fbpx
Wikipedia

Truth

Truth or verity is the property of being in accord with fact or reality.[1] In everyday language, truth is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise correspond to it, such as beliefs, propositions, and declarative sentences.[2]

Truth is usually held to be the opposite of false statement. The concept of truth is discussed and debated in various contexts, including philosophy, art, theology, law, and science. Most human activities depend upon the concept, where its nature as a concept is assumed rather than being a subject of discussion, including journalism and everyday life. Some philosophers view the concept of truth as basic, and unable to be explained in any terms that are more easily understood than the concept of truth itself.[2] Most commonly, truth is viewed as the correspondence of language or thought to a mind-independent world. This is called the correspondence theory of truth.

Various theories and views of truth continue to be debated among scholars, philosophers, and theologians.[2][3] There are many different questions about the nature of truth which are still the subject of contemporary debates. These include the question of defining truth; whether it is even possible to give an informative definition of truth; identifying things as truth-bearers capable of being true or false; if truth and falsehood are bivalent, or if there are other truth values; identifying the criteria of truth that allow us to identify it and to distinguish it from falsehood; the role that truth plays in constituting knowledge; and, if truth is always absolute or if it can be relative to one's perspective.

Definition and etymology edit

The English word truth is derived from Old English tríewþ, tréowþ, trýwþ, Middle English trewþe, cognate to Old High German triuwida, Old Norse tryggð. Like troth, it is a -th nominalisation of the adjective true (Old English tréowe).

The English word true is from Old English (West Saxon) (ge)tríewe, tréowe, cognate to Old Saxon (gi)trûui, Old High German (ga)triuwu (Modern German treu "faithful"), Old Norse tryggr, Gothic triggws,[4] all from a Proto-Germanic *trewwj- "having good faith", perhaps ultimately from PIE *dru- "tree", on the notion of "steadfast as an oak" (e.g., Sanskrit dā́ru "(piece of) wood").[5] Old Norse trú, "faith, word of honour; religious faith, belief"[6] (archaic English troth "loyalty, honesty, good faith", compare Ásatrú).

Thus, "truth" involves both the quality of "faithfulness, fidelity, loyalty, sincerity, veracity",[7] and that of "agreement with fact or reality", in Anglo-Saxon expressed by sōþ (Modern English sooth).

All Germanic languages besides English have introduced a terminological distinction between truth "fidelity" and truth "factuality". To express "factuality", North Germanic opted for nouns derived from sanna "to assert, affirm", while continental West Germanic (German and Dutch) opted for continuations of wâra "faith, trust, pact" (cognate to Slavic věra "(religious) faith", but influenced by Latin verus). Romance languages use terms following the Latin veritas, while the Greek aletheia, Russian pravda, South Slavic istina and Sanskrit sat (related to English sooth and North Germanic sanna) have separate etymological origins.

In some modern contexts, the word "truth" is used to refer to fidelity to an original or standard. It can also be used in the context of being "true to oneself" in the sense of acting with authenticity.[1]

Major theories edit

 
Walter Seymour Allward's Veritas (Truth) outside Supreme Court of Canada, Ottawa, Ontario Canada

The question of what is a proper basis for deciding how words, symbols, ideas and beliefs may properly be considered true, whether by a single person or an entire society, is dealt with by the five most prevalent substantive theories of truth listed below. Each presents perspectives that are widely shared by published scholars.[8][9][10]

Theories other than the most prevalent substantive theories are also discussed. According to a survey of professional philosophers and others on their philosophical views which was carried out in November 2009 (taken by 3226 respondents, including 1803 philosophy faculty members and/or PhDs and 829 philosophy graduate students) 45% of respondents accept or lean towards correspondence theories, 21% accept or lean towards deflationary theories and 14% epistemic theories.[11]

Substantive edit

Correspondence edit

Correspondence theories emphasize that true beliefs and true statements correspond to the actual state of affairs.[12] This type of theory stresses a relationship between thoughts or statements on one hand, and things or objects on the other. It is a traditional model tracing its origins to ancient Greek philosophers such as Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle.[13] This class of theories holds that the truth or the falsity of a representation is determined in principle entirely by how it relates to "things" according to whether it accurately describes those "things". A classic example of correspondence theory is the statement by the thirteenth century philosopher and theologian Thomas Aquinas: "Veritas est adaequatio rei et intellectus" ("Truth is the adequation of things and intellect"), which Aquinas attributed to the ninth century Neoplatonist Isaac Israeli.[14][15][16] Aquinas also restated the theory as: "A judgment is said to be true when it conforms to the external reality".[17]

Correspondence theory centres heavily around the assumption that truth is a matter of accurately copying what is known as "objective reality" and then representing it in thoughts, words, and other symbols.[18] Many modern theorists have stated that this ideal cannot be achieved without analysing additional factors.[8][19] For example, language plays a role in that all languages have words to represent concepts that are virtually undefined in other languages. The German word Zeitgeist is one such example: one who speaks or understands the language may "know" what it means, but any translation of the word apparently fails to accurately capture its full meaning (this is a problem with many abstract words, especially those derived in agglutinative languages). Thus, some words add an additional parameter to the construction of an accurate truth predicate. Among the philosophers who grappled with this problem is Alfred Tarski, whose semantic theory is summarized further on.[20]

Proponents of several of the theories below have gone further to assert that there are yet other issues necessary to the analysis, such as interpersonal power struggles, community interactions, personal biases, and other factors involved in deciding what is seen as truth.

Coherence edit

For coherence theories in general, truth requires a proper fit of elements within a whole system. Very often, however, coherence is taken to imply something more than simple logical consistency; often there is a demand that the propositions in a coherent system lend mutual inferential support to each other. So, for example, the completeness and comprehensiveness of the underlying set of concepts is a critical factor in judging the validity and usefulness of a coherent system.[21] A pervasive tenet of coherence theories is the idea that truth is primarily a property of whole systems of propositions, and can be ascribed to individual propositions only according to their coherence with the whole. Among the assortment of perspectives commonly regarded as coherence theory, theorists differ on the question of whether coherence entails many possible true systems of thought or only a single absolute system.

Some variants of coherence theory are claimed to describe the essential and intrinsic properties of formal systems in logic and mathematics.[22] However, formal reasoners are content to contemplate axiomatically independent and sometimes mutually contradictory systems side by side, for example, the various alternative geometries. On the whole, coherence theories have been rejected for lacking justification in their application to other areas of truth, especially with respect to assertions about the natural world, empirical data in general, assertions about practical matters of psychology and society, especially when used without support from the other major theories of truth.[23]

Coherence theories distinguish the thought of rationalist philosophers, particularly of Baruch Spinoza, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, along with the British philosopher F. H. Bradley.[24] They have found a resurgence also among several proponents of logical positivism, notably Otto Neurath and Carl Hempel.

Pragmatic edit

The three most influential forms of the pragmatic theory of truth were introduced around the turn of the 20th century by Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. Although there are wide differences in viewpoint among these and other proponents of pragmatic theory, they hold in common that truth is verified and confirmed by the results of putting one's concepts into practice.[25]

Peirce defines truth as follows: "Truth is that concordance of an abstract statement with the ideal limit towards which endless investigation would tend to bring scientific belief, which concordance the abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its inaccuracy and one-sidedness, and this confession is an essential ingredient of truth."[26] This statement stresses Peirce's view that ideas of approximation, incompleteness, and partiality, what he describes elsewhere as fallibilism and "reference to the future", are essential to a proper conception of truth. Although Peirce uses words like concordance and correspondence to describe one aspect of the pragmatic sign relation, he is also quite explicit in saying that definitions of truth based on mere correspondence are no more than nominal definitions, which he accords a lower status than real definitions.

William James's version of pragmatic theory, while complex, is often summarized by his statement that "the 'true' is only the expedient in our way of thinking, just as the 'right' is only the expedient in our way of behaving."[27] By this, James meant that truth is a quality, the value of which is confirmed by its effectiveness when applying concepts to practice (thus, "pragmatic").

John Dewey, less broadly than James but more broadly than Peirce, held that inquiry, whether scientific, technical, sociological, philosophical, or cultural, is self-corrective over time if openly submitted for testing by a community of inquirers in order to clarify, justify, refine, and/or refute proposed truths.[28]

Though not widely known, a new variation of the pragmatic theory was defined and wielded successfully from the 20th century forward. Defined and named by William Ernest Hocking, this variation is known as "negative pragmatism". Essentially, what works may or may not be true, but what fails cannot be true because the truth always works.[29] Philosopher of science Richard Feynman also subscribed to it: "We never are definitely right, we can only be sure we are wrong."[30] This approach incorporates many of the ideas from Peirce, James, and Dewey. For Peirce, the idea of "endless investigation would tend to bring about scientific belief" fits negative pragmatism in that a negative pragmatist would never stop testing. As Feynman noted, an idea or theory "could never be proved right, because tomorrow's experiment might succeed in proving wrong what you thought was right."[30] Similarly, James and Dewey's ideas also ascribe truth to repeated testing which is "self-corrective" over time.

Pragmatism and negative pragmatism are also closely aligned with the coherence theory of truth in that any testing should not be isolated but rather incorporate knowledge from all human endeavors and experience. The universe is a whole and integrated system, and testing should acknowledge and account for its diversity. As Feynman said, "... if it disagrees with experiment, it is wrong."[31]

Constructivist edit

Social constructivism holds that truth is constructed by social processes, is historically and culturally specific, and that it is in part shaped through the power struggles within a community. Constructivism views all of our knowledge as "constructed," because it does not reflect any external "transcendent" realities (as a pure correspondence theory might hold). Rather, perceptions of truth are viewed as contingent on convention, human perception, and social experience. It is believed by constructivists that representations of physical and biological reality, including race, sexuality, and gender, are socially constructed.

Giambattista Vico was among the first to claim that history and culture were man-made. Vico's epistemological orientation gathers the most diverse rays and unfolds in one axiom—verum ipsum factum—"truth itself is constructed". Hegel and Marx were among the other early proponents of the premise that truth is, or can be, socially constructed. Marx, like many critical theorists who followed, did not reject the existence of objective truth, but rather distinguished between true knowledge and knowledge that has been distorted through power or ideology. For Marx, scientific and true knowledge is "in accordance with the dialectical understanding of history" and ideological knowledge is "an epiphenomenal expression of the relation of material forces in a given economic arrangement".[32][page needed]

Consensus edit

Consensus theory holds that truth is whatever is agreed upon, or in some versions, might come to be agreed upon, by some specified group. Such a group might include all human beings, or a subset thereof consisting of more than one person.

Among the current advocates of consensus theory as a useful accounting of the concept of "truth" is the philosopher Jürgen Habermas.[33] Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed upon in an ideal speech situation.[34] Among the current strong critics of consensus theory is the philosopher Nicholas Rescher.[35]

Minimalist edit

Deflationary edit

Modern developments in the field of philosophy have resulted in the rise of a new thesis: that the term truth does not denote a real property of sentences or propositions. This thesis is in part a response to the common use of truth predicates (e.g., that some particular thing "...is true") which was particularly prevalent in philosophical discourse on truth in the first half of the 20th century. From this point of view, to assert that "'2 + 2 = 4' is true" is logically equivalent to asserting that "2 + 2 = 4", and the phrase "is true" is completely dispensable in this and every other context. In common parlance, truth predicates are not commonly heard, and it would be interpreted as an unusual occurrence were someone to utilise a truth predicate in an everyday conversation when asserting that something is true. Newer perspectives that take this discrepancy into account and work with sentence structures that are actually employed in common discourse can be broadly described:

  • as deflationary theories of truth, since they attempt to deflate the presumed importance of the words "true" or truth,
  • as disquotational theories, to draw attention to the disappearance of the quotation marks in cases like the above example, or
  • as minimalist theories of truth.[8][36]

Whichever term is used, deflationary theories can be said to hold in common that "the predicate 'true' is an expressive convenience, not the name of a property requiring deep analysis."[8] Once we have identified the truth predicate's formal features and utility, deflationists argue, we have said all there is to be said about truth. Among the theoretical concerns of these views is to explain away those special cases where it does appear that the concept of truth has peculiar and interesting properties. (See, e.g., Semantic paradoxes, and below.)

In addition to highlighting such formal aspects of the predicate "is true", some deflationists point out that the concept enables us to express things that might otherwise require infinitely long sentences. For example, one cannot express confidence in Michael's accuracy by asserting the endless sentence:

Michael says, 'snow is white' and snow is white, or he says 'roses are red' and roses are red or he says ... etc.

This assertion can also be succinctly expressed by saying: What Michael says is true.[37]

Performative edit

Attributed to philosopher P. F. Strawson is the performative theory of truth which holds that to say "'Snow is white' is true" is to perform the speech act of signaling one's agreement with the claim that snow is white (much like nodding one's head in agreement). The idea that some statements are more actions than communicative statements is not as odd as it may seem. For example, when a wedding couple says "I do" at the appropriate time in a wedding, they are performing the act of taking the other to be their lawful wedded spouse. They are not describing themselves as taking the other, but actually doing so (perhaps the most thorough analysis of such "illocutionary acts" is J. L. Austin, most notably in "How to Do Things With Words"[38]).

Strawson holds that a similar analysis is applicable to all speech acts, not just illocutionary ones: "To say a statement is true is not to make a statement about a statement, but rather to perform the act of agreeing with, accepting, or endorsing a statement. When one says 'It's true that it's raining,' one asserts no more than 'It's raining.' The function of [the statement] 'It's true that...' is to agree with, accept, or endorse the statement that 'it's raining.'"[39]

Redundancy and related edit

According to the redundancy theory of truth, asserting that a statement is true is completely equivalent to asserting the statement itself. For example, making the assertion that " 'Snow is white' is true" is equivalent to asserting "Snow is white". Redundancy theorists infer from this premise that truth is a redundant concept; that is, it is merely a word that is traditionally used in conversation or writing, generally for emphasis, but not a word that actually equates to anything in reality. This theory is commonly attributed to Frank P. Ramsey, who held that the use of words like fact and truth was nothing but a roundabout way of asserting a proposition, and that treating these words as separate problems in isolation from judgment was merely a "linguistic muddle".[8][40][41]

A variant of redundancy theory is the disquotational theory which uses a modified form of the logician Alfred Tarski's schema: To say that '"P" is true' is to say that P. A version of this theory was defended by C. J. F. Williams in his book What is Truth? Yet another version of deflationism is the prosentential theory of truth, first developed by Dorothy Grover, Joseph Camp, and Nuel Belnap as an elaboration of Ramsey's claims. They argue that sentences like "That's true", when said in response to "It's raining", are prosentences, expressions that merely repeat the content of other expressions. In the same way that it means the same as my dog in the sentence My dog was hungry, so I fed it, That's true is supposed to mean the same as It's raining—if one says the latter and another then says the former. These variations do not necessarily follow Ramsey in asserting that truth is not a property, but rather can be understood to say that, for instance, the assertion "P" may well involve a substantial truth, and the theorists in this case are minimizing only the redundancy or prosentence involved in the statement such as "that's true".[8]

The scope of deflationary principles is limited to representations that resemble sentences. They do not encompass a broader range of entities that are typically considered true or otherwise.

