fbpx
Wikipedia

Yogachara

Yogachara (Sanskrit: योगाचार, IAST: Yogācāra) is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of cognition, perception, and consciousness through the interior lens of meditation, as well as philosophical reasoning (hetuvidyā).[1][2] Yogachara was one of the two most influential traditions of Mahayana Buddhism in India, along with Madhyamaka.[3]

Translations of
Yogacāra school
EnglishYoga Practice, Doctrine of Consciousness, Consciousness-Only Doctrine, Cognizance-Only, Mind-Only
SanskritYogacāra, Vijñānavāda, Vijñaptivāda, Vijñaptimātratā, Cittamātra
Chinese唯識瑜伽行派
(Pinyin: Wéishí Yúqiexíng Pài)
Japanese瑜伽行唯識派
(Rōmaji: Yugagyō Yuishiki Ha)
Korean유식유가행파
(RR: Yusik-Yugahaeng-pa)
Tibetanརྣལ་འབྱོར་སྤྱོད་པ་
(rnal 'byor spyod pa)
VietnameseDu-già Hành Tông
Glossary of Buddhism

The compound Yogācāra literally means "practitioner of yoga", or "one whose practice is yoga", hence the name of the school is literally "the school of the yogins".[4][3] Yogācāra was also variously termed Vijñānavāda (the doctrine of consciousness), Vijñaptivāda (the doctrine of ideas or percepts) or Vijñaptimātratā-vāda (the doctrine of 'mere representation'), which is also the name given to its major theory of mind which seeks to deconstruct how we perceive the world. There are several interpretations of this main theory: various forms of Idealism, as well as a phenomenology or representationalism. Aside from this, Yogācāra also developed an elaborate analysis of consciousness (vijñana) and mental phenomena (dharmas), as well as an extensive system of Buddhist spiritual practice, i.e. yoga.[1]

The movement has been traced to the first centuries of the common era and seems to have developed as some yogis of the Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika traditions in north India adopted Mahayana Buddhism.[5][6] The Gandhāran brothers Asaṅga and Vasubandhu (both c. 4-5th century CE), are considered the classic philosophers and systematizers of this school, along with the figure of Maitreya.[7] Yogācāra was later imported to Tibet and East Asia by figures like Shantaraksita (8th century) and Xuanzang (7th-century). Today, Yogācāra ideas and texts continue to be influential subjects of study for Tibetan Buddhism and East Asian Buddhism.

Doctrine edit

Yogācāra philosophy is primarily meant to aid in the practice of yoga and meditation and thus it also sets forth a systematic analysis of the Mahayana path of mental training (see five paths pañcamārga).[8] Yogācārins made use of ideas from previous traditions, such as Prajñāpāramitā and the Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma tradition, to develop a novel analysis of conscious experience and a corresponding schema for Mahāyāna spiritual practice.[9][10][11] In its analysis, Yogācāra works like the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra developing various core concepts such as vijñapti-mātra, the ālaya-vijñāna (store consciousness), the turning of the basis (āśraya-parāvṛtti), the three natures (trisvabhāva), and emptiness.[1] They form a complex system, and each can be taken as a point of departure for understanding Yogācāra.[12]

The doctrine of vijñapti-mātra edit

One of the main features of Yogācāra philosophy is the concept of vijñapti-mātra. It is often used interchangeably with the term citta-mātra in modern and ancient Yogacara sources.[7][13][14] The standard translation of both terms is "consciousness-only" or "mind-only." Several modern researchers object to this translation in favor of alternative like representation-only.[10] The meaning of this term is at the heart of the modern scholarly disagreement about whether Yogacara Buddhism can be said to be a form of idealism (as supported by Garfield, Hopkins, and others) or whether it is definitely not idealist (Anacker, Lusthaus, Wayman).[15]

Origins edit

According to Lambert Schmithausen, the earliest surviving appearance of this term is in chapter 8 of the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra, which has only survived in Tibetan and Chinese translations that differ in syntax and meaning.[16] The passage is depicted as a response by the Buddha to a question which asks "whether the images or replicas (*pratibimba) which are the object (*gocara) of meditative concentration (*samadhi), are different/separate (*bhinna) from the contemplating mind (*citta) or not." The Buddha says they are not different, "Because these images are vijñapti-mātra." The text goes on to affirm that the same is true for objects of ordinary perception.[17]

The term is sometimes used as a synonym with citta-mātra (mere citta), which is also used as a name for the school that suggests Idealism.[7][13] Schmithausen writes that the first appearance of this term is in the Pratyupanna samadhi sutra, which states "this (or: whatever belongs to this) triple world is nothing but mind (or thought: *cittamatra). Why? Because however I imagine things, that is how they appear."[18]

Regarding existing Sanskrit sources, the term appears in the first verse of Vasubandhu's Vimśatikā (Twenty Verses), which states:[19]

This [world] is vijñaptimātra, since it manifests itself as an unreal object (artha), just like the case of those with cataracts seeing unreal hairs in the moon and the like (vijñaptimātram evaitad asad arthāvabhāsanāt yathā taimirikasyāsat keśa candrādi darśanam).

According to Mark Siderits, what Vasubandhu means here is that we are only ever aware of mental images or impressions which manifest themselves as external objects, but "there is actually no such thing outside the mind."[19]

The term also appears in Asaṅga's classic work, the Mahāyānasaṃgraha (no Sanskrit original, trans. from Tibetan):

These representations (vijñapti) are mere representations (vijñapti-mātra), because there is no [corresponding] thing/object (artha)...Just as in a dream there appear, even without a thing/object (artha), just in the mind alone, forms/images of all kinds of things/objects like visibles, sounds, smells, tastes, tangibles, houses, forests, land, and mountains, and yet there are no [such] things/objects at all in that [place]. MSg II.6[20]

Another classic statement of the doctrine appears in Dharmakīrti's Pramānaṿārttika (Commentary on Epistemology) which states: "cognition experiences itself, and nothing else whatsoever. Even the particular objects of perception, are by nature just consciousness itself."[21]

Interpretations of vijñapti-mātra edit

Idealism edit

According to Bruce Cameron Hall, the interpretation of this doctrine as a form of subjective or absolute idealism has been "the most common "outside" interpretation of Vijñānavāda, not only by modern writers, but by its ancient opponents, both Hindu and Buddhist."[22] Scholars such as Jay Garfield, Saam Trivedi, Nobuyoshi Yamabe, Paul Williams, and Sean Butler argue that Yogācāra is similar to Idealism (and they compare it to the idealisms of Kant and Berkeley), though they note that it is its own unique form and that it might be confusing to categorize it as such.[23][24][25][26][27]

The German scholar and philologist Lambert Schmithausen affirms that Yogacara sources teach a type of idealism which is supposed to be a middle way between Abhidharma realism and what it often considered a nihilistic position which only affirms emptiness as the ultimate.[28] Schmithausen notes that philological study of Yogacara texts shows that they clearly reject the independent existence of mind and the external world.[29] He also notes that the current trend in rejecting the idealistic interpretation might be related to the unpopularity of idealism among Western academics.[29] Florin Delenau likewise affirms the idealist nature of Yogācāra texts, while also underscoring how Yogācāra retains a strong orientation to a soteriology which aims at contemplative realization of an ultimate reality that is an ‘inexpressible essence’ (nirabhilāpyasvabhāva) beyond any subject-object duality.[3]

Similarly, Jonathan Gold writes that the Yogācāra thinker Vasubandhu can be said to be an idealist (similar to Kant), in the sense that for him, everything in experience as well as its causal support is mental, and thus he gives causal priority to the mental. At the same time however, this is only in the conventional realm, since "mind" is just another concept and true reality for Vasubandhu is ineffable, "an inconceivable 'thusness' (tathatā)." Indeed, the Vimśatikā states that the very idea of vijñapti-mātra must also be understood to be itself a self-less construction and thus vijñapti-mātra is not the ultimate truth (paramārtha-satya) in Yogācāra.[13] Thus according to Gold, while Vasubandhu's vijñapti-mātra can be said to be a “conventionalist idealism”, it is to be seen as unique and different from Western forms, especially Hegelian Absolute Idealism.[13]

Mere representation edit

The interpretation of Yogācāra as a type of idealism was standard until recently, when it began to be challenged by scholars such as Kochumuttom, Anacker, Kalupahana,[30] Dunne, Lusthaus,[31] Powers, and Wayman.[32][a]

Some scholars like David Kalupahana argue that it is a mistake to conflate the terms citta-mātra (which is sometimes seen as a different, more metaphysical position) with vijñapti-mātra (which need not be idealist).[10][33] However, Delenau points out that Vasubandhu clearly states in his Twenty Verses and Abhidharmakosha that vijñapti and citta are synonymous.[34] Nevertheless, different alternative translations for vijñapti-mātra have been proposed, such as representation-only, ideation-only, impressions-only and perception-only.[22][35][36][7]

Alex Wayman notes that one's interpretation of Yogācāra will depend on how the qualifier mātra is to be understood in this context, and he objects to interpretations which claim that Yogācāra rejects the external world altogether, preferring translations such as "amounting to mind" or "mirroring mind" for citta-mātra.[36] For Wayman, what this doctrine means is that "the mind has only a report or representation of what the sense organ had sensed."[36] The representationalist interpretation is also supported by Stefan Anacker.[37]

According to Thomas Kochumuttom, Yogācāra is a realistic pluralism which does not deny the existence of individual beings.[10] Kochumuttom argues that Yogācāra is not idealism since it denies that absolute reality is a consciousness, that individual beings are transformations or illusory appearances of an absolute consciousness.[38] Thus, for Kochumuttom, vijñapti-mātra means "mere representation of consciousness," a view which states "that the world as it appears to the unenlightened ones is mere representation of consciousness".[35] Furthermore, according to Kochumuttom, in Yogācāra "the absolute state is defined simply as emptiness, namely the emptiness of subject-object distinction. Once thus defined as emptiness (sunyata), it receives a number of synonyms, none of which betray idealism."[39]

Soterological phenomenology edit

According to Dan Lusthaus, the vijñapti-mātra theory is closer in some ways to Western Phenomenological theories and Epistemological Idealism. However, it is not a form of metaphysical idealism because Yogācāra rejects the construction of any type of metaphysical or ontological theories.[1] Moreover, Western idealism lacks any counterpart to karma, samsara or awakening, all of which are central for Yogācāra. Regarding vijñapti-mātra, Lusthaus translates it as "nothing but conscious construction" and states it is a kind of trick built into consciousness which "projects and constructs a cognitive object in such a way that it disowns its own creation - pretending the object is "out there" - in order to render that object capable of being appropriated." This reification of cognition aids in constructing the notion of a permanent and independent self, which is believed to appropriate and possess external 'things'. Yogācāra offers an analysis and meditative means to negate this reification, thereby also negating the notion of a solid self. According to Lusthaus, this analysis is not a rejection of external phenomena, and it does not grant foundational or transcendent status to consciousness.[1] In this interpretation, instead of offering an ontological theory, Yogācāra focuses on understanding and eliminating the underlying tendencies (anuśaya) that lead to clinging concepts and theories, which are just cognitive projections (pratibimba, parikalpita). Thus, for Lusthaus, the orientation of the Yogācāra school is largely consistent with the thinking of the Pāli nikāyas and seeks to realign Mahayana with early Buddhist theory.[40]

Arguments for consciousness-only edit

According to the contemporary philosopher Jan Westerhoff, Yogācāra philosophers came up with various arguments in defense of the consciousness-only view. He outlines three main arguments: the explanatory equivalence argument, the causation-resemblance argument, and the constant co-cognition argument.[41]

Explanatory equivalence argument edit

This argument is found in Vasubandhu's Vimśatikā (Twenty Verses) and is an inference to the best explanation. It argues that consciousness-only can provide an account of the various features of experience which are explained by the existence of mind-independent material objects. This is coupled with a principle of ontological parsimony to argue in favor of idealism.[41]

Vasubandhu mentions three key features of experience which are supposed to be explained by matter and refutes them:[42][43][44]

  1. According to critics, the problem of spatio-temporal determination (or non-arbitrariness in regard to place and time) indicates that there must be some external basis for our experiences, since experiences of any particular object do not occur everywhere and at every time. Vasubandhu responds with the dream argument, which shows how a world created by mind can still seem to have spatio-temporal localization.
  2. The problem of inter-subjective experience (multiple minds experiencing the same world). Vasubandhu counters that mass hallucinations (such as those said to occur to hungry ghosts) caused by the fact they share similar karma (which is here understood as traces or seeds in the mind-stream), show that inter-subjective agreement is possible without positing real external objects.
  3. Another criticism states that hallucinations have no pragmatic results, efficacy or causal function and thus can be determined to be unreal, but entities we generally accept as being "real" have actual causal results (such as the 'resistance' of external objects) that cannot be of the same class as hallucinations. Against this claim, Vasubandhu argues that waking life is the same as in a dream, where objects have pragmatic results within the very rules of the dream. He also uses the example of a wet dream to show that mental content can have causal efficacy even outside of a dream.

According to Mark Siderits, after disposing of these objections, Vasubandhu believes he has shown that mere cognizance is just as good at explaining the relevant phenomena of experience as any theory of realism that posits external objects. Therefore, he then applies the Indian philosophical principle termed the "Principle of Lightness" (Sanskrit: lāghava, which is similar to Occam's Razor) to rule out realism since vijñapti-mātra is the simpler and "lighter" theory which "posits the least number of unobservable entities."[45]

Another objection that Vasubandhu answers is that of how one person can influence another's experiences, if everything arises from mental karmic seeds in one's mind stream. Vasubandhu argues that "impressions can also be caused in a mental stream by the occurrence of a distinct impression in another suitably linked mental stream."[46] As Siderits notes, this account can explain how it is possible to influence or even totally disrupt (murder) another mind, even if there is no physical medium or object in existence, since a suitably strong enough intention in one mind stream can have effects on another mind stream.[46] From the mind-only position, it is easier to posit a mind to mind causation than to have to explain mind to body causation, which the realist must do. However, Siderits then goes on to question whether Vasubandhu's position is indeed "lighter" since he must make use of multiple interactions between different minds to take into account an intentionally created artifact, like a pot. Since we can be aware of a pot even when we are not "linked" to the potter's intentions (even after the potter is dead), a more complex series of mental interactions must be posited.[47] Nevertheless, not all interpretations of Yogācāra's view of the external world rely on multiple relations between individual minds. Some interpretations in Chinese Buddhism defended the view of a single shared external world (bhājanaloka) which was still made of consciousness, while some later Indian thinkers like Ratnakīrti (11th century CE) defended a type of non-dual monism.[48][49]

Causation-resemblance argument edit

This argument was famously defended in Dignāga's Ālambanaparīkṣā (Examination of the Object of Consciousness) and its main target is Indian atomism, which was the main theory of matter in the 5th century.[50] The argument is based on the premise that a perception must resemble the perceived object (ālambana) and have been caused by the object.[50][41] According to this argument, since atoms are not extended, they do not resemble the object of perception (which appears as spatially extended). Furthermore, collections of atoms might resemble the object of perception, but they cannot have caused it. This is because collections of things are unreal in classic Buddhist thought (thus it is a mereological nihilism), since they are composites and composites made of parts do not have any causal efficacy (only individual atoms do).[50][41]

In disproving the possibility of external objects, Vasubandhu's Vimśatikā similarly attacks Indian theories of atomism and property particulars as incoherent on mereological grounds.[51]

Constant co-cognition argument edit

This argument was defended by Dharmakīrti in his Ascertainment of Epistemology (Pramāṇaviniścaya), which calls it "the necessity of things only ever being experienced together with experience" (Sanskrit: sahopalambhaniyama).[50] According to Dharmakīrti:

Because [something blue] is not apprehended without the additional qualification of consciousness, [and] because [blue] is apprehended when this [qualification of consciousness] is apprehended, consciousness [itself] has the appearance of blue. There is no external object by itself. (PV 3.335)[50]

According this argument, any object of consciousness, like blue, cannot be differentiated from the conscious awareness of blue since both are always experienced as one thing. Since we never experience blue without the experience of blue, they cannot be differentiated empirically. Furthermore, we cannot differentiate them through an inference either, since this would need to be based on a pattern of past experiences which included the absence or presence of the two elements.[50][41] Thus, this is a type of epistemological argument for idealism which attempts to show there is no good reason to accept the existence of mind-independent objects.[50]

Soteriological importance of mind-only edit

Vasubandhu also explains why it is soteriologically important to get rid of the idea of really existing external objects. According to Siderits, this is because:

When we wrongly imagine there to be external objects we are led to think in terms of the duality of 'grasped and grasper', of what is 'out there' and what is ' in here' - in short, of external world and self. Coming to see that there is no external world is a means, Vasubandhu thinks, of overcoming a very subtle way of believing in an 'I'... once we see why physical objects can't exist we will lose all temptation to think there is a true ' me' within. There are really just impressions, but we superimpose on these the false constructions of object and subject. Seeing this will free us from the false conception of an 'I'.[52]

Siderits notes how Kant had a similar notion, that is, without the idea of an objective mind independent world, one cannot derive the concept of a subjective "I". But Kant drew the opposite conclusion to Vasubandhu, since he held that we must believe in an enduring subject, and thus, also believe in external objects.[52]

Analysis of Consciousness edit

Yogācāra gives a detailed explanation of the workings of the mind and the way it constructs the reality we experience. The central Yogācāra theory of mind is that of the eight consciousnesses.

Eight consciousnesses edit

A key innovation of the Yogācāra school was the doctrine of eight consciousnesses.[1] These "eight bodies of consciousnesses" (aṣṭa vijñānakāyāḥ) are: the five sense-consciousnesses (of seeing, hearing, smelling, tasting and bodily sense), mentation (mano or citta), the defiled self-consciousness (kliṣṭamanovijñāna),[53] and the storehouse or substratum consciousness (Skt: ālayavijñāna).[54][55] Traditional Buddhist descriptions of consciousness taught just the first six vijñānas, each corresponding to a sense base (ayatana) and having their own sense objects (sounds etc). Five are based on the five senses, while the sixth (mano-vijñāna), was seen as the surveyor of the content of the five senses as well as of mental content like thoughts and ideas. Standard Buddhist doctrine held that these eighteen "elements" (dhatus), i.e. six external sense bases (smells, sounds etc.), six internal bases (sense organs like the eye, ear, etc.), and six consciousnesses "exhaust the full extent of everything in the universe, or more accurately, the sensorium."[1] The six consciousnesses are also not substantial entities, but a series or stream of events (dharmas), which arise and vanish very rapidly moment by moment. This is the Abhidharma doctrine of "momentariness" (kṣaṇavada), which Yogācāra also accepts.[56]

Yogācāra expanded the six vijñāna schema into a new system which with two new categories. The seventh consciousness developed from the early Buddhist concept of manas, and was seen as the defiled mentation (kliṣṭa-manas) which is obsessed with notions of "self". According to Paul Williams, this consciousness "takes the substratum consciousness as its object and mistakenly considers the substratum consciousness to be a true Self."[55]

Ālaya-vijñāna edit

The eighth consciousness, ālaya-vijñāna (storehouse or repository consciousness), was defined as the storehouse of all karmic seeds (bīja), where they gradually matured until ripe, at which point they manifested as karmic consequences. Because of this, it is also called the "mind which has all the seeds" (sarvabījakam cittam), as well as the "basis consciousness" (mūla-vijñāna) and the "appropriating consciousness" (ādānavijñāna). According to the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra, this kind of consciousness underlies and supports the six types of manifest awareness, all of which occur simultaneously with the ālaya.[57] William S. Waldron sees this "simultaneity of all the modes of cognitive awareness" as the most significant departure of Yogācāra theory from traditional Buddhist models of vijñāna, which were "thought to occur solely in conjunction with their respective sense bases and epistemic objects".[58]

As noted by Schmithausen, the ālaya-vijñāna, being a kind of vijñāna, has an object as well (as all vijñāna has intentionality). That object is the sentient being's surrounding world, that is to say, the "receptable" or "container" (bhājana) world. This is stated in the 8th chapter of the Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra, which states that the ādānavijñāna is characterized by "an unconscious (or not fully conscious?) steady perception (or "representation") of the Receptacle (*asaṃvidita-sthira-bhājana-vijñapti)."[59]

The ālaya-vijñāna is also what experiences rebirth into future lives and what descents into the womb to appropriate the fetal material. Therefore, the ālaya-vijñāna's holding on to the body's sense faculties and "profuse imaginings" (prapañca) are the two appropriations which make up the "kindling" or "fuel" (lit. upādāna) that samsaric existence depends upon.[57] Yogācāra thought thus holds that being unaware of the processes going on in the ālaya-vijñāna is an important element of ignorance (avidya). The ālaya is also individual, so that each person has their own ālaya-vijñāna, which is an ever changing process and therefore not a permanent self.[1]

According to Williams, this consciousness "seen as a defiled form of consciousness (or perhaps sub- or unconsciousness), is personal, individual, continually changing and yet serving to give a degree of personal identity and to explain why it is that certain karmic results pertain to this particular individual. The seeds are momentary, but they give rise to a perfumed series which eventually culminates in the result including, from seeds of a particular type, the whole ‘inter-subjective’ phenomenal world."[60] Also, Asanga and Vasubandhu write that the ālaya-vijñāna ‘ceases’ at awakening, becoming transformed into a pure consciousness.[61]

According to Waldron, while there were various similar concepts in other Buddhist Abhidharma schools which sought to explain karmic continuity, the ālaya-vijñāna is the most comprehensive and systematic.[62] Waldron notes that the ālaya-vijñāna concept was probably influenced by these theories, particularly the Sautrantika theory of seeds and Vasumitra's theory of a subtle form of mind (suksma-citta).[63]

Transformations of consciousness edit

Yogācāra sources do not necessarily describe the eight consciousnesses as absolutely separate or substantial phenomena. For example, Kalupahana notes that the Triṃśika describes the various forms of consciousness as transformations and functions of a being's stream of consciousness.[64][65][b] These transformations are threefold according to Kalupahana. The first is the ālaya and its seeds, which is the flow or stream of consciousness, without any of the usual projections on top of it.[65] The second transformation is manana, self-consciousness or "Self-view, self-confusion, self-esteem and self-love".[66] It is "thinking" about the various perceptions occurring in the stream of consciousness".[67] The ālaya is defiled by this self-interest.[66] The third transformation is visaya-vijñapti, the "concept of the object".[68] In this transformation the concept of objects is created. By creating these concepts human beings become "susceptible to grasping after the object" as if it were a real object (sad artha) even though it is just a conception (vijñapti).[68]

A similar perspective which emphasizes Yogācāra's continuity with early Buddhism is given by Walpola Rahula. According to Rahula, all the elements of this theory of consciousness with its three layers of vijñāna are already found in the Pāli Canon, corresponding to the terms viññāna (sense cognition), manas (mental function, thinking, reasoning, conception) and citta (the deepest layer of the aggregate of consciousness which retains karmic impressions and the defilements).[69][70]

The Three Natures edit

Yogācāra works often define three basic modes or "natures" (svabhāva) of experience. Jonathan Gold explains that "the three natures are all one reality viewed from three distinct angles. They are the appearance, the process, and the emptiness of that same apparent entity."[13] According to Paul Williams, "all things which can be known can be subsumed under these Three Natures."[71] Since this schema is Yogācāra's systematic explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of emptiness (śūnyatā), each of the three natures are also explained as having a lack of own-nature (niḥsvabhāvatā).[72][73] The Trisvabhāva-nirdeśa (Exposition of the Three Natures) gives a brief definition of these three natures:

What appears is the dependent. How it appears is the fabricated. Because of being dependent on conditions. Because of being only fabrication. The eternal non-existence of the appearance as it is appears: That is known to be the perfected nature, because of being always the same. What appears there? The unreal fabrication. How does it appear? As a dual self. What is its nonexistence? That by which the nondual reality is there.[13]

In detail, three natures (trisvabhāva) are:[71][74][75][13]

  1. Parikalpita-svabhāva (the "fully conceptualized" or "imagined" nature). This is the "imaginary" or "constructed" nature, wherein things are incorrectly comprehended based on conceptual construction, through the activity of language and through attachment and erroneous discrimination which attributes intrinsic existence to things. According to the Mahāyānasaṃgraha, it also refers to the appearance of things in terms of subject-object dualism (literally "grasper" and "grasped"). The conceptualized nature is the world of everyday unenlightened people, i.e. samsara. It is false and empty, and does not really exist (Triṃśikā v. 20). According to Xuanzang's Cheng Weishi Lun, this nature is an "absence of an existential nature by its very defining characteristic" (lakṣana-niḥsvabhāvatā). Because these conceptualized natures and distinct characteristics (lakṣana) are wrongly imputed and not truly real, "they are like mirages and blossoms in the sky."
  2. Paratantra-svabhāva (literally, "other dependent"), which is the dependently originated nature of dharmas, or the causal flow of phenomena which is erroneously confused into the conceptualized nature. According to Williams, it is "the basis for the erroneous partition into supposedly intrinsically existing subjects and objects which marks the conceptualized nature." Jonathan Gold writes that it is "the causal process of the thing's fabrication, the causal story that brings about the thing's apparent nature." This basis is considered to be an ultimately existing (paramārtha) basis in classical Yogācāra (see Mahāyānasaṃgraha, 2:25).[76] However, as Xuanzang notes, this nature is also empty in that there is an "absence of an existential nature in conditions that arise and perish" (utpatti-niḥsvabhāvatā). That is, the events in this causal flow, while "seeming to have real existence of their own" are actually like magical illusions since "they are said to only be hypothetical and not really exist on their own." As Siderits writes "to the extent that we are thinking of it at all - even if only as the non-dual flow of impressions-only - we are still conceptualizing it."
  3. Pariniṣpanna-svabhāva (literally, "fully accomplished", "perfected", "consummated"): This is the true nature of things, the experience of Suchness or Thatness (Tathātā) discovered in meditation unaffected by conceptualization, causality, or duality. It is defined as "the complete absence, in the dependent nature, of objects – that is, the objects of the conceptualized nature" (see Mahāyānasaṃgraha, 2:4).[76] What this refers to is that empty non-dual experience which has been stripped of the duality of the constructed nature through yogic praxis. According to Williams, this is "what has to be known for enlightenment" and Siderits defines it as "just pure seeing without any attempt at conceptualization or interpretation. Now this is also empty, but only of itself as an interpretation. That is, this mode of cognition is devoid of all concepts, and so is empty of being of the nature of the perfected. About it nothing can be said or thought, it is just pure immediacy." According to Xuanzang, this nature has the "absence of any existential nature of ultimate meaning" (paramārtha-niḥsvabhāvatā) since it is "completely free from any clinging to entirely imagined speculations about its identity or purpose. Because of this, it is conventionally said that it does not exist. However, it is also not entirely without a real existence."

