowledge 41 TypesA common distinction among types of knowledge is between propositional knowledge or knowledge that and non propositional knowledge in the form of practical skills or acquaintance 42 e Other distinctions focus on how the knowledge is acquired and on the content of the known information 44 Propositional Main article Declarative knowledge nbsp Declarative knowledge can be stored in books Propositional knowledge also referred to as declarative and descriptive knowledge is a form of theoretical knowledge about facts like knowing that 2 2 4 It is the paradigmatic type of knowledge in analytic philosophy 45 Propositional knowledge is propositional in the sense that it involves a relation to a proposition Since propositions are often expressed through that clauses it is also referred to as knowledge that as in Akari knows that kangaroos hop 46 In this case Akari stands in the relation of knowing to the proposition kangaroos hop Closely related types of knowledge are know wh for example knowing who is coming to dinner and knowing why they are coming 47 These expressions are normally understood as types of propositional knowledge since they can be paraphrased using a that clause 48 f Propositional knowledge takes the form of mental representations involving concepts ideas theories and general rules These representations connect the knower to certain parts of reality by showing what they are like They are often context independent meaning that they are not restricted to a specific use or purpose 50 Propositional knowledge encompasses both knowledge of specific facts like that the atomic mass of gold is 196 97 u and generalities like that the color of leaves of some trees changes in autumn 51 Because of the dependence on mental representations it is often held that the capacity for propositional knowledge is exclusive to relatively sophisticated creatures such as humans This is based on the claim that advanced intellectual capacities are needed to believe a proposition that expresses what the world is like 52 Non propositional nbsp Knowing how to ride a bicycle is one form of non propositional knowledge Non propositional knowledge is knowledge in which no essential relation to a proposition is involved The two most well known forms are knowledge how know how or procedural knowledge and knowledge by acquaintance 53 To possess knowledge how means to have some form of practical ability skill or competence 54 like knowing how to ride a bicycle or knowing how to swim Some of the abilities responsible for knowledge how involve forms of knowledge that as in knowing how to prove a mathematical theorem but this is not generally the case 55 Some types of knowledge how do not require a highly developed mind in contrast to propositional knowledge and are more common in the animal kingdom For example an ant knows how to walk even though it presumably lacks a mind sufficiently developed to represent the corresponding proposition 52 g Knowledge by acquaintance is familiarity with something that results from direct experiential contact 57 The object of knowledge can be a person a thing or a place For example by eating chocolate one becomes acquainted with the taste of chocolate and visiting Lake Taupō leads to the formation of knowledge by acquaintance of Lake Taupō In these cases the person forms non inferential knowledge based on first hand experience without necessarily acquiring factual information about the object By contrast it is also possible to indirectly learn a lot of propositional knowledge about chocolate or Lake Taupō by reading books without having the direct experiential contact required for knowledge by acquaintance 58 The concept of knowledge by acquaintance was first introduced by Bertrand Russell He holds that knowledge by acquaintance is more basic than propositional knowledge since to understand a proposition one has to be acquainted with its constituents 59 A priori and a posteriori Main article A priori and a posteriori The distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge depends on the role of experience in the processes of formation and justification 60 To know something a posteriori means to know it based on experience 61 For example by seeing that it rains outside or hearing that the baby is crying one acquires a posteriori knowledge of these facts 62 A priori knowledge is possible without any experience to justify or support the known proposition 63 Mathematical knowledge such as that 2 2 4 is traditionally taken to be a priori knowledge since no empirical investigation is necessary to confirm this fact In this regard a posteriori knowledge is empirical knowledge while a priori knowledge is non empirical knowledge 64 The relevant experience in question is primarily identified with sensory experience Some non sensory experiences like memory and introspection are often included as well Some conscious phenomena are excluded from the relevant experience like rational insight For example conscious thought processes may be required to arrive at a priori knowledge regarding the solution of mathematical problems like when performing mental arithmetic to multiply two numbers 65 The same is the case for the experience needed to learn the words through which the claim is expressed For example knowing that all bachelors are unmarried is a priori knowledge because no sensory experience is necessary to confirm this fact even though experience was needed to learn the meanings of the words bachelor and unmarried 66 It is difficult to explain how a priori knowledge is possible and some empiricists deny it exists It is usually seen as unproblematic that one can come to know things through experience but it is not clear how knowledge is possible without experience One of the earliest solutions to this problem comes from Plato who argues that the soul already possesses the knowledge and just needs to recollect or remember it to access it again 67 A similar explanation is given by Descartes who holds that a priori knowledge exists as innate knowledge present in the mind of each human 68 A further approach posits a special mental faculty responsible for this type of knowledge often referred to as rational intuition or rational insight 69 Others Various other types of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature In philosophy self knowledge refers to a person s knowledge of their own sensations thoughts beliefs and other mental states A common view is that self knowledge is more direct than knowledge of the external world which relies on the interpretation of sense data Because of this it is traditionally claimed that self knowledge is indubitable like the claim that a person cannot be wrong about whether they are in pain However this position is not universally accepted in the contemporary discourse and an alternative view states that self knowledge also depends on interpretations that could be false 70 In a slightly different sense self knowledge can also refer to knowledge of the self as a persisting entity with certain personality traits preferences physical attributes relationships goals and social identities 71 h Metaknowledge is knowledge about knowledge It can arise in the form of self knowledge but includes other types as well such as knowing what someone else knows or what information is contained in a scientific article Other aspects of metaknowledge include knowing how knowledge can be acquired stored distributed and used 73 Common knowledge is knowledge that is publicly known and shared by most individuals within a community It establishes a common ground for communication understanding social cohesion and cooperation 74 General knowledge encompasses common knowledge but also includes knowledge that many people have been exposed to but may not be able to immediately recall 75 Common knowledge contrasts with domain knowledge or specialized knowledge which belongs to a specific domain and is only possessed by experts 76 Situated knowledge is knowledge specific to a particular situation 77 It is closely related to practical or tacit knowledge which is learned and applied in specific circumstances This especially concerns certain forms of acquiring knowledge such as trial and error or learning from experience 78 In this regard situated knowledge usually lacks a more explicit structure and is not articulated in terms of universal ideas 79 The term is often used in feminism and postmodernism to argue that many forms of knowledge are not absolute but depend on the concrete historical cultural and linguistic context 77 Explicit knowledge is knowledge that can be fully articulated shared and explained like the knowledge of historical dates and mathematical formulas It can be acquired through traditional learning methods such as reading books and attending lectures It contrasts with tacit knowledge which is not easily articulated or explained to others like the ability to recognize someone s face and the practical expertise of a master craftsman Tacit knowledge is often learned through first hand experience or direct practice 80 Cognitive load theory distinguishes between biologically primary and secondary knowledge Biologically primary knowledge is knowledge that humans have as part of their evolutionary heritage such as knowing how to recognize faces and speech and many general problem solving capacities Biologically secondary knowledge is knowledge acquired because of specific social and cultural circumstances such as knowing how to read and write 81 Knowledge can be occurrent or dispositional Occurrent knowledge is knowledge that is actively involved in cognitive processes Dispositional knowledge by contrast lies dormant in the back of a person s mind and is given by the mere ability to access the relevant information For example if a person knows that cats have whiskers then this knowledge is dispositional most of the time and becomes occurrent while they are thinking about it 82 Many forms of Eastern spirituality and religion distinguish between higher and lower knowledge They are also referred to as para vidya and apara vidya in Hinduism or the two truths doctrine in Buddhism Lower knowledge is based on the senses and the intellect It encompasses both mundane or conventional truths as well as discoveries of the empirical sciences 83 Higher knowledge is understood as knowledge of God the absolute the true self or the ultimate reality It belongs neither to the external world of physical objects nor to the internal world of the experience of emotions and concepts Many spiritual teachings stress the importance of higher knowledge to progress on the spiritual path and to see reality as it truly is beyond the veil of appearances 84 Sources nbsp Perception relies on the senses to acquire knowledge Sources of knowledge are ways in which people come to know things They can be understood as cognitive capacities that are exercised when a person acquires new knowledge 85 Various sources of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature often in terms of the mental faculties responsible They include perception introspection memory inference and testimony However not everyone agrees that all of them actually lead to knowledge Usually perception or observation i e using one of the senses is identified as the most important source of empirical knowledge 86 Knowing that a baby is sleeping is observational knowledge if it was caused by a perception of the snoring baby However this would not be the case if one learned about this fact through a telephone conversation with one s spouse Perception comes in different modalities including vision sound touch smell and taste which correspond to different physical stimuli 87 It is an active process in which sensory signals are selected organized and interpreted to form a representation of the environment This leads in some cases to illusions that misrepresent certain aspects of reality like the Muller Lyer illusion and the Ponzo illusion 88 Introspection is often seen in analogy to perception as a source of knowledge not of external physical objects but of internal mental states A traditionally common view is that introspection has a special epistemic status by being infallible According to this position it is not possible to be mistaken about introspective facts like whether one is in pain because there is no difference between appearance and reality However this claim has been contested in the contemporary discourse and critics argue that it may be possible for example to mistake an unpleasant itch for a pain or to confuse the experience of a slight ellipse for the experience of a circle 89 Perceptual and introspective knowledge often act as a form of fundamental or basic knowledge According to some empiricists they are the only sources of basic knowledge and provide the foundation for all other knowledge 90 Memory differs from perception and introspection in that it is not as independent or basic as they are since it depends on other previous experiences 91 The faculty of memory retains knowledge acquired in the past and makes it accessible in the present as when remembering a past event or a friend s phone number 92 It is generally seen as a reliable source of knowledge However it can be deceptive at times nonetheless either because the original experience was unreliable or because the memory degraded and does not accurately represent the original experience anymore 93 i Knowledge based on perception introspection and memory may give rise to inferential knowledge which comes about when reasoning is applied to draw inferences from other known facts 95 For example the perceptual knowledge of a Czech stamp on a postcard may give rise to the inferential knowledge that one s friend