Philosophical skepticism edit

Philosophical skepticism is generally any questioning attitude or doubt towards one or more items of knowledge or belief which ascribe truth to their assertions and propositions.[42][43] The primary target of philosophical skepticism is epistemology, but it can be applied to any domain, such as the supernatural, morality (moral skepticism), and religion (skepticism about the existence of God).[44]

Philosophical skepticism comes in various forms. Radical forms of skepticism deny that knowledge or rational belief is possible and urge us to suspend judgment regarding ascription of truth on many or all controversial matters. More moderate forms of skepticism claim only that nothing can be known with certainty, or that we can know little or nothing about the "big questions" in life, such as whether God exists or whether there is an afterlife. Religious skepticism is "doubt concerning basic religious principles (such as immortality, providence, and revelation)".[45] Scientific skepticism concerns testing beliefs for reliability, by subjecting them to systematic investigation using the scientific method, to discover empirical evidence for them.

Pluralist edit

Several of the major theories of truth hold that there is a particular property the having of which makes a belief or proposition true. Pluralist theories of truth assert that there may be more than one property that makes propositions true: ethical propositions might be true by virtue of coherence. Propositions about the physical world might be true by corresponding to the objects and properties they are about.

Some of the pragmatic theories, such as those by Charles Peirce and William James, included aspects of correspondence, coherence and constructivist theories.[26][27] Crispin Wright argued in his 1992 book Truth and Objectivity that any predicate which satisfied certain platitudes about truth qualified as a truth predicate. In some discourses, Wright argued, the role of the truth predicate might be played by the notion of superassertibility.[46] Michael Lynch, in a 2009 book Truth as One and Many, argued that we should see truth as a functional property capable of being multiply manifested in distinct properties like correspondence or coherence.[47]

Formal theories edit

Logic edit

Logic is concerned with the patterns in reason that can help tell if a proposition is true or not. Logicians use formal languages to express the truths they are concerned with, and as such there is only truth under some interpretation or truth within some logical system.

A logical truth (also called an analytic truth or a necessary truth) is a statement that is true in all possible worlds[48] or under all possible interpretations, as contrasted to a fact (also called a synthetic claim or a contingency), which is only true in this world as it has historically unfolded. A proposition such as "If p and q, then p" is considered to be a logical truth because of the meaning of the symbols and words in it and not because of any fact of any particular world. They are such that they could not be untrue.

Degrees of truth in logic may be represented using two or more discrete values, as with bivalent logic (or binary logic), three-valued logic, and other forms of finite-valued logic.[49][50] Truth in logic can be represented using numbers comprising a continuous range, typically between 0 and 1, as with fuzzy logic and other forms of infinite-valued logic.[51][52] In general, the concept of representing truth using more than two values is known as many-valued logic.[53]

Mathematics edit

There are two main approaches to truth in mathematics. They are the model theory of truth and the proof theory of truth.[54]

Historically, with the nineteenth century development of Boolean algebra, mathematical models of logic began to treat "truth", also represented as "T" or "1", as an arbitrary constant. "Falsity" is also an arbitrary constant, which can be represented as "F" or "0". In propositional logic, these symbols can be manipulated according to a set of axioms and rules of inference, often given in the form of truth tables.

In addition, from at least the time of Hilbert's program at the turn of the twentieth century to the proof of Gödel's incompleteness theorems and the development of the Church–Turing thesis in the early part of that century, true statements in mathematics were generally assumed to be those statements that are provable in a formal axiomatic system.[55]

The works of Kurt Gödel, Alan Turing, and others shook this assumption, with the development of statements that are true but cannot be proven within the system.[56] Two examples of the latter can be found in Hilbert's problems. Work on Hilbert's 10th problem led in the late twentieth century to the construction of specific Diophantine equations for which it is undecidable whether they have a solution,[57] or even if they do, whether they have a finite or infinite number of solutions. More fundamentally, Hilbert's first problem was on the continuum hypothesis.[58] Gödel and Paul Cohen showed that this hypothesis cannot be proved or disproved using the standard axioms of set theory.[59] In the view of some, then, it is equally reasonable to take either the continuum hypothesis or its negation as a new axiom.

Gödel thought that the ability to perceive the truth of a mathematical or logical proposition is a matter of intuition, an ability he admitted could be ultimately beyond the scope of a formal theory of logic or mathematics[60][61] and perhaps best considered in the realm of human comprehension and communication. But he commented, "The more I think about language, the more it amazes me that people ever understand each other at all".[62]

Tarski's semantics edit

The semantic theory of truth has as its general case for a given language:

'P' is true if and only if P

where 'P' refers to the sentence (the sentence's name), and P is just the sentence itself.

Tarski's theory of truth (named after Alfred Tarski) was developed for formal languages, such as formal logic. Here he restricted it in this way: no language could contain its own truth predicate, that is, the expression is true could only apply to sentences in some other language. The latter he called an object language, the language being talked about. (It may, in turn, have a truth predicate that can be applied to sentences in still another language.) The reason for his restriction was that languages that contain their own truth predicate will contain paradoxical sentences such as, "This sentence is not true". As a result, Tarski held that the semantic theory could not be applied to any natural language, such as English, because they contain their own truth predicates. Donald Davidson used it as the foundation of his truth-conditional semantics and linked it to radical interpretation in a form of coherentism.

Bertrand Russell is credited with noticing the existence of such paradoxes even in the best symbolic formations of mathematics in his day, in particular the paradox that came to be named after him, Russell's paradox. Russell and Whitehead attempted to solve these problems in Principia Mathematica by putting statements into a hierarchy of types, wherein a statement cannot refer to itself, but only to statements lower in the hierarchy. This in turn led to new orders of difficulty regarding the precise natures of types and the structures of conceptually possible type systems that have yet to be resolved to this day.

Kripke's semantics edit

Kripke's theory of truth (named after Saul Kripke) contends that a natural language can in fact contain its own truth predicate without giving rise to contradiction. He showed how to construct one as follows:

  • Beginning with a subset of sentences of a natural language that contains no occurrences of the expression "is true" (or "is false"). So, The barn is big is included in the subset, but not "The barn is big is true", nor problematic sentences such as "This sentence is false".
  • Defining truth just for the sentences in that subset.
  • Extending the definition of truth to include sentences that predicate truth or falsity of one of the original subset of sentences. So "The barn is big is true" is now included, but not either "This sentence is false" nor "'The barn is big is true' is true".
  • Defining truth for all sentences that predicate truth or falsity of a member of the second set. Imagine this process repeated infinitely, so that truth is defined for The barn is big; then for "The barn is big is true"; then for "'The barn is big is true' is true", and so on.

Truth never gets defined for sentences like This sentence is false, since it was not in the original subset and does not predicate truth of any sentence in the original or any subsequent set. In Kripke's terms, these are "ungrounded." Since these sentences are never assigned either truth or falsehood even if the process is carried out infinitely, Kripke's theory implies that some sentences are neither true nor false. This contradicts the principle of bivalence: every sentence must be either true or false. Since this principle is a key premise in deriving the liar paradox, the paradox is dissolved.[63]

However, it has been shown by Gödel that self-reference cannot be avoided naively[clarification needed][citation needed], since propositions about seemingly unrelated objects can have an informal self-referential meaning; in Gödel's work, these objects are integer numbers, and they have an informal meaning regarding propositions[clarification needed]. In fact, this idea — manifested by the diagonal lemma—is the basis for Tarski's theorem that truth cannot be consistently defined.[clarification needed]

It has thus been claimed[64] that Kripke's system indeed leads to contradiction[dubious ]: while its truth predicate is only partial, it does give truth value (true/false) to propositions such as the one built in Tarski's proof,[dubious ] and is therefore inconsistent. While there is still a debate on whether Tarski's proof can be implemented to every similar partial truth system,[clarification needed] none have been shown to be consistent by acceptable methods used in mathematical logic.[citation needed]

Kripke's semantics are related to the use of topoi and other concepts from category theory in the study of mathematical logic.[65] They provide a choice of formal semantics for intuitionistic logic.

Folk beliefs edit

The truth predicate "P is true" has great practical value in human language, allowing efficient endorsement or impeaching of claims made by others, to emphasize the truth or falsity of a statement, or to enable various indirect (Gricean) conversational implications.[66] Individuals or societies will sometime punish "false" statements to deter falsehoods;[67] the oldest surviving law text, the Code of Ur-Nammu, lists penalties for false accusations of sorcery or adultery, as well as for committing perjury in court. Even four-year-old children can pass simple "false belief" tests and successfully assess that another individual's belief diverges from reality in a specific way;[68] by adulthood there are strong implicit intuitions about "truth" that form a "folk theory" of truth. These intuitions include:[69]

  • Capture (T-in): If P, then P is true
  • Release (T-out): If P is true, then P
  • Noncontradiction: A statement can not be both true and false
  • Normativity: It is usually good to believe what is true
  • False beliefs: The notion that believing a statement does not necessarily make it true

Like many folk theories, the folk theory of truth is useful in everyday life but, upon deep analysis, turns out to be technically self-contradictory; in particular, any formal system that fully obeys "capture and release" semantics for truth (also known as the T-schema), and that also respects classical logic, is provably inconsistent and succumbs to the liar paradox or to a similar contradiction.[70]

Notable views edit

Ancient Greek philosophy edit

Socrates', Plato's and Aristotle's ideas about truth are seen by some as consistent with correspondence theory. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle stated: "To say of what is that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true".[71] The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy proceeds to say of Aristotle:

[...] Aristotle sounds much more like a genuine correspondence theorist in the Categories (12b11, 14b14), where he talks of "underlying things" that make statements true and implies that these "things" (pragmata) are logically structured situations or facts (viz., his sitting, his not sitting). Most influential is his claim in De Interpretatione (16a3) that thoughts are "likenesses" (homoiosis) of things. Although he nowhere defines truth in terms of a thought's likeness to a thing or fact, it is clear that such a definition would fit well into his overall philosophy of mind. [...][71]

Similar statements can also be found in Plato's dialogues (Cratylus 385b2, Sophist 263b).[71]

Some Greek philosophers maintained that truth was either not accessible to mortals, or of greatly limited accessibility, forming early philosophical skepticism. Among these were Xenophanes, Democritus, and Pyrrho, the founder of Pyrrhonism, who argued that there was no criterion of truth.

The Epicureans believed that all sense perceptions were true,[72][73] and that errors arise in how we judge those perceptions.

The Stoics conceived truth as accessible from impressions via cognitive grasping.

Medieval philosophy edit

Avicenna (980–1037) edit

In early Islamic philosophy, Avicenna (Ibn Sina) defined truth in his work Kitab Al-Shifa The Book of Healing, Book I, Chapter 8, as:

What corresponds in the mind to what is outside it.[74]

Avicenna elaborated on his definition of truth later in Book VIII, Chapter 6:

The truth of a thing is the property of the being of each thing which has been established in it.[75]

However, this definition is merely a rendering of the medieval Latin translation of the work by Simone van Riet.[76] A modern translation of the original Arabic text states:

Truth is also said of the veridical belief in the existence [of something].[77]

Aquinas (1225–1274) edit

Reevaluating Avicenna, and also Augustine and Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas stated in his Disputed Questions on Truth:

A natural thing, being placed between two intellects, is called true insofar as it conforms to either. It is said to be true with respect to its conformity with the divine intellect insofar as it fulfills the end to which it was ordained by the divine intellect... With respect to its conformity with a human intellect, a thing is said to be true insofar as it is such as to cause a true estimate about itself.[78]

Thus, for Aquinas, the truth of the human intellect (logical truth) is based on the truth in things (ontological truth).[79] Following this, he wrote an elegant re-statement of Aristotle's view in his Summa I.16.1:

Veritas est adæquatio intellectus et rei.
(Truth is the conformity of the intellect and things.)

Aquinas also said that real things participate in the act of being of the Creator God who is Subsistent Being, Intelligence, and Truth. Thus, these beings possess the light of intelligibility and are knowable. These things (beings; reality) are the foundation of the truth that is found in the human mind, when it acquires knowledge of things, first through the senses, then through the understanding and the judgement done by reason. For Aquinas, human intelligence ("intus", within and "legere", to read) has the capability to reach the essence and existence of things because it has a non-material, spiritual element, although some moral, educational, and other elements might interfere with its capability.

Changing concepts of truth in the Middle Ages edit

Richard Firth Green examined the concept of truth in the later Middle Ages in his A Crisis of Truth, and concludes that roughly during the reign of Richard II of England the very meaning of the concept changes. The idea of the oath, which was so much part and parcel of for instance Romance literature,[80] changes from a subjective concept to a more objective one (in Derek Pearsall's summary).[81] Whereas truth (the "trouthe" of Sir Gawain and the Green Knight) was first "an ethical truth in which truth is understood to reside in persons", in Ricardian England it "transforms...into a political truth in which truth is understood to reside in documents".[82]

Modern philosophy edit

Kant (1724–1804) edit

Immanuel Kant endorses a definition of truth along the lines of the correspondence theory of truth.[71] Kant writes in the Critique of Pure Reason: "The nominal definition of truth, namely that it is the agreement of cognition with its object, is here granted and presupposed".[83] However, Kant denies that this correspondence definition of truth provides us with a test or criterion to establish which judgements are true. Kant states in his logic lectures:

[...] Truth, it is said, consists in the agreement of cognition with its object. In consequence of this mere nominal definition, my cognition, to count as true, is supposed to agree with its object. Now I can compare the object with my cognition, however, only by cognizing it. Hence my cognition is supposed to confirm itself, which is far short of being sufficient for truth. For since the object is outside me, the cognition in me, all I can ever pass judgement on is whether my cognition of the object agrees with my cognition of the object. The ancients called such a circle in explanation a diallelon. And actually the logicians were always reproached with this mistake by the sceptics, who observed that with this definition of truth it is just as when someone makes a statement before a court and in doing so appeals to a witness with whom no one is acquainted, but who wants to establish his credibility by maintaining that the one who called him as witness is an honest man. The accusation was grounded, too. Only the solution of the indicated problem is impossible without qualification and for every man. [...][84]

This passage makes use of his distinction between nominal and real definitions. A nominal definition explains the meaning of a linguistic expression. A real definition describes the essence of certain objects and enables us to determine whether any given item falls within the definition.[85] Kant holds that the definition of truth is merely nominal and, therefore, we cannot employ it to establish which judgements are true. According to Kant, the ancient skeptics were critical of the logicians for holding that, by means of a merely nominal definition of truth, they can establish which judgements are true. They were trying to do something that is "impossible without qualification and for every man".[84]

Hegel (1770–1831) edit

G. W. F. Hegel distanced his philosophy from empiricism by presenting truth as a self-moving process, rather than a matter of merely subjective thoughts. Hegel's truth is analogous to organics in that it is self-determining according to its own inner logic: "Truth is its own self-movement within itself."[86]

Schopenhauer (1788–1860) edit

For Arthur Schopenhauer,[87] a judgment is a combination or separation of two or more concepts. If a judgment is to be an expression of knowledge, it must have a sufficient reason or ground by which the judgment could be called true. Truth is the reference of a judgment to something different from itself which is its sufficient reason (ground). Judgments can have material, formal, transcendental, or metalogical truth. A judgment has material truth if its concepts are based on intuitive perceptions that are generated from sensations. If a judgment has its reason (ground) in another judgment, its truth is called logical or formal. If a judgment, of, for example, pure mathematics or pure science, is based on the forms (space, time, causality) of intuitive, empirical knowledge, then the judgment has transcendental truth.