Emptiness edit

The central meaning of emptiness (śūnyatā) in Yogācāra is a twofold "absence of duality." The first element of this is the unreality of any conceptual duality such as "physical" and "non-physical", "self" and "other". To define something conceptually is to divide the world into what it is and what it is not, but the world is a causal flux that does not accord with conceptual constructs.[13] The second element of this is a perceptual duality between the sensorium and its objects, between what is "external" and "internal", between subject (grāhaka, literally "grasper") and object (grāhya, "grasped").[77] This is also an unreal superimposition, since there is really no such separation of inner and outer, but an interconnected causal stream of mentality which is falsely divided up.[13]

An important difference between the Yogācāra conception of emptiness and the Madhyamaka conception is that in classical Yogācāra, emptiness does exist (as a real absence) and so does consciousness (which is that which is empty, the referent of emptiness), while Madhyamaka refuses to endorse such existential statements. The Madhyāntavibhāga for example, states "the imagination of the nonexistent [abhūta-parikalpa] exists. In it duality does not exist. Emptiness, however, exists in it," which indicates that even though that which is dualistically imagined (subjects and objects), is unreal and empty, their basis does exist (i.e. the dependently arisen conscious manifestation).[78][79]

The Yogācāra school also gave special significance to the Āgama sutra called Lesser Discourse on Emptiness (parallel to the Pali Cūḷasuññatasutta, MN 121) and relies on this sutra in its explanations of emptiness. According to Gadjin Nagao, this sutra affirms that "emptiness includes both being and non-being. both negation and affirmation."[80][c]

Disagreement with Madhyamaka edit

Indian sources indicate that Yogācāra thinkers sometimes debated with the defenders of the Madhyamaka tradition.[82] However, there is disagreement among contemporary Western and traditional Buddhist scholars about the degree to which they were opposed, if at all.[83] The main difference between these schools was related to issues of existence and the nature of emptiness. The Chinese pilgrim Yijing (635–713) concisely summarized the differences thus: “For Yogācāra the real exists, but the conventional does not exist; and [Yogācāra] takes the three natures as foundational. For Madhyamaka the real does not exist, but the conventional does exist; and actually the two truths are primary".[84] Garfield and Westerhoff write that "Yogācāra is both ontologically and epistemologically foundationalist; Madhyamaka is antifoundationalist in both senses."[83] Another way to state this key difference is that Madhyamaka defends a "global antirealism" while Yogācāra "restrict[s] the scope of their antirealism to the external and the conventional".[82]

While Madhyamaka generally states that asserting the ultimate existence or non-existence of anything (including emptiness) was inappropriate, Yogācāra treatises (like the Madhyāntavibhāga) often assert that the dependent nature (paratantra-svabhāva) really exists and that emptiness is an actual absence that also exists ultimatelly.[79] In a similar fashion, Asaṅga states "that of which it is empty does not truly exist; that which is empty truly exists: emptiness makes sense in this way".[85] He also describes emptiness as "the non-existence of the self, and the existence of the no-self."[78] Classical Yogācāras like Vasubandhu and Sthiramati also affirm the reality of conscious appearance, i.e. that truly existent stream of dependent arisen and constantly changing consciousness which projects false and illusory subjective minds and their cognitive objects. It is this real flow of conscious transformation (vijñānapariṇāma) which is said to be empty (of duality and conceptuality).[86] Against the radically anti-foundationalist interpretation of Madhyamaka, the classic Yogācāra position is that there is something (the dependent nature which is mere-consciousness) that "exists" (sat) independently of conceptual designation (prajñapti), and that it is this real thing (vāstu) which is said to be empty of duality and yet is a basis for all dualistic conceptions.[87]

Furthermore, Yogācāra thinkers like Asaṅga and Vasubandhu critiqued those who "adhere to non-existence" (nāstikas, vaināśkas, likely referring to certain Madhyamikas) because they saw them as straying into metaphysical nihilism (abhāvānta, see Vimśatikā v. 10).[73][78] They held that there was really something which could be said to "exist", that is, vijñapti, and that was what is described as being "empty" in their system.[73] For Yogācāra, all conventional existence must be based on something which is real (dravya).[88] Sthiramati argues that we cannot say that everything exists conventionally (saṁvṛtisat) or nominally (prajñaptisat) and that nothing truly exists in an ultimate fashion (which would entail a global conventionalism and nominalism without any metaphysical ground). For Sthiramati, this view is false because "what would follow is non-existence even conventionally. That is because conventions are not possible without something to depend upon (or, “without taking up something”—upādāna)."[89] Thus, for Sthiramati, consciousness (vijñana) "since it is dependently arisen, exists as dravya (substance)."[89]

The Bodhisattvabhūmi likewise argues that it is only logical to speak of emptiness if there is something (i.e. dharmatā, an ultimate nature) that is empty. The Bodhisattvabhūmi's Chapter on Reality (Tattvārthapaṭala) states that emptiness is "wrongly grasped" by those who "do not accept that of which something is empty, nor do they accept that which is empty".[90] This is because "emptiness holds good only as long as that of which something is [said to be] empty does not exist, but on the other hand, that which is empty exists. If, however, all [elements involved in this relation] were non-existent, in what respect, what would be empty, [and] of what?" For the Bodhisattvabhūmi, the "right" way to understand emptiness is "one regards that something is empty of that which does not exist in it and correctly comprehends that what remains there does actually exist here".[90] That which "remains" and "actually exists" is the true reality, the thing itself (vastumātra), the foundation (āśraya) which remains (avaśiṣṭa) after all conceptual constructs have been removed.[91]

Yogācārins also criticized certain Madhyamaka accounts of conventional truth, that is, the view which says that conventional truth is merely erroneous cognitive processes (designations, expressions, and linguistic conventions) which project an inherent nature.[92] The Yogācārabhūmi's Viniścayasaṃgrahanī states that either Madhyamakas see conventional reality as produced by linguistic expressions and also by causal forces, or they see it as produced merely by linguistic expressions and convention. If the former, then Madhyamikas must accept the reality of causal efficacy, which is a kind of existence (since things which are causally produced can be said to exist in some way). If the latter, then without any basis for linguistic expression and convention, it makes no sense to even use these terms (for Yogācāra these conventions must have some kind of referential basis).[93]

Yogācārins further held that if all phenomena are equally conventional and unreal in the same way this would lead to laxity in ethics and in following the path, in other words to moral relativism.[94] The basic idea behind this critique is that if only convention exists (as Madhyamaka claims) and there are no truths that are independent of convention and linguistic expression, there would be no epistemic foundations for critiquing worldly (non-buddhist) conventions and affirming other conventions as closer to the truth (like the conventions used by Buddhists to establish their ethics and their teachings).[94]

Madhyamaka thinkers like Bhaviveka, Candrakirti and Shantideva also critiqued Yogācāra views in their works for what they saw as an improper reification (samāropa) of mind and for a nihilistic denial of conventional truth. The work of Xuanzang (7th century) also contains evidence for this Indian debate.[95]

Two interpretations of the three natures edit

Various Buddhist studies scholars such as Alan Spongberg, Mario D'amato, Daniel McNamara, and Matthew T. Kapstein have noted that there are two main interpretations of the three natures doctrine among the various texts of the Yogacara corpus. The two models have been named the "pivot" model and "progressive" model by these Western scholars.[96][97] The "pivot" model, found in texts like the Triṃśikā and the Mahāyānasaṃgraha, presents the dependent nature as a kind of "ontological pivot" since it is the basis for conceptual construction (the imagined nature) and for the perfected nature (which is nothing but absence of the imagined nature in the dependent nature).[97] As such, the imagined nature is an incorrect way of experiencing the dependent, while the perfected nature is the correct way.[96]

The "progressive model" meanwhile can be found in the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa and in the Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra and its bhāṣya. In this model, it is the perfected nature which is the primary element of the three natures schema. Here, the perfected nature is the pure basis of reality, while the other two natures are both impaired by ignorance.[96][97][98] As the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa states: "The imputed and the other-dependent are to be known as having defiled characteristics. The perfected is asserted to have the characteristic of purity."[96] In this text, the dependent nature is seen as something which must be abandoned since it has the "appearance of duality" (dvayākāra).[96] As such, in this "progressive" model, the dependent nature is the basis for the imagined nature, but not the basis for the perfected nature.[96][97] The perfected nature on the other hand is a fundamentally pure true reality (which nevertheless is covered by adventitious defilements). As the Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra states:

Reality - which is always without duality, is the basis of error, and is entirely inexpressible - does not have the nature of discursivity. It is to be known, abandoned, and purified. It should properly be thought of as naturally immaculate, since it is purified from defilements, as are space, gold, and water.[98]

Furthermore, according to the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa (TSN 17-20), the three natures are inseparable (abhinna) and as such non-dual. This is a key difference between this model and the pivot model, where the dependent nature is ultimately devoid of the imagined nature.[96][97]

Another difference between these sources is that in the Triṃśikā, the main model of liberation is a radical transformation of the basis (āśrayaparāvṛtti). The Trisvabhāvanirdeśa meanwhile claims that liberation occurs through knowledge of the three natures as they are (in their non-duality).[97] Some scholars, like McNamara, argue that these two models are incompatible, ontologically and soteriologically.[96] Kapstein thinks that it is possible that the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa is attempting to reconcile them.[97] These differences have also led some scholars (Kapstein and Thomas Wood) to question the attribution of the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa to Vasubandhu.[96][97]

Karma edit

An explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of karma (action) is central to Yogācāra, and the school sought to explain important questions such as how moral actions can have effects on individuals long after that action was done, that is, how karmic causality works across temporal distances. Previous Abhidharma schools like the Sautrantika had developed theories of karma based on the notion of "seeds" (bījā) in the mind stream, which are unseen karmic habits (good and bad) which remain until they meet with the necessary conditions to manifest. Yogācāra adopts and expanded this theory.[1] Yogācāra then posited the "storehouse consciousness" as the container of the seeds, as the storage place for karmic latencies and as a fertile matrix of predispositions that bring karma to a state of fruition. In the Yogācāra system, all experience without exception is said to result from karma or mental intention (cetana), either arising from one's own subliminal seeds or from other minds.[99]

For Yogācāra, the seemingly external or dualistic world is merely a "by-product" (adhipati-phala) of karma. The term vāsanā ("perfuming") is also used when explaining karma. Yogācārins were divided on the issue of whether vāsāna and bija were essentially the same, whether the seeds were the effect of the perfuming, or whether the perfuming simply affected the seeds.[100] The type, quantity, quality and strength of the seeds determine where and how a sentient being will be reborn: one's race, sex, social status, proclivities, bodily appearance and so forth. The conditioning of the mind resulting from karma is called saṃskāra.[101] Vasubandhu's Treatise on Action (Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa), treats the subject of karma in detail from the Yogācāra perspective.[102]

Meditation and awakening edit

As the name of the school suggests, meditation practice is central to the Yogācāra tradition. Yogācāra texts prescribe various yogic practices such as mindfulness and the four investigations, out of which a revolutionary and radically transformative understanding of the non-duality of self and other is said to arise. This process is referred to as āśraya-parāvṛtti ("overturning the cognitive basis", or "revolution of the basis"), which refers to "overturning the conceptual projections and imaginings which act as the base of our cognitive actions."[1] This event is seen as the transformation of the basic mode of cognition into jñāna (knowledge, direct knowing), which is seen as a non-dual knowledge that is non-conceptual (nirvikalpa), i.e., "devoid of interpretive overlay".[1][103] Roger R. Jackson describes this as a "'fundamental unconstructed awareness' (mūla-nirvikalpa-jñāna)".[104] When this knowledge arises, the eight consciousnesses come to an end and are replaced by direct knowings. According to Lusthaus:

Overturning the Basis turns the five sense consciousnesses into immediate cognitions that accomplish what needs to be done (kṛtyānuṣṭhāna-jñāna). The sixth consciousness becomes immediate cognitive mastery (pratyavekṣaṇa-jñāna), in which the general and particular characteristics of things are discerned just as they are. This discernment is considered nonconceptual (nirvikalpa-jñāna). Manas becomes the immediate cognition of equality (samatā-jñāna), equalizing self and other. When the Warehouse Consciousness finally ceases it is replaced by the Great Mirror Cognition (Mahādarśa-jñāna) that sees and reflects things just as they are, impartially, without exclusion, prejudice, anticipation, attachment, or distortion. The grasper-grasped relation has ceased. ..."purified" cognitions all engage the world in immediate and effective ways by removing the self-bias, prejudice, and obstructions that had prevented one previously from perceiving beyond one's own narcissistic consciousness. When consciousness ends, true knowledge begins. Since enlightened cognition is nonconceptual its objects cannot be described.[1]

Five Categories of Beings edit

One of the more controversial Yogācāra teachings was the "five categories of beings", which was an extension of the teachings on the seeds of the storehouse consciousness. This teacing states that sentient beings have certain innate seeds that determine their capability of achieving a particular state of enlightenment and no other. Thus, beings were placed into five categories:[105]

  1. Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to practice the bodhisattva path and achieve full Buddhahood
  2. Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of a pratyekabuddha (private Buddha)
  3. Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of an arhat
  4. Beings whose innate seeds had an indeterminate nature, and could potentially be any of the above
  5. Beings whose innate seeds were incapable of achieving enlightenment ever because they lacked any wholesome seeds

The fifth class of beings, the icchantika, were described in various Mahayana sutras as being incapable of achieving enlightenment, unless in some cases through the aid of a Buddha or Bodhisattva. Nevertheless, the notion was highly criticized by later Mahayanists who supported the universalist doctrine of ekayana. This tension is important in East Asian Buddhist history and later East Asian Yogācārins attempted to resolve the dispute by softening their stance on the five categories.[105][106]

Mental images: true vs false edit

An important debate about the reality of mental appearances within Yogācāra led to its later subdivision into two systems of Alikākāravāda (Tib. rnam rdzun pa, False Aspectarians, also known as Nirākāravāda) and Satyākāravāda (rnam bden pa, True Aspectarians, also known as Sākāravāda). They are also termed "Aspectarians" (ākāra) and "Non-Aspectarians" (anākāra). The core issue is whether appearances or “aspects” (rnam pa, ākāra) of objects in the mind are treated as true (bden pa, satya) or false (rdzun pa, alika).[107] While this division did not exist in the works of the early Yogācāra philosophers, tendencies similar to these views can be discerned in the works of Yogacara thinkers like Dharmapala (c. 530–561?) and Sthiramati (c. 510–570?).[108][109][110]

According to Yaroslav Komarovski the distinction is as follows:

Although Yogācāras in general do not accept the existence of an external material world, according to Satyākāravāda its appearances or “aspects” (rnam pa, ākāra) reflected in consciousness have a real existence, because they are of one nature with the really existent consciousness, their creator. According to Alikākāravāda, neither external phenomena nor their appearances and/in the minds that reflect them really exist. What exists in reality is only primordial mind (ye shes, jñāna), described as self-cognition (rang rig, svasamvedana/ svasamvitti) or individually self-cognizing primordial mind (so so(r) rang gis rig pa’i ye shes).[111]

Davey K. Tomlinson describes the difference (with reference to later Yogacara scholars from Vikramashila) as follows:

On one hand is the Nirākāravāda, typified by Ratnākaraśānti (ca. 970–1045); on the other, the Sākāravāda, articulated by his colleague and critic Jñānaśrīmitra (ca. 980–1040). The Nirākāravādin argues that all appearances do not really exist. They are ersatz or false (alīka). Ephemeral forms appear to us but are the erroneous construction of ignorance, which fundamentally characterizes our existence as suffering beings in saṃsāra. In the ultimately real experience of an awakened buddha, no appearances show up at all. Pure experience, unstained by false appearance (which is nirākāra, “without appearance”), is possible. The Sākāravādin, on the other hand, defends the view that all conscious experience is necessarily the experience of a manifest appearance (consciousness is sākāra, or constitutively “has appearance”). Manifest appearances, properly understood, are really real. A buddha's experience has appearances, and there is nothing about this fact that makes a buddha's experience mistaken.[112]

Practice edit

 
Maitreya meditating, 2nd century CE, Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum, Kolkata

A key early source for the yogic practices of Indian Yogācāra is the encyclopedic Yogācārabhūmi-Śāstra (YBh, Treatise on the Foundation for Yoga Practitioners). The YBh presents a structured exposition of the Mahāyāna Buddhist path of yoga (here referring to spiritual practice in general) from a Yogācāra perspective and relies in both Āgama/Nikāya texts and Mahāyāna sūtras while also being influenced by Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma.[113] According to some scholars, this text can be traced to communities of yogācāras, which initially referred not to a philosophical school, but to groups of meditation specialists whose main focus was Buddhist yoga.[114] Other Yogācāra texts which also discuss meditation and spiritual practice (and show some relationship with the YBh) include the Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra, the Madhyāntavibhāga, Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra, Dharmadharmatāvibhāga and Asanga's Mahāyānasaṃgraha.[115]

The YBh discusses various topics relevant to the bodhisattva practice, including: the eight different forms of dhyāna (meditative absorptions), the three samādhis, different types of liberation (vimokṣa), meditative attainments (samāpatti) such as nirodhasamāpatti, the five hindrances (nivaraṇa), the various types of foci (ālambana) or 'images' (nimitta) used in meditation, the various types contemplative antidotes (pratipakṣa) against the afflictions (like contemplating death, unattractiveness, impermanence, and suffering), the practice of śamatha through "the nine aspects of resting the mind" (navākārā cittasthitiḥ), the practice of insight (vipaśyanā), mindfulness of breathing (ānāpānasmṛti), how to understand the four noble truths, the thirty-seven factors of Awakening (saptatriṃśad bodhipakṣyā dharmāḥ), the four immeasurables (apramāṇa), and how to practice the six perfections (pāramitā).[116]

Bodhisattva path edit

Yogācāra sources like the Abhidharmasamuccaya, the Chéng Wéishì Lùn and the commentaries to the Mahāyānasaṃgraha and the Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra also contain various descriptions of the main stages of the bodhisattva path.[117][118] These Yogācāra sources integrate the Mahayana teaching of the ten bodhisattva stages (bhūmis) with the earlier Abhidharma outline of the path called the "five paths" (pañcamārga), to produce a Mahayanist version of "five stages" (pañcāvasthā).[118][119] In classic Yogācāra, this bodhisattva path is said to last for three incaculable eons (asaṃkhyeya kalpas), i.e. millions upon millions of years.[120][119]

The five paths or stages are outlined in Yogācāra sources as follows:[118][117][119][121]

  1. Path of accumulation (sambhāra-mārga, 資糧位), in which a bodhisattva gives rise to bodhicitta, and works on the two accumulations of merit (puṇya) and wisdom (jñana). These are linked with the practice of the six perfections. In this first stage of the path, one attains merit by doing good deeds like giving (dana) and one also accumulates wisdom by listening to the Mahayana teachings many times, contemplating them and meditating on them. One also associates with good spiritual friends. According to the Mahāyānasaṃgraha, at this stage the bodhisattva focuses on accumulating wholesome roots (kuśalamūla) and on permeating one's mind with learning (bahuśrutaprabhāvita).[122] This leads to the accumulation of great faith and conviction in the Mahayana and in the principle of consciousness-only.[123]
  2. Path of engagement (prayoga-mārga, 加行位), also termed "the stage of the practice of faith and convinction" (adhimukticaryābhūmi). Here, a bodhisattva practices morality, meditation, and wisdom in order to quell the manifest activities of the two types of obscurations: emotionally afflictive and cognitive. While their active elements are quelled, they remain as seeds in the foundation consciousness. Furthermore, one also cultivates the "factors conducive to penetration", which consists of the "four investigations" and the "four correct cognitions". These are ways of contemplating the truth of mind-only and lead to the "entrance into the principle of cognizance-only" (vijñaptimātrapraveśa) as well as to "the certainty as to the non-existence of the object" (arthābhāvaniścaya).[124] At this stage one relies on the fourth dhyana and also attains various samadhis (meditative concentrations). The final stage of this path which is just before the path of seeing is called "the elimination of the ideation of cognizance-only" (vijñaptimātrasaṃjñāvibhāvana). As the Mahāyānasaṃgraha states, at this point, the realization of the absolute nature (pariniṣpannasvabhāvabuddhi) eliminates the very "perception of mind-only" (vijñaptimātratābuddhi).[125] The resulting wisdom is described by Asanga as "the non-conceptual cognition (nirvikalpakajñāna) in which the object (ālambana) and the subject (ālambaka) are completely identical (samasama)."[126]
  3. Path of seeing (darśana-mārga, 見道位), at this stage (which lasts for only a few moments), a bodhisattva attains an untainted knowledge (Skt. anāsrava-jñāna, 無漏智) into emptiness, the non-duality of self and other, and consciousness-only. The Cheng wei shi lun describes this knowledge which realises Suchness (tathatā) as being "entirely undifferentiated (samasama) from Suchness since both are free from the characteristics (lakṣaṇa) of subject (grāhaka) and object (grāhya)."[127] This stage is equated with the first bodhisattva stage, the stage of joy. At this point, one is a proper noble (arya) bodhisattva instead of just a beginner.
  4. Path of cultivation (bhāvanā-mārga, 修道位), at this stage, a bodhisattva continues to train themselves in two main cognitions in order to fully eliminate all the seeds of the two types of obscurations. They train in the non-conceptual gnosis (nirvikalpakajñāna) of ultimate reality, and the wordly or subsequent knowledge (pṛṣṭhtalabdhajñāna) which knows conventional reality as illusory, and is yet able to conceptually understand it and use it for guiding sentient beings according to their needs. Part of this path requires effort, as the bodhisattva is said to "repeatedly (abhīkṣṇam) cultivate the non-conceptual cognition" (Cheng wei shi lun). However, after a certain point one advances effortlessly. This path corresponds to the second to ninth stages of the bodhisattva path. The Mahāyānasaṃgraha states that at this stage the yogin "dwells in intense cultivation for hundreds of thousands of koṭis of niyutas [an astronomical number] of aeons and consequently attains the transformation of the basis (āśrayaparavṛtti)".[128]
  5. Path of fulfillment (niṣṭhā-mārga), also known as the path of no more learning (aśaikṣa-mārga, 無學位) in other sources. This is equivalent to complete Buddhahood. It also entails attaining the three bodies (trikāya) of the Buddha (a doctrine which was also invented by the Yogācāra school).

Bodhisattva practice edit

The Bodhisattvabhūmi discusses the Yogācāra school's specifically Mahāyāna forms of practice which are tailored to bodhisattvas.[129] The aim of the bodhisattva's practice in the Bodhisattvabhūmi is the wisdom (prajñā) which realizes of the inexpressible Ultimate Reality (tathata) or the 'thing-in-itself (vastumatra), which is essenceless and beyond the duality (advaya) of existence (bhāva) and non-existence (abhāva).[130][131]

The Bodhisattvabhūmi outlines several practices of bodhisattvas, including the six perfections (pāramitā), the thirty-seven factors of Awakening, and the four immeasurables. Two key practices which are unique to bodhisattvas in this text are the four investigations and the four correct cognitions or "the four kinds of understanding in accordance with true reality".[132][133] These two sets of four practices and cognitions are also taught in the Abhidharmasamuccaya and its commentaries.[133]

The four investigations and four correct cognitions edit

The four investigations (catasraḥ paryeṣaṇāḥ) and the corresponding four correct cognitions (catvāri yathābhūtaparijñānāni) are a set of original contemplations found in Yogācāra works. These were seen as very important contemplative methods by the authors of the Bodhisattvabhūmi. They were considered to lead to awakening, and were linked with the thirty-seven factors leading to Awakening.[134]

The four investigations and the corresponding four correct cognitions (which are said to arise out of the investiations) are:[135][136]

  1. The investigation of the names [of things] (nāmaparyeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of names just for what they are, which is "just names" (nāmamātra), i.e. arbitrary linguistic signs.
  2. The investigation of things (vastuparyeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of things. One sees things just for what they are, namely a mere presence or a thing-in-itself (vastumātra). One understands that this is apart from all labels and is inexpressible (nirabhilāpya).
  3. The investigation of verbal designations suggesting and portraying an intrinsic nature (svabhāva-prajñapti-paryeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere designations (prajñaptimātratā). Thus, one sees the idea of intrinsic nature to be illusory like a hallucination or a dream.
  4. The investigation of verbal designations expressing individuation and differences (viśeṣaprajñaptiparyeṣaṇā), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere designations. For example, a thing may be designated as existing or non-existing, but such designations do not apply to true reality or the thing-in-itself.