is visiting the Czech Republic This type of knowledge depends on other sources of knowledge responsible for the premises Some rationalists argue for rational intuition as a further source of knowledge that does not rely on observation and introspection They hold for example that some beliefs like the mathematical belief that 2 2 4 are justified through pure reason alone 96 nbsp Knowledge by testimony relies on statements given by other people like the testimony given at a trial Testimony is often included as an additional source of knowledge that unlike the other sources is not tied to one specific cognitive faculty Instead it is based on the idea that one person can come to know a fact because another person talks about this fact Testimony can happen in numerous ways like regular speech a letter a newspaper or a blog The problem of testimony consists in clarifying why and under what circumstances testimony can lead to knowledge A common response is that it depends on the reliability of the person pronouncing the testimony only testimony from reliable sources can lead to knowledge 97 LimitsThe problem of the limits of knowledge concerns the question of which facts are unknowable 98 These limits constitute a form of inevitable ignorance that can affect both what is knowable about the external world as well as what one can know about oneself and about what is good 99 Some limits of knowledge only apply to particular people in specific situations while others pertain to humanity at large 100 A fact is unknowable to a person if this person lacks access to the relevant information like facts in the past that did not leave any significant traces For example it may be unknowable to people today what Caesar s breakfast was the day he was assassinated but it was knowable to him and some contemporaries 101 Another factor restricting knowledge is given by the limitations of the human cognitive faculties Some people may lack the cognitive ability to understand highly abstract mathematical truths and some facts cannot be known by any human because they are too complex for the human mind to conceive 102 A further limit of knowledge arises due to certain logical paradoxes For instance there are some ideas that will never occur to anyone It is not possible to know them because if a person knew about such an idea then this idea would have occurred at least to them 103 j There are many disputes about what can or cannot be known in certain fields Religious skepticism is the view that beliefs about God or other religious doctrines do not amount to knowledge 105 Moral skepticism encompasses a variety of views including the claim that moral knowledge is impossible meaning that one cannot know what is morally good or whether a certain behavior is morally right 106 An influential theory about the limits of metaphysical knowledge was proposed by Immanuel Kant For him knowledge is restricted to the field of appearances and does not reach the things in themselves which exist independently of humans and lie beyond the realm of appearances Based on the observation that metaphysics aims to characterize the things in themselves he concludes that no metaphysical knowledge is possible like knowing whether the world has a beginning or is infinite 107 There are also limits to knowledge in the empirical sciences such as the uncertainty principle which states that it is impossible to know the exact magnitudes of certain certain pairs of physical properties like the position and momentum of a particle at the same time 108 Other examples are physical systems studied by chaos theory for which it is not practically possible to predict how they will behave since they are so sensitive to initial conditions that even the slightest of variations may produce a completely different behavior This phenomenon is known as the butterfly effect 109 nbsp Pyrrho was one of the first philosophical skeptics The strongest position about the limits of knowledge is radical or global skepticism which holds that humans lack any form of knowledge or that knowledge is impossible For example the dream argument states that perceptual experience is not a source of knowledge since dreaming provides unreliable information and a person could be dreaming without knowing it Because of this inability to discriminate between dream and perception it is argued that there is no perceptual knowledge of the external world 110 k This thought experiment is based on the problem of underdetermination which arises when the available evidence is not sufficient to make a rational decision between competing theories In such cases a person is not justified in believing one theory rather than the other If this is always the case then global skepticism follows 111 Another skeptical argument assumes that knowledge requires absolute certainty and aims to show that all human cognition is fallible since it fails to meet this standard 112 An influential argument against radical skepticism states that radical skepticism is self contradictory since denying the existence of knowledge is itself a knowledge claim 113 Other arguments rely on common sense 114 or deny that infallibility is required for knowledge 115 Very few philosophers have explicitly defended radical skepticism but this position has been influential nonetheless usually in a negative sense many see it as a serious challenge to any epistemological theory and often try to show how their preferred theory overcomes it 116 Another form of philosophical skepticism advocates the suspension of judgment as a form of attaining tranquility while remaining humble and open minded 117 A less radical limit of knowledge is identified by falliblists who argue that the possibility of error can never be fully excluded This means that even the best researched scientific theories and the most fundamental commonsense views could still be subject to error Further research may reduce the possibility of being wrong but it can never fully exclude it Some fallibilists reach the skeptical conclusion from this observation that there is no knowledge but the more common view is that knowledge exists but is fallible 118 Pragmatists argue that one consequence of fallibilism is that inquiry should not aim for truth or absolute certainty but for well supported and justified beliefs while remaining open to the possibility that one s beliefs may need to be revised later 119 StructureThe structure of knowledge is the way in which the mental states of a person need to be related to each other for knowledge to arise 120 A common view is that a person has to have good reasons for holding a belief if this belief is to amount to knowledge When the belief is challenged the person may justify it by referring to their reason for holding it In many cases this reason depends itself on another belief that may as well be challenged An example is a person who believes that Ford cars are cheaper than BMWs When their belief is challenged they may justify it by claiming that they heard it from a reliable source This justification depends on the assumption that their source is reliable which may itself be challenged The same may apply to any subsequent reason they cite 121 This threatens to lead to an infinite regress since the epistemic status at each step depends on the epistemic status of the previous step 122 Theories of the structure of knowledge offer responses for how to solve this problem 121 nbsp Foundationalism coherentism and infinitism are theories of the structure of knowledge The black arrows symbolize how one belief supports another belief Three traditional theories are foundationalism coherentism and infinitism Foundationalists and coherentists deny the existence of an infinite regress in contrast to infinitists 121 According to foundationalists some basic reasons have their epistemic status independent of other reasons and thereby constitute the endpoint of the regress 123 Some foundationalists hold that certain sources of knowledge like perception provide basic reasons Another view is that this role is played by certain self evident truths like the knowledge of one s own existence and the content of one s ideas 124 The view that basic reasons exist is not universally accepted One criticism states that there should be a reason why some reasons are basic while others are not According to this view the putative basic reasons are not actually basic since their status would depend on other reasons Another criticism is based on hermeneutics and argues that all understanding is circular and requires interpretation which implies that knowledge does not need a secure foundation 125 Coherentists and infinitists avoid these problems by denying the contrast between basic and non basic reasons Coherentists argue that there is only a finite number of reasons which mutually support and justify one another This is based on the intuition that beliefs do not exist in isolation but form a complex web of interconnected ideas that is justified by its coherence rather than by a few privileged foundational beliefs 126 One difficulty for this view is how to demonstrate that it does not involve the fallacy of circular reasoning 127 If two beliefs mutually support each other then a person has a reason for accepting one belief if they already have the other However mutual support alone is not a good reason for newly accepting both beliefs at once A closely related issue is that there can be distinct sets of coherent beliefs Coherentists face the problem of explaining why someone should accept one coherent set rather than another 126 For infinitists in contrast to foundationalists and coherentists there is an infinite number of reasons This view embraces the idea that there is a regress since each reason depends on another reason One difficulty for this view is that the human mind is limited and may not be able to possess an infinite number of reasons This raises the question of whether according to infinitism human knowledge is possible at all 128 Value nbsp Los portadores de la antorcha The Torch Bearers sculpture by Anna Hyatt Huntington symbolizing the transmission of knowledge from one generation to the next Ciudad Universitaria Madrid Spain Knowledge may be valuable either because it is useful or because it is good in itself Knowledge can be useful by helping a person achieve their goals For example if one knows the answers to questions in an exam one is able to pass that exam or by knowing which horse is the fastest one can earn money from bets In these cases knowledge has instrumental value 129 Not all forms of knowledge are useful and many beliefs about trivial matters have no instrumental value This concerns for example knowing how many grains of sand are on a specific beach or memorizing phone numbers one never intends to call In a few cases knowledge may even have a negative value For example if a person s life depends on gathering the courage to jump over a ravine then having a true belief about the involved dangers may hinder them from doing so 130 nbsp The value of knowledge plays a key role in education for deciding which knowledge to pass on to the students Besides having instrumental value knowledge may also have intrinsic value This means that some forms of knowledge are good in themselves even if they do not provide any practical benefits According to philosopher Duncan Pritchard this applies to forms of knowledge linked to wisdom 131 It is controversial whether all knowledge has intrinsic value including knowledge about trivial facts like knowing whether the biggest apple tree had an even number of leaves yesterday morning One view in favor of the intrinsic value of knowledge states that having no belief about a matter is a neutral state and knowledge is always better than this neutral state even if the value difference is only minimal 132 A more specific issue in epistemology concerns the question of whether or why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief 133 There is wide agreement that knowledge is usually good in some sense but the thesis that knowledge is better than true belief is controversial An early discussion of this problem is found in Plato s Meno in relation to the claim that both knowledge and true belief can successfully guide action and therefore have apparently the same value For example it seems that mere true belief is as effective as knowledge when trying to find the way to Larissa 134 According to Plato knowledge is better because it is more stable 135 Another suggestion is that knowledge gets its additional value from justification One difficulty for this view is that while justification makes it more probable that a belief is true it is not clear what additional value it provides in comparison to an unjustified belief that is already true 136 The problem of the value of knowledge is often discussed in relation to reliabilism and virtue epistemology 137 Reliabilism can be defined as the thesis that knowledge is reliably formed true belief This view has difficulties in explaining why knowledge is valuable or how a reliable belief forming process adds additional value 138 According to an analogy by philosopher Linda Zagzebski a cup of coffee made by a reliable coffee machine has the same value as an equally good cup of coffee made by an unreliable coffee machine 139 This difficulty in solving the value problem is sometimes used as an argument against reliabilism 140 Virtue epistemology by contrast offers a unique solution to the value problem Virtue epistemologists see knowledge as the manifestation of cognitive virtues They hold that knowledge has additional value due to its association with virtue This is based on the idea that cognitive success in the form of the manifestation