Kierkegaard (1813–1855) edit

When Søren Kierkegaard, as his character Johannes Climacus, ends his writings: My thesis was, subjectivity, heartfelt is the truth, he does not advocate for subjectivism in its extreme form (the theory that something is true simply because one believes it to be so), but rather that the objective approach to matters of personal truth cannot shed any light upon that which is most essential to a person's life. Objective truths are concerned with the facts of a person's being, while subjective truths are concerned with a person's way of being. Kierkegaard agrees that objective truths for the study of subjects like mathematics, science, and history are relevant and necessary, but argues that objective truths do not shed any light on a person's inner relationship to existence. At best, these truths can only provide a severely narrowed perspective that has little to do with one's actual experience of life.[88]

While objective truths are final and static, subjective truths are continuing and dynamic. The truth of one's existence is a living, inward, and subjective experience that is always in the process of becoming. The values, morals, and spiritual approaches a person adopts, while not denying the existence of objective truths of those beliefs, can only become truly known when they have been inwardly appropriated through subjective experience. Thus, Kierkegaard criticizes all systematic philosophies which attempt to know life or the truth of existence via theories and objective knowledge about reality. As Kierkegaard claims, human truth is something that is continually occurring, and a human being cannot find truth separate from the subjective experience of one's own existing, defined by the values and fundamental essence that consist of one's way of life.[89]

Nietzsche (1844–1900) edit

Friedrich Nietzsche believed the search for truth, or 'the will to truth', was a consequence of the will to power of philosophers. He thought that truth should be used as long as it promoted life and the will to power, and he thought untruth was better than truth if it had this life enhancement as a consequence. As he wrote in Beyond Good and Evil, "The falseness of a judgment is to us not necessarily an objection to a judgment... The question is to what extent it is life-advancing, life-preserving, species-preserving, perhaps even species-breeding..." (aphorism 4). He proposed the will to power as a truth only because, according to him, it was the most life-affirming and sincere perspective one could have.

Robert Wicks discusses Nietzsche's basic view of truth as follows:

[...] Some scholars regard Nietzsche's 1873 unpublished essay, "On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense" ("Über Wahrheit und Lüge im außermoralischen Sinn") as a keystone in his thought. In this essay, Nietzsche rejects the idea of universal constants, and claims that what we call "truth" is only "a mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, and anthropomorphisms." His view at this time is that arbitrariness completely prevails within human experience: concepts originate via the very artistic transference of nerve stimuli into images; "truth" is nothing more than the invention of fixed conventions for merely practical purposes, especially those of repose, security and consistence. [...][90]

Separately Nietzsche suggested that an ancient, metaphysical belief in the divinity of Truth lies at the heart of and has served as the foundation for the entire subsequent Western intellectual tradition: "But you will have gathered what I am getting at, namely, that it is still a metaphysical faith on which our faith in science rests—that even we knowers of today, we godless anti-metaphysicians still take our fire too, from the flame lit by the thousand-year old faith, the Christian faith which was also Plato's faith, that God is Truth; that Truth is 'Divine'..."[91][92]

Moreover, Nietzsche challenges the notion of objective truth, arguing that truths are human creations and serve practical purposes. He wrote, "Truths are illusions about which one has forgotten that this is what they are."[93] He argues that truth is a human invention, arising from the artistic transference of nerve stimuli into images, serving practical purposes like repose, security, and consistency; formed through metaphorical and rhetorical devices, shaped by societal conventions and forgotten origins:

"What, then, is truth? A mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, and anthropomorphisms – in short, a sum of human relations which have been enhanced, transposed, and embellished poetically and rhetorically..."[94]

Nietzsche argues that truth is always filtered through individual perspectives and shaped by various interests and biases. In "On the Genealogy of Morality," he asserts, "There are no facts, only interpretations."[95] He suggests that truth is subject to constant reinterpretation and change, influenced by shifting cultural and historical contexts as he writes in "Thus Spoke Zarathustra" that "I say unto you: one must still have chaos in oneself to be able to give birth to a dancing star."[96] In the same book, Zarathustra proclaims, "Truths are illusions which we have forgotten are illusions; they are metaphors that have become worn out and have been drained of sensuous force, coins which have lost their embossing and are now considered as metal and no longer as coins."[97]

Heidegger (1889–1976) edit

Other philosophers take this common meaning to be secondary and derivative. According to Martin Heidegger, the original meaning and essence of truth in Ancient Greece was unconcealment, or the revealing or bringing of what was previously hidden into the open, as indicated by the original Greek term for truth, aletheia.[98][99] On this view, the conception of truth as correctness is a later derivation from the concept's original essence, a development Heidegger traces to the Latin term veritas. Owing to the primacy of ontology in Heidegger's philosophy, he considered this truth to lie within Being itself, and already in Being and Time (1927) had identified truth with "being-truth" or the "truth of Being" and partially with the Kantian thing-in-itself in an epistemology essentially concerning a mode of Dasein.[100]

Sartre (1905–1980) edit

In Being and Nothingness (1943), partially following Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre identified our knowledge of the truth as a relation between the in-itself and for-itself of being - yet simultaneously closely connected in this vein to the data available to the material personhood, in the body, of an individual in their interaction with the world and others - with Sartre's description that "the world is human" allowing him to postulate all truth as strictly understood by self-consciousness as self-consciousness of something,[101] a view also preceded by Henri Bergson in Time and Free Will (1889), the reading of which Sartre had credited for his interest in philosophy.[102] This first existentialist theory, more fully fleshed out in Sartre's essay Truth and Existence (1948), which already demonstrates a more radical departure from Heidegger in its emphasis on the primacy of the idea, already formulated in Being and Nothingness, of existence as preceding essence in its role in the formulation of truth, has nevertheless been critically examined as idealist rather than materialist in its departure from more traditional idealist epistemologies such as those of Ancient Greek philosophy in Plato and Aristotle, and staying as does Heidegger with Kant.[103]

Later, in the Search for a Method (1957), in which Sartre used a unification of existentialism and Marxism that he would later formulate in the Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960), Sartre, with his growing emphasis on the Hegelian totalisation of historicity, posited a conception of truth still defined by its process of relation to a container giving it material meaning, but with specfiic reference to a role in this broader totalisation, for "subjectivity is neither everything nor nothing; it represents a moment in the objective process (that in which externality is internalised), and this moment is perpetually eliminated only to be perpetually reborn": "For us, truth is something which becomes, it has and will have become. It is a totalisation which is forever being totalised. Particular facts do not signify anything; they are neither true nor false so long as they are not related, through the mediation of various partial totalities, to the totalisation in process." Sartre describes this as a "realistic epistemology", developed out of Marx's ideas but with such a development only possible in an existentialist light, as with the theme of the whole work.[104][105] In an early segment of the lengthy two-volume Critique of 1960, Sartre continued to describe truth as a "totalising" "truth of history" to be interpreted by a "Marxist historian", whilst his break with Heidegger's epistemological ideas is finalised in the description of a seemingly antinomous "dualism of Being and Truth" as the essence of a truly Marxist epistemology.[106]

Camus (1913–1960) edit

The well-regarded French philosopher Albert Camus wrote in his famous essay, The Myth of Sisyphus (1942), that "there are truths but no truth", in fundamental agreement with Nietzsche's perspectivism, and favourably cites Kierkergaad in posing that "no truth is absolute or can render satisfactory an existence that is impossible in itself".[107] Later, in The Rebel (1951), he declared, akin to Sartre, that "the very lowest form of truth" is "the truth of history",[108] but describes this in the context of its abuse and like Kierkergaad in the Concluding Unscientific Postscript he criticizes Hegel in holding a historical attitude "which consists of saying: 'This is truth, which appears to us, however, to be error, but which is true precisely because it happens to be error. As for proof, it is not I, but history, at its conclusion, that will furnish it.'"[109]

Whitehead (1861–1947) edit

Alfred North Whitehead, a British mathematician who became an American philosopher, said: "There are no whole truths; all truths are half-truths. It is trying to treat them as whole truths that plays the devil".[110]

The logical progression or connection of this line of thought is to conclude that truth can lie, since half-truths are deceptive and may lead to a false conclusion.

Peirce (1839–1914) edit

Pragmatists like C. S. Peirce take truth to have some manner of essential relation to human practices for inquiring into and discovering truth, with Peirce himself holding that truth is what human inquiry would find out on a matter, if our practice of inquiry were taken as far as it could profitably go: "The opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate, is what we mean by the truth..."[111]

Nishida (1870–1945) edit

According to Kitaro Nishida, "knowledge of things in the world begins with the differentiation of unitary consciousness into knower and known and ends with self and things becoming one again. Such unification takes form not only in knowing but in the valuing (of truth) that directs knowing, the willing that directs action, and the feeling or emotive reach that directs sensing."[112]

Fromm (1900–1980) edit

Erich Fromm finds that trying to discuss truth as "absolute truth" is sterile and that emphasis ought to be placed on "optimal truth". He considers truth as stemming from the survival imperative of grasping one's environment physically and intellectually, whereby young children instinctively seek truth so as to orient themselves in "a strange and powerful world". The accuracy of their perceived approximation of the truth will therefore have direct consequences on their ability to deal with their environment. Fromm can be understood to define truth as a functional approximation of reality. His vision of optimal truth is described partly in Man for Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics (1947), from which excerpts are included below.

the dichotomy between 'absolute = perfect' and 'relative = imperfect' has been superseded in all fields of scientific thought, where "it is generally recognized that there is no absolute truth but nevertheless that there are objectively valid laws and principles".
In that respect, "a scientifically or rationally valid statement means that the power of reason is applied to all the available data of observation without any of them being suppressed or falsified for the sake of the desired result". The history of science is "a history of inadequate and incomplete statements, and every new insight makes possible the recognition of the inadequacies of previous propositions and offers a springboard for creating a more adequate formulation."
As a result "the history of thought is the history of an ever-increasing approximation to the truth. Scientific knowledge is not absolute but optimal; it contains the optimum of truth attainable in a given historical period." Fromm furthermore notes that "different cultures have emphasized various aspects of the truth" and that increasing interaction between cultures allows for these aspects to reconcile and integrate, increasing further the approximation to the truth.

Foucault (1926–1984) edit

Truth, says Michel Foucault, is problematic when any attempt is made to see truth as an "objective" quality. He prefers not to use the term truth itself but "Regimes of Truth". In his historical investigations he found truth to be something that was itself a part of, or embedded within, a given power structure. Thus Foucault's view shares much in common with the concepts of Nietzsche. Truth for Foucault is also something that shifts through various episteme throughout history.[113]

Baudrillard (1929–2007) edit

Jean Baudrillard considered truth to be largely simulated, that is pretending to have something, as opposed to dissimulation, pretending to not have something. He took his cue from iconoclasts whom he claims knew that images of God demonstrated that God did not exist.[114] Baudrillard wrote in "Precession of the Simulacra":

The simulacrum is never that which conceals the truth—it is the truth which conceals that there is none. The simulacrum is true.
—Ecclesiastes[115][116]

Some examples of simulacra that Baudrillard cited were: that prisons simulate the "truth" that society is free; scandals (e.g., Watergate) simulate that corruption is corrected; Disney simulates that the U.S. itself is an adult place. Though such examples seem extreme, such extremity is an important part of Baudrillard's theory. For a less extreme example, movies usually end with the bad being punished, humiliated, or otherwise failing, thus affirming for viewers the concept that the good end happily and the bad unhappily, a narrative which implies that the status quo and established power structures are largely legitimate.[114]

Other contemporary positions edit

Truthmaker theory is "the branch of metaphysics that explores the relationships between what is true and what exists".[117] It is different from substantive theories of truth in the sense that it does not aim at giving a definition of what truth is. Instead, it has the goal of determining how truth depends on being.[118]

Theological views edit

Hinduism edit

In Hinduism, truth is defined as "unchangeable", "that which has no distortion", "that which is beyond distinctions of time, space, and person", "that which pervades the universe in all its constancy". The human body, therefore, is not completely true as it changes with time, for example. There are many references, properties and explanations of truth by Hindu sages that explain varied facets of truth, such as the national motto of India: "Satyameva Jayate" (Truth alone triumphs), as well as "Satyam muktaye" (Truth liberates), "Satya' is 'Parahit'artham' va'unmanaso yatha'rthatvam' satyam" (Satya is the benevolent use of words and the mind for the welfare of others or in other words responsibilities is truth too), "When one is firmly established in speaking truth, the fruits of action become subservient to him (patanjali yogasutras, sutra number 2.36), "The face of truth is covered by a golden bowl. Unveil it, O Pusan (Sun), so that I who have truth as my duty (satyadharma) may see it!" (Brhadaranyaka V 15 1–4 and the brief IIsa Upanisad 15–18), Truth is superior to silence (Manusmriti), etc. Combined with other words, satya acts as a modifier, like ultra or highest, or more literally truest, connoting purity and excellence. For example, satyaloka is the "highest heaven" and Satya Yuga is the "golden age" or best of the four cyclical cosmic ages in Hinduism, and so on. The Buddha, the 9th incarnation of Bhagwan Vishnu, quoted as such - Three things cannot be long hidden: the sun, the moon and the truth.