The practice which leads to the realization of the true nature of things is based on the elimination of all conceptual proliferations (prapañca) and ideations (saṃjñā) that one superimposes on true reality.[137] The YBh states that the yogin must "repeatedly remove any ideation conducive to the proliferation directed at all phenomena and should consistently dwell on the thing-in-itself by a non-conceptualizing mental state which is focused on grasping only the object perceived without any characteristics".[138]

Four prayogas edit

Various Yogācāra sources provide a four step process of realization leading to the path of seeing, these four are the four yogic practices (prayogas):[139]

  • Yogic practice of observation (upalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects are observed to be nothing but mind.
  • Yogic practice of non-observation (anupalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects are not observed as such
  • Yogic practice of observation and non-observation (upalambhānupalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects being unobservable, a mind cognizing them is not observed either
  • Yogic practice of double non-observation (nopalambhopalambha-prayoga) - Not observing both, nonduality is observed

This process is conceisely explained in the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa which says "through the observation of it being merely mind, a knowable object is not observed. Through not observing a knowable object, mind is not observed [either]. Through not observing both, the dharmadhātu is observed."[140] Thus, the goal of meditation is a totally unified mind that goes beyond all concepts and language to directly know the undifferentiated "uniformity of phenomena" (dharmasamatāḥ) and the thing-in-itself, the supreme reality.[141] The elimination of all concepts applies even to the very idea of mind only or "mere-cognizance" itself.[142] As the Dharmadharmatāvibhāga states: "through [referents] being observed in this way, they are observed as mere cognizance. By virtue of observing them as mere cognizance, Referents are not observed, and through not observing referents, mere cognizance is not observed [either]."[143] This elimination of concepts and ideas is the basic framework applied by the bodhisattva to all meditative practices, including the different mindfulness meditations.[137] The three samādhis (meditative absorptions) are likewise adapted into this new framework. These three are the emptiness (śūnyatā), wishlessness (apraṇihita), and imagelessness (ānimitta) samādhis.[144]

Meditation edit

As the "school of yoga practitioners", meditative practice is discussed in various Yogācāra sources. The sixth chapter (the Maitreya Chapter) of the Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra focuses entirely on meditation. It extensively discusses the meditative aspects of ‘calm’ (śamatha) and ‘insight’ (vipaśyanā) from unique perspectives.[145] Success in both of these is based on pure ethics and on pure views based on listening and reflecting (viśuddhaṃ śrutamayacintāmayadarśanam).[145] Insight is paired with "objects consisting in images accompanied by reflection" (savikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ) while tranquility is seen as based on objects consisting in images unaccompanied by reflection (nirvikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ).[145] Thus, insight meditation is based on the uninterrupted contemplation of mental images, while calming meditation is simply focusing on "the continuous flow of mind with uninterrupted attention".[146] The Saṃdhinirmocana also states that the teachings themselves are an important object of meditative contemplation. This includes the Yogācāra teaching of consciousness-only, the teachings on the twofold emptiness (of self and phenomena), and the schematic analysis of the subject and its objects of consciousness.[147]

While insight meditation is initially based on conceptual reflection, these are gradually abandoned at later stages until the yogin lets go of all concepts, teachings, and mental images.[147] Furthermore, at the higher stages of meditation, the calm and insight meditations must ultimately be blended or yoked together (yuganaddha) in a single state of one-pointedness of mind (cittaikāgratā).[146] This unified state is described as that state in which the yogin: "realises that these images (pratibimba) which are the domain of concentration (samādhigocara) are nothing but representation (vijñaptimātra), and having realised this, he contemplates (manasikaroti) Suchness (tathatā)."[146]

History edit

Yogācāra, along with Madhyamaka (Middle Way), is one of the two principal philosophical schools of Indian Mahāyāna Buddhism,[148] though the related movement of Tathāgatagarbha-thought was also influential.[149][note 1]

Origin and early Yogācāra edit

 
The Kushan Empire ruled much of north India during the early period of the Yogācāra school.

The term "yogācāra" (yoga practitioner) was originally used to refer to the Buddhist meditation adepts of the first centuries of the common era which were associated with the Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika traditions in north India (some of their key centers included Gandhara, Kashmir and Mathura). Modern scholars like Florin Delenau have suggested that some yogis in this north Indian Buddhist milieu gradually adopted Mahāyāna ideas, eventually developing into a separate movement (a process which was complete by the 5th century).[150][5][6] According to Delenau, the Chinese Dhyana Sutras indicate just such a gradual adoption of Mahāyāna elements.[5]

 
The bodhisattva Maitreya and disciples, a central figure in Yogacara origin myth. Gandhara, 3rd century CE.

One of the earliest texts of the Mahāyāna Yogācāra tradition proper is the Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra (Unraveling the Profound Intent) which might be as early as the first or second century CE.[151] It includes new theories such as the basis-consciousness (ālaya-vijñāna), the doctrine of vijñapti-mātra and the "three natures" (trisvabhāva). However, these theories were not completely new, as they have predecessors in older theories held by previous Buddhist schools, such as the Sautrāntika theory of seeds (bīja) and the Sthavira theory of the bhavanga.[152] Philosophically speaking, Richard King notes that Sautrāntikas defended a kind of representationalism, in which the mind only perceives an image (akara) or representation (vijñapti) of an external object (never the object itself). Mahayana Yogācāras adopted a similar model but removed the need for any external object which acts as a cause for the image.[153] As the doctrinal trailblazer of the Yogācāra, the Saṃdhinirmocana also introduced the paradigm of the Three Turnings of the Wheel of Dharma, with its own teachings being placed into the final and definitive teaching (which supersedes those of the Prajñaparamita sutras).[148]

The early layers of the massive Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra (Treatise on the Stages of the Yogācāras) also contains very ancient Yogācāra material which is earlier than the Saṃdhinirmocana.[154] However, in its current form it is a "conglomeration of heterogenous materials" (Schmithausen) which was finally compiled (perhaps by Asanga) after the Saṃdhinirmocana (hence, later layers quote the sutra directly). Modern scholars consider the Yogācārabhūmi to contain the work of several authors (mainly of a Mūlasarvāstivāda milieu), though it has traditionally been attributed in full to the bodhisattva Maitreya or to Asanga.[155][156] It is influenced by Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma and Sautrāntika traditions, who also had similar texts called by the name "Yogācārabhūmi", such as the Yogācārabhūmi of Saṅgharakṣa.[157]

Classical Yogācāra - Asaṅga and Vasubandhu edit

 
 
Asaṅga (left) and Vasubandhu statues at Kofuku-ji

Yogācāra's systematic exposition owes much to the Gandharan Buddhist brothers Asaṅga (4th c. CE) and Vasubandhu (c. 4th - 5th CE). Little is known of these figures, but traditional accounts (in authors like Xuanzang) state that Asaṅga received Yogācāra teachings from the bodhisattva and future Buddha, Maitreya.[158][159] However, there are various discrepancies between the Chinese and Tibetan traditions concerning these so called "five works of Maitreya".[160]

Modern scholars argue that the various works traditionally attributed to Maitreya are actually by other authors. According to Mario D'amato, the Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra and the Madhyāntavibhāga are part of a second phase of Yogācāra scholarship which took place after the completion of the Bodhisattvabhumi, but before the composition of Asanga's Mahāyānasaṃgraha (which quotes the Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra as an authoritative text).[161] Regarding the Abhisamayalankara and the Ratnagotravibhaga, modern scholars generally see these as the works of different authors.[162][163]

Asaṅga went on to write many of the key Yogācāra treatises such as the Mahāyānasaṃgraha and the Abhidharma-samuccaya.[160] Asaṅga also went on to convert his brother Vasubandhu to Yogācāra. Vasubandhu was a top scholar of Vaibhāṣika and Sautrāntika Abhidharma thought, and the Abhidharmakośakārikā is his main work which discusses the doctrines of these traditions.[164] Vasubandhu also went on to write important Yogācāra works like the Twenty Verses and the Thirty Verses on Consciousness-Only.

The middle period and the epistemological turn edit

The Yogācāra school held a prominent position in Indian Buddhism for centuries after the time of the two brothers. According to Lusthaus and Delenau, after Asaṅga and Vasubandhu, two distinct "wings" of the school developed during the "Middle Period" of Yogācāra, the epistemological school and the scholastic school. Another important third movement developed a synthesis of Yogācāra with buddha-nature thought.[1][165]

Thus, the three main branches of the Yogācāra movement which developed during the so called middle period are:[1][165]

  1. A logico-epistemic tradition (pramāṇavāda) focusing on issues of epistemology (Sanskrit: pramāṇa) and logic (hetuvidyā), exemplified by such thinkers as Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, Dharmottara, Devendrabuddhi, Prajñakaragupta, Jinendrabuddhi, Śākyabuddhi
  2. A scholastic and exegetical tradition which refined and elaborated Yogācāra Abhidharma and wrote various commentaries, exemplified by such thinkers as Gunamati, Asvabhāva, Sthiramati, Jinaputra, Dharmapāla, Śīlabhadra, Xuanzang, and Vinītadeva (710-770).
  3. The Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis, found in the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra, and Ghanavyūha sūtra, two treatises attributed to an author named Sāramati: the Ratnagotravibhāga, and Dharmadhātvaviśeṣaśāstra (Dasheng fajie wuchabie lun 大乘法界無差別論), as well as in the works of Paramārtha (499-569 CE), including his translations: Buddhagotraśāstra (Fó xìng lùn, 佛性論), and Anuttarâśrayasūtra.[166]

These branches of Yogācāra thought were not mutually exclusive however, for example, Vinītadeva wrote pramāṇa works as well as commentaries on the works of Vasubandhu. Aside from these, there were also Yogācāra authors writing commentaries on the Prajñaparamita sutras, including the unknown author of the Abhisamayālaṅkāra (AA), Arya Vimuktisena (6th century) who commented on the AA, and Daṃṣṭrāsena (author of the Bṛhaṭṭīkā).

The doctrines of the exegetical tradition sometimes came under attack by other Buddhists, especially the notion of ālaya-vijñāna, which was seen as close to the Hindu ideas of ātman and prakṛti. It was perhaps due to this that the logical tradition shifted over time to using the term citta-santāna instead, since it was easier to defend a "stream" (santāna) of thoughts as a doctrine that did not contradict not-self. By the end of the eighth century, the scholastic tradition had mostly become eclipsed by the pramāṇa tradition as well as by a new hybrid school that "combined basic Yogācāra doctrines with Tathāgatagarbha thought."[1]

The influential Pramāṇavāda tradition led by Dignāga and Dharmakīrti defined the main epistemological method for Indian Buddhism. Modern scholars see this school as having ushered in an "epistemological turn" for all Indian philosophy.[167] The pramāṇa tradition continued to thrive in Magadha (especially at Nalanda) as well as in Kashmir well into the 11th century. One of the most important late figures of this tradition was Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century), "the second Dharmakīrti".[168]

Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis edit

 
Panorama of the site of Vikramaśīla university (Bhagalpur district, Bihar). Vikramaśīla was an important center for late Indian Yogacara scholars, including the great panditas like Jñānaśrīmitra and Ratnākaraśānti.

According to Lusthaus, the synthetic Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha school accepted the definition of tathāgatagarbha (the buddha-womb, buddha-source, or "buddha-within") as "permanent, pleasurable, self, and pure" (nitya, sukha, ātman, śuddha) which is found in various tathāgatagarbha sutras.[1] This hybrid school eventually went on to link the tathāgatagarbha with the ālaya-vijñāna doctrine. Some key sources of this tendency are the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra, Ratnagotravibhāga (Uttaratantra), and in China the Awakening of Faith.[1]

The synthesis of Yogācāra and Tathāgatagarbha thought became extremely influential in both East Asia and Tibet. During the sixth and seventh centuries, various forms of competing Yogācāra systems were popular in Chinese Buddhism. The translator Bodhiruci (6th century CE) for example, took a more "classical" approach while Ratnamati was attracted to Tathāgatagarbha thought and sought to translate texts like the Dasabhumika commentary accordingly. Their disagreement on this issue led to the end of their collaboration as co-translators.[169] The translator Paramārtha is another example of a hybrid thinker. He promoted the theory of a "stainless consciousness" (amala-vijñāna, a pure wisdom within all beings, i.e. the tathāgatagarbha), which is revealed once the ālaya-vijñāna is purified.[170]

According to Lusthaus, Xuanzang's travels to India and his translation work was an attempt to return to a more "orthodox" and "authentic" Indian Yogācāra, and thus put to rest the debates and confusions in the Chinese Yogācāra of his time. The Cheng Weishi Lun returns to the use of the theory of seeds instead of the tathāgatagarbha to explain how some beings can reach Buddhahood.[171] However, by the eighth century, the Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis became the dominant interpretation of Yogācāra in East Asian Buddhism.[1] Later Chinese thinkers like Fa-Tsang would thus criticize Xuanzang for failing to teach the tathāgatagarbha.[171]

Karl Brunnhölzl notes that this syncretic tendency also existed in Indian Yogācāra scholasticism, but that it only became widespread during the later tantric era (when Vajrayana became prominent) with the work of thinkers like Jñānaśrīmitra, Ratnākaraśānti, and Maitripa.[172] Kashmir also became an important center for this tradition, as can be seen in the works of Kashmiri Yogacarins Sajjana and Mahājana.[173]

Yogācāra and Madhyamaka edit

Yogācāra and Madhyamaka philosophers demonstrated two opposing tendencies throughout the history of Buddhist philosophy in India, an antagonistic stance which saw both systems as rival and incompatible views and another inclusive tendency which worked towards harmonizing their views.[174] Some authors like the Madhyamikas Bhaviveka, Candrakīrti, and Śāntideva, and the Yogācāras Asanga, Dharmapala, Sthiramati criticized the philosophical theories of the other tradition. While Indian Yogācāras criticized certain interpretations of Madhyamaka (which they term “those who misunderstand emptiness”), they never criticize the founders of Madhyamaka themselves (Nāgārjuna and Āryadeva), and saw their work as implicitly in agreement with Yogācāra. This inclusivism saw Nāgārjuna's teachings as needing further expansion and explication (since it was part of the "second turning" of the wheel of Dharma). Thus, Yogācāra thinkers affirmed the importance Nāgārjuna's work and some even wrote commentaries on Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārika as a way to draw out the implicit meaning of Madhyamaka and show it was compatible with Yogācāra. These include Asanga's Treatise on Comforming to the Middle Way (Shun zhonglun 順中論) and Sthiramati's Mahayana Middle Way Commentary (Dasheng zhongguanshi lun 大乘中觀釋論 T.30.1567).[175] Similarly, Vasubandhu and Dharmapāla both wrote commentaries on Āryadeva's Catuḥśātaka (Four Hundred Verses).[176]

The harmonizing tendency can be seen in the work of philosophers like Kambala (5-6th century, author of the Ālokamālā), Jñānagarbha (8th century), his student Śāntarakṣita (8th century) and Ratnākaraśānti (c. 1000).[174] Śāntarakṣita (8th century), whose view was later called "Yogācāra-Svatantrika-Madhyamaka" by the Tibetan tradition, saw the Mādhyamika position as ultimately true and at the same time saw the Yogācāra view as a useful way to relate to conventional truth (which leads one to the ultimate).[177] Ratnākaraśānti on the other hand saw Nagarjuna as agreeing with the intent of Yogācāra texts, while criticizing the interpretations of later Madhyamikas like Bhaviveka. Later Tibetan Buddhist thinkers like Shakya Chokden would also work to show the compatibility of the alikākāravāda sub-school with Madhyamaka, arguing that it is in fact a form of Madhyamaka.[178] Likewise, the Seventh Karmapa Chödrak Gyamtso has a similar view which holds that the "profound important points and intents" of the two systems are one.[179] Ju Mipham is also another Tibetan philosopher whose project is aimed as showing the harmony between Yogacara and Madhyamaka, arguing that there is only a very subtle difference between them, being a subtle clinging by Yogacaras to the existence of an "inexpressible, naturally luminous cognition" (rig pa rang bzhin gyis ’od gsal ba).[180]

Yogācāra in East Asia edit

 
Statue of a traveling Xuanzang at Longmen Grottoes, Luoyang
 
Kuījī (632–682), a student of Xuanzang

Translations of Indian Yogācāra texts were first introduced to China in the early 5th century CE.[181] Among these was Guṇabhadra's translation of the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra in four fascicles, which would also become important in the early history of Chan Buddhism. Influential 5th century figures include the translators Bodhiruci, Ratnamati, and Paramārtha.[182] Their followers founded the Dilun (Daśabhūmikā Commentary) and Shelun (Mahāyānasaṃgraha) schools, both of which included Yogācāra and tathāgatagarbha elements.[183] Modern scholars also hold that the Awakening of Faith, a very influential work in East Asian Buddhism, was written by a member of the Dilun tradition.[184]

Xuanzang (fl. c. 602 – 664) is famous for having made a dangerous journey to India in order to study Buddhism, obtain more indic Yogācāra sources.[185][95] Xuanzang spent over ten years in India traveling and studying under various Buddhist masters and drew on a variety of Indian sources in his studies.[185][95] [186] Upon his return to China, Xuanzang brought with him 657 Buddhist texts, including the Yogācārabhūmi and began the work of translating them.[185][187] Xuanzang composed the Cheng Weishi Lun (Discourse on the Establishment of Consciousness Only) which drew on many Indian sources and commentaries and became a central work of East Asian Yogācāra.[188]

Xuanzang's student Kuiji continued this tradition, writing several important commentaries. However, another student of Xuanzang, the Korean monk Wŏnch’ŭk, defended some of the doctrines of the Shelun school of Paramārtha, for which he was criticized by the followers of Kuiji. Wŏnch’ŭk's teachings were influential on the Yogācāra (Beopsang) of Silla Korea. Both of these competing Yogācāra sub-sects were then imported to Japan where they became the two sub-sects (the northern and southern temple lineages) of the Hossō school.[189] Xuanzang's school later came under criticism from later Chinese masters like Fazang and it became less influential as the fortunes of other native Chinese schools rose. Nevertheless, Yogācāra studies continued to be important at different times throughout Chinese history, including during the modern revival of Yogācāra in the 20th century.[190]

Yogācāra in Tibet edit

 
Rangjung Dorje, 3rd Karmapa Lama (1284–1339)

Yogācāra is studied in all schools of Tibetan Buddhism, though it receives different emphasis in each of these. Yogācāra thought is an integral part of the history of Tibetan Buddhism. It was first transmitted to Tibet by figures like Śāntarakṣita, Kamalaśīla and Atiśa.[191]

The Tibetan Nyingma school and its Dzogchen teachings draw on both Madhyamaka and Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha thought.[1][192] Similarly, Kagyu school figures like the Third Karmapa also rely on the Madhyamaka and Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha systems in their presentation of the ultimate view (termed Mahamudra in Kagyu).[193] The Jonang school also developed its own synthetic philosophy which they termed shentong ("other-emptiness" Wylie: gzhan-stong), which also included elements from Yogācāra, Madhyamaka and Tathāgatagarbha.[194] In contrast, the Gelug and Sakya schools generally see Yogācāra as a lesser view than the Madhyamaka philosophy of Candrakirti, which is seen as the definitive view in these traditions.[195]

Today, Yogācāra topics remain important in Tibetan Buddhism and Yogācāra texts are widely studied. There are various debates and discussions among the Tibetan Buddhist schools regarding key Yogācāra ideas, like svasaṃvedana (reflexive awareness) and the foundational consciousness. Furthermore, the debates between the other-emptiness and self-emptiness views are also similar in some ways to the historical debates between Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha and Madhyamaka, though the specific viewpoints have evolved further and changed in complex ways.[196] Modern thinkers continue to discuss Yogācāra issues, and attempt to synthesize it with Madhyamaka. For example, Ju Mipham, the 19th-century Rimé commentator, wrote a commentary on Śāntarakṣita's synthesis arguing that the ultimate intent of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra is the same.[177]

Influence edit

Virtually all contemporary schools of Mahāyāna Buddhism are influenced by Yogācāra to some extent. This includes modern East Asian Buddhist traditions (like Zen and Pure Land) and Tibetan Buddhism.[197] Zen was heavily influenced by Yogācāra sources, especially the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra.[197] In Tibetan Buddhism, Yogācāra sources are still widely studied and several are part of the monastic education curriculum in various traditions.[198] Some influential Yogācāra texts in Tibetan Buddhism include: Asanga's Abhidharma-samuccaya, and the "Five Treatises of Maitreya" including the Mahayanasutralankara, and the Ratnagotravibhāga.[198]

Hindu philosophers such as Vācaspati Miśra, Utpaladeva, Abhinavagupta, and Śrīharṣa were also influenced by Yogacara ideas and responded to their theories in their own works.[199][200]

Textual corpus edit

 
A wall painting depicting Xuanzang's travels and his translation work, Xuanzang Memorial Hall, modern Nalanda

Sūtras edit

The Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra (Sūtra of the Explanation of the Profound Secrets; 2nd century CE), is a key early Yogācāra sutra which is considered to be the foundational sutra for the Yogācāra tradition.[201] There are two Indian commentaries to this, one by Asanga and one by Jñanagarbha.[202] The Avataṃsaka Sūtra (which includes the Daśabhūmikasūtra) also contains numerous teachings on mind-only and is very influential for East Asian Buddhism.[203] Vasubandhu's Commentary on the Daśabhūmikasūtra is an important commentary to this.[204][205] Another text, the Mahāyānābhidharmasūtra is often quoted in Yogācāra works and is assumed to also be an early Yogācāra sutra.[206]

The Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra also later assumed considerable importance in East Asia, and portions of this text were considered by Étienne Lamotte as being contemporaneous with the Saṃdhinirmocana.[207][208] This text equates the Yogācāra theory of ālayavijñāna with the tathāgatagarbha (buddha-nature) and thus seems to be part of the tradition which sought to merge Yogācāra with tathāgatagarbha thought.[209] Another sutra which contains similar themes to the Laṅkāvatāra is the Ghanavyūha Sūtra.[210][211]

All these five sutras are listed by Kuiji as key sutras for the Yogācāra school in his Commentary on the Cheng weishi lun (成唯識 論述記; Taishō no. 1830).[212][213] Another lesser known sutra which was important in East Asian Yogācāra is the Buddha Land Sutra (Buddhabhūmi-sūtra; Taishō vol. 16, no. 680) which along with its commentary (Buddhabhūmyupadeśa), teaches that the pure land is not a physical place, but a symbol for wisdom.[214]

There are also various Indian, Chinese and Tibetan commentaries to these various Mahayana sutras. Furthermore, the Prajñaparamita sutras are also important sources in Yogācāra, even though most do not cover specifically "Yogācāra" doctrines. This is shown by the fact that various Yogācāra commentaries were written on Prajñaparamita sutras, including commentaries by Asanga (Vajracchedikākāvyākhyā), Vasubandhu, Dignāga, Daṃṣṭrasena (Bṛhaṭṭīkā), Ratnākaraśānti (various), and the Abhisamayālaṅkāra.[215][216]

Treatises edit

 
Tibetan depiction of Asaṅga receiving teachings from the bodhisattva Maitreya. This is one of the founding religious myth of Yogācāra scholasticism.

Yogācāra authors wrote numerous scholastic and philosophical treatises (śāstra) and commentaries (ṭīkā, bhāṣya, vyākhyāna, etc). The following is a list in historical order and only includes specifically Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda figures and works:[217][218]

  • Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra, the earliest Yogācāra treatise, a massive encyclopedic work on Yogācāra theory and praxis which is a composite work reflecting various stages of historical development (compiled 3rd to 5th century CE).[154][1]
  • Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra and its bhāṣya, traditionally attributed to the bodhisattva Maitreya or Asanga, modern scholars like D'amato place this text (together with the commentary) after the Bodhisattvabhumi, but before Asanga.[219]
  • Madhyāntavibhāga (Distinguishing the Middle and the Extremes), another work of the "second phase" of post-Yogācārabhūmi Yogācāra thought, traditionally attributed to the bodhisattva Maitreya who is said to have revealed it to Asanga.[220]
  • Dharmadharmatāvibhāga (Distinguishing Dharmas and Dharmata), another work of the so called "Maitreya corpus"
  • Nāgamitra's (3rd-4th century?) Kāyatrayāvatāramukha (a treatise on the trikaya and the three natures)
  • The works of Asaṅga (4th-5th century CE): the Mahāyānasaṃgraha and the Abhidharma-samuccaya.[221]
  • Vasubandhu's (4th-5th century CE) Viṃśaṭikā-kārikā (Treatise in Twenty Stanzas), Triṃśikā-kārikā (Treatise in Thirty Stanzas), Vyākhyāyukti ("Proper Mode of Exposition"), Karmasiddhiprakarana ("A Treatise on Karma"), and Pañcaskandhaprakaraṇa (Explanation of the Five Aggregates).[206][222]
  • Ālokamālāprakaraṇanāma (An Explanation named 'Garland of Light') by Kambala (c. fifth to sixth century) which attempts to harmonize Madhyamaka and Yogācāra, mostly by assimilating Madhyamaka under Yogācāra.[217][223]
  • The Saṃdhinirmocanasūtravyākhyāna is a commentary to the Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra attributed to Asanga, but this has been questioned by modern scholars.[224]
  • Abhisamayālaṅkāra (Ornament of Realization), a commentary on the Prajñaparamita sutras. It is attributed to Maitreya-Asanga by Tibetan tradition, but it is unknown in Chinese sources. Modern scholars see this as a post-Asanga text. Makransky attributes it to Ārya Vimuktisena, the first commentator on this text.[225][226]
  • Dignāga's Ālambanaparīkṣā and its vrtti (commentary) defend the view of consciousness-only using epistemological arguments
  • The Indian Paramārtha (499–569) translated many works to Chinese, and also wrote some original treatises and commentaries, possibly including the Buddhagotraśāstra (Fo Xing Lun)
  • Sthiramati (6th century), wrote numerous commentaries like Pañcaskandhakavibhāṣā and Triṃśikāvijñaptibhāṣya
  • Mahayana Awakening of Faith (author unknown)
  • Dharmapala of Nalanda (6th century), wrote commentaries to the Ālambanaparīkṣā and Āryadeva's Catuḥśataka
  • Asvabhāva, wrote Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra-ṭīkā, Mahāyānasaṃgrahopanibandhana and a commentary on Ālokamālā
  • Dharmakīrti's (6th or 7th century) Pramānaṿārttika (Commentary on Epistemology), is mostly a work on pramana, but it also argues for consciousness-only
  • Śīlabhadra (529–645) - Buddhabhūmivyākhyāna
  • Xuanzang's (602-664) Cheng Wei Shi Lun is a large Chinese commentary on the Triṃśikā which draws on numerous Indian sources
  • Kuiji (632–682) - Various commentaries on texts like Cheng weishi lun, Heart-sutra, Madhyāntavibhāga etc.
  • Wŏnch'ŭk (613–696) - Commentaries on the Samdhinirmocanasutra, Heart-sutra, and Benevolent King Sutra
  • Wŏnhyo (617–686) - wrote commentaries on various works such as the Madhyāntavibhāga
  • Guṇaprabha - Bodhisattvabhūmiśīlaparivarta-bhāṣya
  • Jinaputra, wrote a commentary to the Abhidharmasamucchaya
  • Candragomī (sixth/seventh century) - Śiṣyalekha, Bodhisattvasaṃvaraviṃsaka
  • Vinītadeva (c. 645–715) - wrote commentaries on Viṃśatikā, Triṃśika and Ālambanaparīkśā
  • Jñānacandra (eighth century) - Yogacaryābhāvanātātparyārthanirdeśa, a meditation manual
  • Sāgaramegha (eighth century) - Yogācārabhūmaubodhisattvabhūmivyākhyā, a large Yogācārabhūmi commentary
  • Sumatiśīla (late eighth century) wrote a commentary on Vasubandhu's Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa
  • Prajñakaragupta (8th-9th century) - Pramāṇavārttikālaṃkāra and Sahāvalambanirṇayasiddhi, a proof of idealism
  • Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century) - Prajñālaṅkāra (Ornament of Wisdom), an exposition of vijñaptimātratā [227]
  • Dharmakīrti of Sumatra - Durbodhālokā (Light on the Hard-to-Illuminate), a sub-commentary to the Abhisamayālaṃkāra-śāstra-vṛtti of Haribhadra.[228]
  • Jñānaśrīmitra (fl. 975-1025 C.E.) - Sākarasiddhi, Sākarasaṃgraha, and Sarvajñāsiddhi
  • Ratnakīrti (11th century CE) - Ratnakīrtinibandhāvalī and Sarvajñāsiddhi
  • Ratnākāraśānti (10-11th century) - Prajñāpāramitopadeśa, Madhyamakālaṃkāropadeśa, Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi, Triyānavyavasthāna, Madhyamakālaṃkāravṛtti-Madhyamapratipadāsiddhi
  • Jñānaśrībhadra - commentaries on Laṅkāvatārasūtra, Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra, and Pramāṇavārttika
  • Sajjana (11th century) - Putralekha, Mahāyānottaratantraśāstropadeśa and Sūtrālaṃkārapiṇḍārtha[173]
  • Jōkei (1155–1213) - Gumei hosshin shū (Anthology of Awakenings from Delusion)
  • Ryōhen (1194–1252) - Kanjin kakumushō (Précis on Contemplating the Mind and Awakening from the Dream)

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Alex Wayman, A Defense of Yogacara Buddhism. Philosophy East and West, Volume 46, Number 4, October 1996, pages 447-476: "Of course, the Yogacara put its trust in the subjective search for truth by way of a samadhi. This rendered the external world not less real, but less valuable as the way of finding truth. The tide of misinformation on this, or on any other topic of Indian lore comes about because authors frequently read just a few verses or paragraphs of a text, then go to secondary sources, or to treatises by rivals, and presume to speak authoritatively. Only after doing genuine research on such a topic can one begin to answer the question: why were those texts and why do the moderns write the way they do?"
  2. ^ Kalupahana: "The above explanation of alaya-vijnana makes it very different from that found in the Lankavatara. The latter assumes alaya to be the eight consciousness, giving the impression that it represents a totally distinct category. Vasubandhu does not refer to it as the eight, even though his later disciples like Sthiramati and Hsuan Tsang constantly refer to it as such".[65]
  3. ^ Majhima Nikaya 121: Cula-suññata Sutta [81]
  1. ^ Frauwallner, Die Philosophie des Buddhismus,treats Tathāgatagarbha-thought as a separate school of Mahayana, providing an excerpt from the Uttaratantra, written by a certain Sāramati (娑囉末底), c.q. Maitreya-nātha.