of virtues is inherently valuable independent of whether the resulting states are instrumentally useful 141 Acquiring and transmitting knowledge often comes with certain costs such as the material resources required to obtain new information and the time and energy needed to understand it For this reason an awareness of the value of knowledge is crucial to many fields that have to make decisions about whether to seek knowledge about a specific matter On a political level this concerns the problem of identifying the most promising research programs to allocate funds 142 Similar concerns affect businesses where stakeholders have to decide whether the cost of acquiring knowledge is justified by the economic benefits that this knowledge may provide and the military which relies on intelligence to identify and prevent threats 143 In the field of education the value of knowledge can be used to choose which knowledge should be passed on to the students 144 ScienceMain article Philosophy of science The scientific approach is usually regarded as an exemplary process of how to gain knowledge about empirical facts 145 Scientific knowledge includes mundane knowledge about easily observable facts for example chemical knowledge that certain reactants become hot when mixed together It also encompasses knowledge of less tangible issues like claims about the behavior of genes neutrinos and black holes 146 A key aspect of most forms of science is that they seek natural laws that explain empirical observations 145 Scientific knowledge is discovered and tested using the scientific method l This method aims to arrive at reliable knowledge by formulating the problem in a clear way and by ensuring that the evidence used to support or refute a specific theory is public reliable and replicable This way other researchers can repeat the experiments and observations in the initial study to confirm or disconfirm it 148 The scientific method is often analyzed as a series of steps that begins with regular observation and data collection Based on these insights scientists then try to find a hypothesis that explains the observations The hypothesis is then tested using a controlled experiment to compare whether predictions based on the hypothesis match the observed results As a last step the results are interpreted and a conclusion is reached whether and to what degree the findings confirm or disconfirm the hypothesis 149 The empirical sciences are usually divided into natural and social sciences The natural sciences like physics biology and chemistry focus on quantitative research methods to arrive at knowledge about natural phenomena 150 Quantitative research happens by making precise numerical measurements and the natural sciences often rely on advanced technological instruments to perform these measurements and to setup experiments Another common feature of their approach is to use mathematical tools to analyze the measured data and formulate exact and general laws to describe the observed phenomena 151 The social sciences like sociology anthropology and communication studies examine social phenomena on the level of human behavior relationships and society at large 152 While they also make use of quantitative research they usually give more emphasis to qualitative methods Qualitative research gathers non numerical data often with the goal of arriving at a deeper understanding of the meaning and interpretation of social phenomena from the perspective of those involved 153 This approach can take various forms such as interviews focus groups and case studies 154 Mixed method research combines quantitative and qualitative methods to explore the same phenomena from a variety of perspectives to get a more comprehensive understanding 155 The progress of scientific knowledge is traditionally seen as a gradual and continuous process in which the existing body of knowledge is increased at each step This view has been challenged by some philosophers of science such as Thomas Kuhn who holds that between phases of incremental progress there are so called scientific revolutions in which a paradigm shift occurs According to this view some basic assumptions are changed due to the paradigm shift resulting in a radically new perspective on the body of scientific knowledge that is incommensurable with the previous outlook 156 m Scientism refers to a group of views that privilege the sciences and the scientific method over other forms of inquiry and knowledge acquisition In its strongest formulation it is the claim that there is no other knowledge besides scientific knowledge 158 A common critique of scientism made by philosophers such as Hans Georg Gadamer and Paul Feyerabend is that the fixed requirement of following the scientific method is too rigid and results in a misleading picture of reality by excluding various relevant phenomena from the scope of knowledge 159 HistoryMain article History of knowledge The history of knowledge is the field of inquiry that studies how knowledge in different fields has developed and evolved in the course of history It is closely related to the history of science but covers a wider area that includes knowledge from fields like philosophy mathematics education literature art and religion It further covers practical knowledge of specific crafts medicine and everyday practices It investigates not only how knowledge is created and employed but also how it is disseminated and preserved 160 Before the ancient period knowledge about social conduct and survival skills was passed down orally and in the form of customs from one generation to the next 161 The ancient period saw the rise of major civilizations starting about 3000 BCE in Mesopotamia Egypt India and China The invention of writing in this period significantly increased the amount of stable knowledge within society since it could be stored and shared without being limited by imperfect human memory 162 During this time the first developments in scientific fields like mathematics astronomy and medicine were made They were later formalized and greatly expanded by the ancient Greeks starting in the 6th century BCE Other ancient advancements concerned knowledge in the fields of agriculture law and politics 163 nbsp The invention of the printing press in the 15th century greatly expanded access to written materials In the medieval period religious knowledge was a central concern and religious institutions like the Catholic Church in Europe influenced intellectual activity 164 Jewish communities set up yeshivas as centers for studying religious texts and Jewish law 165 In the Muslim world madrasa schools were established and focused on Islamic law and Islamic philosophy 166 Many intellectual achievements of the ancient period were preserved refined and expanded during the Islamic Golden Age from the 8th to 13th centuries 167 Centers of higher learning were established in this period in various regions like Al Qarawiyyin University in Morocco 168 the Al Azhar University in Egypt 169 the House of Wisdom in Iraq 170 and the first universities in Europe 171 This period also saw the formation of guilds which preserved and advanced technical and craft knowledge 172 In the Renaissance period starting in the 14th century there was a renewed interest in the humanities and sciences 173 The printing press was invented in the 15th century and significantly increased the availability of written media and general literacy of the population 174 These developments served as the foundation of the Scientific Revolution in the Age of Enlightenment starting in the 16th and 17th centuries It led to an explosion of knowledge in fields such as physics chemistry biology and the social sciences 175 The technological advancements that accompanied this development made possible the Industrial Revolution in the 18th and 19th centuries 176 In the 20th century the development of computers and the Internet led to a vast expansion of knowledge by revolutionizing how knowledge is stored shared and created 177 n In various disciplinesReligion See also Desacralization of knowledge and Resacralization of knowledge Knowledge plays a central role in many religions Knowledge claims about the existence of God or religious doctrines about how each one should live their lives are found in almost every culture 179 However such knowledge claims are often controversial and are commonly rejected by religious skeptics and atheists 180 The epistemology of religion is the field of inquiry studying whether belief in God and in other religious doctrines is rational and amounts to knowledge 181 One important view in this field is evidentialism which states that belief in religious doctrines is justified if it is supported by sufficient evidence Suggested examples of evidence for religious doctrines include religious experiences such as direct contact with the divine or inner testimony when hearing God s voice 182 Evidentialists often reject that belief in religious doctrines amounts to knowledge based on the claim that there is not sufficient evidence 183 A famous saying in this regard is due to Bertrand Russell When asked how he would justify his lack of belief in God when facing his judgment after death he replied Not enough evidence God Not enough evidence 184 However religious teachings about the existence and nature of God are not always seen as knowledge claims by their defenders Some explicitly state that the proper attitude towards such doctrines is not knowledge but faith This is often combined with the assumption that these doctrines are true but cannot be fully understood by reason or verified through rational inquiry For this reason it is claimed that one should accept them even though they do not amount to knowledge 180 Such a view is reflected in a famous saying by Immanuel Kant where he claims that he had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith 185 Distinct religions often differ from each other concerning the doctrines they proclaim as well as their understanding of the role of knowledge in religious practice 186 In both the Jewish and the Christian traditions knowledge plays a role in the fall of man in which Adam and Eve were expelled from the Garden of Eden Responsible for this fall was that they ignored God s command and ate from the tree of knowledge which gave them the knowledge of good and evil This is seen as a rebellion against God since this knowledge belongs to God and it is not for humans to decide what is right or wrong 187 In the Christian literature knowledge is seen as one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit 188 In Islam the Knowing al ʿAlim is one of the 99 names reflecting distinct attributes of God The Qur an asserts that knowledge comes from Allah and the acquisition of knowledge is encouraged in the teachings of Muhammad 189 nbsp Saraswati is the goddess of knowledge and the arts in Hinduism In Buddhism knowledge that leads to liberation is called vijja It contrasts with avijja or ignorance which is understood as the root of all suffering This is often explained in relation to the claim that humans suffer because they crave things that are impermanent The ignorance of the impermanent nature of things is seen as the factor responsible for this craving 190 The central goal of Buddhist practice is to stop suffering This aim is to be achieved by understanding and practicing the teaching known as the Four Noble Truths and thereby overcoming ignorance 191 Knowledge plays a key role in the classical path of Hinduism known as jnana yoga or path of knowledge It aims to achieve oneness with the divine by fostering an understanding of the self and its relation to Brahman or ultimate reality 192 Anthropology The anthropology of knowledge is a multi disciplinary field of inquiry 193 It studies how knowledge is acquired stored retrieved and communicated 194 Special interest is given to how knowledge is reproduced and changes in relation to social and cultural circumstances 195 In this context the term knowledge is used in a very broad sense roughly equivalent to terms like understanding and culture 196 This means that the forms and reproduction of understanding are studied irrespective of their truth value In epistemology by contrast knowledge is usually restricted to forms of true belief The main focus in anthropology is on empirical observations of how people ascribe truth values to meaning contents like when affirming an assertion even if these contents are false 195 This also includes practical components knowledge is what is employed when interpreting and acting on the world and involves diverse phenomena such as feelings embodied skills information and concepts It is used to understand and anticipate events to prepare and react accordingly 197 The reproduction of knowledge and its changes often happen through some form of communication used to transfer knowledge 198 This includes face to face discussions and online communications as well as seminars and rituals An important role in this context falls to institutions like university departments or scientific journals in the academic context 195 Anthropologists of knowledge understand traditions as knowledge that has been reproduced within a society or geographic region over several generations They are interested in how this reproduction is affected by external influences For example societies tend to interpret knowledge claims found in other societies and incorporate them in a modified form 199 Within a society people belonging to the same social group usually understand things and organize knowledge in similar ways to one another In this regard social identities play a significant role people who associate themselves with similar identities like