Buddhism edit

In Buddhism, particularly in the Mahayana tradition, the notion of truth is often divided into the two truths doctrine, which consists of relative or conventional truth and ultimate truth. The former refers to truth that is based on common understanding among ordinary people and is accepted as a practical basis for communication of higher truths. Ultimate truth necessarily transcends logic in the sphere of ordinary experience, and recognizes such phenomena as illusory. Mādhyamaka philosophy asserts that any doctrine can be analyzed with both divisions of truth. Affirmation and negation belong to relative and absolute truth respectively. Political law is regarded as relative, while religious law is absolute.

Christianity edit

 
What is Truth? by Nikolai Ge, depicting John 18:38, in which Pilate asks Christ "What is truth?"

Christianity has a soteriological view of truth. According to the Bible in John 14:6, Jesus is quoted as having said "I am the way, the truth and the life: no man cometh unto the Father, but by me".

See also edit

Other theorists edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionary, truth 2009-12-29 at the Wayback Machine, 2005
  2. ^ a b c "Truth". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 20 January 2022. Retrieved 29 June 2020.
  3. ^ Alexis G. Burgess and John P. Burgess (2011). Truth (hardcover) (1st ed.). Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-14401-6. from the original on October 6, 2014. Retrieved October 4, 2014. a concise introduction to current philosophical debates about truth
  4. ^ see Holtzmann's law for the -ww- : -gg- alternation.
  5. ^ Etymology, Online. "Online Etymology". from the original on 2007-07-13. Retrieved 2013-11-27.
  6. ^ A Concise Dictionary of Old Icelandic 2007-09-30 at the Wayback Machine, Geir T. Zoëga (1910), Northvegr.org
  7. ^ OED on true has "Steadfast in adherence to a commander or friend, to a principle or cause, to one's promises, faith, etc.; firm in allegiance; faithful, loyal, constant, trusty; honest, honourable, upright, virtuous, trustworthy; free from deceit, sincere, truthful" besides "Conformity with fact; agreement with reality; accuracy, correctness, verity; Consistent with fact; agreeing with the reality; representing the thing as it is; real, genuine; rightly answering to the description; properly so called; not counterfeit, spurious, or imaginary."
  8. ^ a b c d e f Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Supp., "Truth", auth: Michael Williams, pp. 572–73 (Macmillan, 1996)
  9. ^ Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Includes papers by James, Ramsey, Russell, Tarski, and more recent work.
  10. ^ Hale, Bob; Wright, Crispin, eds. (1999). "A Companion to the Philosophy of Language". pp. 309–30. doi:10.1111/b.9780631213260.1999.00015.x (inactive 31 January 2024). ISBN 978-0-631-21326-0. {{cite book}}: Missing or empty |title= (help)CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024 (link)
  11. ^ "The PhilPapers Surveys – Preliminary Survey results". The PhilPapers Surveys. Philpapers.org. from the original on 2012-03-20. Retrieved 2012-05-27.
  12. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth.: Arthur N. Prior, p. 223 (Macmillan, 1969). Prior uses Bertrand Russell's wording in defining correspondence theory. According to Prior, Russell was substantially responsible for helping to make correspondence theory widely known under this name.
  13. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth.: Arthur N. Prior, pp. 223–24 (Macmillan, 1969).
  14. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth.: Arthur N. Prior, Macmillan, 1969, p. 224.
  15. ^ "Correspondence Theory of Truth", in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2019-10-31 at the Wayback Machine.
  16. ^ Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I. Q.16, A.2 arg. 2.
  17. ^ "Correspondence Theory of Truth", in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2019-10-31 at the Wayback Machine (citing De Veritate Q.1, A.1–3 and Summa Theologiae, I. Q.16).
  18. ^ See, e.g., Bradley, F.H., "On Truth and Copying", in Blackburn, et al. (eds., 1999),Truth, 31–45.
  19. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, pp. 223 ff. Macmillan, 1969. See especially, section on "Moore's Correspondence Theory", 225–26, "Russell's Correspondence Theory", 226–27, "Remsey and Later Wittgenstein", 228–29, "Tarski's Semantic Theory", 230–31.
  20. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Correspondence Theory of Truth", auth: Arthur N. Prior, pp. 223 ff. Macmillan, 1969. See the section on "Tarski's Semantic Theory", 230–31.
  21. ^ Immanuel Kant, for instance, assembled a controversial but quite coherent system in the early 19th century, whose validity and usefulness continues to be debated even today. Similarly, the systems of Leibniz and Spinoza are characteristic systems that are internally coherent but controversial in terms of their utility and validity.
  22. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Coherence Theory of Truth", auth: Alan R. White, pp. 130–31 (Macmillan, 1969)
  23. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Coherence Theory of Truth", auth: Alan R. White, pp. 131–33, see esp., section on "Epistemological assumptions" (Macmillan, 1969)
  24. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Coherence Theory of Truth", auth: Alan R. White, p. 130
  25. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 5, "Pragmatic Theory of Truth", 427 (Macmillan, 1969).
  26. ^ a b Peirce, C.S. (1901), "Truth and Falsity and Error" (in part), pp. 716–20 in James Mark Baldwin, ed., Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, v. 2. Peirce's section is entitled "Logical", beginning on p. 718, column 1, and ending on p. 720 with the initials "(C.S.P.)", see Google Books Eprint. Reprinted, Collected Papers v. 5, pp. 565–73.
  27. ^ a b James, William, The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism', (1909).
  28. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol.2, "Dewey, John", auth Richard J. Bernstein, p. 383 (Macmillan, 1969)
  29. ^ Sahakian, W.S. & Sahakian, M.L., Ideas of the Great Philosophers, New York: Barnes & Noble, 1966, LCCN 66--23155
  30. ^ a b Feynman, The Character of Physical Law, New York: Random House, 1994, 978-0-679-60127-2.
  31. ^ Feynman, The Character of Physical Law, p. 150.
  32. ^ May, Todd (1993). Between Genealogy and Epistemology: Psychology, Politics, and Knowledge in the Thought of Michel Foucault. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. ISBN 978-0271027821. OCLC 26553016.
  33. ^ See, e.g., Habermas, Jürgen, Knowledge and Human Interests (English translation, 1972).
  34. ^ See, e.g., Habermas, Jürgen, Knowledge and Human Interests (English translation, 1972), esp. Part III, pp. 187 ff.
  35. ^ Rescher, Nicholas, Pluralism: Against the Demand for Consensus (1995).
  36. ^ Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth in the Introductory section of the book.
  37. ^ Richard Kirkham, Theories of Truth: A Critical Introduction, MIT Press, 1992.
  38. ^ J. L. Austin, "How to Do Things With Words". Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975
  39. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 6: Performative Theory of Truth, auth: Gertrude Ezorsky, p. 88 (Macmillan, 1969)
  40. ^ Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7, 153–70. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990
  41. ^ Le Morvan, Pierre. (2004) "Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey", The British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12(4), pp. 705–18.
  42. ^ Popkin, R. H. The History of Skepticism from Erasmus to Descartes (rev. ed. 1968); C. L. Stough, Greek Skepticism (1969); M. Burnyeat, ed., The Skeptical Tradition (1983); B. Stroud, The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism (1984). Archived from the original on 2012-07-13. Retrieved 2018-06-04. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  43. ^ "Philosophical views are typically classed as skeptical when they involve advancing some degree of doubt regarding claims that are elsewhere taken for granted." utm.edu 2009-01-13 at the Wayback Machine
  44. ^ Greco, John (2008). The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism. Oxford University Press, US. ISBN 978-0-19-518321-4.
  45. ^ "Definition of SKEPTICISM". Merriam-Webster. from the original on 2019-04-24. Retrieved 2016-02-05.
  46. ^ Truth and Objectivity, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1992.
  47. ^ Truth as One and Many (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
  48. ^ Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
  49. ^ Kretzmann, Norman (1968). "IV, section=2. 'Infinitely Many' and 'Finitely Many'". William of Sherwood's Treatise on Syncategorematic Words. University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 978-0-8166-5805-3.
  50. ^ Smith, Nicholas J.J. (2010). "Article 2.6" (PDF). Many-Valued Logics. Routledge. (PDF) from the original on 2018-04-08. Retrieved 2018-05-25.
  51. ^ Mancosu, Paolo; Zach, Richard; Badesa, Calixto (2004). "7.2 Many-valued logics". 9. The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski 1900-1935. Oxford University Press. pp. 418–20. ISBN 978-0-19-972272-3. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  52. ^ Garrido, Angel (2012). "A Brief History of Fuzzy Logic". Revista EduSoft. from the original on 2018-05-17. Retrieved 2018-05-25., Editorial
  53. ^ Rescher, Nicholas (1968). "Many-Valued Logic". Topics in Philosophical Logic. Humanities Press Synthese Library volume 17. pp. 54–125. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-3546-9_6. ISBN 978-90-481-8331-9.
  54. ^ Penelope Maddy; Realism in Mathematics; Series: Clarendon Paperbacks; Paperback: 216 pages; Publisher: Oxford University Press, US (1992); 978-0-19-824035-8.
  55. ^ Elliott Mendelson; Introduction to Mathematical Logic; Series: Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications; Hardcover: 469 pages; Publisher: Chapman and Hall/CRC; 5 edition (August 11, 2009); 978-1-58488-876-5.
  56. ^ See, e.g., Chaitin, Gregory L., The Limits of Mathematics (1997) esp. 89 ff.
  57. ^ M. Davis. "Hilbert's Tenth Problem is Unsolvable." American Mathematical Monthly 80, pp. 233–69, 1973
  58. ^ Yandell, Benjamin H.. The Honors Class. Hilbert's Problems and Their Solvers (2002).
  59. ^ Chaitin, Gregory L., The Limits of Mathematics (1997) 1–28, 89 ff.
  60. ^ Ravitch, Harold (1998). "On Gödel's Philosophy of Mathematics". from the original on 2018-02-28. Retrieved 2018-05-25.
  61. ^ Solomon, Martin (1998). "On Kurt Gödel's Philosophy of Mathematics". from the original on 2016-03-04. Retrieved 2018-05-25.
  62. ^ Wang, Hao (1997). A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy. The MIT Press. (A discussion of Gödel's views on logical intuition is woven throughout the book; the quote appears on page 75.)
  63. ^ Kripke, Saul. "Outline of a Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy, 72 (1975), 690–716
  64. ^ Keith Simmons, Universality and the Liar: An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1993
  65. ^ Goldblatt, Robert (1983). Topoi, the categorial analysis of logic (revised ed.). Amsterdam: Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier North-Holland. ISBN 0-444-86711-2. OCLC 9622076.
  66. ^ Scharp, Kevin (2013). "6: What is the Use?". Replacing truth (First ed.). Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN 978-0-19-965385-0.
  67. ^ "truth | philosophy and logic". Encyclopedia Britannica. from the original on 5 June 2019. Retrieved 28 July 2017. Truth is important. Believing what is not true is apt to spoil a person's plans and may even cost him his life. Telling what is not true may result in legal and social penalties.
  68. ^ Wellman, Henry M., David Cross, and Julanne Watson. "Meta‐analysis of theory‐of‐mind development: the truth about false belief." Child development 72.3 (2001): 655–84.
  69. ^ Lynch, Michael P. "Alethic functionalism and our folk theory of truth." Synthese 145.1 (2005): 29–43.
  70. ^ Bueno, Otávio, and Mark Colyvan. "Logical non-apriorism and the law of non-contradiction." The law of non-contradiction: New philosophical essays (2004): 156–75.
  71. ^ a b c d David, Marion (2005). "Correspondence Theory of Truth" 2014-02-25 at the Wayback Machine in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  72. ^ Asmis, Elizabeth (2009). "Epicurean empiricism". In Warren, James (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism. Cambridge University Press. p. 84.
  73. ^ O'Keefe, Tim (2010). Epicureanism. University of California Press. pp. 97–98.
  74. ^ Osman Amin (2007), "Influence of Muslim Philosophy on the West", Monthly Renaissance 17 (11).
  75. ^ Jan A. Aertsen (1988), Nature and Creature: Thomas Aquinas's Way of Thought, p. 152. Brill, 978-90-04-08451-3.
  76. ^ Simone van Riet. Liber de philosophia prima, sive Scientia divina (in Latin). p. 413.
  77. ^ Avicenna: The Metaphysics of The Healing. Michael E. Marmura. Brigham Young University Press. 2005. p. 284. ISBN 978-0-934893-77-0.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  78. ^ Disputed Questions on Truth, 1, 2, c, reply to Obj. 1. Trans. Mulligan, McGlynn, Schmidt, Truth, vol. I, pp. 10–12.
  79. ^ "Veritas supra ens fundatur" (Truth is founded on being). Disputed Questions on Truth, 10, 2, reply to Obj. 3.
  80. ^ Rock, Catherine A. (2006). "Forsworn and Fordone: Arcite as Oath-Breaker in the "Knight's Tale"". The Chaucer Review. 40 (4): 416–32. doi:10.1353/cr.2006.0009. JSTOR 25094334. S2CID 159853483.
  81. ^ Pearsall, Derek (2004). "Medieval Literature and Historical Enquiry". Modern Language Review. 99 (4): xxxi–xlii. doi:10.2307/3738608. JSTOR 3738608. S2CID 155446847.
  82. ^ Fowler, Elizabeth (2003). "Rev. of Green, A Crisis of Truth". Speculum. 78 (1): 179–82. doi:10.1017/S0038713400099310. JSTOR 3301477.
  83. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1781/1787), Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), A58/B82.
  84. ^ a b Kant, Immanuel (1801), The Jäsche Logic, in Lectures on Logic. Translated and edited by J. Michael Young (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 557–58.
  85. ^ Alberto Vanzo, "Kant on the Nominal Definition of Truth", Kant-Studien, 101 (2010), pp. 147–66.
  86. ^ "Die Wahrheit ist die Bewegung ihrer an ihr selbst." The Phenomenology of Spirit, Preface, ¶ 48
  87. ^ On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, §§ 29–33
  88. ^ Kierkegaard, Søren. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1992
  89. ^ Watts, Michael. Kierkegaard, Oxford: Oneworld Publications, 2003
  90. ^ Robert Wicks, Friedrich Nietzsche – Early Writings: 1872–1876 2018-09-04 at the Wayback Machine, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  91. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich; Williams, Bernard; Nauckhoff, Josefine (2001). Nietzsche: The Gay Science: With a Prelude in German Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-63645-2 – via Google Books.
  92. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (2006). Nietzsche: 'On the Genealogy of Morality' and Other Writings Student Edition. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-46121-4 – via Google Books.
  93. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1997). Beyond Good and Evil. Dover Publications. p. 46. ISBN 978-0486298689.
  94. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1976). The Portable Nietzsche. Penguin Books. p. 46. ISBN 978-0140150629.
  95. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1887). On the Genealogy of Morality. Oxford University Press. p. 73. ISBN 978-0199537082.
  96. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1883). Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Penguin UK. p. 46. ISBN 9780140441185.
  97. ^ Nietzsche, Friedrich (1883). Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Penguin UK. p. 121. ISBN 9780140441185.
  98. ^ Heidegger, Martin. "On the Essence of Truth" (PDF). aphelis.net. Retrieved 3 October 2023.
  99. ^ . Archived from the original on 2015-06-26. Retrieved 2010-08-13.
  100. ^ Heidegger, Martin (1962). Being and Time (1st ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackswell. pp. 256–274.
  101. ^ Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956). Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontolgoy (1st ed.). New York: Philosophical Library.
  102. ^ Sartre, Jean-Paul (2004). The imaginary : a phenomenological psychology of the imagination. Arlette Elkaïm-Sartre, Jonathan Webber. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-203-64410-7. OCLC 56549324.
  103. ^ Wilder, Kathleen (1995). "Truth and existence: The idealism in Sartre's theory of truth". International Journal of Philosophical Studies. 3 (1): 91–109. doi:10.1080/09672559508570805.
  104. ^ Sartre, Jean-Paul (1963). Search for a Method (1st ed.). New York: Knopf.
  105. ^ Skirke, Christian (2014-04-28), "Jean-Paul Sartre", Philosophy, Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0192, ISBN 978-0-19-539657-7, retrieved 2023-02-25
  106. ^ Sartre, Jean-Paul (2004). Critique of Dialectical Reason. London: Verso. pp. 15–41.
  107. ^ Camus, Albert (2020). The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays (1st ed.). London: Penguin Group. pp. 14–16.
  108. ^ Camus, Albert (2013). The Rebel (3rd ed.). London: Penguin Group. p. 180.
  109. ^ Camus, Albert (2013). The Rebel (3rd ed.). London: Penguin Group. p. 90.
  110. ^ Alfred North Whitehead, Dialogues, 1954: Prologue.
  111. ^ "How to Make Our Ideas Clear". from the original on 2018-10-03. Retrieved 2015-08-31.
  112. ^ John Maraldo, Nishida Kitarô – Self-Awareness 2010-12-04 at the Wayback Machine, in: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  113. ^ Foucault, M. "The Order of Things", London: Vintage Books, 1970 (1966)
  114. ^ a b Jean Baudrillard. Simulacra and Simulation. Michigan: Michigan University Press, 1994.
  115. ^ Baudrillard, Jean. "Simulacra and Simulations", in Selected Writings 2004-02-09 at the Wayback Machine, ed. Mark Poster, Stanford University Press, 1988; 166 ff
  116. ^ Baudrillard's attribution of this quote to Ecclesiastes is deliberately fictional. "Baudrillard attributes this quote to Ecclesiastes. However, the quote is a fabrication (see Jean Baudrillard. Cool Memories III, 1991–95. London: Verso, 1997). Editor's note: In Fragments: Conversations With François L'Yvonnet. New York: Routledge, 2004:11, Baudrillard acknowledges this 'Borges-like' fabrication." Cited in footnote #4 in Smith, Richard G., "Lights, Camera, Action: Baudrillard and the Performance of Representations" 2018-04-25 at the Wayback Machine, International Journal of Baudrillard Studies, Volume 2, Number 1 (January 2005)
  117. ^ Asay, Jamin. "Truthmaker Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2020-11-24. Retrieved 2020-11-28.
  118. ^ Beebee, Helen; Dodd, Julian (2005). Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate. Clarendon Press. pp. 13–14. from the original on 2020-12-06. Retrieved 2020-11-28.