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t Lusthaus, Dan (2018). What is and isn't Yogacara, Yogācāra Buddhism Research Association.
  2. ^ Makransky, John (1997). Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet. SUNY Press. p. 211. ISBN 978-0-7914-3431-4.
  3. ^ a b c Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  4. ^ Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief) (2005). Encyclopedia of Religion. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14: p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference. ISBN 0-02-865983-X (v.14)
  5. ^ a b c Deleanu, F. (Ed.). (2006). The Chapter on the Mundane Path (Laukikamārga): A Trilingual Edition(Sanskrit, Tibetan, Chinese), Annotated Translation and Introductory Study (2 vol), p. 162. Tokyo:International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
  6. ^ a b Kragh, U.T. (editor), The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners: The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1, pp. 30-31. Harvard University, Department of South Asian studies, 2013.
  7. ^ a b c d Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 146.
  8. ^ Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief)(2005). Encyclopedia of Religion. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14; Masaaki, Hattori (Ed.)(1987 & 2005)"Yogācāra": p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference. ISBN 0-02-865983-X (v.14)
  9. ^ Keenan, John P. (tr). The Scripture on the Explication of the Underlying Meaning. 2000. p. 1
  10. ^ a b c d Kochumuttom 1999, p. 1.
  11. ^ Peter Harvey, "An Introduction to Buddhism." Cambridge University Press, 1993, page 106.
  12. ^ Muller, A. Charles (2005; 2007). Wonhyo's Reliance on Huiyuan in his Exposition of the Two Hindrances. (Published in Reflecting Mirrors: Perspectives on Huayan Buddhism. Imre Hamar, ed., Harrassowitz Verlag, 2007, p. 281-295.) Source: [1] (accessed: April 7, 2010)
  13. ^ a b c d e f g h i Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/
  14. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 597.
  15. ^ Trivedi, Saam (November 2005). "Idealism and Yogacara Buddhism". Asian Philosophy. 15 (3): 231–246. doi:10.1080/09552360500285219. S2CID 144090250.
  16. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 387.
  17. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 391.
  18. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 598.
  19. ^ a b Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 149.
  20. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 389.
  21. ^ Kapstein, Matthew T. (July 2014). "Buddhist Idealists and Their Jain Critics On Our Knowledge of External Objects". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. 74: 123–147. doi:10.1017/S1358246114000083. S2CID 170689422.
  22. ^ a b Cameron Hall, Bruce, The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind, JIABS Vol 9, 1986, Number 1, p. 7.
  23. ^ Saam Trivedi, Idealism and Yogacara Buddhism, Asian Philosophy Volume 15, 2005 - Issue 3 Pages 231-246.
  24. ^ Butler, Sean, Idealism in Yogācāra Buddhism, The Hilltop Review Volume 4 Issue 1 Spring 2010,
  25. ^ Garfield, Jay L. Vasubandhu's treatise on the three natures translated from the Tibetan edition with a commentary, Asian Philosophy, Volume 7, 1997, Issue 2, pp. 133-154.
  26. ^ Williams 2008, p. 94.
  27. ^ Yamabe, Nobuyoshi (2004), "Consciousness, Theories of", in Buswell, Jr., Robert E., Macmillan Encyclopedia of Buddhism, USA: Macmillan Reference USA, pp. 177, ISBN 0-02-865910-4
  28. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert, The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections, Tokyo, The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2014, p. 625.
  29. ^ a b Schmithausen, Lambert (2005). On the Problem of the External World in the Ch’eng wei shih lun. Tōkyō: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies. The International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
  30. ^ Kalupahana 1992.
  31. ^ Dan Lusthaus, What is and isn't Yogacara. [2]. June 12, 2008, at the Wayback Machine
  32. ^ Garfield, Jay L. (2002). Empty words : Buddhist philosophy and cross-cultural interpretation ([Online-Ausg.]. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195145519.
  33. ^ Kalupahana 1992, pp. 122-126, 135-136.
  34. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, p. 162. 2010, Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies). Vasubandhu: cittaṃ mano vijñānaṃ vijñaptiś ceti paryāyaḥ (Viṃś 3.3); ‘mind, thinking, consciousness, and representation are synonymous terms’. Cf. AKBh II.34 (p. 61, l. 20): cittaṃ mano ʼtha vijñānam ekārthaṃ; ‘now, the mind, thinking, and consciousness have the same meaning’.
  35. ^ a b Kochumuttom 1999, p. 5.
  36. ^ a b c Wayman, Alex, A Defense of Yogācāra Buddhism, Philosophy East and West, Vol. 46, No. 4 (Oct., 1996), pp. 447-476.
  37. ^ Vasubandhu (author), Stefan Anacker (translator, annotator) (1984). Seven works of Vasubandhu, the Buddhist psychological doctor. Issue 4 of Religions of Asia series. Motilal Banarsidass Publ. ISBN 978-81-208-0203-2. Source: [1] (accessed: Wednesday April 21, 2010), p.159
  38. ^ Kochumuttom 1999, p. 1-2.
  39. ^ Kochumuttom 1999, p. 6.
  40. ^ Dan Lusthaus (4 February 2014). Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun. Taylor & Francis. p. 43. ISBN 978-1-317-97342-3.
  41. ^ a b c d e Westerhoff, Jan (November 2020), "For your eyes only: the Problem on Solipsism in Ancient Indian Philosophy", BSHP Annual Lecture 2020, British Society for the History of Philosophy, retrieved 2024-02-21
  42. ^ Williams, 2008, pp. 94-95.
  43. ^ Fernando Tola, Carmen Dragonetti, Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of Buddhism, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., 2004, p xxiv.
  44. ^ Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, pp. 150-151.
  45. ^ Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 157.
  46. ^ a b Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 170.
  47. ^ Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 173.
  48. ^ Brewster, Ernest Billings. "What is Our Shared Sensory World?: Ming Dynasty Debates on Yogacara versus Huayan Doctrines." Journal of Chinese Buddhist Studies (2018, 31: 117–170) New Taipei: Chung-Hwa Institute of Buddhist Studies. ISSN: 2313-2000 e-ISSN: 2313-2019
  49. ^ Wood, Thomas E. Mind Only: A Philosophical and Doctrinal Analysis of the Vijñānavāda, p. 205. University of Hawaii Press, 1991
  50. ^ a b c d e f g Finnigan, Bronwyn (2017). "Buddhist Idealism." In Tyron Goldschmidt & Kenneth Pearce (eds.), Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press. pp. 178-199.
  51. ^ Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/
  52. ^ a b Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 175.
  53. ^ Kalupahana 1992, p. 138-140.
  54. ^ Kalupahana 1992, p. 137-139.
  55. ^ a b Williams, Paul (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations, Routledge, p. 97.
  56. ^ Fernando Tola, Carmen Dragonetti, Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of Buddhism, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., 2004, p xxv.
  57. ^ a b Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, pp 94-95.
  58. ^ Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, p 97.
  59. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert (1987). Ālayavijñāna: on the origin and the early development of a central concept of Yogācāra philosophy, Part I: Text, page 89. Tokyo, International Institute for Buddhist Studies, Studia Philologica Buddhica Monograph Series IVa.
  60. ^ Williams, 2008, pp. 97-98.
  61. ^ Williams, 2008, pp. 98-99.
  62. ^ Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, page 131.
  63. ^ Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, page 93.
  64. ^ Kalupahana 1992, p. 137.
  65. ^ a b c Kalupahana 1992, p. 139.
  66. ^ a b Kalupahana 1992, p. 138.
  67. ^ Kalupahana 1992, p. 140.
  68. ^ a b Kalupahana 1992, p. 141.
  69. ^ Padmasiri De Silva, Robert Henry Thouless, Buddhist and Freudian Psychology. Third revised edition published by NUS Press, 1992 page 66.
  70. ^ Walpola Rahula, quoted in Padmasiri De Silva, Robert Henry Thouless, Buddhist and Freudian Psychology. Third revised edition published by NUS Press, 1992 page 66, [3].
  71. ^ a b Williams (2008), p. 90.
  72. ^ Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, p. 176.
  73. ^ a b c King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 PP.659-683.
  74. ^ Peter Lunde Johnson, Xuanzang, On There Only Being the Virtual Nature of Consciousness, 2019, p. 470.
  75. ^ Siderits, Mark, Buddhism as philosophy, 2017, pp. 177-178.
  76. ^ a b Williams (2008), pp. 90-91.
  77. ^ Skilton, Andrew (1994). A Concise History of Buddhism. Windhorse Publications, London:. pg 124
  78. ^ a b c King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 pp. 659-683.
  79. ^ a b Williams (2008), p. 93.
  80. ^ Gadjin M. Nagao, Madhyamika and Yogachara. Leslie S. Kawamura, translator, SUNY Press, Albany 1991, pp. 53-57, 200.
  81. ^ Cula-suññata Sutta: The Lesser Discourse on Emptiness
  82. ^ a b Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 3. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  83. ^ a b Conze, Edward (1993). A Short History of Buddhism (2nd ed.). Oneworld. ISBN 1-85168-066-7.:50f.
  84. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 133. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  85. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 68. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3.
  86. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? pp. 41-52. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  87. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 59. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  88. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 50. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  89. ^ a b Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 46. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  90. ^ a b Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 76. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  91. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 77. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  92. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 86. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  93. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? pp. 86-87. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  94. ^ a b Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 116. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  95. ^ a b c Lusthaus, Dan (undated). Xuanzang (Hsüan-tsang). Source: . Archived from the original on December 8, 2013. Retrieved December 8, 2013.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link) (accessed: December 12, 2007)
  96. ^ a b c d e f g h i McNamara, Daniel (2011). “On the Status of the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa in Contemporary Conceptions of Yogācāra Thought.”
  97. ^ a b c d e f g h Matthew Kapstein. Who Wrote the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa? Reflections on an Enigmatic Text and Its Place in the History of Buddhist Philosophy. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 2017. ⟨halshs-02503277⟩
  98. ^ a b D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
  99. ^ Harvey, Brian Peter (2000). An Introduction to Buddhist ethics: Foundations, Values, and Issues. Cambridge University Press. p. 297. ISBN 0-521-55640-6.
  100. ^ Lusthaus, Dan (2002). Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih lun. RoutledgeCurzon. p. 194. ISBN 0-415-40610-2.
  101. ^ Lusthaus, Dan (2002). Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih lun. RoutledgeCurzon. p. 48. ISBN 0-415-40610-2.
  102. ^ Karmasiddhiprakarana: The Treatise on Action by Vasubandhu. translated by Etienne Lamotte and Leo M. Pruden. Asian Humanities Press: 2001 ISBN 0-89581-908-2. pg 13, 35
  103. ^ Williams, 2008, p. 95.
  104. ^ "How Mystical is Buddhism?" by Roger R. Jackson Asian Philosophy, Vol. 6, No.2, 1996 pg 150
  105. ^ a b Groner, Paul (2000). The Establishment of the Tendai School. University of Hawaii Press. pp. 97–100. ISBN 0824823710.
  106. ^ Ford, James L. (2006). Jokei and Buddhist Devotion in Early Medieval Japan. Oxford University Press, USA. pp. 35-68. ISBN 978-0-19-518814-1
  107. ^ Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 8.
  108. ^ Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 73.
  109. ^ Zhihua Yao. The Buddhist Theory of Self-Cognition, pp. 149-150. Routledge, 2012.
  110. ^ Kajiyama, Yuichi. “Controversy between the sakara- and nirakara-vadins of the Yogacara school-some materials.” Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 14 (1965): n. pag. https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Controversy-between-the-sakara-and-nirakara-vadins-Kajiyama/655a1f561c18725188c0916ca05ec334b5f9f7cd
  111. ^ Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 73-74.
  112. ^ Tomlinson, Davey (2022). "Limiting the Scope of the Neither-One-Nor-Many Argument: The Nirākāravādin's Defense of Consciousness and Pleasure". Philosophy East and West. doi:10.1353/pew.0.0235. ISSN 1529-1898.
  113. ^ Timme Kragh 2013, pp. 16, 25-26, 30, 46.
  114. ^ Timme Kragh 2013, p. 31.
  115. ^ Timme Kragh 2013, p. 34.
  116. ^ Timme Kragh 2013 pp. 51, 60–230
  117. ^ a b Brunnholzl, Karl (trans.), Asanga. (2019) A Compendium of the Mahayana: Asanga's Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries, Appendix 10. Shambhala Publications.
  118. ^ a b c Watanabe, Chikafumi, A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III: The Relation of Practical Theories and Philosophical Theories, pp. 40-65. University of Calgary, 2000.
  119. ^ a b c Muller, Charles. Five stages of cultivating the Yogâcāra path 唯識修道五位, Digital Dictionary of Buddhism, 2006
  120. ^ Watanabe, Chikafumi, A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III: The Relation of Practical Theories and Philosophical Theories, p. 66. University of Calgary, 2000.
  121. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, pp. 97-107, 119-125. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  122. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, pp. 107. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  123. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, pp. 119. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  124. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 109. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  125. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 111. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  126. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 111. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  127. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 122. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  128. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 114. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  129. ^ Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 884-885.
  130. ^ Kragh 2013, p. 157.
  131. ^ Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 889-891.
  132. ^ Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 893-894.
  133. ^ a b Brunnholzl, Karl (trans.), Asanga. (2019) A Compendium of the Mahayana: Asanga's Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries, Appendix 8. Shambhala Publications.
  134. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 78. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  135. ^ Kragh 2013, p. 160.
  136. ^ Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 894-896.
  137. ^ a b Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 896-897.
  138. ^ Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 897-898.
  139. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, pp. 21-22. Snow Lion Publications.
  140. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, p. 24. Snow Lion Publications.
  141. ^ Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 87. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  142. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, p. 25. Snow Lion Publications.
  143. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl (2009). Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, pp. 23-24. Snow Lion Publications.
  144. ^ Deleanu, Florin. "Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself," in Kragh 2013 pp. 898-899.
  145. ^ a b c Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 90. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  146. ^ a b c Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, p. 92. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  147. ^ a b Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, pp. 94-95. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  148. ^ a b Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief)(2005). Encyclopedia of Religion. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14; Masaaki, Hattori (Ed.)(1987 & 2005)"Yogācāra": p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference. ISBN 0-02-865983-X (v.14)
  149. ^ E. Frauwallner (2010 (1956)), Die Philosophie des Buddhismus, p.166
  150. ^ O’Brien-Kop, K. Dharmamegha in yoga and yogācāra: the revision of a superlative metaphor. J Indian Philos 48, 605–635 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-020-09432-3
  151. ^ Powers, John (2004). Hermeneutics and Tradition in the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 4–11. ISBN 978-81-208-1926-9.
  152. ^ Waldron, William S (2003). The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the Context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-42886-1.
  153. ^ King, Richard; Vijnaptimatrata and the Abhidharma context of early Yogacara
  154. ^ a b Kritzer (2005), p. xvii, xix.
  155. ^ M. Delhey, ‘The Yogācārabhūmi Corpus: Sources, Editions, Translations, and Reference Works’. 2013.
  156. ^ Kragh, U.T. (editor), The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners: The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1, p. 312. Harvard University, Department of South Asian studies, 2013.
  157. ^ Deleanu, F. (Ed.). (2006). The Chapter on the Mundane Path (Laukikamārga): A Trilingual Edition(Sanskrit, Tibetan, Chinese), Annotated Translation and Introductory Study (2 vol), pp. 157-18. Tokyo:International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
  158. ^ Xuanzang; Bianji; Li, Jung-hsi (1996). The great Tang dynasty record of the western regions. Numata Center for Buddhist Translation & Research. ISBN 978-1-886439-02-3.
  159. ^ Wayman, Alex. Untying the Knots in Buddhism: Selected Essays. 1997. p. 213
  160. ^ a b Tucci, Giuseppe (1975). On Some Aspects of the Doctrines of the Maitreya (Natha) and Asanga: Being a Course of Five Lectures Delivered at the University of Calcutta \. Chinese Materials Center.
  161. ^ D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
  162. ^ Makransky, John J. Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet SUNY Press, 1997, p. 187.
  163. ^ Williams, Paul, Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations, Routledge, 1989, p. 103.
  164. ^ Gold, Jonathan, Paving the Great Way: Vasubandhu's Unifying Buddhist Philosophy, Columbia University Press, 2014, p. 2.
  165. ^ a b Delenau, Florin. Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation, 2010, pp. 17-20. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
  166. ^ Takasaki, Jikido (1966). A Study on the Ratnagotravibhāga (Uttaratantra) Being a Treatise on the Tathāgatagarbha Theory of Mahāyāna Buddhism (Rome Oriental Series 33). Rome: Istituto Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente, pp. 45–52.
  167. ^ Dreyfus, Georges B. J. Recognizing Reality: Dharmakirti's Philosophy and its Tibetan Interpretations, Suny, 1997, pp. 15-16.
  168. ^ "Śaṅkaranandana" in Silk, Jonathan A (editor in chief). Brill's Encyclopedia of Buddhism Volume II: Lives.
  169. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl, When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra, Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 117.
  170. ^ Lusthaus, Dan, Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun, Routledge, 2014, p. 274.
  171. ^ a b Lusthaus, Dan, Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun, Routledge, 2014, pp. 8-10.
  172. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl, When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra, Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 118.
  173. ^ a b Kano, Kazuo. "Sajjana and Mahājana: Yogācāra Exegeses in the Eleventh Century Kashmir." Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu (Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies) 69, no. 2 (2021): 118–124
  174. ^ a b Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 74.
  175. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 142. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3.
  176. ^ Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals? p. 6. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-023129-3
  177. ^ a b Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005) pp.117-122
  178. ^ Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 10.
  179. ^ Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 81.
  180. ^ Komarovski, Yaroslav, Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 80.
  181. ^ Paul, Diana. Philosophy of Mind in Sixth-Century China: Paramartha's Evolution of Consciousness. 1984. p. 6
  182. ^ Paul, Diana. Philosophy of Mind in Sixth-Century China: Paramartha's Evolution of Consciousness. 1984. pp. 32-33
  183. ^ Muller, A.C. "Quick Overview of the Faxiang School 法相宗". www.acmuller.net. Retrieved 2023-04-24.
  184. ^ Jorgensen, John; Lusthaus, Dan; Makeham, John; Strange, Mark, trans. (2019), Treatise on Awakening Mahāyāna Faith, New York, NY: Oxford University Press, in Introduction (pp. 1–10).
  185. ^ a b c Liu, JeeLoo. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism. 2006. p. 220
  186. ^ Wei Tat. Cheng Weishi Lun. 1973. p. li
  187. ^ Tagawa, Shun'ei (2009). Charles Muller (ed.). Living Yogacara: An Introduction to Consciousness-Only Buddhism. Wisdom Publications. p. xx-xxi (forward). ISBN 978-0-86171-589-3.
  188. ^ Liu, JeeLoo. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism. 2006. p. 221
  189. ^ Green, Ronald S. (2020). Early Japanese Hosso in Relation to Silla Yogacara in Disputes between Nara'€™s Northern and Southern Temple Traditions. Journal of Korean Religions, 11(1), 97–121. doi:10.1353/jkr.2020.0003
  190. ^ Makeham, John. Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China, pp. 13-14. Oxford University Press, 2014
  191. ^ Khyentse Rinpoche, Dzongsar Jamyang (2003). "Introduction". In Alex Trisoglio (ed.). Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti's Madhyamakavatara with Commentary (PDF) (1st ed.). Dordogne, France: Khyentse Foundation. p. 8. Retrieved 7 January 2013. In the 8th century, Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the monastery at Samyé. He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka, but the disciple of one of his disciples. He combined the Madhyamika-Svatantrika and Cittamatra schools, and created a new school of Madhyamika called Svatantrika-Yogachara-Madhyamika. His disciple Kamalashila, who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika (uma'i sgom rim), developed his ideas further, and together they were very influential in Tibet.
  192. ^ Germano, David F.; Waldron, William S. (2006), "A Comparison of Alaya-vijñāna in Yogacara and Dzogchen" (PDF), in Nauriyal, D. K.; Drummond, Michael S.; Lal, Y. B. (eds.), Buddhist Thought and Applied Psychological Research: Transcending the boundaries, Abingdon, Oxon.: Routledge, pp. 36–68, ISBN 978-0-415-37431-6
  193. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl. Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature, Introduction. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009).
  194. ^ Taranatha. . Jonang Foundation. Archived from the original on December 13, 2012. Retrieved 19 December 2012. Accordingly, those who adhere to rangtong take the first wheel of the Buddha's teachings which is the Wheel of Dharma that teaches the Four Noble Truths to be provisional in meaning, the middle Wheel of Dharma that teaches the absence of characteristics as ultimately definitive in meaning, and the final excellently distinguished Wheel of Dharma as teaching the circumstantial definitive meaning, which is provisional in meaning. Those who uphold zhentong take the first Wheel of Dharma to be provisional, the middle Wheel of Dharma to teach the circumstantial definitive meaning, and the final Wheel of Dharma to teach to ultimate definitive meaning.
  195. ^ Je Tsongkhapa (1993). Kapstein, Matthew (ed.). Ocean of Eloquence: Tsong kha pa's Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind (in Tibetan and English). Sparham, Gareth, trans.; in collaboration with Shotaro Iida (1st. ed.). Albany, NY: State University of New York. ISBN 0791414795. Retrieved 18 December 2012.
  196. ^ Berzin, Alexander. "Brief Survey of Self-voidness and Other-voidness Views". Retrieved 20 June 2016.
  197. ^ a b Dumoulin, Heinrich (2005). Zen Buddhism: A History. Vol. 1 India and China. Bloomington, IN: World Wisdom. p. 52. ISBN 0-941532-89-5.
  198. ^ a b Kapstein, Matthew T. Tibetan Buddhism: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014, p. 64.
  199. ^ Torella, Raffaele. "The Pratyabhijñā and the logical-epistemological school of Buddhism" in Goudriaan ed. (1992) Ritual and Speculation in Early Tantrism: Studies in Honor of Andre Padoux pp. 327-346. SUNY Press.
  200. ^ Stcherbatsky, Fyodor Th. Buddhist Logic. Vol. I, p. 51. Dover Publications.
  201. ^ Keown, Damien (2004). A Dictionary of Buddhism, p. 302. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-860560-7.
  202. ^ Powers, John. The Yogācāra School of Buddhism: A Bibliography, p. 18. American Theological Library Association, 1991.
  203. ^ Paul Williams; Anthony Tribe; Alexander Wynne. Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition. p. 121. 2012.
  204. ^ Muller, A.C. "Quick Overview of the Faxiang School 法相宗". www.acmuller.net. Retrieved 2023-04-24.
  205. ^ Makeham, John. Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China, p. 6. Oxford University Press, 2014
  206. ^ a b Kritzer (2005), p. xii.
  207. ^ Fernando Tola, Carmen Dragonetti. Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of Buddhism, p. xii
  208. ^ Foundations of Buddhism, by Rupert Gethin. Oxford University Press: 1998. ISBN 0-19-289223-1
  209. ^ Williams, 2008, p. 103.
  210. ^ Harris, Ian Charles (1991). The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra in Indian Mahāyāna Buddhism, p. 78. BRILL.
  211. ^ "Ghanavyūhasūtra - Buddha-Nature". buddhanature.tsadra.org. Retrieved 2023-08-07.
  212. ^ T1830 成唯識論述記 [T43.229c29-230a1], CBETA
  213. ^ Shih, Jen-Kuan (2006). Doctrinal Connection Between Panjiao Schemata and Human Capacity for Enlightenment in Jizang's and Kuiji's Thought. University of Wisconsin--Madison.
  214. ^ Keenan, John P. The Interpretation of the Buddha Land, BDK English Tripitaka, Numata Center for Buddhist Translation & Research, 2006.
  215. ^ Makransky, John J. (1997). Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet, p. 10. SUNY. ISBN 0-7914-3431-1. — a study of interpretations of the Abhisamayalankara.
  216. ^ Brunnhölzl, Karl (2014). "The Meditative Tradition of the Uttaratantra and Shentong". When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sūtra and Tantra. Boston: Snow Lion Publications. pp. 123–50.
  217. ^ a b Williams (2008), pp. 87-88.
  218. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl. Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature pp. 10-11. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009).
  219. ^ D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
  220. ^ D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” Journal of Indian Philosophy, vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024.
  221. ^ Lugli, Ligeia, Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com, LAST MODIFIED: 25 NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
  222. ^ Kalupahana 1992, p. 126.
  223. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl. Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature p. 9. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009).
  224. ^ Lugli, Ligeia, Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com, LAST MODIFIED: 25 NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
  225. ^ Makransky, John J. Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet SUNY Press, 1997, p. 187.
  226. ^ Brunnholzl, Karl, When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra, Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 81.
  227. ^ "Śaṅkaranandana" in Silk, Jonathan A (editor in chief). Brill's Encyclopedia of Buddhism Volume II: Lives.
  228. ^ Sinclair, Iain. Dharmakirti of Kedah: His, life, work and troubled times. Temasek Working Paper No. 2: 2021. Temasek History Research Centre ISEAS – Yusof Ishak Institute

Sources edit

  • Bayer, Achim (2012). Hamburg: Zentrum für Buddhismuskunde.
  • Kalupahana, David J. (1992), The Principles of Buddhist Psychology, Delhi: ri Satguru Publications
  • Keenan, John P. (1993). Yogācarā. pp. 203–212 published in Yoshinori, Takeuchi; with Van Bragt, Jan; Heisig, James W.; O'Leary, Joseph S.; Swanson, Paul L.(1993). Buddhist Spirituality: Indian, Southeast Asian, Tibetan, and Early Chinese. New York City: The Crossroad Publishing Company. ISBN 0-8245-1277-4
  • King, Richard (1998). "Vijnaptimatrata and the Abhidharma context of early Yogacara". Asian Philosophy. 8 (1): 5–18. doi:10.1080/09552369808575468.
  • Kochumuttom, Thomas A. (1999), A buddhist Doctrine of Experience. A New Translation and Interpretation of the Works of Vasubandhu the Yogacarin, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass
  • Norbu, Namkhai (2001), The Precious Vase: Instructions on the Base of Santi Maha Sangha. Shang Shung Edizioni. Second revised edition. (Translated from the Tibetan, edited and annotated by Adriano Clemente with the help of the author. Translated from Italian into English by Andy Lukianowicz.)
  • Park, Sung-bae (1983), Buddhist Faith and Sudden Enlightenment, SUNY Press
  • Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005). The Adornment of the Middle Way Padmakara Translation of Ju Mipham's commentary on Shantarakshita's root versus on his synthesis.
  • Sponberg, Alan (1979). Dynamic Liberation in Yogacara Buddhism, Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 2(1), pp. 44–64.
  • Stcherbatsky, Theodore (1936). ascribed to Bodhisattva Maiteya and commented by Vasubhandu and Sthiramathi, translated from the sanscrit, Academy of Sciences USSR Press, Moscow/Leningrad.
  • Timme Kragh, Ulrich (editor) 2013, The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners: The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1 Harvard University, Department of South Asian studies.
  • Zim, Robert (1995). Basic ideas of Yogacara Buddhism. San Francisco State University. Source: [4] (accessed: October 18, 2007).