age influenced professional religious and ethnic identities tend to embody similar forms of knowledge Such identities concern both how a person sees themselves for example in terms of the ideals they pursue as well as how other people see them such as the expectations they have toward the person 200 Sociology Main article Sociology of knowledge The sociology of knowledge is the subfield of sociology that studies how thought and society are related to each other 201 Like the anthropology of knowledge it understands knowledge in a wide sense that encompasses philosophical and political ideas religious and ideological doctrines folklore law and technology The sociology of knowledge studies in what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises what consequences it has and on what existential conditions it depends The examined conditions include physical demographic economic and sociocultural factors For instance philosopher Karl Marx claimed that the dominant ideology in a society is a product of and changes with the underlying socioeconomic conditions 201 Another example is found in forms of decolonial scholarship that claim that colonial powers are responsible for the hegemony of Western knowledge systems They seek a decolonization of knowledge to undermine this hegemony 202 A related issue concerns the link between knowledge and power in particular the extent to which knowledge is power The philosopher Michel Foucault explored this issue and examined how knowledge and the institutions responsible for it control people through what he termed biopower by shaping societal norms values and regulatory mechanisms in fields like psychiatry medicine and the penal system 203 A central subfield is the sociology of scientific knowledge which investigates the social factors involved in the production and validation of scientific knowledge This encompasses examining the impact of the distribution of resources and rewards on the scientific process which leads some areas of research to flourish while others languish Further topics focus on selection processes such as how academic journals decide whether to publish an article and how academic institutions recruit researchers and the general values and norms characteristic of the scientific profession 204 Others Formal epistemology studies knowledge using formal tools found in mathematics and logic 205 An important issue in this field concerns the epistemic principles of knowledge These are rules governing how knowledge and related states behave and in what relations they stand to each other The transparency principle also referred to as the luminosity of knowledge states that it is impossible for someone to know something without knowing that they know it o 206 According to the conjunction principle if a person has justified beliefs in two separate propositions then they are also justified in believing the conjunction of these two propositions In this regard if Bob has a justified belief that dogs are animals and another justified belief that cats are animals then he is justified to believe the conjunction that both dogs and cats are animals Other commonly discussed principles are the closure principle and the evidence transfer principle 207 Knowledge management is the process of creating gathering storing and sharing knowledge It involves the management of information assets that can take the form of documents databases policies and procedures It is of particular interest in the field of business and organizational development as it directly impacts decision making and strategic planning Knowledge management efforts are often employed to increase operational efficiency in attempts to gain a competitive advantage 208 Key processes in the field of knowledge management are knowledge creation knowledge storage knowledge sharing and knowledge application Knowledge creation is the first step and involves the production of new information Knowledge storage can happen through media like books audio recordings film and digital databases Secure storage facilitates knowledge sharing which involves the transmission of information from one person to another For the knowledge to be beneficial it has to be put into practice meaning that its insights should be used to either improve existing practices or implement new ones 209 Knowledge representation is the process of storing organized information which may happen using various forms of media and also includes information stored in the mind 210 It plays a key role in the artificial intelligence where the term is used for the field of inquiry that studies how computer systems can efficiently represent information This field investigates how different data structures and interpretative procedures can be combined to achieve this goal and which formal languages can be used to express knowledge items Some efforts in this field are directed at developing general languages and systems that can be employed in a great variety of domains while others focus on an optimized representation method within one specific domain Knowledge representation is closely linked to automatic reasoning because the purpose of knowledge representation formalisms is usually to construct a knowledge base from which inferences are drawn 211 Influential knowledge base formalisms include logic based systems rule based systems semantic networks and frames Logic based systems rely on formal languages employed in logic to represent knowledge They use linguistic devices like individual terms predicates and quantifiers For rule based systems each unit of information is expressed using a conditional production rule of the form if A then B Semantic nets model knowledge as a graph consisting of vertices to represent facts or concepts and edges to represent the relations between them Frames provide complex taxonomies to group items into classes subclasses and instances 212 Pedagogy is the study of teaching methods or the art of teaching p It explores how learning takes place and which techniques teachers may employ to transmit knowledge to students and improve their learning experience while keeping them motivated 214 There is a great variety of teaching methods and the most effective approach often depends on factors like the subject matter and the age and proficiency level of the learner 215 In teacher centered education the teacher acts as the authority figure imparting information and directing the learning process Student centered approaches give a more active role to students with the teacher acting as a coach to facilitate the process 216 Further methodological considerations encompass the difference between group work and individual learning and the use of instructional media and other forms of educational technology 217 See alsoEpistemic modal logic subfield of modal logic that is concerned with reasoning about knowledgePages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Ignorance Lack of knowledge and understanding Knowledge falsification Deliberate misrepresentation of knowledge Omniscience Capacity to know everything Outline of knowledge Knowledge what is known understood proven information and products of learningReferencesNotes In this context testimony is what other people report both in spoken and written form A similar approach was already discussed in Ancient Greek philosophy in Plato s dialogue Theaetetus where Socrates pondered the distinction between knowledge and true belief but rejected this definition 22 Truth is usually associated with objectivity This view is rejected by relativism about truth which argues that what is true depends on one s perspective 24 A defeater of a belief is evidence that this belief is false 37 A distinction similar to the one between knowledge that and knowledge how was already discussed in ancient Greece as the contrast between episteme unchanging theoretical knowledge and techne expert technical knowledge 43 For instance to know whether Ben is rich can be understood as knowing that Ben is rich in case he is and knowing that Ben is not rich in case he is not 49 However it is controversial to what extent goal directed behavior in lower animals is comparable to human knowledge how 56 Individuals may lack a deeper understanding of their character and feelings and attaining self knowledge is one step in psychoanalysis 72 Confabulation is a special type of memory error that consists remembering events that did not happen often provoked by an attempt to fill memory gaps 94 An often cited paradox from the field of formal epistemology is Fitch s paradox of knowability which states that knowledge has limits because denying this claim leads to the absurd conclusion that every truth is known 104 A similar often cited thought experiment assumes that a person is not a regular human being but a brain in a vat that receives electrical stimuli These stimuli give the brain the false impression of having a body and interacting with the external world Since the person is unable to tell the difference it is argued that they do not know that they have a body responsible for reliable perceptions 111 It is controversial to what extent there is a single scientific method that applies equally to all sciences rather than a group of related approaches 147 It is controversial how radical the difference between paradigms is and whether they truly are incommensurable 157 The internet also reduced the cost of accessing knowledge with a lot of information being freely available 178 This principle implies that if Heike knows that today is Monday then she also knows that she knows that today is Monday The exact definition of the term is disputed 213 Citations AHD staff 2022aMW Staff 2023CD staff Zagzebski 1999 p 109Steup amp Neta 2020 Lead Section 1 The Varieties of Cognitive Success Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 1 1 The Truth Condition 1 2 The Belief ConditionKlein 1998 1 The Varieties of KnowledgeHetherington 2022a 1b Knowledge ThatStroll 2023 The Nature of Knowledge Hetherington 2022a 1 Kinds of KnowledgeStanley amp Willlamson 2001 pp 411 412Zagzebski 1999 p 92 Klausen 2015 pp 813 818Lackey 2021 pp 111 112 Allwood 2013 pp 69 72Allen 2005 Sociology of KnowledgeBarth 2002 p 1 AHD staff 2022aMagee amp Popper 1971 pp 74 75 AHD staff 2022bWalton 2005 pp 59 64 Rothberg amp Erickson 2005 pp 5 14 15Christopher Prasath amp Vanga 2018 pp 93 94AHD staff 2022aAHD staff 2022c Hoad 1993 pp 254 255Wise 2011 p 80 Steup amp Neta 2020 2 What Is Knowledge Allen 2005 Steup amp Neta 2020 Lead SectionTruncellito 2023 Lead SectionMoser 2005 p 3 Zagzebski 1999 p 99Hetherington 2022a 2 Knowledge as a Kind Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 Lead SectionHannon 2021 Knowledge Concept ofLehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of KnowledgeZagzebski 1999 pp 92 96 97 Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 Lead SectionZagzebski 1999 p 96Gupta 2021 Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 7 Is Knowledge Analyzable Pritchard 2013 3 Defining knowledgeMcCain 2022 Lead Section 2 Chisholm on the Problem of the CriterionFumerton 2008 pp 34 36 Stroll 2023 The Origins of Knowledge Analytic EpistemologyLehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of KnowledgeGarcia Arnaldos 2020 p 508 Hetherington 8 Implications of Fallibilism No Knowledge Hetherington 2022a 6 Standards for KnowingBlack 2002 pp 23 32 Klein 1998 Lead Section 3 WarrantZagzebski 1999 pp 99 100 Allen 2005 Lead Section GettierologyParikh amp Renero 2017 pp 93 102Chappell 2019 8 Third Definition D3 Knowledge Is True Judgement With an Account 201d 210a Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 1 1 The Truth ConditionHetherington 2022a 1b Knowledge That 5 Understanding Knowledge Stroll 2023 The Nature of Knowledge Landau 2017 pp 119 120O Grady Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 1 2 The Belief ConditionKlein 1998 1 The Varieties of KnowledgeZagzebski 1999 p 93 Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 1 3 The Justification Condition 6 Doing Without Justification Klein 1998 Lead Section 3 WarrantZagzebski 1999 p 100 Klein 1998 2 Propositional Knowledge Is Not Mere True Belief 3 WarrantHetherington 2022a 5a The Justified True Belief Conception of Knowledge 6e Mere True BeliefLehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of KnowledgeIchikawa amp Steup 2018 1 3 The Justification Condition Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 1 3 The Justification ConditionKlein 1998 3 WarrantHetherington 2022a 5a The Justified True Belief Conception of Knowledge 6e Mere True Belief Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 1 3 The Justification Condition 6 1 Reliabilist Theories of KnowledgeKlein 1998 4 Foundationalism and Coherentism 6 ExternalismHetherington 2022a 5a The Justified True Belief Conception of Knowledge 7 Knowing s Point Hetherington 2022 Lead Section Introduction Klein 1998 5 Defeasibility TheoriesHetherington 2022a 5 Understanding Knowledge Zagzebski 1999 p 100 Rodriguez 2018 pp 29 32Goldman 1976 pp 771 773Sudduth 2022Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 10 2 Fake Barn Cases Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 3 The Gettier Problem 10 2 Fake Barn Cases Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 3 The Gettier Problem 4 No False Lemmas 5 Modal Conditions 6 Doing Without Justification Steup amp Neta 2020 2 3 Knowing Facts Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 3 The Gettier Problem 7 Is Knowledge Analyzable Duran amp Formanek 2018 pp 648 650 McCain Stapleford amp Steup 2021 p 111 Lehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of KnowledgeSudduth 2022 Hetherington 2022a 5c Questioning the Gettier Problem 6 Standards for KnowingKraft 