References edit

  • Aristotle, "The Categories", Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 1–109 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, 1938.
  • Aristotle, "On Interpretation", Harold P. Cooke (trans.), pp. 111–79 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, 1938.
  • Aristotle, "Prior Analytics", Hugh Tredennick (trans.), pp. 181–531 in Aristotle, Volume 1, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, 1938.
  • Aristotle, "On the Soul" (De Anima), W. S. Hett (trans.), pp. 1–203 in Aristotle, Volume 8, Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, 1936.
  • Audi, Robert (ed., 1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995. 2nd edition, 1999. Cited as CDP.
  • Baldwin, James Mark (ed., 1901–1905), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 volumes in 4, Macmillan, New York.
  • Baylis, Charles A. (1962), "Truth", pp. 321–22 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
  • Benjamin, A. Cornelius (1962), "Coherence Theory of Truth", p. 58 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
  • Blackburn, Simon, and Simmons, Keith (eds., 1999), Truth, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Includes papers by James, Ramsey, Russell, Tarski, and more recent work.
  • Chandrasekhar, Subrahmanyan (1987), Truth and Beauty. Aesthetics and Motivations in Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.
  • Chang, C.C., and Keisler, H.J., Model Theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam, Netherlands, 1973.
  • Chomsky, Noam (1995), The Minimalist Program, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Church, Alonzo (1962a), "Name Relation, or Meaning Relation", p. 204 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
  • Church, Alonzo (1962b), "Truth, Semantical", p. 322 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
  • Clifford, W.K. (1877), "The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays". (Prometheus Books, 1999), infidels.org 2009-12-03 at the Wayback Machine
  • Dewey, John (1900–1901), Lectures on Ethics 1900–1901, Donald F. Koch (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL.
  • Dewey, John (1932), Theory of the Moral Life, Part 2 of John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics, Henry Holt and Company, New York, 1908. 2nd edition, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1932. Reprinted, Arnold Isenberg (ed.), Victor Kestenbaum (pref.), Irvingtion Publishers, New York, 1980.
  • Dewey, John (1938), Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938), Holt and Company, New York. Reprinted, John Dewey, The Later Works, 1925–1953, Volume 12: 1938, Jo Ann Boydston (ed.), Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL, 1986.
  • Field, Hartry (2001), Truth and the Absence of Fact, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
  • Foucault, Michel (1997), Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, Volume 1, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, Paul Rabinow (ed.), Robert Hurley et al. (trans.), The New Press, New York.
  • Garfield, Jay L., and Kiteley, Murray (1991), Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, Paragon House, New York.
  • Gupta, Anil (2001), "Truth", in Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford.
  • Gupta, Anil and Belnap, Nuel. (1993). The Revision Theory of Truth. MIT Press.
  • Haack, Susan (1993), Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford.
  • Habermas, Jürgen (1976), "What Is Universal Pragmatics?", 1st published, "Was heißt Universalpragmatik?", Sprachpragmatik und Philosophie, Karl-Otto Apel (ed.), Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. Reprinted, pp. 1–68 in Jürgen Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society, Thomas McCarthy (trans.), Beacon Press, Boston, 1979.
  • Habermas, Jürgen (1990), Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen (trans.), Thomas McCarthy (intro.), MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Habermas, Jürgen (2003), Truth and Justification, Barbara Fultner (trans.), MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Hegel, Georg, (1977), The Phenomenology of Spirit, Oxford University Press, Oxford, ISBN 978-0-19-824597-1.
  • Horwich, Paul, (1988), Truth, 2nd edition, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
  • James, William (1904), A World of Pure Experience.
  • James, William (1907), Pragmatism, A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular Lectures on Philosophy, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York.
  • James, William (1909), The Meaning of Truth, A Sequel to 'Pragmatism, Longmans, Green, and Company, New York.
  • James, William (1912), Essays in Radical Empiricism. Cf. Chapt. 3, "The Thing and its Relations", pp. 92–122.
  • James, William (2014), William James on Habit, Will, Truth, and the Meaning of Life. James Sloan Allen (ed.), Frederic C. Beil, Publisher, Savannah, GA.
  • Kant, Immanuel (1800), Introduction to Logic. Reprinted, Thomas Kingsmill Abbott (trans.), Dennis Sweet (intro.), Barnes and Noble, New York, 2005.
  • Kirkham, Richard L. (1992), Theories of Truth: A Critical Introduction, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Kneale, W., and Kneale, M. (1962), The Development of Logic, Oxford University Press, London, 1962. Reprinted with corrections, 1975.
  • Kreitler, Hans, and Kreitler, Shulamith (1972), Psychology of the Arts, Duke University Press, Durham, NC.
  • Le Morvan, Pierre (2004), "Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey", British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 12 (4) 2004, 705–18, PDF 2017-08-29 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Peirce, C.S., Bibliography.
  • Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as CP vol.para.
  • Peirce, C.S. (1877), "The Fixation of Belief", Popular Science Monthly 12 (1877), 1–15. Reprinted (CP 5.358–387), (CE 3, 242–257), (EP 1, 109–123). Eprint 2020-12-11 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Peirce, C.S. (1901), "Truth and Falsity and Error" (in part), pp. 718–20 in J.M. Baldwin (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, vol. 2. Reprinted, CP 5.565–573.
  • Polanyi, Michael (1966), The Tacit Dimension, Doubleday and Company, Garden City, NY.
  • Quine, W.V. (1956), "Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes", Journal of Philosophy 53 (1956). Reprinted, pp. 185–96 in Quine (1976), Ways of Paradox.
  • Quine, W.V. (1976), The Ways of Paradox, and Other Essays, 1st edition, 1966. Revised and enlarged edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1976.
  • Quine, W.V. (1980 a), From a Logical Point of View, Logico-Philosophical Essays, 2nd edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Quine, W.V. (1980 b), "Reference and Modality", pp. 139–59 in Quine (1980 a), From a Logical Point of View.
  • Rajchman, John, and West, Cornel (ed., 1985), Post-Analytic Philosophy, Columbia University Press, New York.
  • Ramsey, F.P. (1927), "Facts and Propositions", Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7, 153–70. Reprinted, pp. 34–51 in F.P. Ramsey, Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990.
  • Ramsey, F.P. (1990), Philosophical Papers, David Hugh Mellor (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
  • Rawls, John (2000), Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, Barbara Herman (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Rorty, R. (1979), Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
  • Russell, Bertrand (1912), The Problems of Philosophy, 1st published 1912. Reprinted, Galaxy Book, Oxford University Press, New York, 1959. Reprinted, Prometheus Books, Buffalo, NY, 1988.
  • Russell, Bertrand (1918), "The Philosophy of Logical Atomism", The Monist, 1918. Reprinted, pp. 177–281 in Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950, Robert Charles Marsh (ed.), Unwin Hyman, London, 1956. Reprinted, pp. 35–155 in The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, David Pears (ed.), Open Court, La Salle, IL, 1985.
  • Russell, Bertrand (1956), Logic and Knowledge: Essays 1901–1950, Robert Charles Marsh (ed.), Unwin Hyman, London, 1956. Reprinted, Routledge, London, 1992.
  • Russell, Bertrand (1985), The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, David Pears (ed.), Open Court, La Salle, IL.
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur, (1974), On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, Open Court, La Salle, IL, ISBN 978-0-87548-187-6.
  • Smart, Ninian (1969), The Religious Experience of Mankind, Charles Scribner's Sons, New York.
  • Tarski, A., Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J.H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1956. 2nd edition, John Corcoran (ed.), Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN, 1983.
  • Wallace, Anthony F.C. (1966), Religion: An Anthropological View, Random House, New York.

Reference works edit

  • Audi, Robert (ed., 1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995. 2nd edition, 1999. Cited as CDP.
  • Blackburn, Simon (1996), The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1994. Paperback edition with new Chronology, 1996. Cited as ODP.
  • Runes, Dagobert D. (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy, Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ, 1962.
  • Webster's New International Dictionary of the English Language, Second Edition, Unabridged (1950), W.A. Neilson, T.A. Knott, P.W. Carhart (eds.), G. & C. Merriam Company, Springfield, MA. Cited as MWU.
  • Webster's Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary (1983), Frederick C. Mish (ed.), Merriam–Webster Inc., Springfield, MA. Cited as MWC.

External links edit

  • by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners.
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • "Truth"
    • "Pluralist Theories of Truth"
    • "Truthmaker Theory"
    • "Prosentential Theory of Truth"
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • Truth
    • Coherence theory of truth
    • Correspondence theory of truth
    • Deflationary theory of truth
    • Identity theory of truth
    • Revision theory of truth
    • Tarski's definition of truth
    • Axiomatic theories of truth
  • History of Truth: The Latin "Veritas"