External links edit

  • Uncompromising Idealism or the School of Vijñānavāda Buddhism, Surendranath Dasgupta, 1940
  • "Early Yogaacaara and Its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School", Richard King, Philosophy East & West, vol. 44 no. 4, October 1994, pp. 659–683
  • "The mind-only teaching of Ching-ying Hui-Yuan" (subtitle) "An early interpretation of Yogaacaara thought in China", Ming-Wood Liu, Philosophy East & West, vol. 35 no. 4, October 1985, pp. 351–375
  • Yogacara Buddhism Research Association; articles, bibliographies, and links to other relevant sites.

yogachara, sanskrit, iast, yogācāra, influential, tradition, buddhist, philosophy, psychology, emphasizing, study, cognition, perception, consciousness, through, interior, lens, meditation, well, philosophical, reasoning, hetuvidyā, most, influential, traditio. Yogachara Sanskrit य ग च र IAST Yogacara is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of cognition perception and consciousness through the interior lens of meditation as well as philosophical reasoning hetuvidya 1 2 Yogachara was one of the two most influential traditions of Mahayana Buddhism in India along with Madhyamaka 3 Translations ofYogacara schoolEnglishYoga Practice Doctrine of Consciousness Consciousness Only Doctrine Cognizance Only Mind OnlySanskritYogacara Vijnanavada Vijnaptivada Vijnaptimatrata CittamatraChinese唯識瑜伽行派 Pinyin Weishi Yuqiexing Pai Japanese瑜伽行唯識派 Rōmaji Yugagyō Yuishiki Ha Korean유식유가행파 RR Yusik Yugahaeng pa Tibetanར ལ འབ ར ས ད པ rnal byor spyod pa VietnameseDu gia Hanh TongGlossary of BuddhismThe compound Yogacara literally means practitioner of yoga or one whose practice is yoga hence the name of the school is literally the school of the yogins 4 3 Yogacara was also variously termed Vijnanavada the doctrine of consciousness Vijnaptivada the doctrine of ideas or percepts or Vijnaptimatrata vada the doctrine of mere representation which is also the name given to its major theory of mind which seeks to deconstruct how we perceive the world There are several interpretations of this main theory various forms of Idealism as well as a phenomenology or representationalism Aside from this Yogacara also developed an elaborate analysis of consciousness vijnana and mental phenomena dharmas as well as an extensive system of Buddhist spiritual practice i e yoga 1 The movement has been traced to the first centuries of the common era and seems to have developed as some yogis of the Sarvastivada and Sautrantika traditions in north India adopted Mahayana Buddhism 5 6 The Gandharan brothers Asaṅga and Vasubandhu both c 4 5th century CE are considered the classic philosophers and systematizers of this school along with the figure of Maitreya 7 Yogacara was later imported to Tibet and East Asia by figures like Shantaraksita 8th century and Xuanzang 7th century Today Yogacara ideas and texts continue to be influential subjects of study for Tibetan Buddhism and East Asian Buddhism Contents 1 Doctrine 1 1 The doctrine of vijnapti matra 1 1 1 Origins 1 2 Interpretations of vijnapti matra 1 2 1 Idealism 1 2 2 Mere representation 1 2 3 Soterological phenomenology 1 3 Arguments for consciousness only 1 3 1 Explanatory equivalence argument 1 3 2 Causation resemblance argument 1 3 3 Constant co cognition argument 1 3 4 Soteriological importance of mind only 1 4 Analysis of Consciousness 1 4 1 Eight consciousnesses 1 4 2 Alaya vijnana 1 4 3 Transformations of consciousness 1 5 The Three Natures 1 6 Emptiness 1 7 Disagreement with Madhyamaka 1 8 Two interpretations of the three natures 1 9 Karma 1 10 Meditation and awakening 1 11 Five Categories of Beings 1 12 Mental images true vs false 2 Practice 2 1 Bodhisattva path 2 2 Bodhisattva practice 2 2 1 The four investigations and four correct cognitions 2 2 2 Four prayogas 2 3 Meditation 3 History 3 1 Origin and early Yogacara 3 2 Classical Yogacara Asaṅga and Vasubandhu 3 3 The middle period and the epistemological turn 3 4 Yogacara tathagatagarbha synthesis 3 5 Yogacara and Madhyamaka 3 6 Yogacara in East Asia 3 7 Yogacara in Tibet 3 8 Influence 4 Textual corpus 4 1 Sutras 4 2 Treatises 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 Sources 9 External linksDoctrine editYogacara philosophy is primarily meant to aid in the practice of yoga and meditation and thus it also sets forth a systematic analysis of the Mahayana path of mental training see five paths pancamarga 8 Yogacarins made use of ideas from previous traditions such as Prajnaparamita and the Sarvastivada Abhidharma tradition to develop a novel analysis of conscious experience and a corresponding schema for Mahayana spiritual practice 9 10 11 In its analysis Yogacara works like the Saṅdhinirmocana Sutra developing various core concepts such as vijnapti matra the alaya vijnana store consciousness the turning of the basis asraya paravṛtti the three natures trisvabhava and emptiness 1 They form a complex system and each can be taken as a point of departure for understanding Yogacara 12 The doctrine of vijnapti matra edit One of the main features of Yogacara philosophy is the concept of vijnapti matra It is often used interchangeably with the term citta matra in modern and ancient Yogacara sources 7 13 14 The standard translation of both terms is consciousness only or mind only Several modern researchers object to this translation in favor of alternative like representation only 10 The meaning of this term is at the heart of the modern scholarly disagreement about whether Yogacara Buddhism can be said to be a form of idealism as supported by Garfield Hopkins and others or whether it is definitely not idealist Anacker Lusthaus Wayman 15 Origins edit According to Lambert Schmithausen the earliest surviving appearance of this term is in chapter 8 of the Saṅdhinirmocana Sutra which has only survived in Tibetan and Chinese translations that differ in syntax and meaning 16 The passage is depicted as a response by the Buddha to a question which asks whether the images or replicas pratibimba which are the object gocara of meditative concentration samadhi are different separate bhinna from the contemplating mind citta or not The Buddha says they are not different Because these images are vijnapti matra The text goes on to affirm that the same is true for objects of ordinary perception 17 The term is sometimes used as a synonym with citta matra mere citta which is also used as a name for the school that suggests Idealism 7 13 Schmithausen writes that the first appearance of this term is in the Pratyupanna samadhi sutra which states this or whatever belongs to this triple world is nothing but mind or thought cittamatra Why Because however I imagine things that is how they appear 18 Regarding existing Sanskrit sources the term appears in the first verse of Vasubandhu s Vimsatika Twenty Verses which states 19 This world is vijnaptimatra since it manifests itself as an unreal object artha just like the case of those with cataracts seeing unreal hairs in the moon and the like vijnaptimatram evaitad asad arthavabhasanat yatha taimirikasyasat kesa candradi darsanam According to Mark Siderits what Vasubandhu means here is that we are only ever aware of mental images or impressions which manifest themselves as external objects but there is actually no such thing outside the mind 19 The term also appears in Asaṅga s classic work the Mahayanasaṃgraha no Sanskrit original trans from Tibetan These representations vijnapti are mere representations vijnapti matra because there is no corresponding thing object artha Just as in a dream there appear even without a thing object artha just in the mind alone forms images of all kinds of things objects like visibles sounds smells tastes tangibles houses forests land and mountains and yet there are no such things objects at all in that place MSg II 6 20 Another classic statement of the doctrine appears in Dharmakirti s Pramanaṿarttika Commentary on Epistemology which states cognition experiences itself and nothing else whatsoever Even the particular objects of perception are by nature just consciousness itself 21 Interpretations of vijnapti matra edit Idealism edit According to Bruce Cameron Hall the interpretation of this doctrine as a form of subjective or absolute idealism has been the most common outside interpretation of Vijnanavada not only by modern writers but by its ancient opponents both Hindu and Buddhist 22 Scholars such as Jay Garfield Saam Trivedi Nobuyoshi Yamabe Paul Williams and Sean Butler argue that Yogacara is similar to Idealism and they compare it to the idealisms of Kant and Berkeley though they note that it is its own unique form and that it might be confusing to categorize it as such 23 24 25 26 27 The German scholar and philologist Lambert Schmithausen affirms that Yogacara sources teach a type of idealism which is supposed to be a middle way between Abhidharma realism and what it often considered a nihilistic position which only affirms emptiness as the ultimate 28 Schmithausen notes that philological study of Yogacara texts shows that they clearly reject the independent existence of mind and the external world 29 He also notes that the current trend in rejecting the idealistic interpretation might be related to the unpopularity of idealism among Western academics 29 Florin Delenau likewise affirms the idealist nature of Yogacara texts while also underscoring how Yogacara retains a strong orientation to a soteriology which aims at contemplative realization of an ultimate reality that is an inexpressible essence nirabhilapyasvabhava beyond any subject object duality 3 Similarly Jonathan Gold writes that the Yogacara thinker Vasubandhu can be said to be an idealist similar to Kant in the sense that for him everything in experience as well as its causal support is mental and thus he gives causal priority to the mental At the same time however this is only in the conventional realm since mind is just another concept and true reality for Vasubandhu is ineffable an inconceivable thusness tathata Indeed the Vimsatika states that the very idea of vijnapti matra must also be understood to be itself a self less construction and thus vijnapti matra is not the ultimate truth paramartha satya in Yogacara 13 Thus according to Gold while Vasubandhu s vijnapti matra can be said to be a conventionalist idealism it is to be seen as unique and different from Western forms especially Hegelian Absolute Idealism 13 Mere representation edit The interpretation of Yogacara as a type of idealism was standard until recently when it began to be challenged by scholars such as Kochumuttom Anacker Kalupahana 30 Dunne Lusthaus 31 Powers and Wayman 32 a Some scholars like David Kalupahana argue that it is a mistake to conflate the terms citta matra which is sometimes seen as a different more metaphysical position with vijnapti matra which need not be idealist 10 33 However Delenau points out that Vasubandhu clearly states in his Twenty Verses and Abhidharmakosha that vijnapti and citta are synonymous 34 Nevertheless different alternative translations for vijnapti matra have been proposed such as representation only ideation only impressions only and perception only 22 35 36 7 Alex Wayman notes that one s interpretation of Yogacara will depend on how the qualifier matra is to be understood in this context and he objects to interpretations which claim that Yogacara rejects the external world altogether preferring translations such as amounting to mind or mirroring mind for citta matra 36 For Wayman what this doctrine means is that the mind has only a report or representation of what the sense organ had sensed 36 The representationalist interpretation is also supported by Stefan Anacker 37 According to Thomas Kochumuttom Yogacara is a realistic pluralism which does not deny the existence of individual beings 10 Kochumuttom argues that Yogacara is not idealism since it denies that absolute reality is a consciousness that individual beings are transformations or illusory appearances of an absolute consciousness 38 Thus for Kochumuttom vijnapti matra means mere representation of consciousness a view which states that the world as it appears to the unenlightened ones is mere representation of consciousness 35 Furthermore according to Kochumuttom in Yogacara the absolute state is defined simply as emptiness namely the emptiness of subject object distinction Once thus defined as emptiness sunyata it receives a number of synonyms none of which betray idealism 39 Soterological phenomenology edit According to Dan Lusthaus the vijnapti matra theory is closer in some ways to Western Phenomenological theories and Epistemological Idealism However it is not a form of metaphysical idealism because Yogacara rejects the construction of any type of metaphysical or ontological theories 1 Moreover Western idealism lacks any counterpart to karma samsara or awakening all of which are central for Yogacara Regarding vijnapti matra Lusthaus translates it as nothing but conscious construction and states it is a kind of trick built into consciousness which projects and constructs a cognitive object in such a way that it disowns its own creation pretending the object is out there in order to render that object capable of being appropriated This reification of cognition aids in constructing the notion of a permanent and independent self which is believed to appropriate and possess external things Yogacara offers an analysis and meditative means to negate this reification thereby also negating the notion of a solid self According to Lusthaus this analysis is not a rejection of external phenomena and it does not grant foundational or transcendent status to consciousness 1 In this interpretation instead of offering an ontological theory Yogacara focuses on understanding and eliminating the underlying tendencies anusaya that lead to clinging concepts and theories which are just cognitive projections pratibimba parikalpita Thus for Lusthaus the orientation of the Yogacara school is largely consistent with the thinking of the Pali nikayas and seeks to realign Mahayana with early Buddhist theory 40 Arguments for consciousness only edit According to the contemporary philosopher Jan Westerhoff Yogacara philosophers came up with various arguments in defense of the consciousness only view He outlines three main arguments the explanatory equivalence argument the causation resemblance argument and the constant co cognition argument 41 Explanatory equivalence argument edit This argument is found in Vasubandhu s Vimsatika Twenty Verses and is an inference to the best explanation It argues that consciousness only can provide an account of the various features of experience which are explained by the existence of mind independent material objects This is coupled with a principle of ontological parsimony to argue in favor of idealism 41 Vasubandhu mentions three key features of experience which are supposed to be explained by matter and refutes them 42 43 44 According to critics the problem of spatio temporal determination or non arbitrariness in regard to place and time indicates that there must be some external basis for our experiences since experiences of any particular object do not occur everywhere and at every time Vasubandhu responds with the dream argument which shows how a world created by mind can still seem to have spatio temporal localization The problem of inter subjective experience multiple minds experiencing the same world Vasubandhu counters that mass hallucinations such as those said to occur to hungry ghosts caused by the fact they share similar karma which is here understood as traces or seeds in the mind stream show that inter subjective agreement is possible without positing real external objects Another criticism states that hallucinations have no pragmatic results efficacy or causal function and thus can be determined to be unreal but entities we generally accept as being real have actual causal results such as the resistance of external objects that cannot be of the same class as hallucinations Against this claim Vasubandhu argues that waking life is the same as in a dream where objects have pragmatic results within the very rules of the dream He also uses the example of a wet dream to show that mental content can have causal efficacy even outside of a dream According to Mark Siderits after disposing of these objections Vasubandhu believes he has shown that mere cognizance is just as good at explaining the relevant phenomena of experience as any theory of realism that posits external objects Therefore he then applies the Indian philosophical principle termed the Principle of Lightness Sanskrit laghava which is similar to Occam s Razor to rule out realism since vijnapti matra is the simpler and lighter theory which posits the least number of unobservable entities 45 Another objection that Vasubandhu answers is that of how one person can influence another s experiences if everything arises from mental karmic seeds in one s mind stream Vasubandhu argues that impressions can also be caused in a mental stream by the occurrence of a distinct impression in another suitably linked mental stream 46 As Siderits notes this account can explain how it is possible to influence or even totally disrupt murder another mind even if there is no physical medium or object in existence since a suitably strong enough intention in one mind stream can have effects on another mind stream 46 From the mind only position it is easier to posit a mind to mind causation than to have to explain mind to body causation which the realist must do However Siderits then goes on to question whether Vasubandhu s position is indeed lighter since he must make use of multiple interactions between different minds to take into account an intentionally created artifact like a pot Since we can be aware of a pot even when we are not linked to the potter s intentions even after the potter is dead a more complex series of mental interactions must be posited 47 Nevertheless not all interpretations of Yogacara s view of the external world rely on multiple relations between individual minds Some interpretations in Chinese Buddhism defended the view of a single shared external world bhajanaloka which was still made of consciousness while some later Indian thinkers like Ratnakirti 11th century CE defended a type of non dual monism 48 49 Causation resemblance argument edit This argument was famously defended in Dignaga s Alambanaparikṣa Examination of the Object of Consciousness and its main target is Indian atomism which was the main theory of matter in the 5th century 50 The argument is based on the premise that a perception must resemble the perceived object alambana and have been caused by the object 50 41 According to this argument since atoms are not extended they do not resemble the object of perception which appears as spatially extended Furthermore collections of atoms might resemble the object of perception but they cannot have caused it This is because collections of things are unreal in classic Buddhist thought thus it is a mereological nihilism since they are composites and composites made of parts do not have any causal efficacy only individual atoms do 50 41 In disproving the possibility of external objects Vasubandhu s Vimsatika similarly attacks Indian theories of atomism and property particulars as incoherent on mereological grounds 51 Constant co cognition argument editThis argument was defended by Dharmakirti in his Ascertainment of Epistemology Pramaṇaviniscaya which calls it the necessity of things only ever being experienced together with experience Sanskrit sahopalambhaniyama 50 According to Dharmakirti Because something blue is not apprehended without the additional qualification of consciousness and because blue is apprehended when this qualification of consciousness is apprehended consciousness itself has the appearance of blue There is no external object by itself PV 3 335 50 According this argument any object of consciousness like blue cannot be differentiated from the conscious awareness of blue since both are always experienced as one thing Since we never experience blue without the experience of blue they cannot be differentiated empirically Furthermore we cannot differentiate them through an inference either since this would need to be based on a pattern of past experiences which included the absence or presence of the two elements 50 41 Thus this is a type of epistemological argument for idealism which attempts to show there is no good reason to accept the existence of mind independent objects 50 Soteriological importance of mind only editVasubandhu also explains why it is soteriologically important to get rid of the idea of really existing external objects According to Siderits this is because When we wrongly imagine there to be external objects we are led to think in terms of the duality of grasped and grasper of what is out there and what is in here in short of external world and self Coming to see that there is no external world is a means Vasubandhu thinks of overcoming a very subtle way of believing in an I once we see why physical objects can t exist we will lose all temptation to think there is a true me within There are really just impressions but we superimpose on these the false constructions of object and subject Seeing this will free us from the false conception of an I 52 Siderits notes how Kant had a similar notion that is without the idea of an objective mind independent world one cannot derive the concept of a subjective I But Kant drew the opposite conclusion to Vasubandhu since he held that we must believe in an enduring subject and thus also believe in external objects 52 Analysis of Consciousness edit Yogacara gives a detailed explanation of the workings of the mind and the way it constructs the reality we experience The central Yogacara theory of mind is that of the eight consciousnesses Eight consciousnesses edit Main article Eight Consciousnesses A key innovation of the Yogacara school was the doctrine of eight consciousnesses 1 These eight bodies of consciousnesses aṣṭa vijnanakayaḥ are the five sense consciousnesses of seeing hearing smelling tasting and bodily sense mentation mano or citta the defiled self consciousness kliṣṭamanovijnana 53 and the storehouse or substratum consciousness Skt alayavijnana 54 55 Traditional Buddhist descriptions of consciousness taught just the first six vijnanas each corresponding to a sense base ayatana and having their own sense objects sounds etc Five are based on the five senses while the sixth mano vijnana was seen as the surveyor of the content of the five senses as well as of mental content like thoughts and ideas Standard Buddhist doctrine held that these eighteen elements dhatus i e six external sense bases smells sounds etc six internal bases sense organs like the eye ear etc and six consciousnesses exhaust the full extent of everything in the universe or more accurately the sensorium 1 The six consciousnesses are also not substantial entities but a series or stream of events dharmas which arise and vanish very rapidly moment by moment This is the Abhidharma doctrine of momentariness kṣaṇavada which Yogacara also accepts 56 Yogacara expanded the six vijnana schema into a new system which with two new categories The seventh consciousness developed from the early Buddhist concept of manas and was seen as the defiled mentation kliṣṭa manas which is obsessed with notions of self According to Paul Williams this consciousness takes the substratum consciousness as its object and mistakenly considers the substratum consciousness to be a true Self 55 Alaya vijnana edit The eighth consciousness alaya vijnana storehouse or repository consciousness was defined as the storehouse of all karmic seeds bija where they gradually matured until ripe at which point they manifested as karmic consequences Because of this it is also called the mind which has all the seeds sarvabijakam cittam as well as the basis consciousness mula vijnana and the appropriating consciousness adanavijnana According to the Saṅdhinirmocana Sutra this kind of consciousness underlies and supports the six types of manifest awareness all of which occur simultaneously with the alaya 57 William S Waldron sees this simultaneity of all the modes of cognitive awareness as the most significant departure of Yogacara theory from traditional Buddhist models of vijnana which were thought to occur solely in conjunction with their respective sense bases and epistemic objects 58 As noted by Schmithausen the alaya vijnana being a kind of vijnana has an object as well as all vijnana has intentionality That object is the sentient being s surrounding world that is to say the receptable or container bhajana world This is stated in the 8th chapter of the Saṅdhinirmocana Sutra which states that the adanavijnana is characterized by an unconscious or not fully conscious steady perception or representation of the Receptacle asaṃvidita sthira bhajana vijnapti 59 The alaya vijnana is also what experiences rebirth into future lives and what descents into the womb to appropriate the fetal material Therefore the alaya vijnana s holding on to the body s sense faculties and profuse imaginings prapanca are the two appropriations which make up the kindling or fuel lit upadana that samsaric existence depends upon 57 Yogacara thought thus holds that being unaware of the processes going on in the alaya vijnana is an important element of ignorance avidya The alaya is also individual so that each person has their own alaya vijnana which is an ever changing process and therefore not a permanent self 1 According to Williams this consciousness seen as a defiled form of consciousness or perhaps sub or unconsciousness is personal individual continually changing and yet serving to give a degree of personal identity and to explain why it is that certain karmic results pertain to this particular individual The seeds are momentary but they give rise to a perfumed series which eventually culminates in the result including from seeds of a particular type the whole inter subjective phenomenal world 60 Also Asanga and Vasubandhu write that the alaya vijnana ceases at awakening becoming transformed into a pure consciousness 61 According to Waldron while there were various similar concepts in other Buddhist Abhidharma schools which sought to explain karmic continuity the alaya vijnana is the most comprehensive and systematic 62 Waldron notes that the alaya vijnana concept was probably influenced by these theories particularly the Sautrantika theory of seeds and Vasumitra s theory of a subtle form of mind suksma citta 63 Transformations of consciousness edit Yogacara sources do not necessarily describe the eight consciousnesses as absolutely separate or substantial phenomena For example Kalupahana notes that the Triṃsika describes the various forms of consciousness as transformations and functions of a being s stream of consciousness 64 65 b These transformations are threefold according to Kalupahana The first is the alaya and its seeds which is the flow or stream of consciousness without any of the usual projections on top of it 65 The second transformation is manana self consciousness or Self view self confusion self esteem and self love 66 It is thinking about the various perceptions occurring in the stream of consciousness 67 The alaya is defiled by this self interest 66 The third transformation is visaya vijnapti the concept of the object 68 In this transformation the concept of objects is created By creating these concepts human beings become susceptible to grasping after the object as if it were a real object sad artha even though it is just a conception vijnapti 68 A similar perspective which emphasizes Yogacara s continuity with early Buddhism is given by Walpola Rahula According to Rahula all the elements of this theory of consciousness with its three layers of vijnana are already found in the Pali Canon corresponding to the terms vinnana sense cognition manas mental function thinking reasoning conception and citta the deepest layer of the aggregate of consciousness which retains karmic impressions and the defilements 69 70 The Three Natures editYogacara works often define three basic modes or natures svabhava of experience Jonathan Gold explains that the three natures are all one reality viewed from three distinct angles They are the appearance the process and the emptiness of that same apparent entity 13 According to Paul Williams all things which can be known can be subsumed under these Three Natures 71 Since this schema is Yogacara s systematic explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of emptiness sunyata each of the three natures are also explained as having a lack of own nature niḥsvabhavata 72 73 The Trisvabhava nirdesa Exposition of the Three Natures gives a brief definition of these three natures What appears is the dependent How it appears is the fabricated Because of being dependent on conditions Because of being only fabrication The eternal non existence of the appearance as it is appears That is known to be the perfected nature because of being always the same What appears there The unreal fabrication How does it appear As a dual self What is its nonexistence That by which the nondual reality is there 13 In detail three natures trisvabhava are 71 74 75 13 Parikalpita svabhava the fully conceptualized or imagined nature This is the imaginary or constructed nature wherein things are incorrectly comprehended based on conceptual construction through the activity of language and through attachment and erroneous discrimination which attributes intrinsic existence to things According to the Mahayanasaṃgraha it also refers to the appearance of things in terms of subject object dualism literally grasper and grasped The conceptualized nature is the world of everyday unenlightened people i e samsara It is false and empty and does not really exist Triṃsika v 20 According to Xuanzang s Cheng Weishi Lun this nature is an absence of an existential nature by its very defining characteristic lakṣana niḥsvabhavata Because these conceptualized natures and distinct characteristics lakṣana are wrongly imputed and not truly real they are like mirages and