fbpx
Wikipedia

Pragmatism

Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition that views language and thought as tools for prediction, problem solving, and action, rather than describing, representing, or mirroring reality. Pragmatists contend that most philosophical topics—such as the nature of knowledge, language, concepts, meaning, belief, and science—are all best viewed in terms of their practical uses and successes.

Pragmatism began in the United States in the 1870s. Its origins are often attributed to philosophers Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. In 1878, Peirce described it in his pragmatic maxim: "Consider the practical effects of the objects of your conception. Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object."[1]

Origins edit

 
Charles Peirce: the American polymath who first identified pragmatism

Pragmatism as a philosophical movement began in the United States around 1870.[2] Charles Sanders Peirce (and his pragmatic maxim) is given credit for its development,[3] along with later 20th-century contributors, William James and John Dewey.[4] Its direction was determined by The Metaphysical Club members Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and Chauncey Wright as well as John Dewey and George Herbert Mead.

The word "pragmatic" has existed in English since the 1500s, a word borrowed from French and ultimately derived from Greek via Latin. The Greek word pragma, meaning business, deed or act, is a noun derived from the verb prassein, to do.[5] The first use in print of the name pragmatism was in 1898 by James, who credited Peirce with coining the term during the early 1870s.[6] James regarded Peirce's "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" series—including "The Fixation of Belief" (1877), and especially "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878)—as the foundation of pragmatism.[7][8] Peirce in turn wrote in 1906[9] that Nicholas St. John Green had been instrumental by emphasizing the importance of applying Alexander Bain's definition of belief, which was "that upon which a man is prepared to act". Peirce wrote that "from this definition, pragmatism is scarce more than a corollary; so that I am disposed to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism". John Shook has said, "Chauncey Wright also deserves considerable credit, for as both Peirce and James recall, it was Wright who demanded a phenomenalist and fallibilist empiricism as an alternative to rationalistic speculation."[10]

Peirce developed the idea that inquiry depends on real doubt, not mere verbal or hyperbolic doubt,[11] and said that, in order to understand a conception in a fruitful way, "Consider the practical effects of the objects of your conception. Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object",[1] which he later called the pragmatic maxim. It equates any conception of an object to the general extent of the conceivable implications for informed practice of that object's effects. This is the heart of his pragmatism as a method of experimentational mental reflection arriving at conceptions in terms of conceivable confirmatory and disconfirmatory circumstances—a method hospitable to the generation of explanatory hypotheses, and conducive to the employment and improvement of verification. Typical of Peirce is his concern with inference to explanatory hypotheses as outside the usual foundational alternative between deductivist rationalism and inductivist empiricism, although he was a mathematical logician and a founder of statistics.[citation needed]

Peirce lectured and further wrote on pragmatism to make clear his own interpretation. While framing a conception's meaning in terms of conceivable tests, Peirce emphasized that, since a conception is general, its meaning, its intellectual purport, equates to its acceptance's implications for general practice, rather than to any definite set of real effects (or test results); a conception's clarified meaning points toward its conceivable verifications, but the outcomes are not meanings, but individual upshots. Peirce in 1905 coined the new name pragmaticism "for the precise purpose of expressing the original definition",[12] saying that "all went happily" with James's and F. C. S. Schiller's variant uses of the old name "pragmatism" and that he nonetheless coined the new name because of the old name's growing use in "literary journals, where it gets abused". Yet in a 1906 manuscript, he cited as causes his differences with James and Schiller.[13] and, in a 1908 publication,[14] his differences with James as well as literary author Giovanni Papini. Peirce regarded his own views that truth is immutable and infinity is real, as being opposed by the other pragmatists, but he remained allied with them about the falsity of necessitarianism and about the reality of generals and habits understood in terms of potential concrete effects even if unactualized.[14]

Pragmatism enjoyed renewed attention after Willard Van Orman Quine and Wilfrid Sellars used a revised pragmatism to criticize logical positivism in the 1960s. Inspired by the work of Quine and Sellars, a brand of pragmatism known sometimes as neopragmatism gained influence through Richard Rorty, the most influential of the late 20th century pragmatists along with Hilary Putnam and Robert Brandom. Contemporary pragmatism may be broadly divided into a strict analytic tradition and a "neo-classical" pragmatism (such as Susan Haack) that adheres to the work of Peirce, James, and Dewey.[citation needed]

Core tenets edit

A few of the various but often interrelated positions characteristic of philosophers working from a pragmatist approach include:

  • Epistemology (justification): a coherentist theory of justification that rejects the claim that all knowledge and justified belief rest ultimately on a foundation of noninferential knowledge or justified belief. Coherentists hold that justification is solely a function of some relationship between beliefs, none of which are privileged beliefs in the way maintained by foundationalist theories of justification.
  • Epistemology (truth): a deflationary or pragmatic theory of truth; the former is the epistemological claim that assertions that predicate truth of a statement do not attribute a property called truth to such a statement while the latter is the epistemological claim that assertions that predicate truth of a statement attribute the property of useful-to-believe to such a statement.
  • Metaphysics: a pluralist view that there is more than one sound way to conceptualize the world and its content.
  • Philosophy of science: an instrumentalist and scientific anti-realist view that a scientific concept or theory should be evaluated by how effectively it explains and predicts phenomena, as opposed to how accurately it describes objective reality.
  • Philosophy of language: an anti-representationalist view that rejects analyzing the semantic meaning of propositions, mental states, and statements in terms of a correspondence or representational relationship and instead analyzes semantic meaning in terms of notions like dispositions to action, inferential relationships, and/or functional roles (e.g. behaviorism and inferentialism). Not to be confused with pragmatics, a sub-field of linguistics with no relation to philosophical pragmatism.
  • Additionally, forms of empiricism, fallibilism, verificationism, and a Quinean naturalist metaphilosophy are all commonly elements of pragmatist philosophies. Many pragmatists are epistemological relativists and see this to be an important facet of their pragmatism (e.g. Joseph Margolis), but this is controversial and other pragmatists argue such relativism to be seriously misguided (e.g. Hilary Putnam, Susan Haack).

Anti-reification of concepts and theories edit

Dewey in The Quest for Certainty criticized what he called "the philosophical fallacy": Philosophers often take categories (such as the mental and the physical) for granted because they don't realize that these are nominal concepts that were invented to help solve specific problems.[15] This causes metaphysical and conceptual confusion. Various examples are the "ultimate Being" of Hegelian philosophers, the belief in a "realm of value", the idea that logic, because it is an abstraction from concrete thought, has nothing to do with the action of concrete thinking.

David L. Hildebrand summarized the problem: "Perceptual inattention to the specific functions comprising inquiry led realists and idealists alike to formulate accounts of knowledge that project the products of extensive abstraction back onto experience."[15]: 40 

Naturalism and anti-Cartesianism edit

From the outset, pragmatists wanted to reform philosophy and bring it more in line with the scientific method as they understood it. They argued that idealist and realist philosophy had a tendency to present human knowledge as something beyond what science could grasp. They held that these philosophies then resorted either to a phenomenology inspired by Kant or to correspondence theories of knowledge and truth.[citation needed] Pragmatists criticized the former for its a priorism, and the latter because it takes correspondence as an unanalyzable fact. Pragmatism instead tries to explain the relation between knower and known.

In 1868,[16] C.S. Peirce argued that there is no power of intuition in the sense of a cognition unconditioned by inference, and no power of introspection, intuitive or otherwise, and that awareness of an internal world is by hypothetical inference from external facts. Introspection and intuition were staple philosophical tools at least since Descartes. He argued that there is no absolutely first cognition in a cognitive process; such a process has its beginning but can always be analyzed into finer cognitive stages. That which we call introspection does not give privileged access to knowledge about the mind—the self is a concept that is derived from our interaction with the external world and not the other way around.[17] At the same time he held persistently that pragmatism and epistemology in general could not be derived from principles of psychology understood as a special science:[18] what we do think is too different from what we should think; in his "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" series, Peirce formulated both pragmatism and principles of statistics as aspects of scientific method in general.[19] This is an important point of disagreement with most other pragmatists, who advocate a more thorough naturalism and psychologism.

Richard Rorty expanded on these and other arguments in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature in which he criticized attempts by many philosophers of science to carve out a space for epistemology that is entirely unrelated to—and sometimes thought of as superior to—the empirical sciences. W.V. Quine, who was instrumental in bringing naturalized epistemology back into favor with his essay "Epistemology Naturalized",[20] also criticized "traditional" epistemology and its "Cartesian dream" of absolute certainty. The dream, he argued, was impossible in practice as well as misguided in theory, because it separates epistemology from scientific inquiry.

 
Hilary Putnam said that the combination of antiskepticism and fallibilism is a central feature of pragmatism.[21][22][23]

Reconciliation of anti-skepticism and fallibilism edit

Hilary Putnam has suggested that the reconciliation of anti-skepticism[24] and fallibilism is the central goal of American pragmatism.[21][22][23] Although all human knowledge is partial, with no ability to take a "God's-eye-view", this does not necessitate a globalized skeptical attitude, a radical philosophical skepticism (as distinguished from that which is called scientific skepticism). Peirce insisted that (1) in reasoning, there is the presupposition, and at least the hope,[25] that truth and the real are discoverable and would be discovered, sooner or later but still inevitably, by investigation taken far enough,[1] and (2) contrary to Descartes's famous and influential methodology in the Meditations on First Philosophy, doubt cannot be feigned or created by verbal fiat to motivate fruitful inquiry, and much less can philosophy begin in universal doubt.[26] Doubt, like belief, requires justification. Genuine doubt irritates and inhibits, in the sense that belief is that upon which one is prepared to act.[1] It arises from confrontation with some specific recalcitrant matter of fact (which Dewey called a "situation"), which unsettles our belief in some specific proposition. Inquiry is then the rationally self-controlled process of attempting to return to a settled state of belief about the matter. Note that anti-skepticism is a reaction to modern academic skepticism in the wake of Descartes. The pragmatist insistence that all knowledge is tentative is quite congenial to the older skeptical tradition.

Theory of truth and epistemology edit

Pragmatism was not the first to apply evolution to theories of knowledge: Schopenhauer advocated a biological idealism as what's useful to an organism to believe might differ wildly from what is true. Here knowledge and action are portrayed as two separate spheres with an absolute or transcendental truth above and beyond any sort of inquiry organisms used to cope with life. Pragmatism challenges this idealism by providing an "ecological" account of knowledge: inquiry is how organisms can get a grip on their environment. Real and true are functional labels in inquiry and cannot be understood outside of this context. It is not realist in a traditionally robust sense of realism (what Hilary Putnam later called metaphysical realism), but it is realist in how it acknowledges an external world which must be dealt with.[citation needed]

Many of James' best-turned phrases—"truth's cash value"[27] and "the true is only the expedient in our way of thinking" [28]—were taken out of context and caricatured in contemporary literature as representing the view where any idea with practical utility is true. William James wrote:

It is high time to urge the use of a little imagination in philosophy. The unwillingness of some of our critics to read any but the silliest of possible meanings into our statements is as discreditable to their imaginations as anything I know in recent philosophic history. Schiller says the truth is that which "works." Thereupon he is treated as one who limits verification to the lowest material utilities. Dewey says truth is what gives "satisfaction"! He is treated as one who believes in calling everything true which, if it were true, would be pleasant.[29]

In reality, James asserts, the theory is a great deal more subtle.[nb 1]

The role of belief in representing reality is widely debated in pragmatism. Is a belief valid when it represents reality? "Copying is one (and only one) genuine mode of knowing".[30] Are beliefs dispositions which qualify as true or false depending on how helpful they prove in inquiry and in action? Is it only in the struggle of intelligent organisms with the surrounding environment that beliefs acquire meaning? Does a belief only become true when it succeeds in this struggle? In James's pragmatism nothing practical or useful is held to be necessarily true nor is anything which helps to survive merely in the short term. For example, to believe my cheating spouse is faithful may help me feel better now, but it is certainly not useful from a more long-term perspective because it doesn't accord with the facts (and is therefore not true).

In other fields edit

While pragmatism started simply as a criterion of meaning, it quickly expanded to become a full-fledged epistemology with wide-ranging implications for the entire philosophical field. Pragmatists who work in these fields share a common inspiration, but their work is diverse and there are no received views.

Philosophy of science edit

In the philosophy of science, instrumentalism is the view that concepts and theories are merely useful instruments and progress in science cannot be couched in terms of concepts and theories somehow mirroring reality. Instrumentalist philosophers often define scientific progress as nothing more than an improvement in explaining and predicting phenomena. Instrumentalism does not state that truth does not matter, but rather provides a specific answer to the question of what truth and falsity mean and how they function in science.

One of C. I. Lewis' main arguments in Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge (1929) was that science does not merely provide a copy of reality but must work with conceptual systems and that those are chosen for pragmatic reasons, that is, because they aid inquiry. Lewis' own development of multiple modal logics is a case in point. Lewis is sometimes called a proponent of conceptual pragmatism because of this.[31]

Another development is the cooperation of logical positivism and pragmatism in the works of Charles W. Morris and Rudolf Carnap. The influence of pragmatism on these writers is mostly limited to the incorporation of the pragmatic maxim into their epistemology. Pragmatists with a broader conception of the movement do not often refer to them.

W. V. Quine's paper "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", published in 1951, is one of the most celebrated papers of 20th-century philosophy in the analytic tradition. The paper is an attack on two central tenets of the logical positivists' philosophy. One is the distinction between analytic statements (tautologies and contradictions) whose truth (or falsehood) is a function of the meanings of the words in the statement ('all bachelors are unmarried'), and synthetic statements, whose truth (or falsehood) is a function of (contingent) states of affairs. The other is reductionism, the theory that each meaningful statement gets its meaning from some logical construction of terms which refers exclusively to immediate experience. Quine's argument brings to mind Peirce's insistence that axioms are not a priori truths but synthetic statements.

Logic edit

Later in his life Schiller became famous for his attacks on logic in his textbook, Formal Logic. By then, Schiller's pragmatism had become the nearest of any of the classical pragmatists to an ordinary language philosophy. Schiller sought to undermine the very possibility of formal logic, by showing that words only had meaning when used in context. The least famous of Schiller's main works was the constructive sequel to his destructive book Formal Logic. In this sequel, Logic for Use, Schiller attempted to construct a new logic to replace the formal logic that he had criticized in Formal Logic. What he offers is something philosophers would recognize today as a logic covering the context of discovery and the hypothetico-deductive method.

Whereas Schiller dismissed the possibility of formal logic, most pragmatists are critical rather of its pretension to ultimate validity and see logic as one logical tool among others—or perhaps, considering the multitude of formal logics, one set of tools among others. This is the view of C. I. Lewis. C. S. Peirce developed multiple methods for doing formal logic.