truth, truth, redirects, here, other, uses, truth, disambiguation, other, uses, disambiguation, verity, property, being, accord, with, fact, reality, everyday, language, truth, typically, ascribed, things, that, represent, reality, otherwise, correspond, such,. The truth redirects here For other uses of The truth see The Truth disambiguation For other uses of Truth see Truth disambiguation Truth or verity is the property of being in accord with fact or reality 1 In everyday language truth is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise correspond to it such as beliefs propositions and declarative sentences 2 Truth is usually held to be the opposite of false statement The concept of truth is discussed and debated in various contexts including philosophy art theology law and science Most human activities depend upon the concept where its nature as a concept is assumed rather than being a subject of discussion including journalism and everyday life Some philosophers view the concept of truth as basic and unable to be explained in any terms that are more easily understood than the concept of truth itself 2 Most commonly truth is viewed as the correspondence of language or thought to a mind independent world This is called the correspondence theory of truth Various theories and views of truth continue to be debated among scholars philosophers and theologians 2 3 There are many different questions about the nature of truth which are still the subject of contemporary debates These include the question of defining truth whether it is even possible to give an informative definition of truth identifying things as truth bearers capable of being true or false if truth and falsehood are bivalent or if there are other truth values identifying the criteria of truth that allow us to identify it and to distinguish it from falsehood the role that truth plays in constituting knowledge and if truth is always absolute or if it can be relative to one s perspective Contents 1 Definition and etymology 2 Major theories 2 1 Substantive 2 1 1 Correspondence 2 1 2 Coherence 2 1 3 Pragmatic 2 1 4 Constructivist 2 1 5 Consensus 2 2 Minimalist 2 2 1 Deflationary 2 2 2 Performative 2 2 3 Redundancy and related 2 2 4 Philosophical skepticism 2 3 Pluralist 3 Formal theories 3 1 Logic 3 2 Mathematics 3 3 Tarski s semantics 3 4 Kripke s semantics 4 Folk beliefs 5 Notable views 5 1 Ancient Greek philosophy 5 2 Medieval philosophy 5 2 1 Avicenna 980 1037 5 2 2 Aquinas 1225 1274 5 2 3 Changing concepts of truth in the Middle Ages 5 3 Modern philosophy 5 3 1 Kant 1724 1804 5 3 2 Hegel 1770 1831 5 3 3 Schopenhauer 1788 1860 5 3 4 Kierkegaard 1813 1855 5 3 5 Nietzsche 1844 1900 5 3 6 Heidegger 1889 1976 5 3 7 Sartre 1905 1980 5 3 8 Camus 1913 1960 5 3 9 Whitehead 1861 1947 5 3 10 Peirce 1839 1914 5 3 11 Nishida 1870 1945 5 3 12 Fromm 1900 1980 5 3 13 Foucault 1926 1984 5 3 14 Baudrillard 1929 2007 5 3 15 Other contemporary positions 5 4 Theological views 5 4 1 Hinduism 5 4 2 Buddhism 5 4 3 Christianity 6 See also 6 1 Other theorists 7 Notes 8 References 8 1 Reference works 9 External linksDefinition and etymology editFurther information Veritas Aletheia and Tryggvi The English word truth is derived from Old English triewth treowth trywth Middle English trewthe cognate to Old High German triuwida Old Norse tryggd Like troth it is a th nominalisation of the adjective true Old English treowe The English word true is from Old English West Saxon ge triewe treowe cognate to Old Saxon gi truui Old High German ga triuwu Modern German treu faithful Old Norse tryggr Gothic triggws 4 all from a Proto Germanic trewwj having good faith perhaps ultimately from PIE dru tree on the notion of steadfast as an oak e g Sanskrit da ru piece of wood 5 Old Norse tru faith word of honour religious faith belief 6 archaic English troth loyalty honesty good faith compare Asatru Thus truth involves both the quality of faithfulness fidelity loyalty sincerity veracity 7 and that of agreement with fact or reality in Anglo Saxon expressed by sōth Modern English sooth All Germanic languages besides English have introduced a terminological distinction between truth fidelity and truth factuality To express factuality North Germanic opted for nouns derived from sanna to assert affirm while continental West Germanic German and Dutch opted for continuations of wara faith trust pact cognate to Slavic vera religious faith but influenced by Latin verus Romance languages use terms following the Latin veritas while the Greek aletheia Russian pravda South Slavic istina and Sanskrit sat related to English sooth and North Germanic sanna have separate etymological origins In some modern contexts the word truth is used to refer to fidelity to an original or standard It can also be used in the context of being true to oneself in the sense of acting with authenticity 1 Major theories edit nbsp Walter Seymour Allward s Veritas Truth outside Supreme Court of Canada Ottawa Ontario Canada The question of what is a proper basis for deciding how words symbols ideas and beliefs may properly be considered true whether by a single person or an entire society is dealt with by the five most prevalent substantive theories of truth listed below Each presents perspectives that are widely shared by published scholars 8 9 10 Theories other than the most prevalent substantive theories are also discussed According to a survey of professional philosophers and others on their philosophical views which was carried out in November 2009 taken by 3226 respondents including 1803 philosophy faculty members and or PhDs and 829 philosophy graduate students 45 of respondents accept or lean towards correspondence theories 21 accept or lean towards deflationary theories and 14 epistemic theories 11 Substantive edit Correspondence edit Main article Correspondence theory of truth Correspondence theories emphasize that true beliefs and true statements correspond to the actual state of affairs 12 This type of theory stresses a relationship between thoughts or statements on one hand and things or objects on the other It is a traditional model tracing its origins to ancient Greek philosophers such as Socrates Plato and Aristotle 13 This class of theories holds that the truth or the falsity of a representation is determined in principle entirely by how it relates to things according to whether it accurately describes those things A classic example of correspondence theory is the statement by the thirteenth century philosopher and theologian Thomas Aquinas Veritas est adaequatio rei et intellectus Truth is the adequation of things and intellect which Aquinas attributed to the ninth century Neoplatonist Isaac Israeli 14 15 16 Aquinas also restated the theory as A judgment is said to be true when it conforms to the external reality 17 Correspondence theory centres heavily around the assumption that truth is a matter of accurately copying what is known as objective reality and then representing it in thoughts words and other symbols 18 Many modern theorists have stated that this ideal cannot be achieved without analysing additional factors 8 19 For example language plays a role in that all languages have words to represent concepts that are virtually undefined in other languages The German word Zeitgeist is one such example one who speaks or understands the language may know what it means but any translation of the word apparently fails to accurately capture its full meaning this is a problem with many abstract words especially those derived in agglutinative languages Thus some words add an additional parameter to the construction of an accurate truth predicate Among the philosophers who grappled with this problem is Alfred Tarski whose semantic theory is summarized further on 20 Proponents of several of the theories below have gone further to assert that there are yet other issues necessary to the analysis such as interpersonal power struggles community interactions personal biases and other factors involved in deciding what is seen as truth Coherence edit Main article Coherence theory of truth For coherence theories in general truth requires a proper fit of elements within a whole system Very often however coherence is taken to imply something more than simple logical consistency often there is a demand that the propositions in a coherent system lend mutual inferential support to each other So for example the completeness and comprehensiveness of the underlying set of concepts is a critical factor in judging the validity and usefulness of a coherent system 21 A pervasive tenet of coherence theories is the idea that truth is primarily a property of whole systems of propositions and can be ascribed to individual propositions only according to their coherence with the whole Among the assortment of perspectives commonly regarded as coherence theory theorists differ on the question of whether coherence entails many possible true systems of thought or only a single absolute system Some variants of coherence theory are claimed to describe the essential and intrinsic properties of formal systems in logic and mathematics 22 However formal reasoners are content to contemplate axiomatically independent and sometimes mutually contradictory systems side by side for example the various alternative geometries On the whole coherence theories have been rejected for lacking justification in their application to other areas of truth especially with respect to assertions about the natural world empirical data in general assertions about practical matters of psychology and society especially when used without support from the other major theories of truth 23 Coherence theories distinguish the thought of rationalist philosophers particularly of Baruch Spinoza Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel along with the British philosopher F H Bradley 24 They have found a resurgence also among several proponents of logical positivism notably Otto Neurath and Carl Hempel Pragmatic edit Main article Pragmatic theory of truth The three most influential forms of the pragmatic theory of truth were introduced around the turn of the 20th century by Charles Sanders Peirce William James and John Dewey Although there are wide differences in viewpoint among these and other proponents of pragmatic theory they hold in common that truth is verified and confirmed by the results of putting one s concepts into practice 25 Peirce defines truth as follows Truth is that concordance of an abstract statement with the ideal limit towards which endless investigation would tend to bring scientific belief which concordance the abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its inaccuracy and one sidedness and this confession is an essential ingredient of truth 26 This statement stresses Peirce s view that ideas of approximation incompleteness and partiality what he describes elsewhere as fallibilism and reference to the future are essential to a proper conception of truth Although Peirce uses words like concordance and correspondence to describe one aspect of the pragmatic sign relation he is also quite explicit in saying that definitions of truth based on mere correspondence are no more than nominal definitions which he accords a lower status than real definitions William James s version of pragmatic theory while complex is often summarized by his statement that the true is only the expedient in our way of thinking just as the right is only the expedient in our way of behaving 27 By this James meant that truth is a quality the value of which is confirmed by its effectiveness when applying concepts to practice thus pragmatic John Dewey less broadly than James but more broadly than Peirce held that inquiry whether scientific technical sociological philosophical or cultural is self corrective over time if openly submitted for testing by a community of inquirers in order to clarify justify refine and or refute proposed truths 28 Though not widely known a new variation of the pragmatic theory was defined and wielded successfully from the 20th century forward Defined and named by William Ernest Hocking this variation is known as negative pragmatism Essentially what works may or may not be true but what fails cannot be true because the truth always works 29 Philosopher of science Richard Feynman also subscribed to it We never are definitely right we can only be sure we are wrong 30 This approach incorporates many of the ideas from Peirce James and Dewey For Peirce the idea of endless investigation would tend to bring about scientific belief fits negative pragmatism in that a negative pragmatist would never stop testing As Feynman noted an idea or theory could never be proved right because tomorrow s experiment might succeed in proving wrong what you thought was right 30 Similarly James and Dewey s ideas also ascribe truth to repeated testing which is self corrective over time Pragmatism and negative pragmatism are also closely aligned with the coherence theory of truth in that any testing should not be isolated but rather incorporate knowledge from all human endeavors and experience The universe is a whole and integrated system and testing should acknowledge and account for its diversity As Feynman said if it disagrees with experiment it is wrong 31 Constructivist edit Main article Constructivist epistemology Social constructivism holds that truth is constructed by social processes is historically and culturally specific and that it is in part shaped through the power struggles within a community Constructivism views all of our knowledge as constructed because it does not reflect any external transcendent realities as a pure correspondence theory might hold Rather perceptions of truth are viewed as contingent on convention human perception and social experience It is believed by constructivists that representations of physical and biological reality including race sexuality and gender are socially constructed Giambattista Vico was among the first to claim that history and culture were man made Vico s epistemological orientation gathers the most diverse rays and unfolds in one axiom verum ipsum factum truth itself is constructed Hegel and Marx were among the other early proponents of the premise that truth is or can be socially constructed Marx like many critical theorists who followed did not reject the existence of objective truth but rather distinguished between true knowledge and knowledge that has been distorted through power or ideology For Marx scientific and true knowledge is in accordance with the dialectical understanding of history and ideological knowledge is an epiphenomenal expression of the relation of material forces in a given economic arrangement 32 page needed Consensus edit Main article Consensus theory of truth Consensus theory holds that truth is whatever is agreed upon or in some versions might come to be agreed upon by some specified group Such a group might include all human beings or a subset thereof consisting of more than one person Among the current advocates of consensus theory as a useful accounting of the concept of truth is the philosopher Jurgen Habermas 33 Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed upon in an ideal speech situation 34 Among the current strong critics of consensus theory is the philosopher Nicholas Rescher 35 Minimalist edit Deflationary edit Main article Deflationary theory of truth Modern developments in the field of philosophy have resulted in the rise of a new thesis that the term truth does not denote a real property of sentences or propositions This thesis is in part a response to the common use of truth predicates e g that some particular thing is true which was particularly prevalent in philosophical discourse on truth in the first half of the 20th century From this point of view to assert that 2 2 4 is true is logically equivalent to asserting that 2 2 4 and the phrase is true is completely dispensable in this and every other context In common parlance truth predicates are not commonly heard and it would be interpreted as an unusual occurrence were someone to utilise a truth predicate in an everyday conversation when asserting that something is true Newer perspectives that take this discrepancy into account and work with sentence structures that are actually employed in common discourse can be broadly described as deflationary theories of truth since they attempt to deflate the presumed importance of the words true or truth as disquotational theories to draw attention to the disappearance of the quotation marks in cases like the above example or as minimalist theories of truth 8 36 Whichever term is used deflationary theories can be said to hold in common that the predicate true is an expressive convenience not the name of a property requiring deep analysis 8 Once we have identified the truth predicate s formal features and utility deflationists argue we have said all there is to be said about truth Among the theoretical concerns of these views is to explain away those special cases where it does appear that the concept of truth has peculiar and interesting properties See e g Semantic paradoxes and below In addition to highlighting such formal aspects of the predicate is true some deflationists point out that the concept enables us to express things that might otherwise require infinitely long sentences For example one cannot express confidence in Michael s accuracy by asserting the endless sentence Michael says snow is white and snow is white or he says roses are red and roses are red or he says etc This assertion can also be succinctly expressed by saying What Michael says is true 37 Performative edit Attributed to philosopher P F Strawson is the performative theory of truth which holds that to say Snow is white is true is to perform the speech act of signaling one s agreement with the claim that snow is white much like nodding one s head in agreement The idea that some statements are more actions than communicative statements is not as odd as it may seem For example when a wedding couple says I do at the appropriate time in a wedding they are performing the act of taking the other to be their lawful wedded spouse They are not describing themselves as taking the other but actually doing so perhaps the most thorough analysis of such illocutionary acts is J L Austin most notably in How to Do Things With Words 38 Strawson holds that a similar analysis is applicable to all speech acts not just illocutionary ones To say a statement is true is not to make a statement about a statement but rather to perform the act of agreeing with accepting or endorsing a statement When one says It s true that it s raining one asserts no more than It s raining The function of the statement It s true that is to agree with accept or endorse the statement that it s raining 39 Redundancy and related edit Main article Redundancy theory of truth According to the redundancy theory of truth asserting that a statement is true is completely equivalent to asserting the statement itself For example making the assertion that Snow is white is true is equivalent to asserting Snow is white Redundancy theorists infer from this premise that truth is a redundant concept that is it is merely a word that is traditionally used in conversation or writing generally for emphasis but not a word that actually equates to anything in reality This theory is commonly attributed to Frank P Ramsey who held that the use of words like fact and truth was nothing but a roundabout way of asserting a proposition and that treating these words as separate problems in isolation from judgment was merely a linguistic muddle 8 40 41 A variant of redundancy theory is the disquotational theory which uses a modified form of the logician Alfred Tarski s schema To say that P is true is to say that P A version of this theory was defended by C J F Williams in his book What is Truth Yet another version of deflationism is the prosentential theory of truth first developed by Dorothy Grover Joseph Camp and Nuel Belnap as an elaboration of Ramsey s claims They argue that sentences like That s true when said in response to It s raining are prosentences expressions that merely repeat the content of other expressions In the same way that it means the same as my dog in the sentence My dog was hungry so I fed it That s true is supposed to mean the same as It s raining if one says