blossoms in the sky Paratantra svabhava literally other dependent which is the dependently originated nature of dharmas or the causal flow of phenomena which is erroneously confused into the conceptualized nature According to Williams it is the basis for the erroneous partition into supposedly intrinsically existing subjects and objects which marks the conceptualized nature Jonathan Gold writes that it is the causal process of the thing s fabrication the causal story that brings about the thing s apparent nature This basis is considered to be an ultimately existing paramartha basis in classical Yogacara see Mahayanasaṃgraha 2 25 76 However as Xuanzang notes this nature is also empty in that there is an absence of an existential nature in conditions that arise and perish utpatti niḥsvabhavata That is the events in this causal flow while seeming to have real existence of their own are actually like magical illusions since they are said to only be hypothetical and not really exist on their own As Siderits writes to the extent that we are thinking of it at all even if only as the non dual flow of impressions only we are still conceptualizing it Pariniṣpanna svabhava literally fully accomplished perfected consummated This is the true nature of things the experience of Suchness or Thatness Tathata discovered in meditation unaffected by conceptualization causality or duality It is defined as the complete absence in the dependent nature of objects that is the objects of the conceptualized nature see Mahayanasaṃgraha 2 4 76 What this refers to is that empty non dual experience which has been stripped of the duality of the constructed nature through yogic praxis According to Williams this is what has to be known for enlightenment and Siderits defines it as just pure seeing without any attempt at conceptualization or interpretation Now this is also empty but only of itself as an interpretation That is this mode of cognition is devoid of all concepts and so is empty of being of the nature of the perfected About it nothing can be said or thought it is just pure immediacy According to Xuanzang this nature has the absence of any existential nature of ultimate meaning paramartha niḥsvabhavata since it is completely free from any clinging to entirely imagined speculations about its identity or purpose Because of this it is conventionally said that it does not exist However it is also not entirely without a real existence Emptiness edit The central meaning of emptiness sunyata in Yogacara is a twofold absence of duality The first element of this is the unreality of any conceptual duality such as physical and non physical self and other To define something conceptually is to divide the world into what it is and what it is not but the world is a causal flux that does not accord with conceptual constructs 13 The second element of this is a perceptual duality between the sensorium and its objects between what is external and internal between subject grahaka literally grasper and object grahya grasped 77 This is also an unreal superimposition since there is really no such separation of inner and outer but an interconnected causal stream of mentality which is falsely divided up 13 An important difference between the Yogacara conception of emptiness and the Madhyamaka conception is that in classical Yogacara emptiness does exist as a real absence and so does consciousness which is that which is empty the referent of emptiness while Madhyamaka refuses to endorse such existential statements The Madhyantavibhaga for example states the imagination of the nonexistent abhuta parikalpa exists In it duality does not exist Emptiness however exists in it which indicates that even though that which is dualistically imagined subjects and objects is unreal and empty their basis does exist i e the dependently arisen conscious manifestation 78 79 The Yogacara school also gave special significance to the Agama sutra called Lesser Discourse on Emptiness parallel to the Pali Cuḷasunnatasutta MN 121 and relies on this sutra in its explanations of emptiness According to Gadjin Nagao this sutra affirms that emptiness includes both being and non being both negation and affirmation 80 c Disagreement with Madhyamaka edit Indian sources indicate that Yogacara thinkers sometimes debated with the defenders of the Madhyamaka tradition 82 However there is disagreement among contemporary Western and traditional Buddhist scholars about the degree to which they were opposed if at all 83 The main difference between these schools was related to issues of existence and the nature of emptiness The Chinese pilgrim Yijing 635 713 concisely summarized the differences thus For Yogacara the real exists but the conventional does not exist and Yogacara takes the three natures as foundational For Madhyamaka the real does not exist but the conventional does exist and actually the two truths are primary 84 Garfield and Westerhoff write that Yogacara is both ontologically and epistemologically foundationalist Madhyamaka is antifoundationalist in both senses 83 Another way to state this key difference is that Madhyamaka defends a global antirealism while Yogacara restrict s the scope of their antirealism to the external and the conventional 82 While Madhyamaka generally states that asserting the ultimate existence or non existence of anything including emptiness was inappropriate Yogacara treatises like the Madhyantavibhaga often assert that the dependent nature paratantra svabhava really exists and that emptiness is an actual absence that also exists ultimatelly 79 In a similar fashion Asaṅga states that of which it is empty does not truly exist that which is empty truly exists emptiness makes sense in this way 85 He also describes emptiness as the non existence of the self and the existence of the no self 78 Classical Yogacaras like Vasubandhu and Sthiramati also affirm the reality of conscious appearance i e that truly existent stream of dependent arisen and constantly changing consciousness which projects false and illusory subjective minds and their cognitive objects It is this real flow of conscious transformation vijnanapariṇama which is said to be empty of duality and conceptuality 86 Against the radically anti foundationalist interpretation of Madhyamaka the classic Yogacara position is that there is something the dependent nature which is mere consciousness that exists sat independently of conceptual designation prajnapti and that it is this real thing vastu which is said to be empty of duality and yet is a basis for all dualistic conceptions 87 Furthermore Yogacara thinkers like Asaṅga and Vasubandhu critiqued those who adhere to non existence nastikas vainaskas likely referring to certain Madhyamikas because they saw them as straying into metaphysical nihilism abhavanta see Vimsatika v 10 73 78 They held that there was really something which could be said to exist that is vijnapti and that was what is described as being empty in their system 73 For Yogacara all conventional existence must be based on something which is real dravya 88 Sthiramati argues that we cannot say that everything exists conventionally saṁvṛtisat or nominally prajnaptisat and that nothing truly exists in an ultimate fashion which would entail a global conventionalism and nominalism without any metaphysical ground For Sthiramati this view is false because what would follow is non existence even conventionally That is because conventions are not possible without something to depend upon or without taking up something upadana 89 Thus for Sthiramati consciousness vijnana since it is dependently arisen exists as dravya substance 89 The Bodhisattvabhumi likewise argues that it is only logical to speak of emptiness if there is something i e dharmata an ultimate nature that is empty The Bodhisattvabhumi s Chapter on Reality Tattvarthapaṭala states that emptiness is wrongly grasped by those who do not accept that of which something is empty nor do they accept that which is empty 90 This is because emptiness holds good only as long as that of which something is said to be empty does not exist but on the other hand that which is empty exists If however all elements involved in this relation were non existent in what respect what would be empty and of what For the Bodhisattvabhumi the right way to understand emptiness is one regards that something is empty of that which does not exist in it and correctly comprehends that what remains there does actually exist here 90 That which remains and actually exists is the true reality the thing itself vastumatra the foundation asraya which remains avasiṣṭa after all conceptual constructs have been removed 91 Yogacarins also criticized certain Madhyamaka accounts of conventional truth that is the view which says that conventional truth is merely erroneous cognitive processes designations expressions and linguistic conventions which project an inherent nature 92 The Yogacarabhumi s Viniscayasaṃgrahani states that either Madhyamakas see conventional reality as produced by linguistic expressions and also by causal forces or they see it as produced merely by linguistic expressions and convention If the former then Madhyamikas must accept the reality of causal efficacy which is a kind of existence since things which are causally produced can be said to exist in some way If the latter then without any basis for linguistic expression and convention it makes no sense to even use these terms for Yogacara these conventions must have some kind of referential basis 93 Yogacarins further held that if all phenomena are equally conventional and unreal in the same way this would lead to laxity in ethics and in following the path in other words to moral relativism 94 The basic idea behind this critique is that if only convention exists as Madhyamaka claims and there are no truths that are independent of convention and linguistic expression there would be no epistemic foundations for critiquing worldly non buddhist conventions and affirming other conventions as closer to the truth like the conventions used by Buddhists to establish their ethics and their teachings 94 Madhyamaka thinkers like Bhaviveka Candrakirti and Shantideva also critiqued Yogacara views in their works for what they saw as an improper reification samaropa of mind and for a nihilistic denial of conventional truth The work of Xuanzang 7th century also contains evidence for this Indian debate 95 Two interpretations of the three natures edit Various Buddhist studies scholars such as Alan Spongberg Mario D amato Daniel McNamara and Matthew T Kapstein have noted that there are two main interpretations of the three natures doctrine among the various texts of the Yogacara corpus The two models have been named the pivot model and progressive model by these Western scholars 96 97 The pivot model found in texts like the Triṃsika and the Mahayanasaṃgraha presents the dependent nature as a kind of ontological pivot since it is the basis for conceptual construction the imagined nature and for the perfected nature which is nothing but absence of the imagined nature in the dependent nature 97 As such the imagined nature is an incorrect way of experiencing the dependent while the perfected nature is the correct way 96 The progressive model meanwhile can be found in the Trisvabhavanirdesa and in the Mahayanasutralaṃkara and its bhaṣya In this model it is the perfected nature which is the primary element of the three natures schema Here the perfected nature is the pure basis of reality while the other two natures are both impaired by ignorance 96 97 98 As the Trisvabhavanirdesa states The imputed and the other dependent are to be known as having defiled characteristics The perfected is asserted to have the characteristic of purity 96 In this text the dependent nature is seen as something which must be abandoned since it has the appearance of duality dvayakara 96 As such in this progressive model the dependent nature is the basis for the imagined nature but not the basis for the perfected nature 96 97 The perfected nature on the other hand is a fundamentally pure true reality which nevertheless is covered by adventitious defilements As the Mahayanasutralaṃkara states Reality which is always without duality is the basis of error and is entirely inexpressible does not have the nature of discursivity It is to be known abandoned and purified It should properly be thought of as naturally immaculate since it is purified from defilements as are space gold and water 98 Furthermore according to the Trisvabhavanirdesa TSN 17 20 the three natures are inseparable abhinna and as such non dual This is a key difference between this model and the pivot model where the dependent nature is ultimately devoid of the imagined nature 96 97 Another difference between these sources is that in the Triṃsika the main model of liberation is a radical transformation of the basis asrayaparavṛtti The Trisvabhavanirdesa meanwhile claims that liberation occurs through knowledge of the three natures as they are in their non duality 97 Some scholars like McNamara argue that these two models are incompatible ontologically and soteriologically 96 Kapstein thinks that it is possible that the Trisvabhavanirdesa is attempting to reconcile them 97 These differences have also led some scholars Kapstein and Thomas Wood to question the attribution of the Trisvabhavanirdesa to Vasubandhu 96 97 Karma edit An explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of karma action is central to Yogacara and the school sought to explain important questions such as how moral actions can have effects on individuals long after that action was done that is how karmic causality works across temporal distances Previous Abhidharma schools like the Sautrantika had developed theories of karma based on the notion of seeds bija in the mind stream which are unseen karmic habits good and bad which remain until they meet with the necessary conditions to manifest Yogacara adopts and expanded this theory 1 Yogacara then posited the storehouse consciousness as the container of the seeds as the storage place for karmic latencies and as a fertile matrix of predispositions that bring karma to a state of fruition In the Yogacara system all experience without exception is said to result from karma or mental intention cetana either arising from one s own subliminal seeds or from other minds 99 For Yogacara the seemingly external or dualistic world is merely a by product adhipati phala of karma The term vasana perfuming is also used when explaining karma Yogacarins were divided on the issue of whether vasana and bija were essentially the same whether the seeds were the effect of the perfuming or whether the perfuming simply affected the seeds 100 The type quantity quality and strength of the seeds determine where and how a sentient being will be reborn one s race sex social status proclivities bodily appearance and so forth The conditioning of the mind resulting from karma is called saṃskara 101 Vasubandhu s Treatise on Action Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa treats the subject of karma in detail from the Yogacara perspective 102 Meditation and awakening editAs the name of the school suggests meditation practice is central to the Yogacara tradition Yogacara texts prescribe various yogic practices such as mindfulness and the four investigations out of which a revolutionary and radically transformative understanding of the non duality of self and other is said to arise This process is referred to as asraya paravṛtti overturning the cognitive basis or revolution of the basis which refers to overturning the conceptual projections and imaginings which act as the base of our cognitive actions 1 This event is seen as the transformation of the basic mode of cognition into jnana knowledge direct knowing which is seen as a non dual knowledge that is non conceptual nirvikalpa i e devoid of interpretive overlay 1 103 Roger R Jackson describes this as a fundamental unconstructed awareness mula nirvikalpa jnana 104 When this knowledge arises the eight consciousnesses come to an end and are replaced by direct knowings According to Lusthaus Overturning the Basis turns the five sense consciousnesses into immediate cognitions that accomplish what needs to be done kṛtyanuṣṭhana jnana The sixth consciousness becomes immediate cognitive mastery pratyavekṣaṇa jnana in which the general and particular characteristics of things are discerned just as they are This discernment is considered nonconceptual nirvikalpa jnana Manas becomes the immediate cognition of equality samata jnana equalizing self and other When the Warehouse Consciousness finally ceases it is replaced by the Great Mirror Cognition Mahadarsa jnana that sees and reflects things just as they are impartially without exclusion prejudice anticipation attachment or distortion The grasper grasped relation has ceased purified cognitions all engage the world in immediate and effective ways by removing the self bias prejudice and obstructions that had prevented one previously from perceiving beyond one s own narcissistic consciousness When consciousness ends true knowledge begins Since enlightened cognition is nonconceptual its objects cannot be described 1 Five Categories of Beings edit One of the more controversial Yogacara teachings was the five categories of beings which was an extension of the teachings on the seeds of the storehouse consciousness This teacing states that sentient beings have certain innate seeds that determine their capability of achieving a particular state of enlightenment and no other Thus beings were placed into five categories 105 Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to practice the bodhisattva path and achieve full Buddhahood Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of a pratyekabuddha private Buddha Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of an arhat Beings whose innate seeds had an indeterminate nature and could potentially be any of the above Beings whose innate seeds were incapable of achieving enlightenment ever because they lacked any wholesome seedsThe fifth class of beings the icchantika were described in various Mahayana sutras as being incapable of achieving enlightenment unless in some cases through the aid of a Buddha or Bodhisattva Nevertheless the notion was highly criticized by later Mahayanists who supported the universalist doctrine of ekayana This tension is important in East Asian Buddhist history and later East Asian Yogacarins attempted to resolve the dispute by softening their stance on the five categories 105 106 Mental images true vs false edit An important debate about the reality of mental appearances within Yogacara led to its later subdivision into two systems of Alikakaravada Tib rnam rdzun pa False Aspectarians also known as Nirakaravada and Satyakaravada rnam bden pa True Aspectarians also known as Sakaravada They are also termed Aspectarians akara and Non Aspectarians anakara The core issue is whether appearances or aspects rnam pa akara of objects in the mind are treated as true bden pa satya or false rdzun pa alika 107 While this division did not exist in the works of the early Yogacara philosophers tendencies similar to these views can be discerned in the works of Yogacara thinkers like Dharmapala c 530 561 and Sthiramati c 510 570 108 109 110 According to Yaroslav Komarovski the distinction is as follows Although Yogacaras in general do not accept the existence of an external material world according to Satyakaravada its appearances or aspects rnam pa akara reflected in consciousness have a real existence because they are of one nature with the really existent consciousness their creator According to Alikakaravada neither external phenomena nor their appearances and in the minds that reflect them really exist What exists in reality is only primordial mind ye shes jnana described as self cognition rang rig svasamvedana svasamvitti or individually self cognizing primordial mind so so r rang gis rig pa i ye shes 111 Davey K Tomlinson describes the difference with reference to later Yogacara scholars from Vikramashila as follows On one hand is the Nirakaravada typified by Ratnakarasanti ca 970 1045 on the other the Sakaravada articulated by his colleague and critic Jnanasrimitra ca 980 1040 The Nirakaravadin argues that all appearances do not really exist They are ersatz or false alika Ephemeral forms appear to us but are the erroneous construction of ignorance which fundamentally characterizes our existence as suffering beings in saṃsara In the ultimately real experience of an awakened buddha no appearances show up at all Pure experience unstained by false appearance which is nirakara without appearance is possible The Sakaravadin on the other hand defends the view that all conscious experience is necessarily the experience of a manifest appearance consciousness is sakara or constitutively has appearance Manifest appearances properly understood are really real A buddha s experience has appearances and there is nothing about this fact that makes a buddha s experience mistaken 112 Practice edit nbsp Maitreya meditating 2nd century CE Loriyan Tangai Indian Museum KolkataA key early source for the yogic practices of Indian Yogacara is the encyclopedic Yogacarabhumi Sastra YBh Treatise on the Foundation for Yoga Practitioners The YBh presents a structured exposition of the Mahayana Buddhist path of yoga here referring to spiritual practice in general from a Yogacara perspective and relies in both Agama Nikaya texts and Mahayana sutras while also being influenced by Vaibhaṣika Abhidharma 113 According to some scholars this text can be traced to communities of yogacaras which initially referred not to a philosophical school but to groups of meditation specialists whose main focus was Buddhist yoga 114 Other Yogacara texts which also discuss meditation and spiritual practice and show some relationship with the YBh include the Saṃdhinirmocanasutra the Madhyantavibhaga Mahayanasutralaṃkara Dharmadharmatavibhaga and Asanga s Mahayanasaṃgraha 115 The YBh discusses various topics relevant to the bodhisattva practice including the eight different forms of dhyana meditative absorptions the three samadhis different types of liberation vimokṣa meditative attainments samapatti such as nirodhasamapatti the five hindrances nivaraṇa the various types of foci alambana or images nimitta used in meditation the various types contemplative antidotes pratipakṣa against the afflictions like contemplating death unattractiveness impermanence and suffering the practice of samatha through the nine aspects of resting the mind navakara cittasthitiḥ the practice of insight vipasyana mindfulness of breathing anapanasmṛti how to understand the four noble truths the thirty seven factors of Awakening saptatriṃsad bodhipakṣya dharmaḥ the four immeasurables apramaṇa and how to practice the six perfections paramita 116 Bodhisattva path edit Yogacara sources like the Abhidharmasamuccaya the Cheng Weishi Lun and the commentaries to the Mahayanasaṃgraha and the Mahayanasutralamkara also contain various descriptions of the main stages of the bodhisattva path 117 118 These Yogacara sources integrate the Mahayana teaching of the ten bodhisattva stages bhumis with the earlier Abhidharma outline of the path called the five paths pancamarga to produce a Mahayanist version of five stages pancavastha 118 119 In classic Yogacara this bodhisattva path is said to last for three incaculable eons asaṃkhyeya kalpas i e millions upon millions of years 120 119 The five paths or stages are outlined in Yogacara sources as follows 118 117 119 121 Path of accumulation sambhara marga 資糧位 in which a bodhisattva gives rise to bodhicitta and works on the two accumulations of merit puṇya and wisdom jnana These are linked with the practice of the six perfections In this first stage of the path one attains merit by doing good deeds like giving dana and one also accumulates wisdom by listening to the Mahayana teachings many times contemplating them and meditating on them One also associates with good spiritual friends According to the Mahayanasaṃgraha at this stage the bodhisattva focuses on accumulating wholesome roots kusalamula and on permeating one s mind with learning bahusrutaprabhavita 122 This leads to the accumulation of great faith and conviction in the Mahayana and in the principle of consciousness only 123 Path of engagement prayoga marga 加行位 also termed the stage of the practice of faith and convinction adhimukticaryabhumi Here a bodhisattva practices morality meditation and wisdom in order to quell the manifest activities of the two types of obscurations emotionally afflictive and cognitive While their active elements are quelled they remain as seeds in the foundation consciousness Furthermore one also cultivates the factors conducive to penetration which consists of the four investigations and the four correct cognitions These are ways of contemplating the truth of mind only and lead to the entrance into the principle of cognizance only vijnaptimatrapravesa as well as to the certainty as to the non existence of the object arthabhavaniscaya 124 At this stage one relies on the fourth dhyana and also attains various samadhis meditative concentrations The final stage of this path which is just before the path of seeing is called the elimination of the ideation of cognizance only vijnaptimatrasaṃjnavibhavana As the Mahayanasaṃgraha states at this point the realization of the absolute nature pariniṣpannasvabhavabuddhi eliminates the very perception of mind only vijnaptimatratabuddhi 125 The resulting wisdom is described by Asanga as the non conceptual cognition nirvikalpakajnana in which the object alambana and the subject alambaka are completely identical samasama 126 Path of seeing darsana marga 見道位 at this stage which lasts for only a few moments a bodhisattva attains an untainted knowledge Skt anasrava jnana 無漏智 into emptiness the non duality of self and other and consciousness only The Cheng wei shi lun describes this knowledge which realises Suchness tathata as being entirely undifferentiated samasama from Suchness since both are free from the characteristics lakṣaṇa of subject grahaka and object grahya 127 This stage is equated with the first bodhisattva stage the stage of joy At this point one is a proper noble arya bodhisattva instead of just a beginner Path of cultivation bhavana marga 修道位 at this stage a bodhisattva continues to train themselves in two main cognitions in order to fully eliminate all the seeds of the two types of obscurations They train in the non conceptual gnosis nirvikalpakajnana of ultimate reality and the wordly or subsequent knowledge pṛṣṭhtalabdhajnana which knows conventional reality as illusory and is yet able to conceptually understand it and use it for guiding sentient beings according to their needs Part of this path requires effort as the bodhisattva is said to repeatedly abhikṣṇam cultivate the non conceptual cognition Cheng wei shi lun However after a certain point one advances effortlessly This path corresponds to the second to ninth stages of the bodhisattva path The Mahayanasaṃgraha states that at this stage the yogin dwells in intense cultivation for hundreds of thousands of koṭis of niyutas an astronomical number of aeons and consequently attains the transformation of the basis asrayaparavṛtti 128 Path of fulfillment niṣṭha marga also known as the path of no more learning asaikṣa marga 無學位 in other sources This is equivalent to complete Buddhahood It also entails attaining the three bodies trikaya of the Buddha a doctrine which was also invented by the Yogacara school Bodhisattva practice edit The Bodhisattvabhumi discusses the Yogacara school s specifically Mahayana forms of practice which are tailored to bodhisattvas 129 The aim of the bodhisattva s practice in the Bodhisattvabhumi is the wisdom prajna which realizes of the inexpressible Ultimate Reality tathata or the thing in itself vastumatra which is essenceless and beyond the duality advaya of existence bhava and non existence abhava 130 131 The Bodhisattvabhumi outlines several practices of bodhisattvas including the six perfections paramita the thirty seven factors of Awakening and the four immeasurables Two key practices which are unique to bodhisattvas in this text are the four investigations and the four correct cognitions or the four kinds of understanding in accordance with true reality 132 133 These two sets of four practices and cognitions are also taught in the Abhidharmasamuccaya and its commentaries 133 The four investigations and four correct cognitions edit The four investigations catasraḥ paryeṣaṇaḥ and the corresponding four correct cognitions catvari yathabhutaparijnanani are a set of original contemplations found in Yogacara works These were seen as very important contemplative methods by the authors of the Bodhisattvabhumi They were considered to lead to awakening and were linked with the thirty seven factors leading to Awakening 134 The four investigations and the corresponding four correct cognitions which are said to arise out of the investiations are 135 136 The investigation of the names of things namaparyeṣaṇa leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of names just for what they are which is just names namamatra i e arbitrary linguistic signs The investigation of things vastuparyeṣaṇa leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of things One sees things just for what they are namely a mere presence or a thing in itself vastumatra One understands that this is apart from all labels and is inexpressible nirabhilapya The investigation of verbal designations suggesting and portraying an intrinsic nature svabhava prajnapti paryeṣaṇa leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations One sees the designations just for what they are namely as mere designations prajnaptimatrata Thus one sees the idea of intrinsic nature to be illusory like a hallucination or a dream The investigation of verbal designations expressing individuation and differences viseṣaprajnaptiparyeṣaṇa leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations One sees the designations just for what they are namely as mere designations For example