2012 pp 49 50 Ames Yajun amp Hershock 2021 pp 86 87Legg amp Hookway 2021 4 2 InquiryBaggini amp Southwell 2016 p 48 Ichikawa amp Steup 2018 3 The Gettier Problem 7 Is Knowledge Analyzable Zagzebski 1999 pp 93 94 104 105Steup amp Neta 2020 2 3 Knowing Facts Hetherington 2022a 1 Kinds of KnowledgeBarnett 1990 p 40Lilley Lightfoot amp Amaral 2004 pp 162 163 Allen 2005 Lead Section Baehr 2022 Lead SectionFaber Maruster amp Jorna 2017 p 340Gertler 2021 Lead SectionRescher 2005 p 20 Klein 1998 1 The Varieties of KnowledgeHetherington 2022a 1b Knowledge ThatStroll 2023 The Nature of Knowledge Hetherington 2022a 1b Knowledge ThatStroll 2023 The Nature of KnowledgeZagzebski 1999 p 92 Hetherington 2022a 1b Knowledge That 1c Knowledge Wh Hetherington 2022a 1c Knowledge WhStroll 2023 The Nature of Knowledge Hetherington 2022a 1c Knowledge Wh Morrison 2005 p 371Reif 2008 p 33Zagzebski 1999 p 93 Woolfolk amp Margetts 2012 p 251 a b Pritchard 2013 1 Some preliminaries Hetherington 2022a 1 Kinds of KnowledgeStroll 2023 The Nature of KnowledgeStanley amp Willlamson 2001 pp 411 412 Hetherington 2022a 1d Knowing HowPritchard 2013 1 Some preliminaries Steup amp Neta 2020 2 2 Knowing HowPavese 2022 Lead Section 6 The Epistemology of Knowledge How Pavese 2022 7 4 Knowledge How in Preverbal Children and Nonhuman Animals Hetherington 2022a 1a Knowing by AcquaintanceStroll 2023 St Anselm of CanterburyZagzebski 1999 p 92 Peels 2023 p 28Heydorn amp Jesudason 2013 p 10Foxall 2017 p 75Hasan amp Fumerton 2020DePoe 2022 Lead Section 1 The Distinction Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by DescriptionHetherington 2022a 1a Knowing by Acquaintance Hasan amp Fumerton 2020 introductionHaymes amp Ozdalga 2016 pp 26 28Miah 2006 pp 19 20Alter amp Nagasawa 2015 pp 93 94Hetherington 2022a 1a Knowing by Acquaintance Stroll 2023 A Priori and a Posteriori KnowledgeBaehr 2022 Lead SectionRussell 2020 Lead Section Baehr 2022 Lead SectionMoser 2016 Lead Section Baehr 2022 Lead Section Russell 2020 Lead SectionBaehr 2022 Lead Section Moser 2016 Lead Section Baehr 2022 1 An Initial Characterization 4 The Relevant Sense of Experience Russell 2020 4 1 A Priori Justification Is Justification That Is Independent of Experience Baehr 2022Russell 2020 4 1 A Priori Justification Is Justification That Is Independent of Experience Woolf 2013 pp 192 193Hirschberger 2019 p 22 Moser 1998 2 Innate concepts certainty and the a prioriMarkie 1998 2 Innate ideasO Brien 2006 p 31Markie amp Folescu 2023 2 The Intuition Deduction Thesis Baehr 2022 1 An Initial Characterization 6 Positive Characterizations of the A Priori Gertler 2021 Lead Section 1 The Distinctiveness of Self KnowledgeGertler 2010 p 1McGeer 2001 pp 13837 13841 Gertler 2021aMorin amp Racy 2021 pp 373 374Kernis 2013 p 209 Wilson 2002 pp 3 4Reginster 2017 pp 231 232 Evans amp Foster 2011 pp 721 725Rescher 2005 p 20Cox amp Raja 2011 p 134Leondes 2001 p 416 Desouza amp Awazu 2005 p 53Jorna 2017 p 340Faber Maruster amp Jorna 2017 p 340 Schneider amp McGrew 2022 pp 115 116 Faber Maruster amp Jorna 2017 p 340Vempala 2014 Creativity Theories of Musical a b APA staff 2022Hunter 2009 pp 151 153 Barnett 2006 pp 146 147 Hunter 2009 pp 151 153 Gascoigne amp Thornton 2014 pp 8 37 81 108Hill 2009 Idiosyncratic Views of Knowledge Sweller Ayres amp Kalyuga 2011 pp 3 4Low Jin amp Sweller 2008 p 2 Stroll 2023 Occasional and Dispositional KnowledgeBartlett 2018 pp 1 2Schwitzgebel 2021 Rambachan 2006 pp 10 11Thakchoe 2022 Lead SectionMishra 2021 p 52Ghose 1998 Political Writings and Speeches 1890 1908 The Glory of God in Man Rambachan 2006 pp 10 11Mishra 2021 p 52Ghose 1998 Political Writings and Speeches 1890 1908 The Glory of God in Man Kern 2017 pp 8 10 133Spaulding 2016 pp 223 224 Hetherington 2022a 3 Ways of KnowingStroll 2023 The Origins of KnowledgeO Brien 2022 Lead Section Bertelson amp Gelder 2004 pp 141 142Martin 1998 Lead SectionSteup amp Neta 2020 5 1 Perception 5 5 Testimony Khatoon 2012 p 104Martin 1998 Lead Section Steup amp Neta 2020 5 2 Introspection Hetherington 2022a 3 Ways of KnowingStroll 2023 The Origins of Knowledge Steup amp Neta 2020 5 3 MemoryAudi 2002 pp 72 75 Gardiner 2001 pp 1351 1352Michaelian amp Sutton 2017 Steup amp Neta 2020 5 3 Memory Baird amp Maskill 2017 p 140AHD Staff 2022e Hetherington 2022a 3d Knowing by Thinking Plus ObservingSteup amp Neta 2020 5 4 Reason Audi 2002 pp 85 90 91Markie amp Folescu 2023 Lead Section 1 Introduction Steup amp Neta 2020 5 5 TestimonyLeonard 2021 Lead Section 1 Reductionism and Non ReductionismGreen 2022 Lead Section Rescher 2009 pp ix 1 2Rescher 2005a p 479Markie amp Folescu 2023 1 Introduction Markie amp Folescu 2023 1 IntroductionRescher 2009 pp 2 6Stoltz 2021 p 120 Rescher 2009 p 6 Rescher 2009 pp 2 6Rescher 2009a pp 140 141 Rescher 2009 pp 10 93Rescher 2009a pp x xi 57 58Dika 2023 p 163 Rescher 2009 pp 3 9 65 66Rescher 2009a pp 32 33Weisberg 2021 4 Fourth Case Study The Limits of Knowledge Weisberg 2021 4 2 The Knowability Paradox a k a the Church Fitch Paradox Kreeft amp Tacelli 2009 p 371 Sinnott Armstrong 2019 Lead Section 1 Varieties of Moral Skepticism 2 A Presumption Against Moral Skepticism Sayre McCord 2023 5 Moral Epistemology McCormick 4 Kant s Transcendental IdealismWilliams 2023 Lead Section 1 Theoretical reason reason s cognitive role and limitationsBlackburn 2008 p 101 Rutten 2012 p 189Yanofsky 2013 pp 185 186 Yanofsky 2013 pp 161 164 Windt 2021 1 1 Cartesian Dream SkepticismKlein 1998 8 The Epistemic Principles and ScepticismHetherington 2022a 4 Sceptical Doubts About Knowing a b Steup amp Neta 2020 6 1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism Hetherington 2022a 6 Standards for KnowingKlein 1998 8 The Epistemic Principles and ScepticismSteup amp Neta 2020 6 1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism Stroll 2023 Skepticism Steup amp Neta 2020 6 2 Responses to the Closure ArgumentLycan 2019 pp 21 22 5 36 McDermid 2023Misak 2002 p 53Hamner 2003 p 87 Klein 1998 8 The Epistemic Principles and ScepticismHetherington 2022a 4 Sceptical Doubts About KnowingSteup amp Neta 2020 6 1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism Attie Picker 2020 pp 97 98Perin 2020 pp 285 286 Hetherington Lead Section 9 Implications of Fallibilism Knowing Fallibly Rescher 1998 Lead SectionLegg amp Hookway 2021 4 1 Skepticism versus Fallibilism Legg amp Hookway 2021 4 1 Skepticism versus FallibilismHookway 2012 pp 39 40 Hasan amp Fumerton 2018 Lead Section 2 The Classical Analysis of Foundational JustificationFumerton 2022 Summary a b c Klein 1998 Lead Section 4 Foundationalism and CoherentismSteup amp Neta 2020 4 The Structure of Knowledge and JustificationLehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of Knowledge Cameron 2018Clark 1988 pp 369 370 Klein 1998 Lead Section 4 Foundationalism and CoherentismSteup amp Neta 2020 4 1 FoundationalismLehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of Knowledge Poston Lead SectionHasan amp Fumerton 2022 1 Regress Arguments for Foundationalism Klein 1998 4 Foundationalism and CoherentismSteup amp Neta 2020 4 The Structure of Knowledge and JustificationLehrer 2015 1 The Analysis of KnowledgeGeorge 2021 1 2 Against Foundationalism 1 3 The Hermeneutical Circle a b Klein 1998 4 Foundationalism and CoherentismSteup amp Neta 2020 4 The Structure of Knowledge and Justification Murphy 2022Lammenranta 2022 Klein 1998 4 Foundationalism and Coherentism Degenhardt 2019 pp 1 6Pritchard 2013 2 The value of knowledgeOlsson 2011 pp 874 875 Pritchard 2013 2 The value of knowledge Pritchard 2013 2 The value of knowledgeDegenhardt 2019 pp 1 6 Lemos 1994 pp 88 89Bergstrom 1987 pp 53 55 Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022Olsson 2011 pp 874 875 Olsson 2011 pp 874 875Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022Plato 2002 pp 89 90 97b 98a Olsson 2011 p 875 Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022 Lead Section 6 Other Accounts of the Value of Knowledge Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022Olsson 2011 p 874Pritchard 2007 pp 85 86 Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022 2 Reliabilism and the Meno Problem 3 Virtue Epistemology and the Value Problem Turri Alfano amp Greco 2021 Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022 2 Reliabilism and the Meno Problem Pritchard Turri amp Carter 2022 3 Virtue Epistemology and the Value ProblemOlsson 2011 p 877Turri Alfano amp Greco 2021 6 Epistemic Value Stehr amp Adolf 2016 pp 483 485Powell 2020 pp 132 133Meirmans et al 2019 pp 754 756 Lengnick Hall amp Lengnick Hall 2003 p 85Awad amp Ghaziri 2003 pp 28 29 Degenhardt 2019 pp 1 6 a b Pritchard 2013 pp 115 118 11 Scientific KnowledgeMoser 2005 p 385 Moser 2005 p 386 Hepburn amp Andersen 2021 Lead Section 1 Overview and organizing themes Moser 2005 p 390Hatfield 1998Beins 2017 pp 8 9Hepburn amp Andersen 2021 Dodd Zambetti amp Deneve 2023 pp 11 12Hatfield 1998Hepburn amp Andersen 2021 Lead Section 6 1 The scientific method in science education and as seen by scientists Cohen 2013 p xxvMyers 2009 p 8Repko 2008 p 200 Repko 2008 p 200Hatfield 1998 3 Scientific Method in Scientific PracticeMertler 2021 pp 100 101Myers 2009 p 8 Colander 2016 pp 1 2AHD Staff 2022d Mertler 2021 pp 88 89Travers 2001 pp 1 2 Howell 2013 pp 193 194Travers 2001 pp 1 2Klenke 2014 p 123 Schoonenboom amp Johnson 2017 pp 107 108Shorten amp Smith 2017 pp 74 75 Pritchard 2013 pp 123 125 11 Scientific KnowledgeNiiniluoto 2019 Bird 2022 6 2 Incommensurability Plantinga 2018 pp 222 223 Flynn 2000 pp 83 84Clegg 2022 p 14Mahadevan 2007 p 91Gauch 2003 p 88 Burke 2015 1 Knowledges and Their Histories History and Its Neighbours 3 Processes Four Stages 3 Processes Oral TransmissionDoren 1992 pp xvi xviiiDaston 2017 pp 142 143Mulsow 2018 p 159 Bowen Gelpi amp Anweiler 2023 Introduction Prehistoric and Primitive CulturesBartlett amp Burton 2007 p 15Fagan amp Durrani 2016 p 15Doren 1992 pp 3 4 Doren 1992 pp xxiii xxiv 3 4Friesen 2017 pp 17 18Danesi 2013 pp 168 169Steinberg 1995 pp 3 4Thornton amp Lanzer 2018 p 7 Doren 1992 pp xxiii xxiv 3 4 29 30Conner 2009 p 81 Burke 2015 2 Concepts Authorities and MonopoliesKuhn 1992 p 106Thornton amp Lanzer 2018 p 7 Bowker 2003 YeshivahWalton 2015 p 130 Johnson amp Stearns 2023 pp 5 43 44 47Esposito 2003 Madrasa Trefil 2012 pp 49 51 Aqil Babekri amp Nadmi 2020 p 156 Cosman amp Jones 2009 p 148 Gilliot 2018 p 81 Bowen Gelpi amp Anweiler 2023 The Development of the UniversitiesKemmis amp Edwards Groves 2017 p 50 Power 1970 pp 243 244 Celenza 2021 pp ix xBlack amp Alvarez 2019 p 1 Steinberg 1995 p 5Danesi 2013 pp 169 170 Doren 1992 pp xxiv xxv 184 185Thornton amp Lanzer 2018 p 7 Doren 1992 pp xxiv xxv 213 214Thornton amp Lanzer 2018 p 7 Thornton amp Lanzer 2018 p 8Danesi 2013 pp 178 181 Antonio 2008 p 358Danesi 2013 pp 178 181 Clark 2022 Lead Section 2 The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God a b Penelhum 1971 1 Faith Scepticism and Philosophy Clark 2022 Lead SectionForrest 2021 Lead Section 1 Simplifications Clark 2022 Lead Section 2 The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in GodForrest 2021 Lead Section 2 The Rejection of Enlightenment EvidentialismDougherty 2014 pp 97 98 Clark 2022 2 The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in GodForrest 2021 Lead Section 2 The Rejection of Enlightenment Evidentialism Clark 2022 2 The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God Stevenson 2003 pp 72 73 Paden 2009 pp 225 227Paden 2005 Lead Section Carson amp Cerrito 2003 p 164Delahunty amp Dignen 2012 p 365Blayney 1769 Genesis Legge 2017 p 181Van Nieuwenhove 2020 p 395 Campo 2009 p 515Swartley 2005 p 63 Burton 2002 pp 326 327Chaudhary 2017 pp 202 203Chaudhary 2017a pp 1373 1374 Chaudhary 2017 pp 202 203Chaudhary 2017a pp 1373 1374 Jones amp Ryan 2006 jnanaJones amp Ryan 2006 Bhagavad Gita Allwood 2013 pp 69 72Boyer 2007 1 Of Dialectical Germans and Dialectical Ethnographers Notes from an Engagement with Philosophy Cohen 2010 pp S193 S202 a b c Allwood 2013 pp 69 72 Allwood 2013 pp 69 72Barth 2002 p 1 Barth 2002 pp 1 2 Allwood 2013 pp 69 72Cohen 2010 pp S193 S202 Allwood 2013 pp 69 72Barth 2002 pp 1 4Kuruk 2020 p 25 Allwood 2013 pp 69 72Hansen 1982 p 193 a b Coser 2009 Knowledge Sociology ofTufari 2003 Knowledge Sociology ofScheler amp Stikkers 2012 p 23 Lee 2017 p 67Dreyer 2017 pp 1 7 Bosancic 2018 pp 186 188Gutting amp Oksala 2022 3 1 Histories of Madness and Medicine 3 4 History of the Prison 3 5 History of Modern SexualityPower 2014 pp 32 33Appelrouth amp Edles 2008 p 643 Bloor 2004 pp 919 920Pinch 2013 p 14Kitchener 1996 p 68 Weisberg 2021 Steup amp Neta 2020 3 3 Internal Vs ExternalDas amp Salow 2018 pp 3 4Dokic amp Egre 2009 pp 1 2 Klein 1998 7 Epistemic Principles Lengnick Hall amp Lengnick Hall 2003 p 85Awad amp Ghaziri 2003 p 28 Suzanne 2021 pp 114 115Choo 2002 pp 503 504Witzel 2004 p 252 Sonneveld amp Loening 1993 p 188Markman 2006 p 1Shapiro 2006 p 1 Castilho amp Lopes 2009 p 287Kandel 1992 pp 5 6Cai et al 2021 p 21 Castilho amp Lopes 2009 pp 287 288Kandel 1992 pp 5 6Akerkar amp Sajja 2010 pp 71 72 Watkins amp Mortimore 1999 pp 1 3 Watkins amp Mortimore 1999 pp 1 3Payne 2003 p 264Gabriel 2022 p 16Turuthi Njagi amp Chemwei 2017 p 365 Bartlett amp Burton 2007 pp 81 85Murphy 2003 pp 5 19 20 Emaliana 2017 pp 59 61 Wang amp Cranton 2013 p 143Bukoye 2019 p 1395 Sources AHD staff 2022a Knowledge The American Heritage Dictionary HarperCollins Archived from the original on 29 November 2022 Retrieved 25 October 2022 AHD staff 2022b Knowledge Base The American Heritage Dictionary HarperCollins Archived from the original on 19 March 2022 Retrieved 25 October 2022 AHD staff 2022c Intelligence The American Heritage Dictionary HarperCollins Archived from the original on 8 January 2024 Retrieved 7 March 2023 AHD Staff 