the latter and another then says the former These variations do not necessarily follow Ramsey in asserting that truth is not a property but rather can be understood to say that for instance the assertion P may well involve a substantial truth and the theorists in this case are minimizing only the redundancy or prosentence involved in the statement such as that s true 8 The scope of deflationary principles is limited to representations that resemble sentences They do not encompass a broader range of entities that are typically considered true or otherwise Philosophical skepticism edit See also Philosophical skepticism and Certainty Philosophical skepticism is generally any questioning attitude or doubt towards one or more items of knowledge or belief which ascribe truth to their assertions and propositions 42 43 The primary target of philosophical skepticism is epistemology but it can be applied to any domain such as the supernatural morality moral skepticism and religion skepticism about the existence of God 44 Philosophical skepticism comes in various forms Radical forms of skepticism deny that knowledge or rational belief is possible and urge us to suspend judgment regarding ascription of truth on many or all controversial matters More moderate forms of skepticism claim only that nothing can be known with certainty or that we can know little or nothing about the big questions in life such as whether God exists or whether there is an afterlife Religious skepticism is doubt concerning basic religious principles such as immortality providence and revelation 45 Scientific skepticism concerns testing beliefs for reliability by subjecting them to systematic investigation using the scientific method to discover empirical evidence for them Pluralist edit Main article Pluralist theories of truth Several of the major theories of truth hold that there is a particular property the having of which makes a belief or proposition true Pluralist theories of truth assert that there may be more than one property that makes propositions true ethical propositions might be true by virtue of coherence Propositions about the physical world might be true by corresponding to the objects and properties they are about Some of the pragmatic theories such as those by Charles Peirce and William James included aspects of correspondence coherence and constructivist theories 26 27 Crispin Wright argued in his 1992 book Truth and Objectivity that any predicate which satisfied certain platitudes about truth qualified as a truth predicate In some discourses Wright argued the role of the truth predicate might be played by the notion of superassertibility 46 Michael Lynch in a 2009 book Truth as One and Many argued that we should see truth as a functional property capable of being multiply manifested in distinct properties like correspondence or coherence 47 Formal theories editLogic edit Main articles Logical truth Criteria of truth and Truth value Logic is concerned with the patterns in reason that can help tell if a proposition is true or not Logicians use formal languages to express the truths they are concerned with and as such there is only truth under some interpretation or truth within some logical system A logical truth also called an analytic truth or a necessary truth is a statement that is true in all possible worlds 48 or under all possible interpretations as contrasted to a fact also called a synthetic claim or a contingency which is only true in this world as it has historically unfolded A proposition such as If p and q then p is considered to be a logical truth because of the meaning of the symbols and words in it and not because of any fact of any particular world They are such that they could not be untrue Degrees of truth in logic may be represented using two or more discrete values as with bivalent logic or binary logic three valued logic and other forms of finite valued logic 49 50 Truth in logic can be represented using numbers comprising a continuous range typically between 0 and 1 as with fuzzy logic and other forms of infinite valued logic 51 52 In general the concept of representing truth using more than two values is known as many valued logic 53 Mathematics edit Main articles Model theory and Proof theory There are two main approaches to truth in mathematics They are the model theory of truth and the proof theory of truth 54 Historically with the nineteenth century development of Boolean algebra mathematical models of logic began to treat truth also represented as T or 1 as an arbitrary constant Falsity is also an arbitrary constant which can be represented as F or 0 In propositional logic these symbols can be manipulated according to a set of axioms and rules of inference often given in the form of truth tables In addition from at least the time of Hilbert s program at the turn of the twentieth century to the proof of Godel s incompleteness theorems and the development of the Church Turing thesis in the early part of that century true statements in mathematics were generally assumed to be those statements that are provable in a formal axiomatic system 55 The works of Kurt Godel Alan Turing and others shook this assumption with the development of statements that are true but cannot be proven within the system 56 Two examples of the latter can be found in Hilbert s problems Work on Hilbert s 10th problem led in the late twentieth century to the construction of specific Diophantine equations for which it is undecidable whether they have a solution 57 or even if they do whether they have a finite or infinite number of solutions More fundamentally Hilbert s first problem was on the continuum hypothesis 58 Godel and Paul Cohen showed that this hypothesis cannot be proved or disproved using the standard axioms of set theory 59 In the view of some then it is equally reasonable to take either the continuum hypothesis or its negation as a new axiom Godel thought that the ability to perceive the truth of a mathematical or logical proposition is a matter of intuition an ability he admitted could be ultimately beyond the scope of a formal theory of logic or mathematics 60 61 and perhaps best considered in the realm of human comprehension and communication But he commented The more I think about language the more it amazes me that people ever understand each other at all 62 Tarski s semantics edit Main articles Semantic theory of truth and Tarski s theory of truth The semantic theory of truth has as its general case for a given language P is true if and only if P where P refers to the sentence the sentence s name and P is just the sentence itself Tarski s theory of truth named after Alfred Tarski was developed for formal languages such as formal logic Here he restricted it in this way no language could contain its own truth predicate that is the expression is true could only apply to sentences in some other language The latter he called an object language the language being talked about It may in turn have a truth predicate that can be applied to sentences in still another language The reason for his restriction was that languages that contain their own truth predicate will contain paradoxical sentences such as This sentence is not true As a result Tarski held that the semantic theory could not be applied to any natural language such as English because they contain their own truth predicates Donald Davidson used it as the foundation of his truth conditional semantics and linked it to radical interpretation in a form of coherentism Bertrand Russell is credited with noticing the existence of such paradoxes even in the best symbolic formations of mathematics in his day in particular the paradox that came to be named after him Russell s paradox Russell and Whitehead attempted to solve these problems in Principia Mathematica by putting statements into a hierarchy of types wherein a statement cannot refer to itself but only to statements lower in the hierarchy This in turn led to new orders of difficulty regarding the precise natures of types and the structures of conceptually possible type systems that have yet to be resolved to this day Kripke s semantics edit Main article Kripke s theory of truth Kripke s theory of truth named after Saul Kripke contends that a natural language can in fact contain its own truth predicate without giving rise to contradiction He showed how to construct one as follows Beginning with a subset of sentences of a natural language that contains no occurrences of the expression is true or is false So The barn is big is included in the subset but not The barn is big is true nor problematic sentences such as This sentence is false Defining truth just for the sentences in that subset Extending the definition of truth to include sentences that predicate truth or falsity of one of the original subset of sentences So The barn is big is true is now included but not either This sentence is false nor The barn is big is true is true Defining truth for all sentences that predicate truth or falsity of a member of the second set Imagine this process repeated infinitely so that truth is defined for The barn is big then for The barn is big is true then for The barn is big is true is true and so on Truth never gets defined for sentences like This sentence is false since it was not in the original subset and does not predicate truth of any sentence in the original or any subsequent set In Kripke s terms these are ungrounded Since these sentences are never assigned either truth or falsehood even if the process is carried out infinitely Kripke s theory implies that some sentences are neither true nor false This contradicts the principle of bivalence every sentence must be either true or false Since this principle is a key premise in deriving the liar paradox the paradox is dissolved 63 However it has been shown by Godel that self reference cannot be avoided naively clarification needed citation needed since propositions about seemingly unrelated objects can have an informal self referential meaning in Godel s work these objects are integer numbers and they have an informal meaning regarding propositions clarification needed In fact this idea manifested by the diagonal lemma is the basis for Tarski s theorem that truth cannot be consistently defined clarification needed It has thus been claimed 64 that Kripke s system indeed leads to contradiction dubious discuss while its truth predicate is only partial it does give truth value true false to propositions such as the one built in Tarski s proof dubious discuss and is therefore inconsistent While there is still a debate on whether Tarski s proof can be implemented to every similar partial truth system clarification needed none have been shown to be consistent by acceptable methods used in mathematical logic citation needed Kripke s semantics are related to the use of topoi and other concepts from category theory in the study of mathematical logic 65 They provide a choice of formal semantics for intuitionistic logic Folk beliefs editThe truth predicate P is true has great practical value in human language allowing efficient endorsement or impeaching of claims made by others to emphasize the truth or falsity of a statement or to enable various indirect Gricean conversational implications 66 Individuals or societies will sometime punish false statements to deter falsehoods 67 the oldest surviving law text the Code of Ur Nammu lists penalties for false accusations of sorcery or adultery as well as for committing perjury in court Even four year old children can pass simple false belief tests and successfully assess that another individual s belief diverges from reality in a specific way 68 by adulthood there are strong implicit intuitions about truth that form a folk theory of truth These intuitions include 69 Capture T in If P then P is true Release T out If P is true then P Noncontradiction A statement can not be both true and false Normativity It is usually good to believe what is true False beliefs The notion that believing a statement does not necessarily make it true Like many folk theories the folk theory of truth is useful in everyday life but upon deep analysis turns out to be technically self contradictory in particular any formal system that fully obeys capture and release semantics for truth also known as the T schema and that also respects classical logic is provably inconsistent and succumbs to the liar paradox or to a similar contradiction 70 Notable views editThis section may be too long and excessively detailed Please consider summarizing the material March 2024 Ancient Greek philosophy edit See also Aletheia Socrates Plato s and Aristotle s ideas about truth are seen by some as consistent with correspondence theory In his Metaphysics Aristotle stated To say of what is that it is not or of what is not that it is is false while to say of what is that it is and of what is not that it is not is true 71 The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy proceeds to say of Aristotle Aristotle sounds much more like a genuine correspondence theorist in the Categories 12b11 14b14 where he talks of underlying things that make statements true and implies that these things pragmata are logically structured situations or facts viz his sitting his not sitting Most influential is his claim in De Interpretatione 16a3 that thoughts are likenesses homoiosis of things Although he nowhere defines truth in terms of a thought s likeness to a thing or fact it is clear that such a definition would fit well into his overall philosophy of mind 71 Similar statements can also be found in Plato s dialogues Cratylus 385b2 Sophist 263b 71 Some Greek philosophers maintained that truth was either not accessible to mortals or of greatly limited accessibility forming early philosophical skepticism Among these were Xenophanes Democritus and Pyrrho the founder of Pyrrhonism who argued that there was no criterion of truth The Epicureans believed that all sense perceptions were true 72 73 and that errors arise in how we judge those perceptions The Stoics conceived truth as accessible from impressions via cognitive grasping Medieval philosophy edit Avicenna 980 1037 edit In early Islamic philosophy Avicenna Ibn Sina defined truth in his work Kitab Al Shifa The Book of Healing Book I Chapter 8 as What corresponds in the mind to what is outside it 74 Avicenna elaborated on his definition of truth later in Book VIII Chapter 6 The truth of a thing is the property of the being of each thing which has been established in it 75 However this definition is merely a rendering of the medieval Latin translation of the work by Simone van Riet 76 A modern translation of the original Arabic text states Truth is also said of the veridical belief in the existence of something 77 Aquinas 1225 1274 edit Reevaluating Avicenna and also Augustine and Aristotle Thomas Aquinas stated in his Disputed Questions on Truth A natural thing being placed between two intellects is called true insofar as it conforms to either It is said to be true with respect to its conformity with the divine intellect insofar as it fulfills the end to which it was ordained by the divine intellect With respect to its conformity with a human intellect a thing is said to be true insofar as it is such as to cause a true estimate about itself 78 Thus for Aquinas the truth of the human intellect logical truth is based on the truth in things ontological truth 79 Following this he wrote an elegant re statement of Aristotle s view in his Summa I 16 1 Veritas est adaequatio intellectus et rei Truth is the conformity of the intellect and things Aquinas also said that real things participate in the act of being of the Creator God who is Subsistent Being Intelligence and Truth Thus these beings possess the light of intelligibility and are knowable These things beings reality are the foundation of the truth that is found in the human mind when it acquires knowledge of things first through the senses then through the understanding and the judgement done by reason For Aquinas human intelligence intus within and legere to read has the capability to reach the essence and existence of things because it has a non material spiritual element although some moral educational and other elements might interfere with its capability Changing concepts of truth in the Middle Ages edit Richard Firth Green examined the concept of truth in the later Middle Ages in his A Crisis of Truth and concludes that roughly during the reign of Richard II of England the very meaning of the concept changes The idea of the oath which was so much part and parcel of for instance Romance literature 80 changes from a subjective concept to a more objective one in Derek Pearsall s summary 81 Whereas truth the trouthe of Sir Gawain and the Green Knight was first an ethical truth in which truth is understood to reside in persons in Ricardian England it transforms into a political truth in which truth is understood to reside in documents 82 Modern philosophy edit Kant 1724 1804 edit Immanuel Kant endorses a definition of truth along the lines of the correspondence theory of truth 71 Kant writes in the Critique of Pure Reason The nominal definition of truth namely that it is the agreement of cognition with its object is here granted and presupposed 83 However Kant denies that this correspondence definition of truth provides us with a test or criterion to establish which judgements are true Kant states in his logic lectures Truth it is said consists in the agreement of cognition with its object In consequence of this mere nominal definition my cognition to count as true is supposed to agree with its object Now I can compare the object with my cognition however only by cognizing it Hence my cognition is supposed to confirm itself which is far short of being sufficient for truth For since the object is outside me the cognition in me all I can ever pass judgement on is whether my cognition of the object agrees with my cognition of the object The ancients called such a circle in explanation a diallelon And actually the logicians were always reproached with this mistake by the sceptics who observed that with this definition of truth it is just as when someone makes a statement before a court and in doing so appeals to a witness with whom no one is acquainted but who wants to establish his credibility by maintaining that the one who called him as witness is an honest man The accusation was grounded too Only the solution of the indicated problem is impossible without qualification and for every man 84 This passage makes use of his distinction between nominal and real definitions A nominal definition explains the meaning of a linguistic expression A real definition describes the essence of certain objects and enables us to determine whether any given item falls within the definition 85 Kant holds that the definition of truth is merely nominal and therefore we cannot employ it to establish which judgements are true According to Kant the ancient skeptics were critical of the logicians for holding that by means of a merely nominal definition of truth they can establish which judgements are true They were trying to do something that is impossible without qualification and for every man 84 Hegel 1770 1831 edit G W F Hegel distanced his philosophy from empiricism by presenting truth as a self moving process rather than a matter of merely subjective thoughts Hegel s truth is analogous to organics in that it is self determining according to its own inner logic Truth is its own self movement within itself 86 Schopenhauer 1788 1860 edit For Arthur Schopenhauer 87 a judgment is a combination or separation of two or more concepts If a judgment is to be an expression of knowledge it must have a sufficient reason or ground by which the judgment could be called true Truth is the reference of a judgment to something different from itself which is its sufficient reason ground Judgments can have material formal transcendental or metalogical truth A judgment has material truth if its concepts are based on intuitive perceptions that are generated from sensations If a judgment has its reason ground in another judgment its truth is called logical or formal If a judgment of for example pure mathematics or pure science is based on the forms space time causality of intuitive empirical knowledge then the judgment has transcendental truth