a thing may be designated as existing or non existing but such designations do not apply to true reality or the thing in itself The practice which leads to the realization of the true nature of things is based on the elimination of all conceptual proliferations prapanca and ideations saṃjna that one superimposes on true reality 137 The YBh states that the yogin must repeatedly remove any ideation conducive to the proliferation directed at all phenomena and should consistently dwell on the thing in itself by a non conceptualizing mental state which is focused on grasping only the object perceived without any characteristics 138 Four prayogas edit Various Yogacara sources provide a four step process of realization leading to the path of seeing these four are the four yogic practices prayogas 139 Yogic practice of observation upalambha prayoga Outer objects are observed to be nothing but mind Yogic practice of non observation anupalambha prayoga Outer objects are not observed as such Yogic practice of observation and non observation upalambhanupalambha prayoga Outer objects being unobservable a mind cognizing them is not observed either Yogic practice of double non observation nopalambhopalambha prayoga Not observing both nonduality is observedThis process is conceisely explained in the Trisvabhavanirdesa which says through the observation of it being merely mind a knowable object is not observed Through not observing a knowable object mind is not observed either Through not observing both the dharmadhatu is observed 140 Thus the goal of meditation is a totally unified mind that goes beyond all concepts and language to directly know the undifferentiated uniformity of phenomena dharmasamataḥ and the thing in itself the supreme reality 141 The elimination of all concepts applies even to the very idea of mind only or mere cognizance itself 142 As the Dharmadharmatavibhaga states through referents being observed in this way they are observed as mere cognizance By virtue of observing them as mere cognizance Referents are not observed and through not observing referents mere cognizance is not observed either 143 This elimination of concepts and ideas is the basic framework applied by the bodhisattva to all meditative practices including the different mindfulness meditations 137 The three samadhis meditative absorptions are likewise adapted into this new framework These three are the emptiness sunyata wishlessness apraṇihita and imagelessness animitta samadhis 144 Meditation edit As the school of yoga practitioners meditative practice is discussed in various Yogacara sources The sixth chapter the Maitreya Chapter of the Saṃdhinirmocanasutra focuses entirely on meditation It extensively discusses the meditative aspects of calm samatha and insight vipasyana from unique perspectives 145 Success in both of these is based on pure ethics and on pure views based on listening and reflecting visuddhaṃ srutamayacintamayadarsanam 145 Insight is paired with objects consisting in images accompanied by reflection savikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ while tranquility is seen as based on objects consisting in images unaccompanied by reflection nirvikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ 145 Thus insight meditation is based on the uninterrupted contemplation of mental images while calming meditation is simply focusing on the continuous flow of mind with uninterrupted attention 146 The Saṃdhinirmocana also states that the teachings themselves are an important object of meditative contemplation This includes the Yogacara teaching of consciousness only the teachings on the twofold emptiness of self and phenomena and the schematic analysis of the subject and its objects of consciousness 147 While insight meditation is initially based on conceptual reflection these are gradually abandoned at later stages until the yogin lets go of all concepts teachings and mental images 147 Furthermore at the higher stages of meditation the calm and insight meditations must ultimately be blended or yoked together yuganaddha in a single state of one pointedness of mind cittaikagrata 146 This unified state is described as that state in which the yogin realises that these images pratibimba which are the domain of concentration samadhigocara are nothing but representation vijnaptimatra and having realised this he contemplates manasikaroti Suchness tathata 146 History editYogacara along with Madhyamaka Middle Way is one of the two principal philosophical schools of Indian Mahayana Buddhism 148 though the related movement of Tathagatagarbha thought was also influential 149 note 1 Origin and early Yogacara edit nbsp The Kushan Empire ruled much of north India during the early period of the Yogacara school The term yogacara yoga practitioner was originally used to refer to the Buddhist meditation adepts of the first centuries of the common era which were associated with the Sarvastivada and Sautrantika traditions in north India some of their key centers included Gandhara Kashmir and Mathura Modern scholars like Florin Delenau have suggested that some yogis in this north Indian Buddhist milieu gradually adopted Mahayana ideas eventually developing into a separate movement a process which was complete by the 5th century 150 5 6 According to Delenau the Chinese Dhyana Sutras indicate just such a gradual adoption of Mahayana elements 5 nbsp The bodhisattva Maitreya and disciples a central figure in Yogacara origin myth Gandhara 3rd century CE One of the earliest texts of the Mahayana Yogacara tradition proper is the Saṃdhinirmocana Sutra Unraveling the Profound Intent which might be as early as the first or second century CE 151 It includes new theories such as the basis consciousness alaya vijnana the doctrine of vijnapti matra and the three natures trisvabhava However these theories were not completely new as they have predecessors in older theories held by previous Buddhist schools such as the Sautrantika theory of seeds bija and the Sthavira theory of the bhavanga 152 Philosophically speaking Richard King notes that Sautrantikas defended a kind of representationalism in which the mind only perceives an image akara or representation vijnapti of an external object never the object itself Mahayana Yogacaras adopted a similar model but removed the need for any external object which acts as a cause for the image 153 As the doctrinal trailblazer of the Yogacara the Saṃdhinirmocana also introduced the paradigm of the Three Turnings of the Wheel of Dharma with its own teachings being placed into the final and definitive teaching which supersedes those of the Prajnaparamita sutras 148 The early layers of the massive Yogacarabhumi sastra Treatise on the Stages of the Yogacaras also contains very ancient Yogacara material which is earlier than the Saṃdhinirmocana 154 However in its current form it is a conglomeration of heterogenous materials Schmithausen which was finally compiled perhaps by Asanga after the Saṃdhinirmocana hence later layers quote the sutra directly Modern scholars consider the Yogacarabhumi to contain the work of several authors mainly of a Mulasarvastivada milieu though it has traditionally been attributed in full to the bodhisattva Maitreya or to Asanga 155 156 It is influenced by Sarvastivada Abhidharma and Sautrantika traditions who also had similar texts called by the name Yogacarabhumi such as the Yogacarabhumi of Saṅgharakṣa 157 Classical Yogacara Asaṅga and Vasubandhu edit nbsp nbsp Asaṅga left and Vasubandhu statues at Kofuku ji Yogacara s systematic exposition owes much to the Gandharan Buddhist brothers Asaṅga 4th c CE and Vasubandhu c 4th 5th CE Little is known of these figures but traditional accounts in authors like Xuanzang state that Asaṅga received Yogacara teachings from the bodhisattva and future Buddha Maitreya 158 159 However there are various discrepancies between the Chinese and Tibetan traditions concerning these so called five works of Maitreya 160 Modern scholars argue that the various works traditionally attributed to Maitreya are actually by other authors According to Mario D amato the Mahayanasutralamkara and the Madhyantavibhaga are part of a second phase of Yogacara scholarship which took place after the completion of the Bodhisattvabhumi but before the composition of Asanga s Mahayanasaṃgraha which quotes the Mahayanasutralamkara as an authoritative text 161 Regarding the Abhisamayalankara and the Ratnagotravibhaga modern scholars generally see these as the works of different authors 162 163 Asaṅga went on to write many of the key Yogacara treatises such as the Mahayanasaṃgraha and the Abhidharma samuccaya 160 Asaṅga also went on to convert his brother Vasubandhu to Yogacara Vasubandhu was a top scholar of Vaibhaṣika and Sautrantika Abhidharma thought and the Abhidharmakosakarika is his main work which discusses the doctrines of these traditions 164 Vasubandhu also went on to write important Yogacara works like the Twenty Verses and the Thirty Verses on Consciousness Only The middle period and the epistemological turn edit The Yogacara school held a prominent position in Indian Buddhism for centuries after the time of the two brothers According to Lusthaus and Delenau after Asaṅga and Vasubandhu two distinct wings of the school developed during the Middle Period of Yogacara the epistemological school and the scholastic school Another important third movement developed a synthesis of Yogacara with buddha nature thought 1 165 Thus the three main branches of the Yogacara movement which developed during the so called middle period are 1 165 A logico epistemic tradition pramaṇavada focusing on issues of epistemology Sanskrit pramaṇa and logic hetuvidya exemplified by such thinkers as Dignaga Dharmakirti Dharmottara Devendrabuddhi Prajnakaragupta Jinendrabuddhi Sakyabuddhi A scholastic and exegetical tradition which refined and elaborated Yogacara Abhidharma and wrote various commentaries exemplified by such thinkers as Gunamati Asvabhava Sthiramati Jinaputra Dharmapala Silabhadra Xuanzang and Vinitadeva 710 770 The Yogacara tathagatagarbha synthesis found in the Laṅkavatara Sutra and Ghanavyuha sutra two treatises attributed to an author named Saramati the Ratnagotravibhaga and Dharmadhatvaviseṣasastra Dasheng fajie wuchabie lun 大乘法界無差別論 as well as in the works of Paramartha 499 569 CE including his translations Buddhagotrasastra Fo xing lun 佛性論 and Anuttarasrayasutra 166 These branches of Yogacara thought were not mutually exclusive however for example Vinitadeva wrote pramaṇa works as well as commentaries on the works of Vasubandhu Aside from these there were also Yogacara authors writing commentaries on the Prajnaparamita sutras including the unknown author of the Abhisamayalaṅkara AA Arya Vimuktisena 6th century who commented on the AA and Daṃṣṭrasena author of the Bṛhaṭṭika The doctrines of the exegetical tradition sometimes came under attack by other Buddhists especially the notion of alaya vijnana which was seen as close to the Hindu ideas of atman and prakṛti It was perhaps due to this that the logical tradition shifted over time to using the term citta santana instead since it was easier to defend a stream santana of thoughts as a doctrine that did not contradict not self By the end of the eighth century the scholastic tradition had mostly become eclipsed by the pramaṇa tradition as well as by a new hybrid school that combined basic Yogacara doctrines with Tathagatagarbha thought 1 The influential Pramaṇavada tradition led by Dignaga and Dharmakirti defined the main epistemological method for Indian Buddhism Modern scholars see this school as having ushered in an epistemological turn for all Indian philosophy 167 The pramaṇa tradition continued to thrive in Magadha especially at Nalanda as well as in Kashmir well into the 11th century One of the most important late figures of this tradition was Saṅkaranandana fl c 9th or 10th century the second Dharmakirti 168 Yogacara tathagatagarbha synthesis edit nbsp Panorama of the site of Vikramasila university Bhagalpur district Bihar Vikramasila was an important center for late Indian Yogacara scholars including the great panditas like Jnanasrimitra and Ratnakarasanti According to Lusthaus the synthetic Yogacara tathagatagarbha school accepted the definition of tathagatagarbha the buddha womb buddha source or buddha within as permanent pleasurable self and pure nitya sukha atman suddha which is found in various tathagatagarbha sutras 1 This hybrid school eventually went on to link the tathagatagarbha with the alaya vijnana doctrine Some key sources of this tendency are the Laṅkavatara Sutra Ratnagotravibhaga Uttaratantra and in China the Awakening of Faith 1 The synthesis of Yogacara and Tathagatagarbha thought became extremely influential in both East Asia and Tibet During the sixth and seventh centuries various forms of competing Yogacara systems were popular in Chinese Buddhism The translator Bodhiruci 6th century CE for example took a more classical approach while Ratnamati was attracted to Tathagatagarbha thought and sought to translate texts like the Dasabhumika commentary accordingly Their disagreement on this issue led to the end of their collaboration as co translators 169 The translator Paramartha is another example of a hybrid thinker He promoted the theory of a stainless consciousness amala vijnana a pure wisdom within all beings i e the tathagatagarbha which is revealed once the alaya vijnana is purified 170 According to Lusthaus Xuanzang s travels to India and his translation work was an attempt to return to a more orthodox and authentic Indian Yogacara and thus put to rest the debates and confusions in the Chinese Yogacara of his time The Cheng Weishi Lun returns to the use of the theory of seeds instead of the tathagatagarbha to explain how some beings can reach Buddhahood 171 However by the eighth century the Yogacara tathagatagarbha synthesis became the dominant interpretation of Yogacara in East Asian Buddhism 1 Later Chinese thinkers like Fa Tsang would thus criticize Xuanzang for failing to teach the tathagatagarbha 171 Karl Brunnholzl notes that this syncretic tendency also existed in Indian Yogacara scholasticism but that it only became widespread during the later tantric era when Vajrayana became prominent with the work of thinkers like Jnanasrimitra Ratnakarasanti and Maitripa 172 Kashmir also became an important center for this tradition as can be seen in the works of Kashmiri Yogacarins Sajjana and Mahajana 173 Yogacara and Madhyamaka edit Yogacara and Madhyamaka philosophers demonstrated two opposing tendencies throughout the history of Buddhist philosophy in India an antagonistic stance which saw both systems as rival and incompatible views and another inclusive tendency which worked towards harmonizing their views 174 Some authors like the Madhyamikas Bhaviveka Candrakirti and Santideva and the Yogacaras Asanga Dharmapala Sthiramati criticized the philosophical theories of the other tradition While Indian Yogacaras criticized certain interpretations of Madhyamaka which they term those who misunderstand emptiness they never criticize the founders of Madhyamaka themselves Nagarjuna and Aryadeva and saw their work as implicitly in agreement with Yogacara This inclusivism saw Nagarjuna s teachings as needing further expansion and explication since it was part of the second turning of the wheel of Dharma Thus Yogacara thinkers affirmed the importance Nagarjuna s work and some even wrote commentaries on Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika as a way to draw out the implicit meaning of Madhyamaka and show it was compatible with Yogacara These include Asanga s Treatise on Comforming to the Middle Way Shun zhonglun 順中論 and Sthiramati s Mahayana Middle Way Commentary Dasheng zhongguanshi lun 大乘中觀釋論 T 30 1567 175 Similarly Vasubandhu and Dharmapala both wrote commentaries on Aryadeva s Catuḥsataka Four Hundred Verses 176 The harmonizing tendency can be seen in the work of philosophers like Kambala 5 6th century author of the Alokamala Jnanagarbha 8th century his student Santarakṣita 8th century and Ratnakarasanti c 1000 174 Santarakṣita 8th century whose view was later called Yogacara Svatantrika Madhyamaka by the Tibetan tradition saw the Madhyamika position as ultimately true and at the same time saw the Yogacara view as a useful way to relate to conventional truth which leads one to the ultimate 177 Ratnakarasanti on the other hand saw Nagarjuna as agreeing with the intent of Yogacara texts while criticizing the interpretations of later Madhyamikas like Bhaviveka Later Tibetan Buddhist thinkers like Shakya Chokden would also work to show the compatibility of the alikakaravada sub school with Madhyamaka arguing that it is in fact a form of Madhyamaka 178 Likewise the Seventh Karmapa Chodrak Gyamtso has a similar view which holds that the profound important points and intents of the two systems are one 179 Ju Mipham is also another Tibetan philosopher whose project is aimed as showing the harmony between Yogacara and Madhyamaka arguing that there is only a very subtle difference between them being a subtle clinging by Yogacaras to the existence of an inexpressible naturally luminous cognition rig pa rang bzhin gyis od gsal ba 180 Yogacara in East Asia edit Main article East Asian Yogacara nbsp Statue of a traveling Xuanzang at Longmen Grottoes Luoyang nbsp Kuiji 632 682 a student of XuanzangTranslations of Indian Yogacara texts were first introduced to China in the early 5th century CE 181 Among these was Guṇabhadra s translation of the Laṅkavatara Sutra in four fascicles which would also become important in the early history of Chan Buddhism Influential 5th century figures include the translators Bodhiruci Ratnamati and Paramartha 182 Their followers founded the Dilun Dasabhumika Commentary and Shelun Mahayanasaṃgraha schools both of which included Yogacara and tathagatagarbha elements 183 Modern scholars also hold that the Awakening of Faith a very influential work in East Asian Buddhism was written by a member of the Dilun tradition 184 Xuanzang fl c 602 664 is famous for having made a dangerous journey to India in order to study Buddhism obtain more indic Yogacara sources 185 95 Xuanzang spent over ten years in India traveling and studying under various Buddhist masters and drew on a variety of Indian sources in his studies 185 95 186 Upon his return to China Xuanzang brought with him 657 Buddhist texts including the Yogacarabhumi and began the work of translating them 185 187 Xuanzang composed the Cheng Weishi Lun Discourse on the Establishment of Consciousness Only which drew on many Indian sources and commentaries and became a central work of East Asian Yogacara 188 Xuanzang s student Kuiji continued this tradition writing several important commentaries However another student of Xuanzang the Korean monk Wŏnch ŭk defended some of the doctrines of the Shelun school of Paramartha for which he was criticized by the followers of Kuiji Wŏnch ŭk s teachings were influential on the Yogacara Beopsang of Silla Korea Both of these competing Yogacara sub sects were then imported to Japan where they became the two sub sects the northern and southern temple lineages of the Hossō school 189 Xuanzang s school later came under criticism from later Chinese masters like Fazang and it became less influential as the fortunes of other native Chinese schools rose Nevertheless Yogacara studies continued to be important at different times throughout Chinese history including during the modern revival of Yogacara in the 20th century 190 Yogacara in Tibet edit nbsp Rangjung Dorje 3rd Karmapa Lama 1284 1339 See also Rangtong Shentong Yogacara is studied in all schools of Tibetan Buddhism though it receives different emphasis in each of these Yogacara thought is an integral part of the history of Tibetan Buddhism It was first transmitted to Tibet by figures like Santarakṣita Kamalasila and Atisa 191 The Tibetan Nyingma school and its Dzogchen teachings draw on both Madhyamaka and Yogacara Tathagatagarbha thought 1 192 Similarly Kagyu school figures like the Third Karmapa also rely on the Madhyamaka and Yogacara Tathagatagarbha systems in their presentation of the ultimate view termed Mahamudra in Kagyu 193 The Jonang school also developed its own synthetic philosophy which they termed shentong other emptiness Wylie gzhan stong which also included elements from Yogacara Madhyamaka and Tathagatagarbha 194 In contrast the Gelug and Sakya schools generally see Yogacara as a lesser view than the Madhyamaka philosophy of Candrakirti which is seen as the definitive view in these traditions 195 Today Yogacara topics remain important in Tibetan Buddhism and Yogacara texts are widely studied There are various debates and discussions among the Tibetan Buddhist schools regarding key Yogacara ideas like svasaṃvedana reflexive awareness and the foundational consciousness Furthermore the debates between the other emptiness and self emptiness views are also similar in some ways to the historical debates between Yogacara Tathagatagarbha and Madhyamaka though the specific viewpoints have evolved further and changed in complex ways 196 Modern thinkers continue to discuss Yogacara issues and attempt to synthesize it with Madhyamaka For example Ju Mipham the 19th century Rime commentator wrote a commentary on Santarakṣita s synthesis arguing that the ultimate intent of Madhyamaka and Yogacara is the same 177 Influence edit Virtually all contemporary schools of Mahayana Buddhism are influenced by Yogacara to some extent This includes modern East Asian Buddhist traditions like Zen and Pure Land and Tibetan Buddhism 197 Zen was heavily influenced by Yogacara sources especially the Laṅkavatara Sutra 197 In Tibetan Buddhism Yogacara sources are still widely studied and several are part of the monastic education curriculum in various traditions 198 Some influential Yogacara texts in Tibetan Buddhism include Asanga s Abhidharma samuccaya and the Five Treatises of Maitreya including the Mahayanasutralankara and the Ratnagotravibhaga 198 Hindu philosophers such as Vacaspati Misra Utpaladeva Abhinavagupta and Sriharṣa were also influenced by Yogacara ideas and responded to their theories in their own works 199 200 Textual corpus edit nbsp A wall painting depicting Xuanzang s travels and his translation work Xuanzang Memorial Hall modern NalandaSutras edit The Saṃdhinirmocana Sutra Sutra of the Explanation of the Profound Secrets 2nd century CE is a key early Yogacara sutra which is considered to be the foundational sutra for the Yogacara tradition 201 There are two Indian commentaries to this one by Asanga and one by Jnanagarbha 202 The Avataṃsaka Sutra which includes the Dasabhumikasutra also contains numerous teachings on mind only and is very influential for East Asian Buddhism 203 Vasubandhu s Commentary on the Dasabhumikasutra is an important commentary to this 204 205 Another text the Mahayanabhidharmasutra is often quoted in Yogacara works and is assumed to also be an early Yogacara sutra 206 The Laṅkavatara Sutra also later assumed considerable importance in East Asia and portions of this text were considered by Etienne Lamotte as being contemporaneous with the Saṃdhinirmocana 207 208 This text equates the Yogacara theory of alayavijnana with the tathagatagarbha buddha nature and thus seems to be part of the tradition which sought to merge Yogacara with tathagatagarbha thought 209 Another sutra which contains similar themes to the Laṅkavatara is the Ghanavyuha Sutra 210 211 All these five sutras are listed by Kuiji as key sutras for the Yogacara school in his Commentary on the Cheng weishi lun 成唯識 論述記 Taishō no 1830 212 213 Another lesser known sutra which was important in East Asian Yogacara is the Buddha Land Sutra Buddhabhumi sutra Taishō vol 16 no 680 which along with its commentary Buddhabhumyupadesa teaches that the pure land is not a physical place but a symbol for wisdom 214 There are also various Indian Chinese and Tibetan commentaries to these various Mahayana sutras Furthermore the Prajnaparamita sutras are also important sources in Yogacara even though most do not cover specifically Yogacara doctrines This is shown by the fact that various Yogacara commentaries were written on Prajnaparamita sutras including commentaries by Asanga Vajracchedikakavyakhya Vasubandhu Dignaga Daṃṣṭrasena Bṛhaṭṭika Ratnakarasanti various and the Abhisamayalaṅkara 215 216 Treatises edit nbsp Tibetan depiction of Asaṅga receiving teachings from the bodhisattva Maitreya This is one of the founding religious myth of Yogacara scholasticism Yogacara authors wrote numerous scholastic and philosophical treatises sastra and commentaries ṭika bhaṣya vyakhyana etc The following is a list in historical order and only includes specifically Yogacara Vijnanavada figures and works 217 218 Yogacarabhumi sastra the earliest Yogacara treatise a massive encyclopedic work on Yogacara theory and praxis which is a composite work reflecting various stages of historical development compiled 3rd to 5th century CE 154 1 Mahayanasutralamkara and its bhaṣya traditionally attributed to the bodhisattva Maitreya or Asanga modern scholars like D amato place this text together with the commentary after the Bodhisattvabhumi but before Asanga 219 Madhyantavibhaga Distinguishing the Middle and the Extremes another work of the second phase of post Yogacarabhumi Yogacara thought traditionally attributed to the bodhisattva Maitreya who is said to have revealed it to Asanga 220 Dharmadharmatavibhaga Distinguishing Dharmas and Dharmata another work of the so called Maitreya corpus Nagamitra s 3rd 4th century Kayatrayavataramukha a treatise on the trikaya and the three natures The works of Asaṅga 4th 5th century CE the Mahayanasaṃgraha and the Abhidharma samuccaya 221 Vasubandhu s 4th 5th century CE Viṃsaṭika karika Treatise in Twenty Stanzas Triṃsika karika Treatise in Thirty Stanzas Vyakhyayukti Proper Mode of Exposition Karmasiddhiprakarana A Treatise on Karma and Pancaskandhaprakaraṇa Explanation of the Five Aggregates 206 222 Alokamalaprakaraṇanama An Explanation named Garland of Light by Kambala c fifth to sixth century which attempts to harmonize Madhyamaka and Yogacara mostly by assimilating Madhyamaka under Yogacara 217 223 The Saṃdhinirmocanasutravyakhyana is a commentary to the Saṃdhinirmocanasutra attributed to Asanga but this has been questioned by modern scholars 224 Abhisamayalaṅkara Ornament of Realization a commentary on the Prajnaparamita sutras It is attributed to Maitreya Asanga by Tibetan tradition but it is unknown in Chinese sources Modern scholars see this as a post Asanga text Makransky attributes it to Arya Vimuktisena the first commentator on this text 225 226 Dignaga s Alambanaparikṣa and its vrtti commentary defend the view of consciousness only using epistemological arguments The Indian Paramartha 499 569 translated many works to Chinese and also wrote some original treatises and commentaries possibly including the Buddhagotrasastra Fo Xing Lun Sthiramati 6th century wrote numerous commentaries like Pancaskandhakavibhaṣa and Triṃsikavijnaptibhaṣya Mahayana Awakening of Faith author unknown Dharmapala of Nalanda 6th century wrote commentaries to the Alambanaparikṣa and Aryadeva s Catuḥsataka Asvabhava wrote Mahayanasutralaṃkara ṭika Mahayanasaṃgrahopanibandhana and a commentary on Alokamala Dharmakirti s 6th or 7th century Pramanaṿarttika Commentary on Epistemology is mostly a work on pramana but it also argues for consciousness only Silabhadra 529 645 Buddhabhumivyakhyana Xuanzang s 602 664 Cheng Wei Shi Lun is a large Chinese commentary on the Triṃsika which draws on numerous Indian sources Kuiji 632 682 Various commentaries on texts like Cheng weishi lun Heart sutra Madhyantavibhaga etc Wŏnch ŭk 613 696 Commentaries on the Samdhinirmocanasutra Heart sutra and Benevolent King Sutra Wŏnhyo 617 686 wrote commentaries on various works such as the Madhyantavibhaga Guṇaprabha Bodhisattvabhumisilaparivarta bhaṣya Jinaputra wrote a commentary to the Abhidharmasamucchaya Candragomi sixth seventh century Siṣyalekha Bodhisattvasaṃvaraviṃsaka Vinitadeva c 645 715 wrote commentaries on Viṃsatika Triṃsika and Alambanapariksa Jnanacandra eighth century Yogacaryabhavanatatparyarthanirdesa a meditation manual Sagaramegha eighth century Yogacarabhumaubodhisattvabhumivyakhya a large Yogacarabhumi commentary Sumatisila late eighth century wrote a commentary on Vasubandhu s Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa Prajnakaragupta 8th 9th century Pramaṇavarttikalaṃkara and Sahavalambanirṇayasiddhi a proof of idealism Saṅkaranandana fl c 9th or 10th century Prajnalaṅkara Ornament of Wisdom an exposition of vijnaptimatrata 227 Dharmakirti of Sumatra Durbodhaloka Light on the Hard to Illuminate a sub commentary to the Abhisamayalaṃkara sastra vṛtti of Haribhadra 228 Jnanasrimitra fl 975 1025 C E Sakarasiddhi Sakarasaṃgraha and Sarvajnasiddhi Ratnakirti 11th century CE Ratnakirtinibandhavali and Sarvajnasiddhi Ratnakarasanti 10 11th century Prajnaparamitopadesa Madhyamakalaṃkaropadesa Vijnaptimatratasiddhi Triyanavyavasthana Madhyamakalaṃkaravṛtti Madhyamapratipadasiddhi Jnanasribhadra commentaries on Laṅkavatarasutra Mahayanasutralaṃkara and Pramaṇavarttika Sajjana 11th century Putralekha Mahayanottaratantrasastropadesa and Sutralaṃkarapiṇḍartha 173 Jōkei 1155 1213 Gumei hosshin shu Anthology of Awakenings from Delusion Ryōhen 1194 1252 Kanjin kakumushō Precis on Contemplating the Mind and Awakening from the Dream See also editMadhyamaka Mahayana Idealism Vedanta Kashmir Shaivism School of the Heart MindNotes edit Alex Wayman A Defense of Yogacara Buddhism Philosophy East and West Volume 46 Number 4 October 1996 pages 447 476 Of course the Yogacara put its trust in the subjective search for truth by way of a samadhi This rendered the external world not less real but less valuable as the way of finding truth The tide of misinformation on this or on any other topic of Indian lore comes about because authors frequently read just a few verses or paragraphs of a text then go to secondary sources or to treatises by rivals and presume to speak authoritatively Only after doing genuine research on such a topic can one begin to answer the