Stephen Toulmin's The Uses of Argument inspired scholars in informal logic and rhetoric studies (although it is an epistemological work).

Metaphysics edit

James and Dewey were empirical thinkers in the most straightforward fashion: experience is the ultimate test and experience is what needs to be explained. They were dissatisfied with ordinary empiricism because, in the tradition dating from Hume, empiricists had a tendency to think of experience as nothing more than individual sensations. To the pragmatists, this went against the spirit of empiricism: we should try to explain all that is given in experience including connections and meaning, instead of explaining them away and positing sense data as the ultimate reality. Radical empiricism, or Immediate Empiricism in Dewey's words, wants to give a place to meaning and value instead of explaining them away as subjective additions to a world of whizzing atoms.

 
The "Chicago Club" including Mead, Dewey, Angell, and Moore. Pragmatism is sometimes called American pragmatism because so many of its proponents were and are Americans.

William James gives an interesting example of this philosophical shortcoming:

[A young graduate] began by saying that he had always taken for granted that when you entered a philosophic classroom you had to open relations with a universe entirely distinct from the one you left behind you in the street. The two were supposed, he said, to have so little to do with each other, that you could not possibly occupy your mind with them at the same time. The world of concrete personal experiences to which the street belongs is multitudinous beyond imagination, tangled, muddy, painful and perplexed. The world to which your philosophy-professor introduces you is simple, clean and noble. The contradictions of real life are absent from it. ... In point of fact it is far less an account of this actual world than a clear addition built upon it ... It is no explanation of our concrete universe[32]

F. C. S. Schiller's first book Riddles of the Sphinx was published before he became aware of the growing pragmatist movement taking place in America. In it, Schiller argues for a middle ground between materialism and absolute metaphysics. These opposites are comparable to what William James called tough-minded empiricism and tender-minded rationalism. Schiller contends on the one hand that mechanistic naturalism cannot make sense of the "higher" aspects of our world. These include free will, consciousness, purpose, universals and some would add God. On the other hand, abstract metaphysics cannot make sense of the "lower" aspects of our world (e.g. the imperfect, change, physicality). While Schiller is vague about the exact sort of middle ground he is trying to establish, he suggests that metaphysics is a tool that can aid inquiry, but that it is valuable only insofar as it does help in explanation.

In the second half of the 20th century, Stephen Toulmin argued that the need to distinguish between reality and appearance only arises within an explanatory scheme and therefore that there is no point in asking what "ultimate reality" consists of. More recently, a similar idea has been suggested by the postanalytic philosopher Daniel Dennett, who argues that anyone who wants to understand the world has to acknowledge both the "syntactical" aspects of reality (i.e., whizzing atoms) and its emergent or "semantic" properties (i.e., meaning and value).[citation needed]

Radical empiricism gives answers to questions about the limits of science, the nature of meaning and value and the workability of reductionism. These questions feature prominently in current debates about the relationship between religion and science, where it is often assumed—most pragmatists would disagree—that science degrades everything that is meaningful into "merely" physical phenomena.

Philosophy of mind edit

Both John Dewey in Experience and Nature (1929) and, half a century later, Richard Rorty in his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979) argued that much of the debate about the relation of the mind to the body results from conceptual confusions. They argue instead that there is no need to posit the mind or mindstuff as an ontological category.

Pragmatists disagree over whether philosophers ought to adopt a quietist or a naturalist stance toward the mind-body problem. The former, including Rorty, want to do away with the problem because they believe it's a pseudo-problem, whereas the latter believe that it is a meaningful empirical question.[citation needed]

Ethics edit

Pragmatism sees no fundamental difference between practical and theoretical reason, nor any ontological difference between facts and values. Pragmatist ethics is broadly humanist because it sees no ultimate test of morality beyond what matters for us as humans. Good values are those for which we have good reasons, viz. the good reasons approach. The pragmatist formulation pre-dates those of other philosophers who have stressed important similarities between values and facts such as Jerome Schneewind and John Searle.

 
William James tried to show the meaningfulness of (some kinds of) spirituality but, like other pragmatists, did not see religion as the basis of meaning or morality.

William James' contribution to ethics, as laid out in his essay The Will to Believe has often been misunderstood as a plea for relativism or irrationality. On its own terms it argues that ethics always involves a certain degree of trust or faith and that we cannot always wait for adequate proof when making moral decisions.

Moral questions immediately present themselves as questions whose solution cannot wait for sensible proof. A moral question is a question not of what sensibly exists, but of what is good, or would be good if it did exist. ... A social organism of any sort whatever, large or small, is what it is because each member proceeds to his own duty with a trust that the other members will simultaneously do theirs. Wherever a desired result is achieved by the co-operation of many independent persons, its existence as a fact is a pure consequence of the precursive faith in one another of those immediately concerned. A government, an army, a commercial system, a ship, a college, an athletic team, all exist on this condition, without which not only is nothing achieved, but nothing is even attempted.[33]

Of the classical pragmatists, John Dewey wrote most extensively about morality and democracy.[34] In his classic article "Three Independent Factors in Morals",[35] he tried to integrate three basic philosophical perspectives on morality: the right, the virtuous and the good. He held that while all three provide meaningful ways to think about moral questions, the possibility of conflict among the three elements cannot always be easily solved.[36]

Dewey also criticized the dichotomy between means and ends which he saw as responsible for the degradation of our everyday working lives and education, both conceived as merely a means to an end. He stressed the need for meaningful labor and a conception of education that viewed it not as a preparation for life but as life itself.[37]

Dewey was opposed to other ethical philosophies of his time, notably the emotivism of Alfred Ayer. Dewey envisioned the possibility of ethics as an experimental discipline, and thought values could best be characterized not as feelings or imperatives, but as hypotheses about what actions will lead to satisfactory results or what he termed consummatory experience. An additional implication of this view is that ethics is a fallible undertaking because human beings are frequently unable to know what would satisfy them.

During the late 1900s and first decade of 2000, pragmatism was embraced by many in the field of bioethics led by the philosophers John Lachs and his student Glenn McGee, whose 1997 book The Perfect Baby: A Pragmatic Approach to Genetic Engineering (see designer baby) garnered praise from within classical American philosophy and criticism from bioethics for its development of a theory of pragmatic bioethics and its rejection of the principalism theory then in vogue in medical ethics. An anthology published by the MIT Press titled Pragmatic Bioethics included the responses of philosophers to that debate, including Micah Hester, Griffin Trotter and others many of whom developed their own theories based on the work of Dewey, Peirce, Royce and others. Lachs developed several applications of pragmatism to bioethics independent of but extending from the work of Dewey and James.

A recent pragmatist contribution to meta-ethics is Todd Lekan's Making Morality.[38] Lekan argues that morality is a fallible but rational practice and that it has traditionally been misconceived as based on theory or principles. Instead, he argues, theory and rules arise as tools to make practice more intelligent.

Aesthetics edit

John Dewey's Art as Experience, based on the William James lectures he delivered at Harvard University, was an attempt to show the integrity of art, culture and everyday experience (IEP). Art, for Dewey, is or should be a part of everyone's creative lives and not just the privilege of a select group of artists. He also emphasizes that the audience is more than a passive recipient. Dewey's treatment of art was a move away from the transcendental approach to aesthetics in the wake of Immanuel Kant who emphasized the unique character of art and the disinterested nature of aesthetic appreciation. A notable contemporary pragmatist aesthetician is Joseph Margolis. He defines a work of art as "a physically embodied, culturally emergent entity", a human "utterance" that isn't an ontological quirk but in line with other human activity and culture in general. He emphasizes that works of art are complex and difficult to fathom, and that no determinate interpretation can be given.

Philosophy of religion edit

Both Dewey and James investigated the role that religion can still play in contemporary society, the former in A Common Faith and the latter in The Varieties of Religious Experience.

From a general point of view, for William James, something is true only insofar as it works. Thus, the statement, for example, that prayer is heard may work on a psychological level but (a) may not help to bring about the things you pray for (b) may be better explained by referring to its soothing effect than by claiming prayers are heard. As such, pragmatism is not antithetical to religion but it is not an apologetic for faith either. James' metaphysical position however, leaves open the possibility that the ontological claims of religions may be true. As he observed in the end of the Varieties, his position does not amount to a denial of the existence of transcendent realities. Quite the contrary, he argued for the legitimate epistemic right to believe in such realities, since such beliefs do make a difference in an individual's life and refer to claims that cannot be verified or falsified either on intellectual or common sensorial grounds.

Joseph Margolis in Historied Thought, Constructed World (California, 1995) makes a distinction between "existence" and "reality". He suggests using the term "exists" only for those things which adequately exhibit Peirce's Secondness: things which offer brute physical resistance to our movements. In this way, such things which affect us, like numbers, may be said to be "real", although they do not "exist". Margolis suggests that God, in such a linguistic usage, might very well be "real", causing believers to act in such and such a way, but might not "exist".

Education edit

Pragmatic pedagogy is an educational philosophy that emphasizes teaching students knowledge that is practical for life and encourages them to grow into better people. American philosopher John Dewey is considered one of the main thinkers of the pragmatist educational approach.

Neopragmatism edit

Neopragmatism is a broad contemporary category used for various thinkers that incorporate important insights of, and yet significantly diverge from, the classical pragmatists. This divergence may occur either in their philosophical methodology (many of them are loyal to the analytic tradition) or in conceptual formation: for example, conceptual pragmatist C. I. Lewis was very critical of Dewey; neopragmatist Richard Rorty disliked Peirce.

Important analytic pragmatists include early Richard Rorty (who was the first to develop neopragmatist philosophy in his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979),[39] Hilary Putnam, W. V. O. Quine, and Donald Davidson. Brazilian social thinker Roberto Unger advocates for a radical pragmatism, one that "de-naturalizes" society and culture, and thus insists that we can "transform the character of our relation to social and cultural worlds we inhabit rather than just to change, little by little, the content of the arrangements and beliefs that comprise them".[40] Late Rorty and Jürgen Habermas are closer to Continental thought.

Neopragmatist thinkers who are more loyal to classical pragmatism include Sidney Hook and Susan Haack (known for the theory of foundherentism). Many pragmatist ideas (especially those of Peirce) find a natural expression in the decision-theoretic reconstruction of epistemology pursued in the work of Isaac Levi. Nicholas Rescher advocates his version of methodological pragmatism, based on construing pragmatic efficacy not as a replacement for truths but as a means to its evidentiation.[41] Rescher is also a proponent of pragmatic idealism.

Not all pragmatists are easily characterized. With the advent of postanalytic philosophy and the diversification of Anglo-American philosophy, many philosophers were influenced by pragmatist thought without necessarily publicly committing themselves to that philosophical school. Daniel Dennett, a student of Quine's, falls into this category, as does Stephen Toulmin, who arrived at his philosophical position via Wittgenstein, whom he calls "a pragmatist of a sophisticated kind".[42] Another example is Mark Johnson whose embodied philosophy[43] shares its psychologism, direct realism and anti-cartesianism with pragmatism. Conceptual pragmatism is a theory of knowledge originating with the work of the philosopher and logician Clarence Irving Lewis. The epistemology of conceptual pragmatism was first formulated in the 1929 book Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge.

French pragmatism is attended with theorists such as Michel Callon, Bruno Latour, Michel Crozier, Luc Boltanski, and Laurent Thévenot. It often is seen as opposed to structural problems connected to the French critical theory of Pierre Bourdieu. French pragmatism has more recently made inroads into American sociology and anthropology as well.[44][45][46]

Philosophers John R. Shook and Tibor Solymosi said that "each new generation rediscovers and reinvents its own versions of pragmatism by applying the best available practical and scientific methods to philosophical problems of contemporary concern".[47]

Legacy and contemporary relevance edit

In the 20th century, the movements of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy have similarities with pragmatism. Like pragmatism, logical positivism provides a verification criterion of meaning that is supposed to rid us of nonsense metaphysics; however, logical positivism doesn't stress action as pragmatism does. The pragmatists rarely used their maxim of meaning to rule out all metaphysics as nonsense. Usually, pragmatism was put forth to correct metaphysical doctrines or to construct empirically verifiable ones rather than to provide a wholesale rejection.

Ordinary language philosophy is closer to pragmatism than other philosophy of language because of its nominalist character (although Peirce's pragmatism is not nominalist[14]) and because it takes the broader functioning of language in an environment as its focus instead of investigating abstract relations between language and world.

Pragmatism has ties to process philosophy. Much of the classical pragmatists' work developed in dialogue with process philosophers such as Henri Bergson and Alfred North Whitehead, who aren't usually considered pragmatists because they differ so much on other points.[48] Nonetheless, philosopher Donovan Irven argues there's a strong connection between Henri Bergson, pragmatist William James, and the existentialist Jean-Paul Sartre regarding their theories of truth.[49]

Behaviorism and functionalism in psychology and sociology also have ties to pragmatism, which is not surprising considering that James and Dewey were both scholars of psychology and that Mead became a sociologist.

Pragmatism emphasizes the connection between thought and action. Applied fields like public administration,[50] political science,[51] leadership studies,[52] international relations,[53] conflict resolution,[54] and research methodology[55] have incorporated the tenets of pragmatism in their field. Often this connection is made using Dewey and Addams's expansive notion of democracy.

Effects on social sciences edit

In the early 20th century, Symbolic interactionism, a major perspective within sociological social psychology, was derived from pragmatism, especially the work of George Herbert Mead and Charles Cooley, as well as that of Peirce and William James.[56][57]

Increasing attention is being given to pragmatist epistemology in other branches of the social sciences, which have struggled with divisive debates over the status of social scientific knowledge.[4][58]

Enthusiasts suggest that pragmatism offers an approach that is both pluralist and practical.[59]

Effects on public administration edit

The classical pragmatism of John Dewey, William James, and Charles Sanders Peirce has influenced research in the field of public administration. Scholars claim classical pragmatism had a profound influence on the origin of the field of public administration.[60][61] At the most basic level, public administrators are responsible for making programs "work" in a pluralistic, problems-oriented environment. Public administrators are also responsible for the day-to-day work with citizens. Dewey's participatory democracy can be applied in this environment. Dewey and James' notion of theory as a tool, helps administrators craft theories to resolve policy and administrative problems. Further, the birth of American public administration coincides closely with the period of greatest influence of the classical pragmatists.