2022d Social Science The American Heritage Dictionary HarperCollins AHD Staff 2022e Confabulate The American Heritage Dictionary HarperCollins Ames Roger T Yajun Chen Hershock Peter D 2021 Confucianism and Deweyan Pragmatism Resources for a New Geopolitics of Interdependence University of Hawaii Press ISBN 978 0 8248 8857 2 Akerkar Rajendra Sajja Priti 2010 Knowledge Based Systems Jones amp Bartlett Learning ISBN 978 0 7637 7647 3 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 2 December 2023 Allen Barry 2005 Knowledge In Horowitz Maryanne Cline ed New Dictionary of the History of Ideas Vol 3 Charles Scribner s Sons pp 1199 1204 ISBN 978 0 684 31377 1 OCLC 55800981 Archived from the original on 22 August 2017 Allwood Carl Martin 2013 Anthropology of Knowledge The Encyclopedia of Cross Cultural Psychology John Wiley amp Sons Inc pp 69 72 doi 10 1002 9781118339893 wbeccp025 ISBN 978 1 118 33989 3 Archived from the original on 26 September 2022 Retrieved 26 September 2022 Alter Torin Nagasawa Yujin 2015 Consciousness in the Physical World Perspectives on Russellian Monism Oxford University Press pp 93 94 ISBN 978 0 19 992736 4 Archived from the original on 1 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Antonio Cartelli 2008 Higher Education s New Frontier for the E University and Virtual Campus In Antonio Cartelli Marco Palma eds Encyclopedia of Information Communication Technology IGI Global ISBN 978 1 59904 846 8 APA staff 2022 Situated Knowledge APA Dictionary of Psychology American Psychological Association Archived from the original on 20 September 2022 Retrieved 18 September 2022 Appelrouth Scott Edles Laura Desfor 2008 Classical and Contemporary Sociological Theory Text and Readings Pine Forge Press ISBN 978 0 7619 2793 8 Aqil Moulay Driss Babekri El Hassane Nadmi Mustapha 2020 Morocco Contributions to Mathematics Education From Morocco In Vogeli Bruce R Tom Mohamed E A El eds Mathematics And Its Teaching In The Muslim World World Scientific ISBN 978 981 314 679 2 Archived from the original on 10 December 2023 Retrieved 15 December 2023 Attie Picker Mario 2020 Does Skepticism Lead to Tranquility Exploring a Pyrrhonian Theme In Lombrozo Tania Knobe Joshua Nichols Shaun eds Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy Vol 3 Oxford University Press pp 97 125 doi 10 1093 oso 9780198852407 003 0005 ISBN 978 0 19 885240 7 Audi Robert 2002 The Sources of Knowledge The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Oxford University Press pp 71 94 ISBN 978 0 19 513005 8 Archived from the original on 12 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Awad Elias M Ghaziri Hassan 2003 Knowledge Management Pearson Education India ISBN 978 93 325 0619 0 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 2 December 2023 Baehr Jason S 2022 A Priori and A Posteriori Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 4 October 2019 Retrieved 17 September 2022 Baggini J Southwell G 2016 Philosophy Key Themes Springer ISBN 978 1 137 00887 9 Baird Tess Maskill Linda 2017 Memory In Maskill Linda Tempest Stephanie eds Neuropsychology for Occupational Therapists Cognition in Occupational Performance John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 71132 3 Barnett Michael 2006 Vocational Knowledge and Vocational Pedagogy In Young Michael Gamble Jeanne eds Knowledge Curriculum and Qualifications for South African Further Education HSRC Press ISBN 978 0 7969 2154 3 Archived from the original on 14 December 2023 Retrieved 14 December 2023 Barth Fredrik 2002 An Anthropology of Knowledge Current Anthropology 43 1 1 18 doi 10 1086 324131 hdl 1956 4191 ISSN 0011 3204 Bartlett Steve Burton Diana 2007 Introduction to Education Studies 2nd ed Sage ISBN 978 1 4129 2193 0 Bartlett Gary 2018 Occurrent States Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 1 1 17 doi 10 1080 00455091 2017 1323531 S2CID 220316213 Archived from the original on 4 May 2021 Retrieved 3 April 2021 Beins Bernard C 2017 Research Method A Tool for Life Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 43623 6 Archived from the original on 8 January 2024 Retrieved 8 January 2024 Bergstrom Lars 1987 On the Value of Scientific Knowledge In Lehrer Keith ed Science and Ethics Rodopi ISBN 978 90 6203 670 7 Bertelson Paul Gelder BeAtrice De 2004 The Psychology of Multimodal Perception Crossmodal Space and Crossmodal Attention Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780198524861 003 0007 ISBN 9780191689260 Bird Alexander 2022 Thomas Kuhn The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 March 2024 Black Charlene Villasenor Alvarez Mari Tere 2019 Renaissance Futurities Science Art Invention University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 96951 3 Black Tim 2002 Relevant Alternatives and the Shifting Standards of Knowledge Southwest Philosophy Review 18 1 23 32 doi 10 5840 swphilreview20021813 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Blackburn Simon 2008 Ding an sich The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 954143 0 Blayney Benjamin ed 1769 Genesis The King James Bible Oxford University Press OCLC 745260506 Archived from the original on 30 January 2023 Retrieved 30 January 2023 Bloor David 2004 Sociology of Scientific Knowledge Handbook of Epistemology Springer Netherlands pp 919 962 doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 1986 9 25 ISBN 978 1 4020 1986 9 Bosancic Sasa 2018 Self positioning of Semi skilled Workers Analysing Subjectification Processes with SKAD The Sociology of Knowledge Approach to Discourse Investigating the Politics of Knowledge and Meaning making Routledge ISBN 978 1 138 04872 0 Bowen James Gelpi Ettore Anweiler Oskar 2023 Education Encyclopedia Britannica Archived from the original on 12 December 2007 Retrieved 30 April 2023 Bowker John 2003 The Concise Oxford Dictionary of World Religions Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 280094 7 Boyer Dominic 2007 1 Of Dialectical Germans and Dialectical Ethnographers Notes from an Engagement with Philosophy In Harris Mark ed Ways of Knowing Anthropological Approaches to Crafting Experience and Knowledge Berghahn Books ISBN 978 1 84545 364 0 Bukoye Roseline Olufunke 2019 Utilization of Instruction Materials as Tools for Effective Academic Performance of Students Implications for Counselling The 2nd Innovative and Creative Education and Teaching International Conference ICETIC p 1395 doi 10 3390 proceedings2211395 Burke Peter 2015 What Is the History of Knowledge John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 5095 0306 3 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Burton David 2002 Knowledge and Liberation Philosophical Ruminations on a Buddhist Conundrum Philosophy East and West 52 3 326 345 doi 10 1353 pew 2002 0011 ISSN 0031 8221 JSTOR 1400322 S2CID 145257341 Archived from the original on 17 February 2023 Retrieved 17 February 2023 Cai Zixing Liu Lijue Chen Baifan Wang Yong 2021 Artificial Intelligence From Beginning To Date World Scientific ISBN 978 981 12 2371 6 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 2 December 2023 Cameron Ross 2018 Infinite Regress Arguments Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 2 January 2020 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Campo Juan Eduardo 2009 Encyclopedia of Islam Infobase Publishing p 515 ISBN 978 1 4381 2696 8 Archived from the original on 4 March 2023 Retrieved 4 March 2023 Carson Thomas Cerrito Joann eds 2003 New Catholic Encyclopedia Vol 14 Thi Zwi 2nd ed Thomson Gale p 164 ISBN 978 0 7876 4018 7 Castilho Luciana V Lopes Heitor S 2009 An Ontology Based System for Knowledge Management and Learning in Neuropediatric Physiotherapy In Szczerbicki Edward Nguyen Ngoc Thanh eds Smart Information and Knowledge Management Advances Challenges and Critical Issues Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 3 642 04583 7 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 2 December 2023 CD staff Knowledge Cambridge Advanced Learner s Dictionary amp Thesaurus Cambridge University Press Archived from the original on 16 November 2023 Retrieved 3 December 2023 Celenza Christopher S 2021 The Italian Renaissance and the Origin of the Humanities An Intellectual History 1400 1800 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 83340 0 Chappell Sophie Grace 2019 Plato on Knowledge in the Theaetetus Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 10 July 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Chaudhary Angraj 2017 Avijja In Sarao K T S Long Jeffery D eds Buddhism and Jainism Springer Nature ISBN 978 94 024 0851 5 Chaudhary Angraj 2017a Wisdom Buddhism In Sarao K T S Long Jeffery D eds Buddhism and Jainism Springer Nature ISBN 978 94 024 0851 5 Choo Chun Wei 2002 Knowledge Management In Schement Jorge Reina ed Encyclopedia of Communication and Information Macmillan Reference USA ISBN 978 0 02 865385 3 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 1 December 2023 Christopher Jabez Prasath Rajendra Vanga Odelu 2018 Expert Intelligence Theory of the Missing Facet In Groza Adrian Prasath Rajendra eds Mining Intelligence and Knowledge Exploration 6th International Conference Springer ISBN 978 3 030 05918 7 Clark Romane 1988 Vicious Infinite Regress Arguments Philosophical Perspectives 2 369 380 doi 10 2307 2214081 JSTOR 2214081 Archived from the original on 26 March 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Clark Kelly James 2022 Religious Epistemology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 21 September 2022 Retrieved 21 September 2022 Clegg Joshua W 2022 Good Science Psychological Inquiry as Everyday Moral Practice Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 009 02181 4 Cohen Emma 2010 Anthropology of Knowledge The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 16 S193 S202 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9655 2010 01617 x hdl 11858 00 001M 0000 0012 9B72 7 JSTOR 40606072 Archived from the original on 26 September 2022 Retrieved 26 September 2022 Cohen Robert S 2013 The Natural Sciences and the Social Sciences Some Critical and Historical Perspectives Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 017 3391 5 Colander David C 2016 Social Science An Introduction to the Study of Society Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 317 22573 7 Conner Clifford D 2009 A People s History of Science Miners Midwives and Low Mechanicks Bold Type Books ISBN 978 0 7867 3786 4 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Coser Lewis A 2009 1968 Knowledge Sociology of International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences Gale ISBN 978 0 02 928751 4 Archived from the original on 7 March 2023 Retrieved 7 March 2023 Cosman Madeleine Pelner Jones Linda Gale 2009 Handbook to Life in the Medieval World 3 Volume Set Infobase Publishing ISBN 978 1 4381 0907 7 Cox Michael T Raja Anita 2011 Metareasoning Thinking About Thinking MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 01480 9 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Danesi Marcel 2013 Encyclopedia of Media and Communication University of Toronto Press ISBN 978 1 4426 9553 5 Archived from the original on 13 November 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Das Nilanjan Salow Bernhard 2018 Transparency and the KK Principle Nous 52 1 3 23 doi 10 1111 nous 12158 Archived from the original on 12 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Daston Lorraine 2017 The History of Science and the History of Knowledge KNOW A Journal on the Formation of Knowledge 1 1 131 154 doi 10 1086 691678 hdl 11858 00 001M 0000 002C EDB1 5 S2CID 164680540 Degenhardt M A B 2019 Education and the Value of Knowledge Routledge pp 1 6 ISBN 978 1 000 62799 2 Archived from the original on 5 April 2023 Retrieved 9 March 2023 Delahunty Andrew Dignen Sheila 2012 Tree of Knowledge Oxford Dictionary of Reference and Allusion Oxford University Press p 365 ISBN 978 0 19 956746 1 Archived from the original on 17 February 2023 Retrieved 17 February 2023 DePoe John M 2022 Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 28 May 2022 Desouza K Awazu Y 2005 Engaged Knowledge Management Engagement with New Realities Springer ISBN 978 0 230 00607 2 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Dika Tarek 2023 Descartes s Method The Formation of the Subject of Science Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 286986 9 Dodd Ashley C Zambetti Benjamin R Deneve Jeremiah 2023 Scientific Method Translational Surgery Elsevier ISBN 978 0 323 90630 2 Dokic Jerome Egre Paul 2009 Margin for Error and the Transparency of Knowledge Synthese 166 1 1 20 doi 10 1007 s11229 007 9245 y S2CID 14221986 Archived from the original on 12 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Doren Charles Van 1992 A History of Knowledge Past Present and Future Random House Publishing Group ISBN 978 0 345 37316 8 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Dougherty Trent 2014 Faith Trust and Testimony Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue 97 123 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199672158 003 0005 ISBN 978 0 19 967215 8 Dreyer Jaco S 2017 Practical Theology and the Call for the Decolonisation of Higher Education in South Africa Reflections and Proposals HTS Teologiese Studies Theological Studies 73 4 1 7 doi 10 4102 hts v73i4 4805 Duran Juan M Formanek Nico 2018 Grounds for Trust Essential Epistemic Opacity and Computational Reliabilism Minds and Machines 28 4 645 666 arXiv 1904 01052 doi 10 1007 s11023 018 9481 6 ISSN 1572 8641 S2CID 53102940 Emaliana Ive 2017 Teacher Centered or Student Centered Learning Approach To Promote Learning Jurnal Sosial Humaniora 10 2 59 doi 10 12962 j24433527 v10i2 2161 S2CID 148796695 