question why were those texts and why do the moderns write the way they do Kalupahana The above explanation of alaya vijnana makes it very different from that found in the Lankavatara The latter assumes alaya to be the eight consciousness giving the impression that it represents a totally distinct category Vasubandhu does not refer to it as the eight even though his later disciples like Sthiramati and Hsuan Tsang constantly refer to it as such 65 Majhima Nikaya 121 Cula sunnata Sutta 81 Frauwallner Die Philosophie des Buddhismus treats Tathagatagarbha thought as a separate school of Mahayana providing an excerpt from the Uttaratantra written by a certain Saramati 娑囉末底 c q Maitreya natha References edit a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t Lusthaus Dan 2018 What is and isn t Yogacara Yogacara Buddhism Research Association Makransky John 1997 Buddhahood Embodied Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet SUNY Press p 211 ISBN 978 0 7914 3431 4 a b c Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Jones Lindsay Ed in Chief 2005 Encyclopedia of Religion 2nd Ed Volume 14 p 9897 USA Macmillan Reference ISBN 0 02 865983 X v 14 a b c Deleanu F Ed 2006 The Chapter on the Mundane Path Laukikamarga A Trilingual Edition Sanskrit Tibetan Chinese Annotated Translation and Introductory Study 2 vol p 162 Tokyo International Institute for Buddhist Studies a b Kragh U T editor The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners The Buddhist Yogacarabhumi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India East Asia and Tibet Volume 1 pp 30 31 Harvard University Department of South Asian studies 2013 a b c d Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 146 Jones Lindsay Ed in Chief 2005 Encyclopedia of Religion 2nd Ed Volume 14 Masaaki Hattori Ed 1987 amp 2005 Yogacara p 9897 USA Macmillan Reference ISBN 0 02 865983 X v 14 Keenan John P tr The Scripture on the Explication of the Underlying Meaning 2000 p 1 a b c d Kochumuttom 1999 p 1 Peter Harvey An Introduction to Buddhism Cambridge University Press 1993 page 106 Muller A Charles 2005 2007 Wonhyo s Reliance on Huiyuan in his Exposition of the Two Hindrances Published in Reflecting Mirrors Perspectives on Huayan Buddhism Imre Hamar ed Harrassowitz Verlag 2007 p 281 295 Source 1 accessed April 7 2010 a b c d e f g h i Gold Jonathan C Vasubandhu The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Edward N Zalta ed https plato stanford edu archives sum2018 entries vasubandhu Schmithausen Lambert The Genesis of Yogacara Vijnanavada Responses and Reflections Tokyo The International Institute for Buddhist Studies 2014 p 597 Trivedi Saam November 2005 Idealism and Yogacara Buddhism Asian Philosophy 15 3 231 246 doi 10 1080 09552360500285219 S2CID 144090250 Schmithausen Lambert The Genesis of Yogacara Vijnanavada Responses and Reflections Tokyo The International Institute for Buddhist Studies 2014 p 387 Schmithausen Lambert The Genesis of Yogacara Vijnanavada Responses and Reflections Tokyo The International Institute for Buddhist Studies 2014 p 391 Schmithausen Lambert The Genesis of Yogacara Vijnanavada Responses and Reflections Tokyo The International Institute for Buddhist Studies 2014 p 598 a b Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 149 Schmithausen Lambert The Genesis of Yogacara Vijnanavada Responses and Reflections Tokyo The International Institute for Buddhist Studies 2014 p 389 Kapstein Matthew T July 2014 Buddhist Idealists and Their Jain Critics On Our Knowledge of External Objects Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 74 123 147 doi 10 1017 S1358246114000083 S2CID 170689422 a b Cameron Hall Bruce The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu s Concept of Mind JIABS Vol 9 1986 Number 1 p 7 Saam Trivedi Idealism and Yogacara Buddhism Asian Philosophy Volume 15 2005 Issue 3 Pages 231 246 Butler Sean Idealism in Yogacara Buddhism The Hilltop Review Volume 4 Issue 1 Spring 2010 Garfield Jay L Vasubandhu s treatise on the three natures translated from the Tibetan edition with a commentary Asian Philosophy Volume 7 1997 Issue 2 pp 133 154 Williams 2008 p 94 Yamabe Nobuyoshi 2004 Consciousness Theories of in Buswell Jr Robert E Macmillan Encyclopedia of Buddhism USA Macmillan Reference USA pp 177 ISBN 0 02 865910 4 Schmithausen Lambert The Genesis of Yogacara Vijnanavada Responses and Reflections Tokyo The International Institute for Buddhist Studies 2014 p 625 a b Schmithausen Lambert 2005 On the Problem of the External World in the Ch eng wei shih lun Tōkyō The International Institute for Buddhist Studies The International Institute for Buddhist Studies Kalupahana 1992 Dan Lusthaus What is and isn t Yogacara 2 Archived June 12 2008 at the Wayback Machine Garfield Jay L 2002 Empty words Buddhist philosophy and cross cultural interpretation Online Ausg ed New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195145519 Kalupahana 1992 pp 122 126 135 136 Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation p 162 2010 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Vasubandhu cittaṃ mano vijnanaṃ vijnaptis ceti paryayaḥ Viṃs 3 3 mind thinking consciousness and representation are synonymous terms Cf AKBh II 34 p 61 l 20 cittaṃ mano ʼtha vijnanam ekarthaṃ now the mind thinking and consciousness have the same meaning a b Kochumuttom 1999 p 5 a b c Wayman Alex A Defense of Yogacara Buddhism Philosophy East and West Vol 46 No 4 Oct 1996 pp 447 476 Vasubandhu author Stefan Anacker translator annotator 1984 Seven works of Vasubandhu the Buddhist psychological doctor Issue 4 of Religions of Asia series Motilal Banarsidass Publ ISBN 978 81 208 0203 2 Source 1 accessed Wednesday April 21 2010 p 159 Kochumuttom 1999 p 1 2 Kochumuttom 1999 p 6 Dan Lusthaus 4 February 2014 Buddhist Phenomenology A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch eng Wei shih Lun Taylor amp Francis p 43 ISBN 978 1 317 97342 3 a b c d e Westerhoff Jan November 2020 For your eyes only the Problem on Solipsism in Ancient Indian Philosophy BSHP Annual Lecture 2020 British Society for the History of Philosophy retrieved 2024 02 21 Williams 2008 pp 94 95 Fernando Tola Carmen Dragonetti Being as Consciousness Yogacara Philosophy of Buddhism Motilal Banarsidass Publ 2004 p xxiv Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 pp 150 151 Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 157 a b Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 170 Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 173 Brewster Ernest Billings What is Our Shared Sensory World Ming Dynasty Debates on Yogacara versus Huayan Doctrines Journal of Chinese Buddhist Studies 2018 31 117 170 New Taipei Chung Hwa Institute of Buddhist Studies ISSN 2313 2000 e ISSN 2313 2019 Wood Thomas E Mind Only A Philosophical and Doctrinal Analysis of the Vijnanavada p 205 University of Hawaii Press 1991 a b c d e f g Finnigan Bronwyn 2017 Buddhist Idealism In Tyron Goldschmidt amp Kenneth Pearce eds Idealism New Essays in Metaphysics Oxford University Press pp 178 199 Gold Jonathan C Vasubandhu The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Edward N Zalta ed https plato stanford edu archives sum2018 entries vasubandhu a b Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 175 Kalupahana 1992 p 138 140 Kalupahana 1992 p 137 139 a b Williams Paul 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge p 97 Fernando Tola Carmen Dragonetti Being as Consciousness Yogacara Philosophy of Buddhism Motilal Banarsidass Publ 2004 p xxv a b Waldron William S The Buddhist Unconscious The Alaya vijnana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism 2003 pp 94 95 Waldron William S The Buddhist Unconscious The Alaya vijnana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism 2003 p 97 Schmithausen Lambert 1987 Alayavijnana on the origin and the early development of a central concept of Yogacara philosophy Part I Text page 89 Tokyo International Institute for Buddhist Studies Studia Philologica Buddhica Monograph Series IVa Williams 2008 pp 97 98 Williams 2008 pp 98 99 Waldron William S The Buddhist Unconscious The Alaya vijnana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism 2003 page 131 Waldron William S The Buddhist Unconscious The Alaya vijnana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism 2003 page 93 Kalupahana 1992 p 137 a b c Kalupahana 1992 p 139 a b Kalupahana 1992 p 138 Kalupahana 1992 p 140 a b Kalupahana 1992 p 141 Padmasiri De Silva Robert Henry Thouless Buddhist and Freudian Psychology Third revised edition published by NUS Press 1992 page 66 Walpola Rahula quoted in Padmasiri De Silva Robert Henry Thouless Buddhist and Freudian Psychology Third revised edition published by NUS Press 1992 page 66 3 a b Williams 2008 p 90 Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 p 176 a b c King Richard Early Yogacara and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School Philosophy East amp West Volume 44 Number 4 October 1994 PP 659 683 Peter Lunde Johnson Xuanzang On There Only Being the Virtual Nature of Consciousness 2019 p 470 Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2017 pp 177 178 a b Williams 2008 pp 90 91 Skilton Andrew 1994 A Concise History of Buddhism Windhorse Publications London pg 124 a b c King Richard Early Yogacara and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School Philosophy East amp West Volume 44 Number 4 October 1994 pp 659 683 a b Williams 2008 p 93 Gadjin M Nagao Madhyamika and Yogachara Leslie S Kawamura translator SUNY Press Albany 1991 pp 53 57 200 Cula sunnata Sutta The Lesser Discourse on Emptiness a b Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 3 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 a b Conze Edward 1993 A Short History of Buddhism 2nd ed Oneworld ISBN 1 85168 066 7 50f Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 133 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 68 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals pp 41 52 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 59 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 50 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 a b Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 46 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 a b Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 76 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 77 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 86 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals pp 86 87 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 a b Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 116 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 a b c Lusthaus Dan undated Xuanzang Hsuan tsang Source Archived copy Archived from the original on December 8 2013 Retrieved December 8 2013 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link accessed December 12 2007 a b c d e f g h i McNamara Daniel 2011 On the Status of the Trisvabhavanirdesa in Contemporary Conceptions of Yogacara Thought a b c d e f g h Matthew Kapstein Who Wrote the Trisvabhavanirdesa Reflections on an Enigmatic Text and Its Place in the History of Buddhist Philosophy Journal of Indian Philosophy 2017 halshs 02503277 a b D AMATO M THREE NATURES THREE STAGES AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGACARA TRISVABHAVA THEORY Journal of Indian Philosophy vol 33 no 2 2005 pp 185 207 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 23497001 Accessed 16 Feb 2024 Harvey Brian Peter 2000 An Introduction to Buddhist ethics Foundations Values and Issues Cambridge University Press p 297 ISBN 0 521 55640 6 Lusthaus Dan 2002 Buddhist Phenomenology A philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch eng Wei shih lun RoutledgeCurzon p 194 ISBN 0 415 40610 2 Lusthaus Dan 2002 Buddhist Phenomenology A philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch eng Wei shih lun RoutledgeCurzon p 48 ISBN 0 415 40610 2 Karmasiddhiprakarana The Treatise on Action by Vasubandhu translated by Etienne Lamotte and Leo M Pruden Asian Humanities Press 2001 ISBN 0 89581 908 2 pg 13 35 Williams 2008 p 95 How Mystical is Buddhism by Roger R Jackson Asian Philosophy Vol 6 No 2 1996 pg 150 a b Groner Paul 2000 The Establishment of the Tendai School University of Hawaii Press pp 97 100 ISBN 0824823710 Ford James L 2006 Jokei and Buddhist Devotion in Early Medieval Japan Oxford University Press USA pp 35 68 ISBN 978 0 19 518814 1 Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 8 Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 73 Zhihua Yao The Buddhist Theory of Self Cognition pp 149 150 Routledge 2012 Kajiyama Yuichi Controversy between the sakara and nirakara vadins of the Yogacara school some materials Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 14 1965 n pag https www semanticscholar org paper Controversy between the sakara and nirakara vadins Kajiyama 655a1f561c18725188c0916ca05ec334b5f9f7cd Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 73 74 Tomlinson Davey 2022 Limiting the Scope of the Neither One Nor Many Argument The Nirakaravadin s Defense of Consciousness and Pleasure Philosophy East and West doi 10 1353 pew 0 0235 ISSN 1529 1898 Timme Kragh 2013 pp 16 25 26 30 46 Timme Kragh 2013 p 31 Timme Kragh 2013 p 34 Timme Kragh 2013 pp 51 60 230 a b Brunnholzl Karl trans Asanga 2019 A Compendium of the Mahayana Asanga s Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries Appendix 10 Shambhala Publications a b c Watanabe Chikafumi A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III The Relation of Practical Theories and Philosophical Theories pp 40 65 University of Calgary 2000 a b c Muller Charles Five stages of cultivating the Yogacara path 唯識修道五位 Digital Dictionary of Buddhism 2006 Watanabe Chikafumi A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III The Relation of Practical Theories and Philosophical Theories p 66 University of Calgary 2000 Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 pp 97 107 119 125 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 pp 107 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 pp 119 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 109 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 111 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 111 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 122 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 114 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 884 885 Kragh 2013 p 157 Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 889 891 Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 893 894 a b Brunnholzl Karl trans Asanga 2019 A Compendium of the Mahayana Asanga s Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries Appendix 8 Shambhala Publications Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 78 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Kragh 2013 p 160 Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 894 896 a b Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 896 897 Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 897 898 Brunnholzl Karl 2009 Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature pp 21 22 Snow Lion Publications Brunnholzl Karl 2009 Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature p 24 Snow Lion Publications Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 87 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Brunnholzl Karl 2009 Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature p 25 Snow Lion Publications Brunnholzl Karl 2009 Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature pp 23 24 Snow Lion Publications Deleanu Florin Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhumi Quest for and Liberation through the Thing In Itself in Kragh 2013 pp 898 899 a b c Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 90 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies a b c Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 p 92 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies a b Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 pp 94 95 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies a b Jones Lindsay Ed in Chief 2005 Encyclopedia of Religion 2nd Ed Volume 14 Masaaki Hattori Ed 1987 amp 2005 Yogacara p 9897 USA Macmillan Reference ISBN 0 02 865983 X v 14 E Frauwallner 2010 1956 Die Philosophie des Buddhismus p 166 O Brien Kop K Dharmamegha in yoga and yogacara the revision of a superlative metaphor J Indian Philos 48 605 635 2020 https doi org 10 1007 s10781 020 09432 3 Powers John 2004 Hermeneutics and Tradition in the Saṃdhinirmocana sutra Motilal Banarsidass pp 4 11 ISBN 978 81 208 1926 9 Waldron William S 2003 The Buddhist Unconscious The Alaya vijnana in the Context of Indian Buddhist Thought Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 42886 1 King Richard Vijnaptimatrata and the Abhidharma context of early Yogacara a b Kritzer 2005 p xvii xix M Delhey The Yogacarabhumi Corpus Sources Editions Translations and Reference Works 2013 Kragh U T editor The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners The Buddhist Yogacarabhumi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India East Asia and Tibet Volume 1 p 312 Harvard University Department of South Asian studies 2013 Deleanu F Ed 2006 The Chapter on the Mundane Path Laukikamarga A Trilingual Edition Sanskrit Tibetan Chinese Annotated Translation and Introductory Study 2 vol pp 157 18 Tokyo International Institute for Buddhist Studies Xuanzang Bianji Li Jung hsi 1996 The great Tang dynasty record of the western regions Numata Center for Buddhist Translation amp Research ISBN 978 1 886439 02 3 Wayman Alex Untying the Knots in Buddhism Selected Essays 1997 p 213 a b Tucci Giuseppe 1975 On Some Aspects of the Doctrines of the Maitreya Natha and Asanga Being a Course of Five Lectures Delivered at the University of Calcutta Chinese Materials Center D AMATO M THREE NATURES THREE STAGES AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGACARA TRISVABHAVA THEORY Journal of Indian Philosophy vol 33 no 2 2005 pp 185 207 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 23497001 Accessed 16 Feb 2024 Makransky John J Buddhahood Embodied Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet SUNY Press 1997 p 187 Williams Paul Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge 1989 p 103 Gold Jonathan Paving the Great Way Vasubandhu s Unifying Buddhist Philosophy Columbia University Press 2014 p 2 a b Delenau Florin Mind Only and Beyond History of Yogacara Meditation 2010 pp 17 20 Lectures Series Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies Takasaki Jikido 1966 A Study on the Ratnagotravibhaga Uttaratantra Being a Treatise on the Tathagatagarbha Theory of Mahayana Buddhism Rome Oriental Series 33 Rome Istituto Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente pp 45 52 Dreyfus Georges B J Recognizing Reality Dharmakirti s Philosophy and its Tibetan Interpretations Suny 1997 pp 15 16 Saṅkaranandana in Silk Jonathan A editor in chief Brill s Encyclopedia of Buddhism Volume II Lives Brunnholzl Karl When the Clouds Part The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra Shambhala Publications 2015 p 117 Lusthaus Dan Buddhist Phenomenology A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch eng Wei shih Lun Routledge 2014 p 274 a b Lusthaus Dan Buddhist Phenomenology A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch eng Wei shih Lun Routledge 2014 pp 8 10 Brunnholzl Karl When the Clouds Part The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra Shambhala Publications 2015 p 118 a b Kano Kazuo Sajjana and Mahajana Yogacara Exegeses in the Eleventh Century Kashmir Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 69 no 2 2021 118 124 a b Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 74 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 142 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 Garfield Jay L Westerhoff Jan 2015 Madhyamaka and Yogacara Allies Or Rivals p 6 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 023129 3 a b Shantarakshita amp Ju Mipham 2005 pp 117 122 Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 10 Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 81 Komarovski Yaroslav Visions of Unity The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka Albany New York State University of New York Press 2011 p 80 Paul Diana Philosophy of Mind in Sixth Century China Paramartha s Evolution of Consciousness 1984 p 6 Paul Diana Philosophy of Mind in Sixth Century China Paramartha s Evolution of Consciousness 1984 pp 32 33 Muller A C Quick Overview of the Faxiang School 法相宗 www acmuller net Retrieved 2023 04 24 Jorgensen John Lusthaus Dan Makeham John Strange Mark trans 2019 Treatise on Awakening Mahayana Faith New York NY Oxford University Press in Introduction pp 1 10 a b c Liu JeeLoo An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism 2006 p 220 Wei Tat Cheng Weishi Lun 1973 p li Tagawa Shun ei 2009 Charles Muller ed Living Yogacara An Introduction to Consciousness Only Buddhism Wisdom Publications p xx xxi forward ISBN 978 0 86171 589 3 Liu JeeLoo An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism 2006 p 221 Green Ronald S 2020 Early Japanese Hosso in Relation to Silla Yoga ca ra in Disputes between Nara s Northern and Southern Temple Traditions Journal of Korean Religions 11 1 97 121 doi 10 1353 jkr 2020 0003 Makeham John Transforming Consciousness Yogacara Thought in Modern China pp 13 14 Oxford University Press 2014 Khyentse Rinpoche Dzongsar Jamyang 2003 Introduction In Alex Trisoglio ed Introduction to the Middle Way Chandrakirti s Madhyamakavatara with Commentary PDF 1st ed Dordogne France Khyentse Foundation p 8 Retrieved 7 January 2013 In the 8th century Shantarakshita went to Tibet and founded the monastery at Samye He was not a direct disciple of Bhavaviveka but the disciple of one of his disciples He combined the Madhyamika Svatantrika and Cittamatra schools and created a new school of Madhyamika called Svatantrika Yogachara Madhyamika His disciple Kamalashila who wrote The Stages of Meditation upon Madhyamika uma i sgom rim developed his ideas further and together they were very influential in Tibet Germano David F Waldron William S 2006 A Comparison of Alaya vijnana in Yogacara and Dzogchen PDF in Nauriyal D K Drummond Michael S Lal Y B eds Buddhist Thought and Applied Psychological Research Transcending the boundaries Abingdon Oxon Routledge pp 36 68 ISBN 978 0 415 37431 6 Brunnholzl Karl Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature Introduction Snow Lion Publications The Nitartha Institute 2009 Taranatha An Ascertainment of the Two Systems Jonang Foundation Archived from the original on December 13 2012 Retrieved 19 December 2012 Accordingly those who adhere to rangtong take the first wheel of the Buddha s teachings which is the Wheel of Dharma that teaches the Four Noble Truths to be provisional in meaning the middle Wheel of Dharma that teaches the absence of characteristics as ultimately definitive in meaning and the final excellently distinguished Wheel of Dharma as teaching the circumstantial definitive meaning which is provisional in meaning Those who uphold zhentong take the first Wheel of Dharma to be provisional the middle Wheel of Dharma to teach the circumstantial definitive meaning and the final Wheel of Dharma to teach to ultimate definitive meaning Je Tsongkhapa 1993 Kapstein Matthew ed Ocean of Eloquence Tsong kha pa s Commentary on the Yogacara Doctrine of Mind in Tibetan and English Sparham Gareth trans in collaboration with Shotaro Iida 1st ed Albany NY State University of New York ISBN 0791414795 Retrieved 18 December 2012 Berzin Alexander Brief Survey of Self voidness and Other voidness Views Retrieved 20 June 2016 a b Dumoulin Heinrich 2005 Zen Buddhism A History Vol 1 India and China Bloomington IN World Wisdom p 52 ISBN 0 941532 89 5 a b Kapstein Matthew T Tibetan Buddhism A Very Short Introduction New York Oxford University Press 2014 p 64 Torella Raffaele The Pratyabhijna and the logical epistemological school of Buddhism in Goudriaan ed 1992 Ritual and Speculation in Early Tantrism Studies in Honor of Andre Padoux pp 327 346 SUNY Press Stcherbatsky Fyodor Th Buddhist Logic Vol I p 51 Dover Publications Keown Damien 2004 A Dictionary of Buddhism p 302 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 860560 7 Powers John The Yogacara School of Buddhism A Bibliography p 18 American Theological Library Association 1991 Paul Williams Anthony Tribe Alexander Wynne Buddhist Thought A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition p 121 2012 Muller A C Quick Overview of the Faxiang School 法相宗 www acmuller net Retrieved 2023 04 24 Makeham John Transforming Consciousness Yogacara Thought in Modern China p 6 Oxford University Press 2014 a b Kritzer 2005 p xii Fernando Tola Carmen Dragonetti Being as Consciousness Yogacara Philosophy of Buddhism p xii Foundations of Buddhism by Rupert Gethin Oxford University Press 1998 ISBN 0 19 289223 1 Williams 2008 p 103 Harris Ian Charles 1991 The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism p 78 BRILL Ghanavyuhasutra Buddha Nature buddhanature tsadra org Retrieved 2023 08 07 T1830 成唯識論述記 T43 229c29 230a1 CBETA Shih Jen Kuan 2006 Doctrinal Connection Between Panjiao Schemata and Human Capacity for Enlightenment in Jizang s and Kuiji s Thought University of Wisconsin Madison Keenan John P The Interpretation of the Buddha Land BDK English Tripitaka Numata Center for Buddhist Translation amp Research 2006 Makransky John J 1997 Buddhahood Embodied Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet p 10 SUNY ISBN 0 7914 3431 1 a study of interpretations of the Abhisamayalankara Brunnholzl Karl 2014 The Meditative Tradition of the Uttaratantra and Shentong When the Clouds Part The Uttaratantra and its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra Boston Snow Lion Publications pp 123 50 a b Williams 2008 pp 87 88 Brunnholzl Karl Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature pp 10 11 Snow Lion Publications The Nitartha Institute 2009 D AMATO M THREE NATURES THREE STAGES AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGACARA TRISVABHAVA THEORY Journal of Indian Philosophy vol 33 no 2 2005 pp 185 207 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 23497001 Accessed 16 Feb 2024 D AMATO M THREE NATURES THREE STAGES AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGACARA TRISVABHAVA THEORY Journal of Indian Philosophy vol 33 no 2 2005 pp 185 207 JSTOR http www jstor org stable 23497001 Accessed 16 Feb 2024 Lugli Ligeia Asaṅga oxfordbibliographies com LAST MODIFIED 25 NOVEMBER 2014 DOI 10 1093 OBO 9780195393521 0205 Kalupahana 1992 p 126 Brunnholzl Karl Luminous Heart The Third Karmapa on Consciousness Wisdom and Buddha Nature p 9 Snow Lion Publications The Nitartha Institute 2009 Lugli Ligeia Asaṅga oxfordbibliographies com LAST MODIFIED 25 NOVEMBER 2014 DOI 10 1093 OBO 9780195393521 0205 Makransky John J Buddhahood Embodied Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet SUNY Press 1997 p 187 Brunnholzl Karl When the Clouds Part The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra Shambhala Publications 2015 p 81 Saṅkaranandana in Silk Jonathan A editor in chief Brill s Encyclopedia of Buddhism Volume II Lives Sinclair Iain Dharmakirti of Kedah His life work and troubled times Temasek Working Paper No 2 2021 Temasek History Research Centre ISEAS Yusof Ishak InstituteSources editBayer Achim 2012 Addenda and Corrigenda to The Theory of Karman in the Abhidharmasamuccaya 2012 Hamburg Zentrum fur Buddhismuskunde Kalupahana David J 1992 The Principles of Buddhist Psychology Delhi ri Satguru Publications Keenan John P 1993 Yogacara pp 203 212 published in Yoshinori Takeuchi with Van Bragt Jan Heisig James W O Leary Joseph S Swanson Paul L 1993 Buddhist Spirituality Indian Southeast Asian Tibetan and Early Chinese New York City The Crossroad Publishing Company ISBN 0 8245 1277 4 King Richard 1998 Vijnaptimatrata and the Abhidharma context of early Yogacara Asian Philosophy 8 1 5 18 doi 10 1080 09552369808575468 Kochumuttom Thomas A 1999 A buddhist Doctrine of Experience A New Translation and Interpretation of the Works of Vasubandhu the Yogacarin Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Norbu Namkhai 2001 The Precious Vase Instructions on the Base of Santi Maha Sangha Shang Shung Edizioni Second revised edition Translated from the Tibetan edited and annotated by Adriano Clemente with the help of the author Translated from Italian into English by Andy Lukianowicz Park Sung bae 1983 Buddhist Faith and Sudden Enlightenment SUNY Press Shantarakshita amp Ju Mipham 2005 The Adornment of the Middle Way Padmakara Translation of Ju Mipham s commentary on Shantarakshita s root versus on his synthesis Sponberg Alan 1979 Dynamic Liberation in Yogacara Buddhism Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 2 1 pp 44 64 Stcherbatsky Theodore 1936 Mathyanta Vibhanga Discourse on Discrimination between Middle and Extremes ascribed to Bodhisattva Maiteya and commented by Vasubhandu and Sthiramathi translated from the sanscrit Academy of Sciences USSR Press Moscow Leningrad Timme Kragh Ulrich editor 2013 The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners The Buddhist Yogacarabhumi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India East Asia and Tibet Volume 1 Harvard University Department of South Asian studies Zim Robert 1995 Basic ideas of Yogacara Buddhism San Francisco State University Source 4 accessed October 18 2007 External links editUncompromising Idealism or the School of Vijnanavada Buddhism Surendranath Dasgupta 1940 Early Yogaacaara and Its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School Richard King Philosophy East amp West vol 44 no 4 October 1994 pp 659 683 The mind only teaching of Ching ying Hui Yuan subtitle An early interpretation of Yogaacaara thought in China Ming Wood Liu Philosophy East amp West vol 35 no 4 October 1985 pp 351 375 Yogacara Buddhism Research Association articles bibliographies and links to other relevant sites Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Yogachara amp oldid 1218178175, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.