Which pragmatism (classical pragmatism or neo-pragmatism) makes the most sense in public administration has been the source of debate. The debate began when Patricia M. Shields introduced Dewey's notion of the Community of Inquiry.[62] Hugh Miller objected to one element of the community of inquiry (problematic situation, scientific attitude, participatory democracy): scientific attitude.[63] A debate that included responses from a practitioner,[64] an economist,[65] a planner,[66] other public administration scholars,[67][68] and noted philosophers[69][70] followed. Miller[71] and Shields[72][73] also responded.

In addition, applied scholarship of public administration that assesses charter schools,[74] contracting out or outsourcing,[75] financial management,[76] performance measurement,[77] urban quality of life initiatives,[78] and urban planning[79] in part draws on the ideas of classical pragmatism in the development of the conceptual framework and focus of analysis.[80][81][82]

The health sector's administrators' use of pragmatism has been criticized as incomplete in its pragmatism, however,[83] according to the classical pragmatists, knowledge is always shaped by human interests. The administrator's focus on "outcomes" simply advances their own interest, and this focus on outcomes often undermines their citizen's interests, which often are more concerned with process. On the other hand, David Brendel argues that pragmatism's ability to bridge dualisms, focus on practical problems, include multiple perspectives, incorporate participation from interested parties (patient, family, health team), and provisional nature makes it well suited to address problems in this area.[84]

Effects on feminism edit

Since the mid 1990s, feminist philosophers have re-discovered classical pragmatism as a source of feminist theories. Works by Seigfried,[85] Duran,[86] Keith,[87] and Whipps[88] explore the historic and philosophic links between feminism and pragmatism. The connection between pragmatism and feminism took so long to be rediscovered because pragmatism itself was eclipsed by logical positivism during the middle decades of the twentieth century. As a result, it was lost from feminist discourse. Feminists now consider pragmatism's greatest strength to be the very features that led to its decline. These are "persistent and early criticisms of positivist interpretations of scientific methodology; disclosure of value dimension of factual claims"; viewing aesthetics as informing everyday experience; subordinating logical analysis to political, cultural, and social issues; linking the dominant discourses with domination; "realigning theory with praxis; and resisting the turn to epistemology and instead emphasizing concrete experience".[89]

Feminist philosophers point to Jane Addams as a founder of classical pragmatism. Mary Parker Follett was also an important feminist pragmatist concerned with organizational operation during the early decades of the 20th century.[90][91] In addition, the ideas of Dewey, Mead, and James are consistent with many feminist tenets. Jane Addams, John Dewey, and George Herbert Mead developed their philosophies as all three became friends, influenced each other, and were engaged in the Hull House experience and women's rights causes.

Criticisms edit

In the 1908 essay "The Thirteen Pragmatisms", Arthur Oncken Lovejoy argued that there's significant ambiguity in the notion of the effects of the truth of a proposition and those of belief in a proposition in order to highlight that many pragmatists had failed to recognize that distinction.[92] He identified 13 different philosophical positions that were each labeled pragmatism.[92]

The Franciscan friar Celestine Bittle presented multiple criticisms of pragmatism in his 1936 book Reality and the Mind: Epistemology.[93] He argued that, in William James's pragmatism, truth is entirely subjective and is not the widely accepted definition of truth, which is correspondence to reality. For Bittle, defining truth as what is useful is a "perversion of language".[93] With truth reduced essentially to what is good, it is no longer an object of the intellect. Therefore, the problem of knowledge posed by the intellect is not solved, but rather renamed. Renaming truth as a product of the will cannot help it solve the problems of the intellect, according to Bittle. Bittle cited what he saw as contradictions in pragmatism, such as using objective facts to prove that truth does not emerge from objective fact; this reveals that pragmatists do recognize truth as objective fact, and not, as they claim, what is useful. Bittle argued there are also some statements that cannot be judged on human welfare at all. Such statements (for example the assertion that "a car is passing") are matters of "truth and error" and do not affect human welfare.[93]

British philosopher Bertrand Russell devoted a chapter each to James and Dewey in his 1945 book A History of Western Philosophy; Russell pointed out areas in which he agreed with them but also ridiculed James's views on truth and Dewey's views on inquiry.[94]: 17 [95]: 120–124  Hilary Putnam later argued that Russell "presented a mere caricature" of James's views[94]: 17  and a "misreading of James",[94]: 20  while Tom Burke argued at length that Russell presented "a skewed characterization of Dewey's point of view".[95]: 121  Elsewhere, in Russell's book The Analysis of Mind, Russell praised James's radical empiricism, to which Russell's own account of neutral monism was indebted.[94]: 17 [96] Dewey, in The Bertrand Russell Case, defended Russell against an attempt to remove Russell from his chair at the College of the City of New York in 1940.[97]

Neopragmatism as represented by Richard Rorty has been criticized as relativistic both by other neopragmatists such as Susan Haack[98] and by many analytic philosophers.[99] Rorty's early analytic work, however, differs notably from his later work which some, including Rorty, consider to be closer to literary criticism than to philosophy, and which attracts the brunt of criticism from his detractors.

List of pragmatists edit

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ See Dewey 1910 for a "FAQ."

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d Peirce, C.S. (1878), "How to Make Our Ideas Clear", Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, 286–302. Reprinted often, including Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 388–410 and Essential Peirce v. 1, 124–141. See end of §II for the pragmatic maxim. See third and fourth paragraphs in §IV for the discoverability of truth and the real by sufficient investigation.
  2. ^ Hookway, Christopher (August 16, 2008). "Pragmatism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2010 ed.).
  3. ^ Susan Haack; Robert Edwin Lane (April 11, 2006). Pragmatism, old & new: selected writings. Prometheus Books. pp. 18–67. ISBN 978-1-59102-359-3.
  4. ^ a b Biesta, G.J.J. & Burbules, N. (2003). Pragmatism and educational research. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  5. ^ Barnhart Concise Dictionary of Etymology.
  6. ^ James, William (1898), "Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results", delivered before the Philosophical Union of the University of California at Berkeley, August 26, 1898, and first printed in the University Chronicle 1, September 1898, pp. 287–310. Internet Archive Eprint. On p. 290:

    I refer to Mr. Charles S. Peirce, with whose very existence as a philosopher I dare say many of you are unacquainted. He is one of the most original of contemporary thinkers; and the principle of practicalism or pragmatism, as he called it, when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early [1870s] is the clue or compass by following which I find myself more and more confirmed in believing we may keep our feet upon the proper trail.

    James credited Peirce again in 1906 lectures published in 1907 as Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, see Lecture 2, fourth paragraph.

  7. ^ James, William (1896). The Will to Believe: And Other Essays in Popular Philosophy. Longmans, Green. ISBN 978-0-7905-7948-1.
  8. ^ In addition to James's lectures and publications on pragmatist ideas (Will to Believe 1897, etc.) wherein he credited Peirce, James also arranged for two paid series of lectures by Peirce, including the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism. See pp. 261–264, 290–2, & 324 in Brent, Joseph (1998), Charles Sanders Peirce: A Life, 2nd edition.
  9. ^ Peirce, C.S., "The Founding of Pragmatism", manuscript written 1906, published in The Hound & Horn: A Harvard Miscellany v. II, n. 3, April–June 1929, pp. 282–285, see 283–284, reprinted 1934 as "Historical Affinities and Genesis" in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 11–13, see 12.
  10. ^ Shook, John. "The Metaphysical Club". pragmatism.org. Retrieved March 14, 2023.
  11. ^ Peirce, C.S. (1877), The Fixation of Belief, Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, pp. 1–15. Reprited often, including Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 358–387 and Essential Peirce v. 1, pp. 109–123).
  12. ^ Peirce, C. S. (April 1905). "What Pragmatism Is". The Monist. 15 (2): 161–181, see 165–166. doi:10.5840/monist190515230. Reprinted in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 411–437, see 414.
  13. ^ Manuscript "A Sketch of Logical Critics", Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 451–462, see pp. 457–458. Peirce wrote:

    I have always fathered my pragmaticism (as I have called it since James and Schiller made the word [pragmatism] imply "the will to believe", the mutability of truth, the soundness of Zeno's refutation of motion, and pluralism generally), upon Kant, Berkeley, and Leibniz. ...