Esposito John L ed 2003 Madrasa The Oxford Dictionary of Islam Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 512558 0 Archived from the original on 9 December 2023 Retrieved 15 December 2023 Evans James A Foster Jacob G 2011 Metaknowledge Science 331 6018 721 725 Bibcode 2011Sci 331 721E doi 10 1126 science 1201765 PMID 21311014 S2CID 220090552 Faber Niels R Maruster Laura Jorna Rene J 2017 Assessing and Determining Social Sustainability In Jorna Rene ed Sustainable Innovation The Organisational Human and Knowledge Dimension Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 28034 1 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Fagan Brian M Durrani Nadia 2016 World Prehistory A Brief Introduction Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 317 27910 5 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Flynn Mark 2000 A Critique of Scientism Not Science per se Interchange 31 1 83 86 doi 10 1023 a 1007695016458 S2CID 141495171 Forrest Peter 2021 The Epistemology of Religion The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 10 July 2022 Retrieved 21 September 2022 Foxall Gordon 2017 Context and Cognition in Consumer Psychology How Perception and Emotion Guide Action Routledge p 75 ISBN 978 1 317 67738 3 Archived from the original on 1 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Friesen Norm 2017 The Textbook and the Lecture Education in the Age of New Media JHU Press ISBN 978 1 4214 2434 7 Archived from the original on 13 May 2023 Retrieved 3 May 2023 Fumerton Richard 2008 The Problem of the Criterion The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism Oxford University Press pp 34 52 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780195183214 003 0003 ISBN 978 0 19 518321 4 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Fumerton Richard 2022 Foundationalism Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 9781009028868 ISBN 978 1 009 02886 8 Archived from the original on 12 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Gabriel Cle Anne 2022 Why Teach with Cases Reflections on Philosophy and Practice Emerald Group Publishing ISBN 978 1 80382 399 7 Garcia Arnaldos Maria Dolores 2020 An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge Written by O Brien D History of Philosophy amp Logical Analysis 23 2 508 doi 10 30965 26664275 20210003 ISSN 2666 4275 S2CID 228985437 Archived from the original on 4 March 2023 Retrieved 4 March 2023 Gardiner J M 2001 Episodic Memory and Autonoetic Consciousness A First person Approach Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B Biological Sciences 356 1413 1351 1361 doi 10 1098 rstb 2001 0955 ISSN 0962 8436 PMC 1088519 PMID 11571027 Gascoigne Neil Thornton Tim 2014 Tacit Knowledge Routledge pp 8 37 81 108 ISBN 978 1 317 54726 6 Archived from the original on 6 March 2023 Retrieved 6 March 2023 Gauch Hugh G 2003 Scientific Method in Practice Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 01708 4 George Theodore 2021 Hermeneutics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 6 March 2024 Gertler Brie 2010 1 Introduction Self Knowledge Routledge p 1 ISBN 978 1 136 85811 6 Archived from the original on 8 April 2023 Retrieved 24 October 2022 Gertler Brie 2021 Self Knowledge The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 11 November 2021 Retrieved 22 October 2022 Gertler Brie 2021a Self Knowledge gt Knowledge of the Self Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 3 July 2022 Retrieved 22 October 2022 Ghose Aurobindo 1998 Political Writings and Speeches 1890 1908 The Glory of God in Man Bande Mataram II Sri Aurobindo Ashram Publication Department ISBN 978 81 7058 416 2 Archived from the original on 9 March 2023 Retrieved 9 March 2023 Gilliot Claude 2018 Libraries In Meri Josef ed Routledge Revivals Medieval Islamic Civilization 2006 An Encyclopedia Volume II Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 66813 2 Goldman Alvin I 1976 Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge The Journal of Philosophy 73 20 771 791 doi 10 2307 2025679 JSTOR 2025679 Green Christopher R 2022 Epistemology of Testimony Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 7 March 2022 Retrieved 8 June 2022 Gupta Anil 2021 Definitions 1 1 Real and Nominal Definitions Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 1 May 2022 Retrieved 28 May 2022 Gutting Gary Oksala Johanna 2022 Michel Foucault The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 March 2024 Hamner M Gail 2003 American Pragmatism A Religious Genealogy Oxford University Press p 87 ISBN 978 0 19 515547 1 Archived from the original on 7 March 2023 Retrieved 7 March 2023 Hannon Michael 2021 Knowledge Concept of Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 P031 2 ISBN 978 0 415 07310 3 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Hansen Judith Friedman 1982 From Background to Foreground Toward an Anthropology of Learning Anthropology amp Education Quarterly 13 2 193 doi 10 1525 aeq 1982 13 2 05x1833m ISSN 0161 7761 JSTOR 3216630 Hasan Ali Fumerton Richard 2018 Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 5 August 2019 Retrieved 6 June 2022 Hasan Ali Fumerton Richard 2020 Knowledge by Acquaintance Vs Description 1 The Distinction Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 31 May 2022 Retrieved 28 May 2022 Hasan Ali Fumerton Richard 2022 Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 5 August 2019 Retrieved 11 December 2023 Hatfield Gary 1998 Scientific Method Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 07310 3 Haymes Brian Ozdalga Elisabeth 2016 Concept Of The Knowledge Of God Springer pp 26 28 ISBN 978 1 349 19066 9 Archived from the original on 1 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Hepburn Brian Andersen Hanne 2021 Scientific Method The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 26 February 2020 Retrieved 23 July 2022 Hetherington Stephen Fallibilism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 18 August 2020 Retrieved 13 December 2023 Hetherington Stephen 2022 Gettier Problems Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 19 February 2009 Retrieved 28 May 2022 Hetherington Stephen 2022a Knowledge Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 18 May 2022 Heydorn Wendy Jesudason Susan 2013 Decoding Theory of Knowledge for the IB Diploma Cambridge University Press p 10 ISBN 978 1 107 62842 7 Archived from the original on 1 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Hill Sonya D ed 2009 Knowledge Based View Of The Firm Encyclopedia of Management Gale ISBN 978 1 4144 0691 6 Archived from the original on 6 March 2023 Retrieved 6 March 2023 Hirschberger Johannes 2019 A Short History Western Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 31145 7 Archived from the original on 8 January 2024 Retrieved 8 January 2024 Hoad T F 1993 The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 283098 2 Hookway Christopher 8 November 2012 The Pragmatic Maxim Essays on Peirce and Pragmatism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 958838 1 Howell Kerry E 2013 An Introduction to the Philosophy of Methodology Sage ISBN 978 1 4462 0298 2 Hunter Lynette 2009 Situated Knowledge Mapping Landscapes for Performance as Research Scholarly Acts and Creative Cartographies Palgrave Macmillan UK pp 151 153 doi 10 1057 9780230244481 23 ISBN 978 0 230 24448 1 Archived from the original on 20 September 2022 Retrieved 19 September 2022 Ichikawa Jonathan Jenkins Steup Matthias 2018 The Analysis of Knowledge The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 2 May 2022 Retrieved 24 May 2022 Johnson Mark S Stearns Peter N 2023 Education in World History Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 317 81337 8 Archived from the original on 9 December 2023 Retrieved 3 May 2023 Jones Constance Ryan James D 2006 Encyclopedia of Hinduism Infobase Publishing ISBN 978 0 8160 7564 5 Archived from the original on 20 October 2022 Retrieved 21 September 2022 Jorna Rene 2017 Sustainable Innovation The Organisational Human and Knowledge Dimension Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 28034 1 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Kandel Abraham 1992 Fuzzy Expert Systems CRC Press ISBN 978 0 8493 4297 4 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 2 December 2023 Kemmis Stephen Edwards Groves Christine 2017 Understanding Education History Politics and Practice Springer ISBN 978 981 10 6433 3 Archived from the original on 13 May 2023 Retrieved 3 May 2023 Kern Andrea 2017 Sources of Knowledge On the Concept of a Rational Capacity for Knowledge Harvard University Press pp 8 10 133 ISBN 978 0 674 41611 6 Archived from the original on 28 October 2022 Retrieved 28 October 2022 Kernis Michael H 2013 Self Esteem Issues and Answers A Sourcebook of Current Perspectives Psychology Press p 209 ISBN 978 1 134 95270 0 Archived from the original on 22 October 2022 Retrieved 22 October 2022 Khatoon Naima 2012 General Psychology Pearson Education India ISBN 978 81 317 5999 8 Kitchener Richard F 1996 Genetic Epistemology and Cognitive Psychology of Science In O Donohue William Kitchener Richard F eds The Philosophy of Psychology Sage ISBN 978 0 85702 612 5 Klausen Soren Harnow 2015 Group Knowledge A Real world Approach Synthese 192 3 813 839 doi 10 1007 s11229 014 0589 9 S2CID 207246817 Archived from the original on 1 February 2024 Retrieved 13 November 2022 Klein Peter D 1998 Knowledge Concept of In Craig Edward ed Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 P031 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 OCLC 38096851 Archived from the original on 13 June 2022 Retrieved 13 June 2022 Klenke Karin 2014 Sculpting the Contours of the Qualitative Landscape of Leadership Research In Day David ed The Oxford Handbook of Leadership and Organizations Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 021377 0 Kraft Tim 2012 Scepticism Infallibilism Fallibilism Discipline Filosofiche 22 2 49 70 ISSN 2279 7343 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Kreeft Peter Tacelli Ronald K 2009 Handbook of Christian Apologetics InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 7544 3 Kuhn Thomas S 1992 The Copernican Revolution Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 41747 2 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Kuruk Paul 2020 Traditional Knowledge Genetic Resources Customary Law and Intellectual Property A Global Primer Edward Elgar Publishing p 25 ISBN 978 1 78536 848 6 Archived from the original on 7 March 2023 Retrieved 7 March 2023 Lackey Jennifer 2021 The Epistemology of Groups Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 965660 8 Archived from the original on 25 October 2022 Retrieved 25 October 2022 Lammenranta Markus 2022 Epistemic Circularity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 27 January 2021 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Landau Iddo 2017 Finding Meaning in an Imperfect World Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 065768 0 Thornton Tim Lanzer Peter 2018 Lanzer Peter ed Textbook of Catheter Based Cardiovascular Interventions A Knowledge Based Approach Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 319 55994 0 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Lee Jerry Won 2017 The Politics of Translingualism After Englishes Routledge p 67 ISBN 978 1 315 31051 0 Archived from the original on 8 March 2023 Retrieved 8 March 2023 Legg Catherine Hookway Christopher 2021 Pragmatism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 24 March 2024 Legge Dominic 2017 The Trinitarian Christology of St Thomas Aquinas Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 879419 6 Lehrer Keith 2015 1 The Analysis of Knowledge Theory of Knowledge Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 19609 7 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Lemos Noah M 1994 Intrinsic Value Concept and Warrant Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 46207 5 Lengnick Hall Mark L Lengnick Hall Cynthia A 2003 Human Resource Management in the Knowledge Economy New Challenges New Roles New Capabilities Berrett Koehler Publishers ISBN 978 1 57675 159 6 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 2 December 2023 Leonard Nick 2021 Epistemological Problems of Testimony Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 10 July 2022 Retrieved 8 June 2022 Leondes Cornelius T 2001 Expert Systems The Technology of Knowledge Management and Decision Making for the 21st Century Elsevier ISBN 978 0 08 053145 8 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Lilley Simon Lightfoot Geoffrey Amaral Paulo 2004 Representing Organization Knowledge Management and the Information Age Oxford University Press pp 162 163 ISBN 978 0 19 877541 6 Archived from the original on 10 March 2023 Retrieved 10 March 2023 Low Renae Jin Putai Sweller John 2008 Cognitive Architecture and Instructional Design in a Multimedia Context In Zheng Robert ed Cognitive Effects of Multimedia Learning IGI Global ISBN 978 1 60566 159 9 Lycan William G 2019 2 Moore Against the New Skeptics On Evidence in Philosophy Oxford University Press pp 21 36 ISBN 978 0 19 256526 6 Archived from the original on 6 March 2023 Retrieved 7 March 2023 Magee Bryan Popper Karl R 1971 Conversation with Karl Popper In Magee Bryan ed Modern British Philosophy St Martin s Press pp 74 75 ISBN 978 0 19 283047 0 OCLC 314039 Popper Putting our ideas into words or better writing them down makes an important difference It is what I call knowledge in the objective sense Scientific knowledge belongs to it It is this knowledge which is stored in our libraries rather than our heads Magee And you regard the knowledge stored in our libraries as more important than the knowledge