  14. ^ a b c Peirce, C. S. (1908). "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God", Hibbert Journal 7, reprinted in Collected Papers v. 6, paragraphs 452–85, and in Essential Peirce v. 2, 434–450, and elsewhere. After discussing James, Peirce stated (Section V, fourth paragraph) as the specific occasion of his coinage "pragmaticism", journalist, pragmatist, and literary author Giovanni Papini's declaration of pragmatism's indefinability: see, for example, Papini's "What Is Pragmatism Like", published in translation in October 1907 in Popular Science Monthly v. 71, pp. 351–358].
  15. ^ a b Hildebrand, David L. (2003). Beyond realism and antirealism: John Dewey and the neopragmatists. The Vanderbilt library of American philosophy. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. ISBN 082651426X. OCLC 51053926.
  16. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1868). "Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man". Journal of Speculative Philosophy. 2 (2): 103–114. JSTOR 25665643. Reprinted in Collected Peirce v. 5, paragraphs 213–263, Writings v. 2, pp. 193–211, Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 11–27, and elsewhere.
  17. ^ De Waal 2005, pp. 7–10
  18. ^ Kasser, Jeff (Summer 1999). "Peirce's Supposed Psychologism". Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 35 (3): 501–526. JSTOR 40320777.
  19. ^ Peirce held that (philosophical) logic is a normative field, that pragmatism is a method developed in it, and that philosophy, though not deductive or so general as mathematics, still concerns positive phenomena in general, including phenomena of matter and mind, without depending on special experiences or experiments such as those of optics and experimental psychology, in both of which Peirce was active. See quotes under "Philosophy" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms. Peirce also harshly criticized the Cartesian approach of starting from hyperbolic doubts rather than from the combination of established beliefs and genuine doubts. See the opening of his 1868 "Some Consequences of Four Incapacities", Journal of Speculative Philosophy v. 2, n. 3, pp. 140–157. Reprinted Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 264–317, Writings v. 2, pp. 211–242, and Essential Peirce v. 1, pp. 28–55. Eprint.
  20. ^ Quine, W. V. O. (1969). "Epistemology naturalized". Ontological relativity and other essays. The John Dewey essays in philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press. pp. 69–90. ISBN 0231033079. OCLC 51301.
  21. ^ a b Putnam, Hilary (1994). "Pragmatism and moral objectivity". Words and Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. p. 152. ISBN 9780674956063. OCLC 29218832. that one can be both fallibilistic and antiskeptical is perhaps the unique insight of American pragmatism
  22. ^ a b Rescher, Nicholas (2007). "Pragmatism". In Boundas, Constantin V. (ed.). Edinburgh Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophies. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. p. 137. ISBN 9780748620975. OCLC 85690580.
  23. ^ a b Tiercelin, Claudine (October 14, 2014). "Why we should take a stand, and the stand we should take". The Pragmatists and the Human Logic of Truth. Philosophie de la connaissance. Paris: Collège de France. ISBN 978-2-7226-0339-4. Retrieved May 31, 2022.
  24. ^ McKinsey, Michael (2018). "Skepticism and Content Externalism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved March 14, 2023.
  25. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1902). "The Carnegie Institute Application, Memoir 10, MS L75.361-2". arisbe.sitehost.iu.edu. Retrieved April 4, 2023.
  26. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1868). "Some Consequences of Four Incapacities". Journal of Speculative Philosophy. 2 (3): 140–157. JSTOR 25665649. Google Books. See opening pages. Reprinted in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 264–317, Writings v. 2, pp. 211–242, Essential Peirce v. 1, pp. 28–55.
  27. ^ James 1907, p. 200
  28. ^ James 1907, p. 222
  29. ^ James 1907, p. 90
  30. ^ James 1907, p. 91
  31. ^ Sandra B. Rosenthal, C.I. Lewis in Focus: The Pulse of Pragmatism, Indiana University Press, 2007, p. 28.
  32. ^ James 1907, pp. 8–9
  33. ^ The Will to Believe James 1896
  34. ^ Edel 1993
  35. ^ Dewey 1930
  36. ^ Anderson, SEP
  37. ^ Dewey 2004 [1910] ch. 7; Dewey 1997 [1938], p. 47
  38. ^ Lekan 2003
  39. ^ "Pragmatism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 14, 2023.
  40. ^ Unger, Roberto (2007). The Self Awakened: Pragmatism Unbound. Harvard University Press. pp. 6–7. ISBN 978-0-674-03496-9.
  41. ^ Nicholas Rescher, "Methodological Pragmatism", Journal of Philosophy 76(6):338–342 (1979).
  42. ^ foreword for Dewey 1929 in the 1988 edition, p. xiii
  43. ^ Lakoff and Johnson 1999
  44. ^ Simko, Christina (2012). "Rhetorics of Suffering". American Sociological Review. 77 (6): 880–902. doi:10.1177/0003122412458785. S2CID 145559039.
  45. ^ Dromi, Shai M.; Stabler, Samuel D. (2019). "Good on paper: sociological critique, pragmatism, and secularization theory". Theory and Society. 48 (2): 325–350. doi:10.1007/s11186-019-09341-9. S2CID 151250246.
  46. ^ Cohen, Andrew C.; Dromi, Shai M. (February 15, 2018). "Advertising morality: maintaining moral worth in a stigmatized profession". Theory and Society. 47 (2): 175–206. doi:10.1007/s11186-018-9309-7. S2CID 49319915.
  47. ^ Shook, John R.; Solymosi, Tibor (April 2013). "Pragmatism: key resources". Choice. 50: 1367–1377 (1367).
  48. ^ Douglas Browning et al. 1998; Rescher, SEP
  49. ^ Irven, Donovan (August 24, 2020). "The Pragmatic Truth of Existentialism". Erraticus. Retrieved March 14, 2023.
  50. ^ Patricia M. Shields. 2008. "Rediscovering the Taproot: Is Classical Pragmatism the Route to Renew Public Administration?" Public Administration Review 68(2), 205–221
  51. ^ Ansell, Christopher. 2011. Pragmatist Democracy: Evolutionary Learning as Public Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press
  52. ^ Weber, Eric Thomas. 2013. Democracy and Leadership: On Pragmatism and Virtue. New York: Lexington Books.
  53. ^ Ralston, Shane (Ed). 2013. Philosophical Pragmatism and International Relations: Essays for a Bold New World. New York: Lexington.
  54. ^ Caspary, William. 2000. Dewey on Democracy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  55. ^ Shields, Patricia and Rangarjan, N. 2013. A Playbook for Research Methods: Integrating Conceptual Frameworks and Project Management. [1]. Stillwater, OK: New Forums Press. Shields relies primarily on Dewey's logic of Inquiry.
  56. ^ Stryker, S. (1980). Symbolic Interactionism: A Social Structural Version.. Benjamin/Cummings Publishing.
  57. ^ Nungesser, Frithjof. 2021. "Pragmatism and Interaction." In: Routledge International Handbook of Interactionism, edited by Dirk Vom Lehn, Natalia Ruiz-Junco, and Will Gibson. London; New York: Routledge: 25–36. ISBN 9780367227708
  58. ^ Baert, P. (2004). "Pragmatism as a philosophy of the social sciences." European Journal of Social Theory, 7(3), 355–369.
  59. ^ Cornish, Flora; Gillespie, Alex (2009). "A Pragmatist Approach to the Problem of Knowledge in Health Psychology". Journal of Health Psychology. 14 (6): 800–809. doi:10.1177/1359105309338974. hdl:1893/2453. ISSN 1359-1053. PMID 19687117. S2CID 467193.
  60. ^ Patricia M. Shields. 2008. Rediscovering the Taproot: Is Classical Pragmatism the Route to Renew Public Administration? Public Administration Review 68(2), 205–221
  61. ^ Hildebrand, David L. 2008. Public Administration as Pragmatic, Democratic and Objective. Public Administration Review. 68(2), 222–229
  62. ^ Shields, Patricia 2003. The community of Inquiry: Classical Pragmatism and Public Administration." Administration & Society 35(5): 510–538. abstract
  63. ^ Miller, Hugh. 2004. "Why Old Pragmatism Needs an Upgrade. Administration & Society 36(2), 234–249.
  64. ^ Stolcis, Gregory 2004. "A view from the Trenches: Comment on Miller's 'Why Old Pragmatism needs and upgrade" Administration & Society 36(3):326–369
  65. ^ Webb, James "Comment on Hugh T. Miller's 'Why old Pragmatism needs and upgrade'. Administration & Society 36(4), 479–495.
  66. ^ Hoch C. 2006. "What Can Rorty teach an old pragmatist doing public administration or planning? Administration & Society. 38(3):389–398. abstract
  67. ^ Evans, Karen. 2005. "Upgrade or a different animal altogether?: Why Old Pragmatism Better Informs Public Management and New Pragmatism Misses the Point." Administration & Society 37(2), 248–255.
  68. ^ Snider, Keith. 2005. Rortyan Pragmatism: 'Where's the beef' for public administration." Administration & Society 37(2), 243–247.
  69. ^ Hildebrand, David. 2005. "Pragmatism, Neopragmatism and public administration." Administration & Society 37(3): 360–374. abstract
  70. ^ Hickman, Larry 2004. "On Hugh T. Miller on 'Why old pragmatism needs an upgrade." Administration & Society 36(4):496–499.
  71. ^ Miller, Hugh 2005. "Residues of foundationalism in Classical Pragmatism." Administration & Society. 37(3):345–359.
  72. ^ Patricia M. Shields. 2004. "Classical Pragmatism: Engaging practitioner experience." Administration & Society, 36(3):351–361
  73. ^ Patricia M. Shields. 2005. "Classical Pragmatism does not need an upgrade: Lessons for Public Administration." Administration & Society. 37(4):504–518. abstract
  74. ^ Perez, Shivaun, "Assessing Service Learning Using Pragmatic Principles of Education: A Texas Charter School Case Study" (2000). Applied Research Projects. Texas State University Paper 76. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/76
  75. ^ Alexander, Jason Fields, "Contracting Through the Lens of Classical Pragmatism: An Exploration of Local Government Contracting" (2009). Applied Research Projects. Texas State University. Paper 288. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/288
  76. ^ Bartle, John R. and Shields, Patricia M., "Applying Pragmatism to Public Budgeting and Financial Management" (2008). Faculty Publications-Political Science. Paper 48. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/polsfacp/48
  77. ^ Wilson, Timothy L., "Pragmatism and Performance Measurement: An Exploration of Practices in Texas State Government" (2001). Applied Research Projects. Texas State University. Paper 71. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/71
  78. ^ Howard-Watkins, Demetria C., "The Austin, Texas African-American Quality of Life Initiative as a Community of inquiry: An Exploratory Study" (2006). Applied Research Projects. Texas State University. Paper 115. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/115
  79. ^ Johnson, Timothy Lee, "The Downtown Austin Planning Process as a Community of inquiry: An Exploratory Study" (2008). Applied Research Projects. Paper 276. http://ecommons.txstate.edu/arp/276.
  80. ^ Patricia M. Shields and Hassan Tajalli (2006), "Intermediate Theory: The Missing Link in Successful Student Scholarship," Journal of Public Affairs Education 12(3):313–334. https://digital.library.txstate.edu/handle/10877/3967
  81. ^ Patricia M. Shields (1998). "Pragmatism as a Philosophy of Science: A Tool for Public Administration," Research in Public Administration. Volume 4: 195–225. (Online.)
  82. ^ Patricia M. Shields and Nandhini Rangarajan (2013). A Playbook for Research Methods: Integrating Conceptual Frameworks and Project Management. Stillwater, OK: New Forums Press.
  83. ^ Cornish, Flora; Gillespie, Alex (2009). "A Pragmatist Approach to the Problem of Knowledge in Health Psychology". Journal of Health Psychology. 14 (6): 800–809. doi:10.1177/1359105309338974. hdl:1893/2453. ISSN 1359-1053. PMID 19687117. S2CID 467193.
  84. ^ Brendel, David. 2006. Healing Psychiatry: Bridging the Science/Humanism Divide. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  85. ^ Seigfried, C.H. (2001). Feminist interpretations of John Dewey. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press; Seigfried, C.H. (1996). Pragmatism and feminism: Reweaving the social fabric. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; Seigfried, C. H. (1992). Where are all the pragmatists feminists? Hypatia, 6, 8–21.
  86. ^ Duran, J. (2001). A holistically Deweyan feminism. Metaphilosophy, 32, 279–292. Duran, J. (1993). The intersection of pragmatism and feminism. Hypatia, 8
  87. ^ Keith, H. (1999). Feminism and pragmatism: George Herbert Mead's ethics of care. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 35, 328–344.
  88. ^ Whipps, J.D. (2004). Jane Addams social thought as a model for a pragmatist-feminist communitarianism. Hypatia, 19, 118–113.
  89. ^ Seigfried, C.H. (1996). Pragmatism and Feminism: Reweaving the Social Fabric. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. p. 21
  90. ^ Ansell, Chris (2009). "Mary Parker Follett and Pragmatist Organization". In Adler, Paul (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Sociology and Organization Studies: Classical Foundations. Oxford University Press. pp. 464–485. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199535231.003.0021. ISBN 978-0199535231.
  91. ^ Graham, ed. (1995). Mary Parker Follett, Prophet of Management: A Celebration of Writings from the 1920s. Cambridge MA: Harvard Business Press.
  92. ^ a b Lovejoy, Arthur O. (January 2, 1908). "The thirteen pragmatisms. I". The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods. 5 (1): 5–12. doi:10.2307/2012277. JSTOR 2012277. And: Lovejoy, Arthur O. (January 16, 1908). "The thirteen pragmatisms. II". The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods. 5 (2): 29–39. doi:10.2307/2011563. JSTOR 2011563.
  93. ^ a b c Bittle, Celestine Nicholas Charles (1936). Reality and the Mind: Epistemology. New York: The Bruce Publishing Company. OCLC 1017084.
  94. ^ a b c d Putnam, Hilary (December 1992). "The permanence of William James". Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 46 (3): 17–31. doi:10.2307/3824783. JSTOR 3824783.
  95. ^ a b Burke, F. Thomas (1994). Dewey's new logic: a reply to Russell. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226080692. OCLC 29844394.
  96. ^ Goodman, Russell (October 20, 2017). "William James". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.).
  97. ^ Edwards, Paul (1957). "How Bertrand Russell was prevented from teaching at the College of the City of New York". In Russell, Bertrand (ed.). Why I am not a Christian, and other essays on religion and related subjects. New York: Simon and Schuster. pp. 207–259. ISBN 0671203231. OCLC 376363.
  98. ^ Haack 1997
  99. ^ Dennett 1998
  100. ^ In: Stanley Fish, There's No Such Thing as Free Speech, Oxford University Press, 1994.
  101. ^ Ed. Morris Dickstein, Duke University Press, 1998

Sources edit

  • Baldwin, James Mark (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 volumes in 4, Macmillan, New York, NY.
  • Dewey, John (1900–1901), Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901, Donald F. Koch (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1991.
  • Dewey, John (1910), How We Think, D.C. Heath, Lexington, MA, 1910. Reprinted, Prometheus Books, Buffalo, NY, 1991.
  • Dewey, John (1929), The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action, Minton, Balch, and Company, New York, NY. Reprinted, pp. 1–254 in John Dewey, The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 4: 1929, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Harriet Furst Simon (text. ed.), Stephen Toulmin (intro.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1984.
  • Dewey, John (1932), Theory of the Moral Life, Part 2 of John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics, Henry Holt and Company, New York, NY, 1908. 2nd edition, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1932. Reprinted, Arnold Isenberg (ed.), Victor Kestenbaum (pref.), Irvington Publishers, New York, NY, 1980.
  • Dewey, John (1938), Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, Henry Holt and Company, New York, NY, 1938. Reprinted, pp. 1–527 in John Dewey, The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 12: 1938, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Kathleen Poulos (text. ed.), Ernest Nagel (intro.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1986.
  • James, William (1902), "Pragmatic and Pragmatism", 1 paragraph, vol. 2, pp. 321–322 in J.M. Baldwin (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 volumes in 4, Macmillan, New York, NY. Reprinted, CP 5.2 in C.S. Peirce, Collected Papers.
  • James, William (1907), Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular Lectures on Philosophy, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
  • James, William (1909), The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York, NY.
  • Lundin, Roger (2006) From Nature to Experience: The American Search for Cultural Authority Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
  • Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as CP vol.para.
  • Peirce, C.S., The Essential Peirce, Selected Philosophical Writings, Volume 1 (1867–1893), Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN, 1992.
  • Peirce, C.S., The Essential Peirce, Selected Philosophical Writings, Volume 2 (1893–1913), Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN, 1998.
  • Putnam, Hilary (1994), Words and Life, James Conant (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
  • Quine, W.V. (1951), "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", Philosophical Review (January 1951). Reprinted, pp. 20–46 in W.V. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, 1980.
  • Quine, W.V. (1980), From a Logical Point of View, Logico-Philosophical Essays, 2nd edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1980.
  • Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7, 153–170. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1990.
  • Ramsey, F.P. (1990), Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
  • Rescher, N. (1977), Methodological Pragmatism, Oxford: Blackwell, 1977.
  • Rescher, N. (2000), Realistic Pragmatism, Albany, SUNY Press, 2000.

Further reading edit

Surveys
  • John J. Stuhr, ed. One Hundred Years of Pragmatism: William James's Revolutionary Philosophy (Indiana University Press; 2010) 215 pages; Essays on pragmatism and American culture, pragmatism as a way of thinking and settling disputes, pragmatism as a theory of truth, and pragmatism as a mood, attitude, or temperament.

Primary texts
Note that this is an introductory list: some important works are left out and some less monumental works that are excellent introductions are included.

  • C.S. Peirce, "The Fixation of Belief" (paper)
  • C.S. Peirce, "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (paper)
  • C.S. Peirce, "A Definition of Pragmatism" (paper as titled by Menand in Pragmatism: A Reader, from Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v. 8, some or all of paragraphs 191–195.)
  • William James, Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking (especially lectures I, II and VI)
  • John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy
  • John Dewey, "Three Independent factors in Morals" (lecture published as paper)
  • John Dewey, "" (chapter)
  • W.V.O. Quine, "Two Dogmas of Empiricism". (paper)
Secondary texts
  • Cornelis De Waal, On Pragmatism
  • Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America
  • Hilary Putnam, Pragmatism: An Open Question
  • Abraham Edel,
  • D.S. Clarke, Rational Acceptance and Purpose
  • Haack, Susan & Lane, Robert, Eds. (2006). Pragmatism Old and New: Selected Writings. New York: Prometheus Books.
  • Louis Menand, ed., Pragmatism: A Reader (includes essays by Peirce, James, Dewey, Rorty, others)
  • For a discussion of the ways in which pragmatism offers insights into the theory and practice of urbanism, see: Aseem Inam, Designing Urban Transformation New York and London: Routledge, 2013. ISBN 978-0415837705.
Criticism
  • Edward W. Younkins, Dewey's Pragmatism and the Decline of Education.
  • Pragmatism, Ayn Rand Lexicon.
  • Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism: An Examination into the Respective Rights of Intellectual Aristocracy and Social Democracy. Boston: Small, Maynard and Company, 1909.