stored in our heads Popper Much more important from every point of view Mahadevan Kanchana 2007 Gadamerian Hermeneutics Between Strangers and Friends In Ghosh Manjulika Ghosh Raghunath eds Language and Interpretation Hermeneutics from East West Perspective Northern Book Centre ISBN 978 81 7211 230 1 Markie Peter J 1998 Rationalism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 24 June 2021 Retrieved 8 January 2024 Markie Peter Folescu M 2023 Rationalism vs Empiricism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 29 February 2024 Markman Arthur B 2006 Knowledge Representation Psychology of Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science Wiley doi 10 1002 0470018860 s00558 ISBN 978 0 470 01619 0 Martin M G F 1998 Perception Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 V023 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Retrieved 26 March 2024 McCain Kevin 2022 Problem of the Criterion Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 28 May 2022 McCain Kevin Stapleford Scott Steup Matthias 2021 Epistemic Dilemmas New Arguments New Angles Routledge p 111 ISBN 978 1 000 46851 9 Archived from the original on 21 October 2022 Retrieved 21 October 2022 McCormick Matt Kant Immanuel Metaphysics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 29 February 2024 McDermid Douglas 2023 Pragmatism 2b Anti Cartesianism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 23 May 2019 Retrieved 7 March 2023 McGeer V 2001 Self knowledge Philosophical Aspects International Encyclopedia of the Social amp Behavioral Sciences Elsevier 13837 13841 doi 10 1016 B0 08 043076 7 01073 1 ISBN 978 0 08 043076 8 Meirmans Stephanie Butlin Roger K Charmantier Anne Engelstadter Jan Groot Astrid T King Kayla C Kokko Hanna Reid Jane M Neiman Maurine 2019 Science policies How should science funding be allocated An evolutionary biologists perspective Journal of Evolutionary Biology 32 8 754 768 doi 10 1111 jeb 13497 hdl 2164 12705 PMC 6771946 PMID 31215105 Mertler Craig A 2021 Introduction to Educational Research SAGE Publications ISBN 978 1 5443 8834 2 Miah Sajahan 2006 Russell s Theory of Perception Continuum pp 19 20 ISBN 978 1 84714 284 9 Archived from the original on 1 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Michaelian Kourken Sutton John 2017 Memory 3 Episodicity Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 5 October 2021 Retrieved 2 October 2021 Misak Cheryl 2002 Truth Politics Morality Pragmatism and Deliberation Routledge p 53 ISBN 978 1 134 82618 6 Archived from the original on 7 March 2023 Retrieved 7 March 2023 Mishra T K 2021 The Power of Ethics Some Lessons from the Bhagavad Gita K K Publications p 52 ISBN 978 81 7844 127 6 Archived from the original on 30 July 2022 Retrieved 21 June 2022 Morin Alain Racy Famira 2021 15 Dynamic Self processes Self knowledge The Handbook of Personality Dynamics and Processes Academic Press pp 373 374 ISBN 978 0 12 813995 0 Archived from the original on 22 October 2022 Retrieved 22 October 2022 Morrison Robert 2005 The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning Cambridge University Press p 371 ISBN 978 0 521 82417 0 Archived from the original on 30 March 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Moser Paul K 1998 A priori Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 9 May 2021 Retrieved 8 January 2024 Moser Paul K 2005 13 Scientific Knowledge The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 020818 9 Archived from the original on 19 May 2023 Retrieved 8 March 2023 Moser Paul K 2016 A Posteriori Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge Archived from the original on 20 September 2022 Retrieved 18 September 2022 Mulsow Martin 2018 6 History of Knowledge In Tamm Marek Burke Peter eds Debating New Approaches to History Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 4742 8193 5 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 29 November 2023 Murphy Patricia 2003 1 Defining Pedagogy In Gipps Caroline V ed Equity in the Classroom Towards Effective Pedagogy for Girls and Boys Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 71682 0 Archived from the original on 25 January 2024 Retrieved 22 August 2022 Murphy Peter 2022 Coherentism in Epistemology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 12 June 2022 Retrieved 8 June 2022 MW Staff 2023 Definition of Knowledge Merriam Webster Archived from the original on 21 December 2023 Retrieved 3 December 2023 Myers Michael D 2009 Qualitative Research in Business amp Management Sage Publications ISBN 978 1 4129 2165 7 Niiniluoto Ilkka 2019 Scientific Progress The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 6 March 2023 Retrieved 8 March 2023 O Brien Dan 2006 An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge Polity ISBN 978 0 7456 3316 9 O Brien Daniel 2022 The Epistemology of Perception Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 8 May 2009 Retrieved 25 October 2022 O Grady Paul Relativism Oxford Bibliographies Oxford University Press Retrieved 6 March 2024 Olsson Erik J 2011 The Value of Knowledge Philosophy Compass 6 12 874 883 doi 10 1111 j 1747 9991 2011 00425 x S2CID 143034920 Paden William E 2005 Comparative Religion Encyclopedia of Religion 2nd ed Macmillan Reference USA ISBN 978 0028657332 Paden William E 2009 Comparative Religion The Routledge Companion to the Study of Religion Routledge pp 239 256 doi 10 4324 9780203868768 19 ISBN 978 0 203 86876 8 Archived from the original on 21 September 2022 Retrieved 21 September 2022 Parikh Rohit Renero Adriana 2017 Justified True Belief Plato Gettier and Turing Philosophical Explorations of the Legacy of Alan Turing Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science Vol 324 Springer International Publishing pp 93 102 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 53280 6 4 ISBN 978 3 319 53280 6 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Pavese Carlotta 2022 Knowledge How The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 25 November 2023 Retrieved 12 December 2023 Payne William Harold 2003 Contributions to the Science of Education and The Education of Teachers In Salvatori Mariolina Rizzi ed Pedagogy Disturbing History 1820 1930 University of Pittsburgh Press ISBN 978 0 8229 7246 4 Peels Rik 2023 Ignorance A Philosophical Study Oxford University Press p 28 ISBN 978 0 19 765451 4 Archived from the original on 1 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Penelhum Terence 1971 1 Faith Scepticism and Philosophy Problems of Religious Knowledge Macmillan ISBN 978 0 333 10633 4 Archived from the original on 1 February 2024 Retrieved 21 September 2022 Perin Casey 2020 23 Tranquility as the Goal in Pyrrhonian Skepticism In Arenson Kelly ed The Routledge Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy Routledge pp 285 294 doi 10 4324 9781351168120 23 ISBN 978 1 351 16812 0 S2CID 225751581 Archived from the original on 12 December 2023 Retrieved 12 December 2023 Pinch T 2013 Confronting Nature T he Sociology of Solar Neutrino Detection Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 015 7729 8 Plantinga Alvin 2018 Scientism Who Needs It In Ridder Jeroen de Peels Rik Woudenberg Rene van eds Scientism Prospects and Problems Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 046276 5 Plato 2002 Five Dialogues Hackett Pub Co pp 89 90 97b 98a ISBN 978 0 87220 633 5 Poston Ted Foundationalism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 3 November 2011 Retrieved 11 December 2023 Powell Timothy 2020 The Value of Knowledge The Economics of Enterprise Knowledge and Intelligence Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 059304 4 Power Edward J 1970 Main Currents in the History of Education McGraw Hill ISBN 978 0 07 050581 0 Archived from the original on 3 May 2023 Retrieved 3 May 2023 Power Richenda 2014 A Question of Knowledge Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 88375 3 Pritchard Duncan 2007 Recent Work on Epistemic Value American Philosophical Quarterly 44 2 85 110 JSTOR 20464361 Pritchard Duncan 2013 What Is This Thing Called Knowledge Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 57367 7 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Pritchard Duncan Turri John Carter J Adam 2022 The Value of Knowledge The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 10 July 2022 Retrieved 19 September 2022 Rambachan Anantanand 2006 The Advaita Worldview God World and Humanity SUNY Press ISBN 978 0 7914 6851 7 Reginster Bernard 2017 Self knowledge as Freedom in Schopenhauer and Freud In Renz Ursula ed Self knowledge A History Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022642 8 Reif Frederick 2008 Applying Cognitive Science to Education Thinking and Learning in Scientific and Other Complex Domains MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 18263 8 Archived from the original on 15 April 2023 Retrieved 16 April 2023 Repko Allen F 2008 Interdisciplinary Research Process and Theory Sage ISBN 978 1 4129 5915 5 Rescher Nicholas 1998 Fallibilism Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 P019 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Retrieved 23 March 2024 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a website ignored help Rescher Nicholas 2005 Epistemic Logic A Survey of the Logic of Knowledge University of Pittsburgh Press ISBN 978 0 8229 7092 7 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Rescher Nicholas 2009 Unknowability An Inquiry into the Limits of Knowledge Lexington books ISBN 978 0 7391 3615 7 Rescher Nicholas 2005a Knowledge the Limits of In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Rescher Nicholas 2009a Ignorance On the Wider Implications of Deficient Knowledge University of Pittsburgh Press ISBN 978 0 8229 6014 0 Rodriguez Angel Garcia 2018 Fake Barns and Our Epistemological Theorizing Critica Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofia 50 148 29 54 doi 10 22201 iifs 18704905e 2018 02 ISSN 0011 1503 JSTOR 26767766 S2CID 171635198 Barnett Ronald 1990 The Idea Of Higher Education Open University Press p 40 ISBN 978 0 335 09420 2 Archived from the original on 5 March 2023 Retrieved 5 March 2023 Rothberg Helen N Erickson G Scott 2005 From Knowledge to Intelligence Creating Competitive Advantage in the Next Economy Routledge ISBN 978 0 7506 7762 2 Archived from the original on 8 January 2024 Retrieved 8 January 2024 Russell Bruce 2020 A Priori Justification and Knowledge The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 12 August 2021 Retrieved 18 September 2022 Rutten Emanuel 2012 A Critical Assessment of Contemporary Cosmological Arguments Towards a Renewed Case for Theism Vrije Universiteit ISBN 978 90 819608 0 9 Sayre McCord Geoff 2023 Metaethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 12 July 2023 Retrieved 19 December 2023 Scheler Max Stikkers Kenneth W 2012 Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge Routledge Revivals Routledge p 23 ISBN 978 0 415 62334 6 Archived from the original on 7 March 2023 Retrieved 7 March 2023 Schneider W Joel McGrew Kevin S 2022 The Cattell Horn Carroll Theory of Cognitive Abilities In Flanagan Dawn P McDonough Erin M eds Contemporary Intellectual Assessment Theories Tests and Issues Guilford Publications ISBN 978 1 4625 5203 0 Archived from the original on 2 December 2023 Retrieved 30 November 2023 Schoonenboom Judith Johnson R Burke 2017 How to Construct a Mixed Methods Research Design KZFSS Kolner Zeitschrift fur Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie 69 S2 107 131 doi 10 1007 s11577 017 0454 1 PMC 5602001 PMID 28989188 Schwitzgebel Eric 2021 Belief 2 1 Occurrent Versus Dispositional Belief Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 15 November 2019 Retrieved 8 June 2022 Shapiro Stuart C 2006 Knowledge Representation Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science Wiley doi 10 1002 0470018860 s00058 ISBN 978 0 470 01619 0 Shorten Allison Smith Joanna 2017 Mixed methods research expanding the evidence base Evidence Based Nursing 20 3 74 75 doi 10 1136 eb 2017 102699 PMID 28615184 Sinnott Armstrong Walter 2019 Moral Skepticism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 3 March 2024 Sonneveld Helmi B Loening Kurt L 1993 Terminology Applications in interdisciplinary communication John Benjamins Publishing ISBN 978 90 272 7400 7 Spaulding Shannon 2016 Imagination Through Knowledge In Kind Amy Kung Peter eds Knowledge Through Imagination Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 102619 5 Archived from the original on 5 December 2023 Retrieved 5 December 2023 Stanley Jason Willlamson Timothy 2001 Knowing How Journal of Philosophy 98 8 411 444 doi 10 2307 2678403 JSTOR 2678403 Archived from the original on 2 June 2022 Retrieved 12 June 2022 Stehr Nico Adolf Marian T 2016 The Price of Knowledge Social Epistemology 30 5 6 483 512 doi 10 1080 02691728 2016 1172366 Steinberg Sheila 1995 Introduction to Communication Course Book 1 The Basics Juta and Company Ltd ISBN 978 0 7021 3649 8 Archived from the original on 17 May 2023 Retrieved 28 November 2022 Steup Matthias Neta Ram 2020 Epistemology Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 21 July 2020 Retrieved 22 May 2022 Stevenson Leslie 2003 Opinion Belief or Faith and Knowledge Kantian Review 7 72 101 doi 10 1017 S1369415400001746 ISSN 2044 2394 S2CID 143965507 Archived from the original on 21 September 2022 Retrieved 21 September 2022 Stoltz Jonathan 2021 Illuminating the Mind An Introduction to Buddhist Epistemology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 090756 3 Stroll Avrum 2023 Epistemology Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 10 July 2019 Retrieved 20 May 2022 span, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.