External links edit

General sources
Journals and organizations

There are several peer-reviewed journals dedicated to pragmatism, for example

  • Contemporary Pragmatism, affiliated with the International Pragmatism Society
  • , affiliated with the Associazione Culturale Pragma (Italy)
  • Nordic Studies in Pragmatism, journal of the Nordic Pragmatism Network
  • Pragmatism Today, journal of the Central European Pragmatist Forum (CEPF)
  • , journal of the Charles S. Peirce Society
  • William James Studies, journal of the William James Society

pragmatism, this, article, about, philosophical, movement, other, uses, disambiguation, philosophical, tradition, that, views, language, thought, tools, prediction, problem, solving, action, rather, than, describing, representing, mirroring, reality, pragmatis. This article is about the philosophical movement For other uses see Pragmatism disambiguation Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition that views language and thought as tools for prediction problem solving and action rather than describing representing or mirroring reality Pragmatists contend that most philosophical topics such as the nature of knowledge language concepts meaning belief and science are all best viewed in terms of their practical uses and successes Pragmatism began in the United States in the 1870s Its origins are often attributed to philosophers Charles Sanders Peirce William James and John Dewey In 1878 Peirce described it in his pragmatic maxim Consider the practical effects of the objects of your conception Then your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object 1 Contents 1 Origins 2 Core tenets 2 1 Anti reification of concepts and theories 2 2 Naturalism and anti Cartesianism 2 3 Reconciliation of anti skepticism and fallibilism 2 4 Theory of truth and epistemology 3 In other fields 3 1 Philosophy of science 3 2 Logic 3 3 Metaphysics 3 4 Philosophy of mind 3 5 Ethics 3 6 Aesthetics 3 7 Philosophy of religion 3 8 Education 4 Neopragmatism 5 Legacy and contemporary relevance 5 1 Effects on social sciences 5 2 Effects on public administration 5 3 Effects on feminism 6 Criticisms 7 List of pragmatists 7 1 Classical 1850 1950 7 2 Analytic neo and other 1950 present 7 2 1 In the extended sense 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Sources 12 Further reading 13 External linksOrigins edit nbsp Charles Peirce the American polymath who first identified pragmatismPragmatism as a philosophical movement began in the United States around 1870 2 Charles Sanders Peirce and his pragmatic maxim is given credit for its development 3 along with later 20th century contributors William James and John Dewey 4 Its direction was determined by The Metaphysical Club members Charles Sanders Peirce William James and Chauncey Wright as well as John Dewey and George Herbert Mead The word pragmatic has existed in English since the 1500s a word borrowed from French and ultimately derived from Greek via Latin The Greek word pragma meaning business deed or act is a noun derived from the verb prassein to do 5 The first use in print of the name pragmatism was in 1898 by James who credited Peirce with coining the term during the early 1870s 6 James regarded Peirce s Illustrations of the Logic of Science series including The Fixation of Belief 1877 and especially How to Make Our Ideas Clear 1878 as the foundation of pragmatism 7 8 Peirce in turn wrote in 1906 9 that Nicholas St John Green had been instrumental by emphasizing the importance of applying Alexander Bain s definition of belief which was that upon which a man is prepared to act Peirce wrote that from this definition pragmatism is scarce more than a corollary so that I am disposed to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism John Shook has said Chauncey Wright also deserves considerable credit for as both Peirce and James recall it was Wright who demanded a phenomenalist and fallibilist empiricism as an alternative to rationalistic speculation 10 Peirce developed the idea that inquiry depends on real doubt not mere verbal or hyperbolic doubt 11 and said that in order to understand a conception in a fruitful way Consider the practical effects of the objects of your conception Then your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object 1 which he later called the pragmatic maxim It equates any conception of an object to the general extent of the conceivable implications for informed practice of that object s effects This is the heart of his pragmatism as a method of experimentational mental reflection arriving at conceptions in terms of conceivable confirmatory and disconfirmatory circumstances a method hospitable to the generation of explanatory hypotheses and conducive to the employment and improvement of verification Typical of Peirce is his concern with inference to explanatory hypotheses as outside the usual foundational alternative between deductivist rationalism and inductivist empiricism although he was a mathematical logician and a founder of statistics citation needed Peirce lectured and further wrote on pragmatism to make clear his own interpretation While framing a conception s meaning in terms of conceivable tests Peirce emphasized that since a conception is general its meaning its intellectual purport equates to its acceptance s implications for general practice rather than to any definite set of real effects or test results a conception s clarified meaning points toward its conceivable verifications but the outcomes are not meanings but individual upshots Peirce in 1905 coined the new name pragmaticism for the precise purpose of expressing the original definition 12 saying that all went happily with James s and F C S Schiller s variant uses of the old name pragmatism and that he nonetheless coined the new name because of the old name s growing use in literary journals where it gets abused Yet in a 1906 manuscript he cited as causes his differences with James and Schiller 13 and in a 1908 publication 14 his differences with James as well as literary author Giovanni Papini Peirce regarded his own views that truth is immutable and infinity is real as being opposed by the other pragmatists but he remained allied with them about the falsity of necessitarianism and about the reality of generals and habits understood in terms of potential concrete effects even if unactualized 14 Pragmatism enjoyed renewed attention after Willard Van Orman Quine and Wilfrid Sellars used a revised pragmatism to criticize logical positivism in the 1960s Inspired by the work of Quine and Sellars a brand of pragmatism known sometimes as neopragmatism gained influence through Richard Rorty the most influential of the late 20th century pragmatists along with Hilary Putnam and Robert Brandom Contemporary pragmatism may be broadly divided into a strict analytic tradition and a neo classical pragmatism such as Susan Haack that adheres to the work of Peirce James and Dewey citation needed Core tenets editA few of the various but often interrelated positions characteristic of philosophers working from a pragmatist approach include Epistemology justification a coherentist theory of justification that rejects the claim that all knowledge and justified belief rest ultimately on a foundation of noninferential knowledge or justified belief Coherentists hold that justification is solely a function of some relationship between beliefs none of which are privileged beliefs in the way maintained by foundationalist theories of justification Epistemology truth a deflationary or pragmatic theory of truth the former is the epistemological claim that assertions that predicate truth of a statement do not attribute a property called truth to such a statement while the latter is the epistemological claim that assertions that predicate truth of a statement attribute the property of useful to believe to such a statement Metaphysics a pluralist view that there is more than one sound way to conceptualize the world and its content Philosophy of science an instrumentalist and scientific anti realist view that a scientific concept or theory should be evaluated by how effectively it explains and predicts phenomena as opposed to how accurately it describes objective reality Philosophy of language an anti representationalist view that rejects analyzing the semantic meaning of propositions mental states and statements in terms of a correspondence or representational relationship and instead analyzes semantic meaning in terms of notions like dispositions to action inferential relationships and or functional roles e g behaviorism and inferentialism Not to be confused with pragmatics a sub field of linguistics with no relation to philosophical pragmatism Additionally forms of empiricism fallibilism verificationism and a Quinean naturalist metaphilosophy are all commonly elements of pragmatist philosophies Many pragmatists are epistemological relativists and see this to be an important facet of their pragmatism e g Joseph Margolis but this is controversial and other pragmatists argue such relativism to be seriously misguided e g Hilary Putnam Susan Haack Anti reification of concepts and theories edit Dewey in The Quest for Certainty criticized what he called the philosophical fallacy Philosophers often take categories such as the mental and the physical for granted because they don t realize that these are nominal concepts that were invented to help solve specific problems 15 This causes metaphysical and conceptual confusion Various examples are the ultimate Being of Hegelian philosophers the belief in a realm of value the idea that logic because it is an abstraction from concrete thought has nothing to do with the action of concrete thinking David L Hildebrand summarized the problem Perceptual inattention to the specific functions comprising inquiry led realists and idealists alike to formulate accounts of knowledge that project the products of extensive abstraction back onto experience 15 40 Naturalism and anti Cartesianism edit From the outset pragmatists wanted to reform philosophy and bring it more in line with the scientific method as they understood it They argued that idealist and realist philosophy had a tendency to present human knowledge as something beyond what science could grasp They held that these philosophies then resorted either to a phenomenology inspired by Kant or to correspondence theories of knowledge and truth citation needed Pragmatists criticized the former for its a priorism and the latter because it takes correspondence as an unanalyzable fact Pragmatism instead tries to explain the relation between knower and known In 1868 16 C S Peirce argued that there is no power of intuition in the sense of a cognition unconditioned by inference and no power of introspection intuitive or otherwise and that awareness of an internal world is by hypothetical inference from external facts Introspection and intuition were staple philosophical tools at least since Descartes He argued that there is no absolutely first cognition in a cognitive process such a process has its beginning but can always be analyzed into finer cognitive stages That which we call introspection does not give privileged access to knowledge about the mind the self is a concept that is derived from our interaction with the external world and not the other way around 17 At the same time he held persistently that pragmatism and epistemology in general could not be derived from principles of psychology understood as a special science 18 what we do think is too different from what we should think in his Illustrations of the Logic of Science series Peirce formulated both pragmatism and principles of statistics as aspects of scientific method in general 19 This is an important point of disagreement with most other pragmatists who advocate a more thorough naturalism and psychologism Richard Rorty expanded on these and other arguments in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature in which he criticized attempts by many philosophers of science to carve out a space for epistemology that is entirely unrelated to and sometimes thought of as superior to the empirical sciences W V Quine who was instrumental in bringing naturalized epistemology back into favor with his essay Epistemology Naturalized 20 also criticized traditional epistemology and its Cartesian dream of absolute certainty The dream he argued was impossible in practice as well as misguided in theory because it separates epistemology from scientific inquiry nbsp Hilary Putnam said that the combination of antiskepticism and fallibilism is a central feature of pragmatism 21 22 23 Reconciliation of anti skepticism and fallibilism edit Hilary Putnam has suggested that the reconciliation of anti skepticism 24 and fallibilism is the central goal of American pragmatism 21 22 23 Although all human knowledge is partial with no ability to take a God s eye view this does not necessitate a globalized skeptical attitude a radical philosophical skepticism as distinguished from that which is called scientific skepticism Peirce insisted that 1 in reasoning there is the presupposition and at least the hope 25 that truth and the real are discoverable and would be discovered sooner or later but still inevitably by investigation taken far enough 1 and 2 contrary to Descartes s famous and influential methodology in the Meditations on First Philosophy doubt cannot be feigned or created by verbal fiat to motivate fruitful inquiry and much less can philosophy begin in universal doubt 26 Doubt like belief requires justification Genuine doubt irritates and inhibits in the sense that belief is that upon which one is prepared to act 1 It arises from confrontation with some specific recalcitrant matter of fact which Dewey called a situation which unsettles our belief in some specific proposition Inquiry is then the rationally self controlled process of attempting to return to a settled state of belief about the matter Note that anti skepticism is a reaction to modern academic skepticism in the wake of Descartes The pragmatist insistence that all knowledge is tentative is quite congenial to the older skeptical tradition Theory of truth and epistemology edit Main article Pragmatic theory of truth Pragmatism was not the first to apply evolution to theories of knowledge Schopenhauer advocated a biological idealism as what s useful to an organism to believe might differ wildly from what is true Here knowledge and action are portrayed as two separate spheres with an absolute or transcendental truth above and beyond any sort of inquiry organisms used to cope with life Pragmatism challenges this idealism by providing an ecological account of knowledge inquiry is how organisms can get a grip on their environment Real and true are functional labels in inquiry and cannot be understood outside of this context It is not realist in a traditionally robust sense of realism what Hilary Putnam later called metaphysical realism but it is realist in how it acknowledges an external world which must be dealt with citation needed Many of James best turned phrases truth s cash value 27 and the true is only the expedient in our way of thinking 28 were taken out of context and caricatured in contemporary literature as representing the view where any idea with practical utility is true William James wrote It is high time to urge the use of a little imagination in philosophy The unwillingness of some of our critics to read any but the silliest of possible meanings into our statements is as discreditable to their imaginations as anything I know in recent philosophic history Schiller says the truth is that which works Thereupon he is treated as one who limits verification to the lowest material utilities Dewey says truth is what gives satisfaction He is treated as one who believes in calling everything true which if it were true would be pleasant 29 In reality James asserts the theory is a great deal more subtle nb 1 The role of belief in representing reality is widely debated in pragmatism Is a belief valid when it represents reality Copying is one and only one genuine mode of knowing 30 Are beliefs dispositions which qualify as true or false depending on how helpful they prove in inquiry and in action Is it only in the struggle of intelligent organisms with the surrounding environment that beliefs acquire meaning Does a belief only become true when it succeeds in this struggle In James s pragmatism nothing practical or useful is held to be necessarily true nor is anything which helps to survive merely in the short term For example to believe my cheating spouse is faithful may help me feel better now but it is certainly not useful from a more long term perspective because it doesn t accord with the facts and is therefore not true In other fields editWhile pragmatism started simply as a criterion of meaning it quickly expanded to become a full fledged epistemology with wide ranging implications for the entire philosophical field Pragmatists who work in these fields share a common inspiration but their work is diverse and there are no received views Philosophy of science edit In the philosophy of science instrumentalism is the view that concepts and theories are merely useful instruments and progress in science cannot be couched in terms of concepts and theories somehow mirroring reality Instrumentalist philosophers often define scientific progress as nothing more than an improvement in explaining and predicting phenomena Instrumentalism does not state that truth does not matter but rather provides a specific answer to the question of what truth and falsity mean and how they function in science One of C I Lewis main arguments in Mind and the World Order Outline of a Theory of Knowledge 1929 was that science does not merely provide a copy of reality but must work with conceptual systems and that those are chosen for pragmatic reasons that is because they aid inquiry Lewis own development of multiple modal logics is a case in point Lewis is sometimes called a proponent of conceptual pragmatism because of this 31 Another development is the cooperation of logical positivism and pragmatism in the works of Charles W Morris and Rudolf Carnap The influence of pragmatism on these writers is mostly limited to the incorporation of the pragmatic maxim into their epistemology Pragmatists with a broader conception of the movement do not often refer to them W V Quine s paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism published in 1951 is one of the most celebrated papers of 20th century philosophy in the analytic tradition The paper is an attack on two central tenets of the logical positivists philosophy One is the distinction between analytic statements tautologies and contradictions whose truth or falsehood is a function of the meanings of the words in the statement all bachelors are unmarried and synthetic statements whose truth or falsehood is a function of contingent states of affairs The other is reductionism the theory that each meaningful statement gets its meaning from some logical construction of terms which refers exclusively to immediate experience Quine s argument brings to mind Peirce s insistence that axioms are not a priori truths but synthetic statements Logic edit Later in his life Schiller became famous for his attacks on logic in his textbook Formal Logic By then Schiller s pragmatism had become the nearest of any of the classical pragmatists to an ordinary language philosophy Schiller sought to undermine the very possibility of formal logic by showing that words only had meaning when used in context The least famous of Schiller s main works was the constructive sequel to his destructive book Formal Logic In this sequel Logic for Use Schiller attempted to construct a new logic to replace the formal logic that he had criticized in Formal Logic What he offers is something philosophers would recognize today as a logic covering the context of discovery and the hypothetico deductive method Whereas Schiller dismissed the possibility of formal logic most pragmatists are critical rather of its pretension to ultimate validity and see logic as one logical tool among others or perhaps considering the multitude of formal logics one set of tools among others This is the view of C I Lewis C S Peirce developed multiple methods for doing formal logic Stephen Toulmin s The Uses of Argument inspired scholars in informal logic and rhetoric studies although it is an epistemological work Metaphysics edit James and Dewey were empirical thinkers in the most straightforward fashion experience is the ultimate test and experience is what needs to be explained They were dissatisfied with ordinary empiricism because in the tradition dating from Hume empiricists had a tendency to think of experience as nothing more than individual sensations To the pragmatists this went against the spirit of empiricism we should try to explain all that is given in experience including connections and meaning instead of explaining them away and positing sense data as the ultimate reality Radical empiricism or Immediate Empiricism in Dewey s words wants to give a place to meaning and value instead of explaining them away as subjective additions to a world of whizzing atoms nbsp The Chicago Club including Mead Dewey Angell and Moore Pragmatism is sometimes called American pragmatism because so many of its proponents were and are Americans William James gives an interesting example of this philosophical shortcoming A young graduate began by saying that he had always taken for granted that when you entered a philosophic classroom you had to open relations with a universe entirely distinct from the one you left behind you in the street The two were supposed he said to have so little to do with each other that you could not possibly occupy your mind with them at the same time The world of concrete personal experiences to which the street belongs is multitudinous beyond imagination tangled muddy painful and perplexed The world to which your philosophy professor introduces you is simple clean and noble The contradictions of real life are absent from it In point of fact it is far less an account of this actual world than a clear addition built upon it It is no explanation of our concrete universe 32 F C S Schiller s first book Riddles of the Sphinx was published before he became aware of the growing pragmatist movement taking place in America In it Schiller argues for a middle ground between materialism and absolute metaphysics These opposites are comparable to what William James called tough minded empiricism and tender minded rationalism Schiller contends on the one hand that mechanistic naturalism cannot make sense of the higher aspects of our world These include free will consciousness purpose universals and some would add God On the other hand abstract metaphysics cannot make sense of the lower aspects of our world e g the imperfect change physicality While Schiller is vague about the exact sort of middle ground he is trying to establish he suggests that metaphysics is a tool that can aid inquiry but that it is valuable only insofar as it does help in explanation In the second half of the 20th century Stephen Toulmin argued that the need to distinguish between reality and appearance only arises within an explanatory scheme and therefore that there is no point in asking what ultimate reality consists of More recently a similar idea has been suggested by the postanalytic philosopher Daniel Dennett who argues that anyone who wants to understand the world has to acknowledge both the syntactical aspects of reality i e whizzing atoms and its emergent or semantic properties i e meaning and value citation needed Radical empiricism gives answers to questions about the limits of science the nature of meaning and value and the workability of reductionism These questions feature prominently in current debates about the relationship between religion and science where it is often assumed most pragmatists would disagree that science degrades everything that is meaningful into merely physical phenomena Philosophy of mind edit Both John Dewey in Experience and Nature 1929 and half a century later Richard Rorty in his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature 1979 argued that much of the debate about the relation of the mind to the body results from conceptual confusions They argue instead that there is no need to posit the mind or mindstuff as an ontological category Pragmatists disagree over whether philosophers ought to adopt a quietist or a naturalist stance toward the mind body problem The former including Rorty want to do away with the problem because they believe it s a pseudo problem whereas the latter believe that it is a meaningful empirical question citation needed Ethics edit Main article Pragmatic ethics Pragmatism sees no fundamental difference between practical and theoretical reason nor any ontological difference between facts and values Pragmatist ethics is broadly humanist because it sees no ultimate test of morality beyond what matters for us as humans Good values are those for which we have good reasons viz the good reasons approach The pragmatist formulation pre dates those of other philosophers who have stressed important similarities between values and facts such as Jerome Schneewind and John Searle nbsp William James tried to show the meaningfulness of some kinds of spirituality but like other pragmatists did not see religion as the basis of meaning or morality William James contribution to ethics as laid out in his essay The Will to Believe has often been misunderstood as a plea for relativism or irrationality On its own terms it argues that ethics always involves a certain degree of trust or faith and that we cannot always wait for adequate proof when making moral decisions Moral questions immediately present themselves as questions whose solution cannot wait for sensible proof A moral question is a question not of what sensibly exists but of what is good or would be good if it did exist A social organism of any sort whatever large or small is what it is because each member proceeds to his own duty with a trust that the other members will simultaneously do theirs Wherever a desired result is achieved by the co operation of many independent persons its existence as a fact is a pure consequence of the precursive faith in one another of those immediately concerned A government an army a commercial system a ship a college an athletic team all exist on this condition without which not only is nothing achieved but nothing is even attempted 33 Of the classical pragmatists John Dewey wrote most extensively about morality and democracy 34 In his classic article Three Independent Factors in Morals 35 he tried to integrate three basic philosophical perspectives on morality the right the virtuous and the good He held that while all three provide meaningful ways to think about moral questions the possibility of conflict among the three elements cannot always be easily solved 36 Dewey also criticized the dichotomy between means and ends which he saw as responsible for the degradation of our everyday working lives and education both conceived as merely a means to an end He stressed the need for meaningful labor and a conception of education that viewed it not as a preparation for life but as life itself 37 Dewey was opposed to other ethical philosophies of his time notably the emotivism of Alfred Ayer Dewey envisioned the possibility of ethics as an experimental discipline and thought values could best be characterized not as feelings or imperatives but as hypotheses about what actions will lead to satisfactory results or what he termed consummatory experience An additional implication of this view is that ethics is a fallible undertaking because human beings are frequently unable to know what would satisfy them During the late 1900s and first decade of 2000 pragmatism was embraced by many in the field of bioethics led by the philosophers John Lachs and his student Glenn McGee whose 1997 book The Perfect Baby A Pragmatic Approach to Genetic Engineering see designer baby garnered praise from within classical American philosophy and criticism from bioethics for its development of a theory of pragmatic bioethics and its rejection of the principalism theory then in vogue in medical ethics An anthology published by the MIT Press titled Pragmatic Bioethics included the responses of philosophers to that debate including Micah Hester Griffin Trotter and others many of whom developed their own theories based on the work of Dewey Peirce Royce and others Lachs developed several applications of pragmatism to bioethics independent of but extending from the work of Dewey and James A recent pragmatist contribution to meta ethics is Todd Lekan s Making Morality 38 Lekan argues that morality is a fallible but rational practice and that it has traditionally been misconceived as based on theory or principles Instead he argues theory and rules arise as tools to make practice more intelligent Aesthetics edit John Dewey s Art as Experience based on the William James lectures he delivered at Harvard University was an attempt to show the integrity of art culture and everyday experience IEP Art for Dewey is or should be a part of everyone s creative lives and not just the privilege of a select group of artists He also emphasizes that the audience is more than a passive recipient Dewey s treatment of art was a move away from the transcendental approach to aesthetics in the wake of Immanuel Kant who emphasized the unique character of art and the disinterested nature of aesthetic appreciation A notable contemporary pragmatist aesthetician is Joseph Margolis He defines a work of art as a physically embodied culturally emergent entity a human utterance that isn t an ontological quirk but in line with other human activity and culture in general He emphasizes that works of art are complex and difficult to fathom and that no determinate interpretation can be given Philosophy of religion edit Both Dewey and James investigated the role that religion can still play in contemporary society the former in A Common Faith and the latter in The Varieties of Religious Experience From a general point of view for William James something is true only insofar as it works Thus the statement for example that prayer is heard may work on a psychological level but a may not help to bring about the things you pray for b may be better explained by referring to its soothing effect than by claiming prayers are heard As such pragmatism is not antithetical to religion but it is not an apologetic for faith either James metaphysical position however leaves open the possibility that the ontological claims of religions may be true As he observed in the end of the Varieties his position does not amount to a denial of the existence of transcendent realities Quite the contrary he argued for the legitimate epistemic right to believe in such realities since such beliefs do make a difference in an individual s life and refer to claims that cannot be verified or falsified either on intellectual or common sensorial grounds Joseph Margolis in Historied Thought Constructed World California 1995 makes a distinction between existence and reality He suggests using the term exists only for those things which adequately exhibit Peirce s Secondness things which offer brute physical resistance to our movements In this way such things which affect us like numbers may be said to be real although they do not exist Margolis suggests that God in such a linguistic usage might very well be real causing believers to act in such and such a way but might not exist Education edit This section needs expansion You can help by adding to it October 2023 Pragmatic pedagogy is an educational philosophy that emphasizes teaching students knowledge that is practical for life and encourages them to grow into better people American philosopher John Dewey is considered one of the main thinkers of the pragmatist educational approach Neopragmatism editMain article Neopragmatism Neopragmatism is a broad contemporary category used for various thinkers that incorporate important insights of and yet significantly diverge from the classical pragmatists This divergence may occur either in their philosophical methodology many of them are loyal to the analytic tradition or in conceptual formation for example conceptual pragmatist C I Lewis was very critical of Dewey neopragmatist Richard Rorty disliked Peirce Important analytic pragmatists include early Richard Rorty who was the first to develop neopragmatist philosophy in his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature 1979 39 Hilary Putnam W V O Quine and Donald Davidson Brazilian social thinker Roberto Unger advocates for a radical pragmatism one that de naturalizes society and culture and thus insists that we can transform the character of our relation to social and cultural worlds we inhabit rather than just to change little by little the content of the arrangements and beliefs that comprise them 40 Late Rorty and Jurgen Habermas are closer to Continental thought Neopragmatist thinkers who are more loyal to classical pragmatism include Sidney Hook and Susan Haack known for the theory of foundherentism Many pragmatist ideas especially those of Peirce find a natural expression in the decision theoretic reconstruction of epistemology pursued in the work of Isaac Levi Nicholas Rescher advocates his version of methodological pragmatism based on construing pragmatic efficacy not as a replacement for truths but as a means to its evidentiation 41 Rescher is also a proponent of pragmatic idealism Not all pragmatists are easily characterized With the advent of postanalytic philosophy and the diversification of Anglo American philosophy many philosophers were influenced by pragmatist thought without necessarily publicly committing themselves to that philosophical school Daniel Dennett a student of Quine s falls into this category as does Stephen Toulmin who arrived at his philosophical position via Wittgenstein whom he calls a pragmatist of a sophisticated kind 42 Another example is Mark Johnson whose embodied philosophy 43 shares its psychologism direct realism and anti cartesianism with pragmatism Conceptual pragmatism is a theory of knowledge originating with the work of the philosopher and logician Clarence Irving Lewis The epistemology of conceptual pragmatism was first formulated in the 1929 book Mind and the World Order Outline of a Theory of Knowledge French pragmatism is attended with theorists such as Michel Callon Bruno Latour Michel Crozier Luc Boltanski and Laurent Thevenot It often is seen as opposed to structural problems connected to the French critical theory of Pierre Bourdieu French pragmatism has more recently made inroads into American sociology and anthropology as well 44 45 46 Philosophers John R Shook and Tibor Solymosi said that each new generation rediscovers and reinvents its own versions of pragmatism by applying the best available practical and scientific methods to philosophical problems of contemporary concern 47 Legacy and contemporary relevance editIn the 20th century the movements of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy have similarities with pragmatism Like pragmatism logical positivism provides a verification criterion of meaning that is supposed to rid us of nonsense metaphysics however logical positivism doesn t stress action as pragmatism does The pragmatists rarely used their maxim of meaning to rule out all metaphysics as nonsense Usually pragmatism was put forth to correct metaphysical doctrines or to construct empirically verifiable ones rather than to provide a wholesale rejection Ordinary language philosophy is closer to pragmatism than other philosophy of language because of its nominalist character although Peirce s pragmatism is not nominalist 14 and because it takes the broader functioning of language in an environment as its focus instead of investigating abstract relations between language and world Pragmatism has ties to process philosophy Much of the classical pragmatists work developed in dialogue with process philosophers such as Henri Bergson and Alfred North Whitehead who aren t usually considered pragmatists because they differ so much on other points 48 Nonetheless philosopher Donovan Irven argues there s a strong connection between Henri Bergson pragmatist William James and the existentialist Jean Paul Sartre regarding their theories of truth 49 Behaviorism and functionalism in psychology and sociology also have ties to pragmatism which is not surprising considering that James and Dewey were both scholars of psychology and that Mead became a sociologist Pragmatism emphasizes the connection between thought and action Applied fields like public administration 50 political science 51 leadership studies 52 international relations 53 conflict resolution 54 and research methodology 55 have incorporated the tenets of pragmatism in their field Often this connection is made using Dewey and Addams s expansive notion of democracy Effects on social sciences edit In the early 20th century Symbolic interactionism a major perspective within sociological social psychology was derived from pragmatism especially the work of George Herbert Mead and Charles Cooley as well as that of Peirce and William James 56 57 Increasing attention is being given to pragmatist epistemology in other branches of the social sciences which have struggled with divisive debates over the status of social scientific knowledge 4 58 Enthusiasts suggest that pragmatism offers an approach that is both pluralist and practical 59 Effects on public administration edit The classical pragmatism of John Dewey William James and Charles Sanders Peirce has influenced research in the field of public administration Scholars claim classical pragmatism had a profound influence on the origin of the field of public administration 60 61 At the most basic level public administrators are responsible for making programs work in a pluralistic problems oriented environment Public administrators are also responsible for the day to day work with citizens Dewey s participatory democracy can be applied in this environment Dewey and James notion of theory as a tool helps administrators craft theories to resolve policy and administrative problems Further the birth of American public administration coincides closely with the period of greatest influence of the classical pragmatists Which pragmatism classical pragmatism or neo pragmatism makes the most sense in public administration has been the source of debate The debate began when Patricia M Shields introduced Dewey s notion of the Community of Inquiry 62 Hugh Miller objected to one element of the community of inquiry problematic situation scientific attitude participatory democracy scientific attitude 63 A debate that included responses from a practitioner 64 an economist 65 a planner 66 other public administration scholars 67 68 and noted philosophers 69 70 followed Miller 71 and Shields 72 73 also responded In addition applied scholarship of public administration that assesses charter schools 74 contracting out or outsourcing 75 financial management 76 performance measurement 77 urban quality of life initiatives 78 and urban planning 79 in part draws on the ideas of classical pragmatism in the development of the conceptual framework and focus of analysis 80 81 82 The health sector s administrators use of pragmatism has been criticized as incomplete in its pragmatism however 83 according to the classical pragmatists knowledge is always shaped by human interests The administrator s focus on outcomes simply advances their own interest and this focus on outcomes often undermines their citizen s interests which often are more concerned with process On the other hand David Brendel argues that pragmatism s ability to bridge dualisms focus on practical problems include multiple perspectives incorporate participation from interested parties patient family health team and provisional nature makes it well suited to address problems in this area 84 Effects on feminism edit Since the mid 1990s feminist philosophers have re discovered classical pragmatism as a source of feminist theories Works by Seigfried 85 Duran 86 Keith 87 and Whipps 88 explore the historic and philosophic links between feminism and pragmatism The connection between pragmatism and feminism took so long to be rediscovered because pragmatism itself was eclipsed by logical positivism during the middle decades of the twentieth century As a result it was lost from feminist discourse Feminists now consider pragmatism s greatest strength to be the very features that led to its decline These are persistent and early criticisms of positivist interpretations of scientific methodology disclosure of value dimension of factual claims viewing aesthetics as informing everyday experience subordinating logical analysis to political cultural and social issues linking the dominant discourses with domination realigning theory with praxis and resisting the turn to epistemology and instead emphasizing concrete experience 89 Feminist philosophers point to Jane Addams as a founder of classical pragmatism Mary Parker Follett was also an important feminist pragmatist concerned with organizational operation during the early decades of the 20th century 90 91 In addition the ideas of Dewey Mead and James are consistent with many feminist tenets Jane Addams John Dewey and George Herbert Mead developed their philosophies as all three became friends influenced each other and were engaged in the Hull House experience and women s rights causes Criticisms editIn the 1908 essay The Thirteen Pragmatisms Arthur Oncken Lovejoy argued that there s significant ambiguity in the notion of the effects of the truth of a proposition and those of belief in a proposition in order to highlight that many pragmatists had failed to recognize that distinction 92 He identified 13 different philosophical positions that were each labeled pragmatism 92 The Franciscan friar Celestine Bittle presented multiple criticisms of pragmatism in his 1936 book Reality and the Mind Epistemology 93 He argued that in William James s pragmatism truth is entirely subjective and is not the widely accepted definition of truth which is correspondence to reality For Bittle defining truth as what is useful is a perversion of language 93 With truth reduced essentially to what is good it is no longer an object of the intellect Therefore the problem of knowledge posed by the intellect is not solved but rather renamed Renaming truth as a product of the will cannot help it solve the problems of the intellect according to Bittle Bittle cited what he saw as contradictions in pragmatism such as using objective facts to prove that truth does not emerge from objective fact this reveals that pragmatists do recognize truth as objective fact and not as they claim what is useful Bittle argued there are also some statements that cannot be judged on human welfare at all Such statements for example the assertion that a car is passing are matters of truth and error and do not affect human welfare 93 British philosopher Bertrand Russell devoted a chapter each to James and Dewey in his 1945 book A History of Western Philosophy Russell pointed out areas in which he agreed with them but also ridiculed James s views on truth and Dewey s views on inquiry 94 17 95 120 124 Hilary Putnam later argued that Russell presented a mere caricature of James s views 94 17 and a misreading of James 94 20 while Tom Burke argued at length that Russell presented a skewed characterization of Dewey s point of view 95 121 Elsewhere in Russell s book The Analysis of Mind Russell praised James s radical empiricism to which Russell s own account of neutral monism was indebted 94 17 96 Dewey in The Bertrand Russell Case defended Russell against an attempt to remove Russell from his chair at the College of the City of New York in 1940 97 Neopragmatism as represented by Richard Rorty has been criticized as relativistic both by other neopragmatists such as Susan Haack 98 and by many analytic philosophers 99 Rorty s early analytic work however differs notably from his later work which some including Rorty consider to be closer to literary criticism than to philosophy and which attracts the brunt of criticism from his detractors List of pragmatists editClassical 1850 1950 edit Name Lifetime NotesCharles Sanders Peirce 1839 1914 was the founder of American pragmatism later called by Peirce pragmaticism He wrote on a wide range of topics from mathematical logic and semiotics to psychology William James 1842 1910 influential psychologist and theorist of religion as well as philosopher First to be widely associated with the term pragmatism due to Peirce s lifelong unpopularity John Dewey 1859 1952 prominent philosopher of education referred to his brand of pragmatism as instrumentalism Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr 1841 1935 U S Supreme Court Associate Justice F C S Schiller 1864 1937 one of the most important pragmatists of his time Schiller is largely forgotten today Protopragmatists or related thinkers Name Lifetime NotesGeorge Herbert Mead 1863 1931 philosopher and sociological social psychologist Josiah Royce 1855 1916 colleague of James at Harvard who employed pragmatism in an idealist metaphysical framework he was particularly interested in the philosophy of religion and community his work is often associated with neo Hegelianism George Santayana 1863 1952 although he eschewed the label pragmatism and called it a heresy several critics argue that he applied pragmatist methodologies to naturalism especially in his early masterwork The Life of Reason W E B Du Bois 1868 1963 student of James at Harvard who applied pragmatist principles to his sociological work especially in The Philadelphia Negro and Atlanta University Studies Other Name Lifetime NotesGiovanni Papini 1881 1956 Italian essayist mostly known because James occasionally mentioned him Giovanni Vailati 1863 1909 Italian analytic and pragmatist philosopher Hu Shih 1891 1962 Chinese intellectual and reformer student and translator of Dewey s and advocate of pragmatism in China Reinhold Niebuhr 1892 1971 American philosopher and theologian inserted pragmatism into his theory of Christian realism Analytic neo and other 1950 present edit Name Lifetime NotesRichard J Bernstein 1932 2022 Author of Beyond Objectivism and Relativism Science Hermeneutics and Praxis The New Constellation The Ethical Political Horizons of Modernity Postmodernity The Pragmatic TurnF Thomas Burke 1950 Author of What Pragmatism Was 2013 Dewey s New Logic 1994 His work interprets contemporary philosophy of mind philosophy of language and philosophical logic through the lens of classical American pragmatism Arthur Fine 1937 Philosopher of Science who proposed the Natural Ontological Attitude to the debate of scientific realism Stanley Fish 1938 Literary and Legal Studies pragmatist Criticizes Rorty s and Posner s legal theories as almost pragmatism 100 and authored the afterword in the collection The Revival of Pragmatism 101 Robert Brandom 1950 A student of Rorty has developed a complex analytic version of pragmatism in works such as Making It Explicit Between Saying and Doing and Perspectives on Pragmatism Clarence Irving Lewis 1883 1964 a leading authority on symbolic logic and on the philosophic concepts of knowledge and value Joseph Margolis 1924 2021 still proudly defends the original Pragmatists and sees his recent work on Cultural Realism as extending and deepening their insights especially the contribution of Peirce and Dewey in the context of a rapprochement with Continental philosophy Hilary Putnam 1926 2016 in many ways the opposite of Rorty and thinks classical pragmatism was too permissive a theory Richard Rorty 1931 2007 famous author of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature John J StuhrWillard van Orman Quine 1908 2000 pragmatist philosopher concerned with language logic and philosophy of mathematics Mike Sandbothe 1961 Applied Rorty s neopragmatism to media studies and developed a new branch that he called media philosophy Together with authors such as Juergen Habermas Hans Joas Sami Pihlstroem Mats Bergmann Michael Esfeld and Helmut Pape he belongs to a group of European pragmatists who make use of Peirce James Dewey Rorty Brandom Putnam and other representatives of American pragmatism in continental philosophy Richard Shusterman 1949 philosopher of art Jason Stanley 1969 Defends a pragmatist form of contextualism against semantic varieties of contextualism in his Knowledge and Practical Interest Robert B Talisse 1970 defends an epistemological conception of democratic politics that is explicitly opposed to Deweyan democracy and yet rooted in a conception of social epistemology that derives from the pragmatism of Charles Peirce His work in argumentation theory and informal logic also demonstrates pragmatist leanings Stephen Toulmin 1922 2009 student of Wittgenstein known especially for his The Uses of Argument Roberto Unger 1947 in The Self Awakened Pragmatism Unbound advocates for a radical pragmatism one that de naturalizes society and culture and thus insists that we can transform the character of our relation to social and cultural worlds we inhabit rather than just to change little by little the content of the arrangements and beliefs that comprise them Sidney Hook 1902 1989 a prominent New York intellectual and philosopher a student of Dewey at Columbia Isaac Levi 1930 2018 seeks to apply pragmatist thinking in a decision theoretic perspective Susan Haack 1945 teaches at the University of Miami sometimes called the intellectual granddaughter of C S Peirce known chiefly for foundherentism Nicholas Rescher 1928 advocates a methodological pragmatism that sees functional efficacy as evidentiating validity In the extended sense edit Name Lifetime NotesCornel West 1953 thinker on race politics and religion operates under the sign of prophetic pragmatism Wilfrid Sellars 1912 1989 broad thinker attacked mainstream variants of foundationalism in the analytic tradition Frank P Ramsey 1903 1930 author of the philosophical work Universals Karl Otto Apel 1922 2017 author of Charles S Peirce From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism 1981 Randolph Bourne 1886 1918 author of the 1917 pragmatist anti war essay Twilight of Idols C Wright Mills 1916 1962 author of Sociology and Pragmatism The Higher Learning in America and was a commentator on Dewey Jurgen Habermas 1929 author of What Is Universal Pragmatics See also editAmerican philosophy Activity corpus and tradition of philosophers affiliated with the United States Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography Communication Theory as a Field Russill pragmatism as an eighth tradition Doctrine of internal relations Philosophical doctrine that relations are internal to their bearers Morton White American philosopher and historian of ideas New legal realism Scientific method Pragmatic modelNotes edit See Dewey 1910 for a FAQ References edit a b c d Peirce C S 1878 How to Make Our Ideas Clear Popular Science Monthly v 12 286 302 Reprinted often including Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 388 410 and Essential Peirce v 1 124 141 See end of II for the pragmatic maxim See third and fourth paragraphs in IV for the discoverability of truth and the real by sufficient investigation Hookway Christopher August 16 2008 Pragmatism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2010 ed Susan Haack Robert Edwin Lane April 11 2006 Pragmatism old amp new selected writings Prometheus Books pp 18 67 ISBN 978 1 59102 359 3 a b Biesta G J J amp Burbules N 2003 Pragmatism and educational research Lanham MD Rowman and Littlefield Barnhart Concise Dictionary of Etymology James William 1898 Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results delivered before the Philosophical Union of the University of California at Berkeley August 26 1898 and first printed in the University Chronicle 1 September 1898 pp 287 310 Internet Archive Eprint On p 290 I refer to Mr Charles S Peirce with whose very existence as a philosopher I dare say many of you are unacquainted He is one of the most original of contemporary thinkers and the principle of practicalism or pragmatism as he called it when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early 1870s is the clue or compass by following which I find myself more and more confirmed in believing we may keep our feet upon the proper trail James credited Peirce again in 1906 lectures published in 1907 as Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking see Lecture 2 fourth paragraph James William 1896 The Will to Believe And Other Essays in Popular Philosophy Longmans Green ISBN 978 0 7905 7948 1 In addition to James s lectures and publications on pragmatist ideas Will to Believe 1897 etc wherein he credited Peirce James also arranged for two paid series of lectures by Peirce including the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism See pp 261 264 290 2 amp 324 in Brent Joseph 1998 Charles Sanders Peirce A Life 2nd edition Peirce C S The Founding of Pragmatism manuscript written 1906 published in The Hound amp Horn A Harvard Miscellany v II n 3 April June 1929 pp 282 285 see 283 284 reprinted 1934 as Historical Affinities and Genesis in Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 11 13 see 12 Shook John The Metaphysical Club pragmatism org Retrieved March 14 2023 Peirce C S 1877 The Fixation of Belief Popular Science Monthly v 12 pp 1 15 Reprited often including Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 358 387 and Essential Peirce v 1 pp 109 123 Peirce C S April 1905 What Pragmatism Is The Monist 15 2 161 181 see 165 166 doi 10 5840 monist190515230 Reprinted in Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 411 437 see 414 Manuscript A Sketch of Logical Critics Essential Peirce v 2 pp 451 462 see pp 457 458 Peirce wrote I have always fathered my pragmaticism as I have called it since James and Schiller made the word pragmatism imply the will to believe the mutability of truth the soundness of Zeno s refutation of motion and pluralism generally upon Kant Berkeley and Leibniz a b c Peirce C S 1908 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God Hibbert Journal 7 reprinted in Collected Papers v 6 paragraphs 452 85 and in Essential Peirce v 2 434 450 and elsewhere After discussing James Peirce stated Section V fourth paragraph as the specific occasion of his coinage pragmaticism journalist pragmatist and literary author Giovanni Papini s declaration of pragmatism s indefinability see for example Papini s What Is Pragmatism Like published in translation in October 1907 in Popular Science Monthly v 71 pp 351 358 a b Hildebrand David L 2003 Beyond realism and antirealism John Dewey and the neopragmatists The Vanderbilt library of American philosophy Nashville Vanderbilt University Press ISBN 082651426X OCLC 51053926 Peirce C S 1868 Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man Journal of Speculative Philosophy 2 2 103 114 JSTOR 25665643 Reprinted in Collected Peirce v 5 paragraphs 213 263 Writings v 2 pp 193 211 Essential Peirce v 2 pp 11 27 and elsewhere De Waal 2005 pp 7 10 Kasser Jeff Summer 1999 Peirce s Supposed Psychologism Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society 35 3 501 526 JSTOR 40320777 Peirce held that philosophical logic is a normative field that pragmatism is a method developed in it and that philosophy though not deductive or so general as mathematics still concerns positive phenomena in general including phenomena of matter and mind without depending on special experiences or experiments such as those of optics and experimental psychology in both of which Peirce was active See quotes under Philosophy at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce also harshly criticized the Cartesian approach of starting from hyperbolic doubts rather than from the combination of established beliefs and genuine doubts See the opening of his 1868 Some Consequences of Four Incapacities Journal of Speculative Philosophy v 2 n 3 pp 140 157 Reprinted Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 264 317 Writings v 2 pp 211 242 and Essential Peirce v 1 pp 28 55 Eprint Quine W V O 1969 Epistemology naturalized Ontological relativity and other essays The John Dewey essays in philosophy New York Columbia University Press pp 69 90 ISBN 0231033079 OCLC 51301 a b Putnam Hilary 1994 Pragmatism and moral objectivity Words and Life Cambridge MA Harvard University Press p 152 ISBN 9780674956063 OCLC 29218832 that one can be both fallibilistic and antiskeptical is perhaps the unique insight of American pragmatism a b Rescher Nicholas 2007 Pragmatism In Boundas Constantin V ed Edinburgh Companion to Twentieth Century Philosophies Edinburgh Edinburgh University Press p 137 ISBN 9780748620975 OCLC 85690580 a b Tiercelin Claudine October 14 2014 Why we should take a stand and the stand we should take The Pragmatists and the Human Logic of Truth Philosophie de la connaissance Paris College de France ISBN 978 2 7226 0339 4 Retrieved May 31 2022 McKinsey Michael 2018 Skepticism and Content Externalism In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved March 14 2023 Peirce C S 1902 The Carnegie Institute Application Memoir 10 MS L75 361 2 arisbe sitehost iu edu Retrieved April 4 2023 Peirce C S 1868 Some Consequences of Four Incapacities Journal of Speculative Philosophy 2 3 140 157 JSTOR 25665649 Google Books See opening pages Reprinted in Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 264 317 Writings v 2 pp 211 242 Essential Peirce v 1 pp 28 55 James 1907 p 200 James 1907 p 222 James 1907 p 90 James 1907 p 91 Sandra B Rosenthal C I Lewis in Focus The Pulse of Pragmatism Indiana University Press 2007 p 28 James 1907 pp 8 9 The Will to Believe James 1896 Edel 1993 Dewey 1930 Anderson SEP Dewey 2004 1910 ch 7 Dewey 1997 1938 p 47 Lekan 2003 Pragmatism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved March 14 2023 Unger Roberto 2007 The Self Awakened Pragmatism Unbound Harvard University Press pp 6 7 ISBN 978 0 674 03496 9 Nicholas Rescher Methodological Pragmatism Journal of Philosophy 76 6 338 342 1979 foreword for Dewey 1929 in the 1988 edition p xiii Lakoff and Johnson 1999 Simko Christina 2012 Rhetorics of Suffering American Sociological Review 77 6 880 902 doi 10 1177 0003122412458785 S2CID 145559039 Dromi Shai M Stabler Samuel D 2019 Good on paper sociological critique pragmatism and secularization theory Theory and Society 48 2 325 350 doi 10 1007 s11186 019 09341 9 S2CID 151250246 Cohen Andrew C Dromi Shai M February 15 2018 Advertising morality maintaining moral worth in a stigmatized profession Theory and Society 47 2 175 206 doi 10 1007 s11186 018 9309 7 S2CID 49319915 Shook John R Solymosi Tibor April 2013 Pragmatism key resources Choice 50 1367 1377 1367 Douglas Browning et al 1998 Rescher SEP Irven Donovan August 24 2020 The Pragmatic Truth of Existentialism Erraticus Retrieved March 14 2023 Patricia M Shields 2008 Rediscovering the Taproot Is Classical Pragmatism the Route to Renew Public Administration Public Administration Review 68 2 205 221 Ansell Christopher 2011 Pragmatist Democracy Evolutionary Learning as Public Philosophy New York Oxford University Press Weber Eric Thomas 2013 Democracy and Leadership On Pragmatism and Virtue New York Lexington Books Ralston Shane Ed 2013 Philosophical Pragmatism and International Relations Essays for a Bold New World New York Lexington Caspary William 2000 Dewey on Democracy Ithaca Cornell University Press Shields Patricia and Rangarjan N 2013 A Playbook for Research Methods Integrating Conceptual Frameworks and Project Management 1 Stillwater OK New Forums Press Shields relies primarily on Dewey s logic of Inquiry Stryker S 1980 Symbolic Interactionism A Social Structural Version Benjamin Cummings Publishing Nungesser Frithjof 2021 Pragmatism and Interaction In Routledge International Handbook of Interactionism edited by Dirk Vom Lehn Natalia Ruiz Junco and Will Gibson London New York Routledge 25 36 ISBN 9780367227708 Baert P 2004 Pragmatism as a philosophy of the social sciences European Journal of Social Theory 7 3 355 369 Cornish Flora Gillespie Alex 2009 A Pragmatist Approach to the Problem of Knowledge in Health Psychology Journal of Health Psychology 14 6 800 809 doi 10 1177 1359105309338974 hdl 1893 2453 ISSN 1359 1053 PMID 19687117 S2CID 467193 Patricia M Shields 2008 Rediscovering the Taproot Is Classical Pragmatism the Route to Renew Public Administration Public Administration Review 68 2 205 221 Hildebrand David L 2008 Public Administration as Pragmatic Democratic and Objective Public Administration Review 68 2 222 229 Shields Patricia 2003 The community of Inquiry Classical Pragmatism and Public Administration Administration amp Society 35 5 510 538 abstract Miller Hugh 2004 Why Old Pragmatism Needs an Upgrade Administration amp Society 36 2 234 249 Stolcis Gregory 2004 A view from the Trenches Comment on Miller s Why Old Pragmatism needs and upgrade Administration amp Society 36 3 326 369 Webb James Comment on Hugh T Miller s Why old Pragmatism needs and upgrade Administration amp Society 36 4 479 495 Hoch C 2006 What Can Rorty teach an old pragmatist doing public administration or planning Administration amp Society 38 3 389 398 abstract Evans Karen 2005 Upgrade or a different animal altogether Why Old Pragmatism Better Informs Public Management and New Pragmatism Misses the Point Administration amp Society 37 2 248 255 Snider Keith 2005 Rortyan Pragmatism Where s the beef for public administration Administration amp Society 37 2 243 247 Hildebrand David 2005 Pragmatism Neopragmatism and public administration Administration amp Society 37 3 360 374 abstract Hickman Larry 2004 On Hugh T Miller on Why old pragmatism needs an upgrade Administration amp Society 36 4 496 499 Miller Hugh 2005 Residues of foundationalism in Classical Pragmatism Administration amp Society 37 3 345 359 Patricia M Shields 2004 Classical Pragmatism Engaging practitioner experience Administration amp Society 36 3 351 361 Patricia M Shields 2005 Classical Pragmatism does not need an upgrade Lessons for Public Administration Administration amp Society 37 4 504 518 abstract Perez Shivaun Assessing Service Learning Using Pragmatic Principles of Education A Texas Charter School Case Study 2000 Applied Research Projects Texas State University Paper 76 http ecommons txstate edu arp 76 Alexander Jason Fields Contracting Through the Lens of Classical Pragmatism An Exploration of Local Government Contracting 2009 Applied Research Projects Texas State University Paper 288 http ecommons txstate edu arp 288 Bartle John R and Shields Patricia M Applying Pragmatism to Public Budgeting and Financial Management 2008 Faculty Publications Political Science Paper 48 http ecommons txstate edu polsfacp 48 Wilson Timothy L Pragmatism and Performance Measurement An Exploration of Practices in Texas State Government 2001 Applied Research Projects Texas State University Paper 71 http ecommons txstate edu arp 71 Howard Watkins Demetria C The Austin Texas African American Quality of Life Initiative as a Community of inquiry An Exploratory Study 2006 Applied Research Projects Texas State University Paper 115 http ecommons txstate edu arp 115 Johnson Timothy Lee The Downtown Austin Planning Process as a Community of inquiry An Exploratory Study 2008 Applied Research Projects Paper 276 http ecommons txstate edu arp 276 Patricia M Shields and Hassan Tajalli 2006 Intermediate Theory The Missing Link in Successful Student Scholarship Journal of Public Affairs Education 12 3 313 334 https digital library txstate edu handle 10877 3967 Patricia M Shields 1998 Pragmatism as a Philosophy of Science A Tool for Public Administration Research in Public Administration Volume 4 195 225 Online Patricia M Shields and Nandhini Rangarajan 2013 A Playbook for Research Methods Integrating Conceptual Frameworks and Project Management Stillwater OK New Forums Press Cornish Flora Gillespie Alex 2009 A Pragmatist Approach to the Problem of Knowledge in Health Psychology Journal of Health Psychology 14 6 800 809 doi 10 1177 1359105309338974 hdl 1893 2453 ISSN 1359 1053 PMID 19687117 S2CID 467193 Brendel David 2006 Healing Psychiatry Bridging the Science Humanism Divide Cambridge MA MIT Press Seigfried C H 2001 Feminist interpretations of John Dewey University Park Pennsylvania State University Press Seigfried C H 1996 Pragmatism and feminism Reweaving the social fabric Chicago The University of Chicago Press Seigfried C H 1992 Where are all the pragmatists feminists Hypatia 6 8 21 Duran J 2001 A holistically Deweyan feminism Metaphilosophy 32 279 292 Duran J 1993 The intersection of pragmatism and feminism Hypatia 8 Keith H 1999 Feminism and pragmatism George Herbert Mead s ethics of care Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society 35 328 344 Whipps J D 2004 Jane Addams social thought as a model for a pragmatist feminist communitarianism Hypatia 19 118 113 Seigfried C H 1996 Pragmatism and Feminism Reweaving the Social Fabric Chicago The University of Chicago Press p 21 Ansell Chris 2009 Mary Parker Follett and Pragmatist Organization In Adler Paul ed The Oxford Handbook of Sociology and Organization Studies Classical Foundations Oxford University Press pp 464 485 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199535231 003 0021 ISBN 978 0199535231 Graham ed 1995 Mary Parker Follett Prophet of Management A Celebration of Writings from the 1920s Cambridge MA Harvard Business Press a b Lovejoy Arthur O January 2 1908 The thirteen pragmatisms I The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods 5 1 5 12 doi 10 2307 2012277 JSTOR 2012277 And Lovejoy Arthur O January 16 1908 The thirteen pragmatisms II The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods 5 2 29 39 doi 10 2307 2011563 JSTOR 2011563 a b c Bittle Celestine Nicholas Charles 1936 Reality and the Mind Epistemology New York The Bruce Publishing Company OCLC 1017084 a b c d Putnam Hilary December 1992 The permanence of William James Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 46 3 17 31 doi 10 2307 3824783 JSTOR 3824783 a b Burke F Thomas 1994 Dewey s new logic a reply to Russell Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 0226080692 OCLC 29844394 Goodman Russell October 20 2017 William James In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2017 ed Edwards Paul 1957 How Bertrand Russell was prevented from teaching at the College of the City of New York In Russell Bertrand ed Why I am not a Christian and other essays on religion and related subjects New York Simon and Schuster pp 207 259 ISBN 0671203231 OCLC 376363 Haack 1997 Dennett 1998 In Stanley Fish There s No Such Thing as Free Speech Oxford University Press 1994 Ed Morris Dickstein Duke University Press 1998Sources editBaldwin James Mark ed 1901 1905 Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology 3 volumes in 4 Macmillan New York NY Dewey John 1900 1901 Lectures on Ethics 1900 1901 Donald F Koch ed Southern Illinois University Press Carbondale and Edwardsville IL 1991 Dewey John 1910 How We Think D C Heath Lexington MA 1910 Reprinted Prometheus Books Buffalo NY 1991 Dewey John 1929 The Quest for Certainty A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action Minton Balch and Company New York NY Reprinted pp 1 254 in John Dewey The Later Works 1925 1953 Volume 4 1929 Jo Ann Boydston ed Harriet Furst Simon text ed Stephen Toulmin intro Southern Illinois University Press Carbondale and Edwardsville IL 1984 Dewey John 1932 Theory of the Moral Life Part 2 of John Dewey and James H Tufts Ethics Henry Holt and Company New York NY 1908 2nd edition Holt Rinehart and Winston 1932 Reprinted Arnold Isenberg ed Victor Kestenbaum pref Irvington Publishers New York NY 1980 Dewey John 1938 Logic The Theory of Inquiry Henry Holt and Company New York NY 1938 Reprinted pp 1 527 in John Dewey The Later Works 1925 1953 Volume 12 1938 Jo Ann Boydston ed Kathleen Poulos text ed Ernest Nagel intro Southern Illinois University Press Carbondale and Edwardsville IL 1986 James William 1902 Pragmatic and Pragmatism 1 paragraph vol 2 pp 321 322 in J M Baldwin ed 1901 1905 Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology 3 volumes in 4 Macmillan New York NY Reprinted CP 5 2 in C S Peirce Collected Papers James William 1907 Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking Popular Lectures on Philosophy Longmans Green and Company New York NY James William 1909 The Meaning of Truth A Sequel to Pragmatism Longmans Green and Company New York NY Lundin Roger 2006 From Nature to Experience The American Search for Cultural Authority Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers Inc Peirce C S Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce vols 1 6 Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds vols 7 8 Arthur W Burks ed Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1931 1935 1958 Cited as CP vol para Peirce C S The Essential Peirce Selected Philosophical Writings Volume 1 1867 1893 Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel eds Indiana University Press Bloomington and Indianapolis IN 1992 Peirce C S The Essential Peirce Selected Philosophical Writings Volume 2 1893 1913 Peirce Edition Project eds Indiana University Press Bloomington and Indianapolis IN 1998 Putnam Hilary 1994 Words and Life James Conant ed Harvard University Press Cambridge MA Quine W V 1951 Two Dogmas of Empiricism Philosophical Review January 1951 Reprinted pp 20 46 in W V Quine From a Logical Point of View 1980 Quine W V 1980 From a Logical Point of View Logico Philosophical Essays 2nd edition Harvard University Press Cambridge MA 1980 Ramsey F P 1927 Facts and Propositions Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7 153 170 Reprinted pp 34 51 in F P Ramsey Philosophical Papers David Hugh Mellor ed Cambridge University Press Cambridge UK 1990 Ramsey F P 1990 Philosophical Papers David Hugh Mellor ed Cambridge University Press Cambridge UK Rescher N 1977 Methodological Pragmatism Oxford Blackwell 1977 Rescher N 2000 Realistic Pragmatism Albany SUNY Press 2000 Further reading editSurveysJohn J Stuhr ed One Hundred Years of Pragmatism William James s Revolutionary Philosophy Indiana University Press 2010 215 pages Essays on pragmatism and American culture pragmatism as a way of thinking and settling disputes pragmatism as a theory of truth and pragmatism as a mood attitude or temperament Primary texts Note that this is an introductory list some important works are left out and some less monumental works that are excellent introductions are included C S Peirce The Fixation of Belief paper C S Peirce How to Make Our Ideas Clear paper C S Peirce A Definition of Pragmatism paper as titled by Menand in Pragmatism A Reader from Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 8 some or all of paragraphs 191 195 William James Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking especially lectures I II and VI John Dewey Reconstruction in Philosophy John Dewey Three Independent factors in Morals lecture published as paper John Dewey A short catechism concerning truth chapter W V O Quine Two Dogmas of Empiricism paper Secondary textsCornelis De Waal On Pragmatism Louis Menand The Metaphysical Club A Story of Ideas in America Hilary Putnam Pragmatism An Open Question Abraham Edel Pragmatic Tests and Ethical Insights D S Clarke Rational Acceptance and Purpose Haack Susan amp Lane Robert Eds 2006 Pragmatism Old and New Selected Writings New York Prometheus Books Louis Menand ed Pragmatism A Reader includes essays by Peirce James Dewey Rorty others For a discussion of the ways in which pragmatism offers insights into the theory and practice of urbanism see Aseem Inam Designing Urban Transformation New York and London Routledge 2013 ISBN 978 0415837705 CriticismEdward W Younkins Dewey s Pragmatism and the Decline of Education Pragmatism Ayn Rand Lexicon Albert Schinz Anti Pragmatism An Examination into the Respective Rights of Intellectual Aristocracy and Social Democracy Boston Small Maynard and Company 1909 External links edit nbsp Look up pragmatism in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Pragmatism nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Pragmatism General sourcesPragmatism at PhilPapers Zalta Edward N ed Pragmatism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Pragmatism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Pragmatism at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Pragmatism on In Our Time at the BBC A short film about the pragmatist revival on YouTubeJournals and organizationsThere are several peer reviewed journals dedicated to pragmatism for example Contemporary Pragmatism affiliated with the International Pragmatism Society European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy affiliated with the Associazione Culturale Pragma Italy Nordic Studies in Pragmatism journal of the Nordic Pragmatism Network Pragmatism Today journal of the Central European Pragmatist Forum CEPF Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society journal of the Charles S Peirce Society William James Studies journal of the William James Society Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Pragmatism amp oldid 1187392877, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.