Kierkegaard 1813 1855 edit When Soren Kierkegaard as his character Johannes Climacus ends his writings My thesis was subjectivity heartfelt is the truth he does not advocate for subjectivism in its extreme form the theory that something is true simply because one believes it to be so but rather that the objective approach to matters of personal truth cannot shed any light upon that which is most essential to a person s life Objective truths are concerned with the facts of a person s being while subjective truths are concerned with a person s way of being Kierkegaard agrees that objective truths for the study of subjects like mathematics science and history are relevant and necessary but argues that objective truths do not shed any light on a person s inner relationship to existence At best these truths can only provide a severely narrowed perspective that has little to do with one s actual experience of life 88 While objective truths are final and static subjective truths are continuing and dynamic The truth of one s existence is a living inward and subjective experience that is always in the process of becoming The values morals and spiritual approaches a person adopts while not denying the existence of objective truths of those beliefs can only become truly known when they have been inwardly appropriated through subjective experience Thus Kierkegaard criticizes all systematic philosophies which attempt to know life or the truth of existence via theories and objective knowledge about reality As Kierkegaard claims human truth is something that is continually occurring and a human being cannot find truth separate from the subjective experience of one s own existing defined by the values and fundamental essence that consist of one s way of life 89 Nietzsche 1844 1900 edit Friedrich Nietzsche believed the search for truth or the will to truth was a consequence of the will to power of philosophers He thought that truth should be used as long as it promoted life and the will to power and he thought untruth was better than truth if it had this life enhancement as a consequence As he wrote in Beyond Good and Evil The falseness of a judgment is to us not necessarily an objection to a judgment The question is to what extent it is life advancing life preserving species preserving perhaps even species breeding aphorism 4 He proposed the will to power as a truth only because according to him it was the most life affirming and sincere perspective one could have Robert Wicks discusses Nietzsche s basic view of truth as follows Some scholars regard Nietzsche s 1873 unpublished essay On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense Uber Wahrheit und Luge im aussermoralischen Sinn as a keystone in his thought In this essay Nietzsche rejects the idea of universal constants and claims that what we call truth is only a mobile army of metaphors metonyms and anthropomorphisms His view at this time is that arbitrariness completely prevails within human experience concepts originate via the very artistic transference of nerve stimuli into images truth is nothing more than the invention of fixed conventions for merely practical purposes especially those of repose security and consistence 90 Separately Nietzsche suggested that an ancient metaphysical belief in the divinity of Truth lies at the heart of and has served as the foundation for the entire subsequent Western intellectual tradition But you will have gathered what I am getting at namely that it is still a metaphysical faith on which our faith in science rests that even we knowers of today we godless anti metaphysicians still take our fire too from the flame lit by the thousand year old faith the Christian faith which was also Plato s faith that God is Truth that Truth is Divine 91 92 Moreover Nietzsche challenges the notion of objective truth arguing that truths are human creations and serve practical purposes He wrote Truths are illusions about which one has forgotten that this is what they are 93 He argues that truth is a human invention arising from the artistic transference of nerve stimuli into images serving practical purposes like repose security and consistency formed through metaphorical and rhetorical devices shaped by societal conventions and forgotten origins What then is truth A mobile army of metaphors metonyms and anthropomorphisms in short a sum of human relations which have been enhanced transposed and embellished poetically and rhetorically 94 Nietzsche argues that truth is always filtered through individual perspectives and shaped by various interests and biases In On the Genealogy of Morality he asserts There are no facts only interpretations 95 He suggests that truth is subject to constant reinterpretation and change influenced by shifting cultural and historical contexts as he writes in Thus Spoke Zarathustra that I say unto you one must still have chaos in oneself to be able to give birth to a dancing star 96 In the same book Zarathustra proclaims Truths are illusions which we have forgotten are illusions they are metaphors that have become worn out and have been drained of sensuous force coins which have lost their embossing and are now considered as metal and no longer as coins 97 Heidegger 1889 1976 edit Other philosophers take this common meaning to be secondary and derivative According to Martin Heidegger the original meaning and essence of truth in Ancient Greece was unconcealment or the revealing or bringing of what was previously hidden into the open as indicated by the original Greek term for truth aletheia 98 99 On this view the conception of truth as correctness is a later derivation from the concept s original essence a development Heidegger traces to the Latin term veritas Owing to the primacy of ontology in Heidegger s philosophy he considered this truth to lie within Being itself and already in Being and Time 1927 had identified truth with being truth or the truth of Being and partially with the Kantian thing in itself in an epistemology essentially concerning a mode of Dasein 100 Sartre 1905 1980 edit In Being and Nothingness 1943 partially following Heidegger Jean Paul Sartre identified our knowledge of the truth as a relation between the in itself and for itself of being yet simultaneously closely connected in this vein to the data available to the material personhood in the body of an individual in their interaction with the world and others with Sartre s description that the world is human allowing him to postulate all truth as strictly understood by self consciousness as self consciousness of something 101 a view also preceded by Henri Bergson in Time and Free Will 1889 the reading of which Sartre had credited for his interest in philosophy 102 This first existentialist theory more fully fleshed out in Sartre s essay Truth and Existence 1948 which already demonstrates a more radical departure from Heidegger in its emphasis on the primacy of the idea already formulated in Being and Nothingness of existence as preceding essence in its role in the formulation of truth has nevertheless been critically examined as idealist rather than materialist in its departure from more traditional idealist epistemologies such as those of Ancient Greek philosophy in Plato and Aristotle and staying as does Heidegger with Kant 103 Later in the Search for a Method 1957 in which Sartre used a unification of existentialism and Marxism that he would later formulate in the Critique of Dialectical Reason 1960 Sartre with his growing emphasis on the Hegelian totalisation of historicity posited a conception of truth still defined by its process of relation to a container giving it material meaning but with specfiic reference to a role in this broader totalisation for subjectivity is neither everything nor nothing it represents a moment in the objective process that in which externality is internalised and this moment is perpetually eliminated only to be perpetually reborn For us truth is something which becomes it has and will have become It is a totalisation which is forever being totalised Particular facts do not signify anything they are neither true nor false so long as they are not related through the mediation of various partial totalities to the totalisation in process Sartre describes this as a realistic epistemology developed out of Marx s ideas but with such a development only possible in an existentialist light as with the theme of the whole work 104 105 In an early segment of the lengthy two volume Critique of 1960 Sartre continued to describe truth as a totalising truth of history to be interpreted by a Marxist historian whilst his break with Heidegger s epistemological ideas is finalised in the description of a seemingly antinomous dualism of Being and Truth as the essence of a truly Marxist epistemology 106 Camus 1913 1960 edit The well regarded French philosopher Albert Camus wrote in his famous essay The Myth of Sisyphus 1942 that there are truths but no truth in fundamental agreement with Nietzsche s perspectivism and favourably cites Kierkergaad in posing that no truth is absolute or can render satisfactory an existence that is impossible in itself 107 Later in The Rebel 1951 he declared akin to Sartre that the very lowest form of truth is the truth of history 108 but describes this in the context of its abuse and like Kierkergaad in the Concluding Unscientific Postscript he criticizes Hegel in holding a historical attitude which consists of saying This is truth which appears to us however to be error but which is true precisely because it happens to be error As for proof it is not I but history at its conclusion that will furnish it 109 Whitehead 1861 1947 edit Alfred North Whitehead a British mathematician who became an American philosopher said There are no whole truths all truths are half truths It is trying to treat them as whole truths that plays the devil 110 The logical progression or connection of this line of thought is to conclude that truth can lie since half truths are deceptive and may lead to a false conclusion Peirce 1839 1914 edit Pragmatists like C S Peirce take truth to have some manner of essential relation to human practices for inquiring into and discovering truth with Peirce himself holding that truth is what human inquiry would find out on a matter if our practice of inquiry were taken as far as it could profitably go The opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate is what we mean by the truth 111 Nishida 1870 1945 edit According to Kitaro Nishida knowledge of things in the world begins with the differentiation of unitary consciousness into knower and known and ends with self and things becoming one again Such unification takes form not only in knowing but in the valuing of truth that directs knowing the willing that directs action and the feeling or emotive reach that directs sensing 112 Fromm 1900 1980 edit Erich Fromm finds that trying to discuss truth as absolute truth is sterile and that emphasis ought to be placed on optimal truth He considers truth as stemming from the survival imperative of grasping one s environment physically and intellectually whereby young children instinctively seek truth so as to orient themselves in a strange and powerful world The accuracy of their perceived approximation of the truth will therefore have direct consequences on their ability to deal with their environment Fromm can be understood to define truth as a functional approximation of reality His vision of optimal truth is described partly in Man for Himself An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics 1947 from which excerpts are included below the dichotomy between absolute perfect and relative imperfect has been superseded in all fields of scientific thought where it is generally recognized that there is no absolute truth but nevertheless that there are objectively valid laws and principles In that respect a scientifically or rationally valid statement means that the power of reason is applied to all the available data of observation without any of them being suppressed or falsified for the sake of the desired result The history of science is a history of inadequate and incomplete statements and every new insight makes possible the recognition of the inadequacies of previous propositions and offers a springboard for creating a more adequate formulation As a result the history of thought is the history of an ever increasing approximation to the truth Scientific knowledge is not absolute but optimal it contains the optimum of truth attainable in a given historical period Fromm furthermore notes that different cultures have emphasized various aspects of the truth and that increasing interaction between cultures allows for these aspects to reconcile and integrate increasing further the approximation to the truth Foucault 1926 1984 edit Truth says Michel Foucault is problematic when any attempt is made to see truth as an objective quality He prefers not to use the term truth itself but Regimes of Truth In his historical investigations he found truth to be something that was itself a part of or embedded within a given power structure Thus Foucault s view shares much in common with the concepts of Nietzsche Truth for Foucault is also something that shifts through various episteme throughout history 113 Baudrillard 1929 2007 edit Jean Baudrillard considered truth to be largely simulated that is pretending to have something as opposed to dissimulation pretending to not have something He took his cue from iconoclasts whom he claims knew that images of God demonstrated that God did not exist 114 Baudrillard wrote in Precession of the Simulacra The simulacrum is never that which conceals the truth it is the truth which conceals that there is none The simulacrum is true Ecclesiastes 115 116 dd Some examples of simulacra that Baudrillard cited were that prisons simulate the truth that society is free scandals e g Watergate simulate that corruption is corrected Disney simulates that the U S itself is an adult place Though such examples seem extreme such extremity is an important part of Baudrillard s theory For a less extreme example movies usually end with the bad being punished humiliated or otherwise failing thus affirming for viewers the concept that the good end happily and the bad unhappily a narrative which implies that the status quo and established power structures are largely legitimate 114 Other contemporary positions edit Truthmaker theory is the branch of metaphysics that explores the relationships between what is true and what exists 117 It is different from substantive theories of truth in the sense that it does not aim at giving a definition of what truth is Instead it has the goal of determining how truth depends on being 118 Theological views edit This article relies excessively on references to primary sources Please improve this article by adding secondary or tertiary sources Find sources Truth news newspapers books scholar JSTOR March 2024 Learn how and when to remove this template message Main article Religious views on truth Hinduism edit In Hinduism truth is defined as unchangeable that which has no distortion that which is beyond distinctions of time space and person that which pervades the universe in all its constancy The human body therefore is not completely true as it changes with time for example There are many references properties and explanations of truth by Hindu sages that explain varied facets of truth such as the national motto of India Satyameva Jayate Truth alone triumphs as well as Satyam muktaye Truth liberates Satya is Parahit artham va unmanaso yatha rthatvam satyam Satya is the benevolent use of words and the mind for the welfare of others or in other words responsibilities is truth too When one is firmly established in speaking truth the fruits of action become subservient to him patanjali yogasutras sutra number 2 36 The face of truth is covered by a golden bowl Unveil it O Pusan Sun so that I who have truth as my duty satyadharma may see it Brhadaranyaka V 15 1 4 and the brief IIsa Upanisad 15 18 Truth is superior to silence Manusmriti etc Combined with other words satya acts as a modifier like ultra or highest or more literally truest connoting purity and excellence For example satyaloka is the highest heaven and Satya Yuga is the golden age or best of the four cyclical cosmic ages in Hinduism and so on The Buddha the 9th incarnation of Bhagwan Vishnu quoted as such Three things cannot be long hidden the sun the moon and the truth Buddhism edit In Buddhism particularly in the Mahayana tradition the notion of truth is often divided into the two truths doctrine which consists of relative or conventional truth and ultimate truth The former refers to truth that is based on common understanding among ordinary people and is accepted as a practical basis for communication of higher truths Ultimate truth necessarily transcends logic in the sphere of ordinary experience and recognizes such phenomena as illusory Madhyamaka philosophy asserts that any doctrine can be analyzed with both divisions of truth Affirmation and negation belong to relative and absolute truth respectively Political law is regarded as relative while religious law is absolute Christianity edit nbsp What is Truth by Nikolai Ge depicting John 18 38 in which Pilate asks Christ What is truth Christianity has a soteriological view of truth According to the Bible in John 14 6 Jesus is quoted as having said I am the way the truth and the life no man cometh unto the Father but by me See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Psychology portal Asha Confirmation holism Contextualism Degree of truth Disposition Eclecticism Epistemic theories of truth Imagination Independence probability theory Invariant mathematics McNamara fallacy Normative science On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense Perspectivism Physical symbol system Public opinion Relativism Religious views on truth Revision theory Slingshot argument Subjectivity Tautology logic Tautology rhetoric Theory of justification Truth prevails Truthiness Unity of the proposition Verisimilitude Other theorists edit Augustine of Hippo Brand Blanshard Hartry Field Gottlob Frege Paul Horwich Harold Joachim Karl PopperNotes edit a b Merriam Webster s Online Dictionary truth Archived 2009 12 29 at the Wayback Machine 2005 a b c Truth Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 20 January 2022 Retrieved 29 June 2020 Alexis G Burgess and John P Burgess 2011 Truth hardcover 1st ed Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 14401 6 Archived from the original on October 6 2014 Retrieved October 4 2014 a concise introduction to current philosophical debates about truth see Holtzmann s law for the ww gg alternation Etymology Online Online Etymology Archived from the original on 2007 07 13 Retrieved 2013 11 27 A Concise Dictionary of Old Icelandic Archived 2007 09 30 at the Wayback Machine Geir T Zoega 1910 Northvegr org OED on true has Steadfast in adherence to a commander or friend to a principle or cause to one s promises faith etc firm in allegiance faithful loyal constant trusty honest honourable upright virtuous trustworthy free from deceit sincere truthful besides Conformity with fact agreement with reality accuracy correctness verity Consistent with fact agreeing with the reality representing the thing as it is real genuine rightly answering to the description properly so called not counterfeit spurious or imaginary a b c d e f Encyclopedia of Philosophy Supp Truth auth Michael Williams pp 572 73 Macmillan 1996 Blackburn Simon and Simmons Keith eds 1999 Truth Oxford University Press Oxford Includes papers by James Ramsey Russell Tarski and more recent work Hale Bob Wright Crispin eds 1999 A Companion to the Philosophy of Language pp 309 30 doi 10 1111 b 9780631213260 1999 00015 x inactive 31 January 2024 ISBN 978 0 631 21326 0 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a Missing or empty title help CS1 maint DOI inactive as of January 2024 link The PhilPapers Surveys Preliminary Survey results The PhilPapers Surveys Philpapers org Archived from the original on 2012 03 20 Retrieved 2012 05 27 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Correspondence Theory of Truth auth Arthur N Prior p 223 Macmillan 1969 Prior uses Bertrand Russell s wording in defining correspondence theory According to Prior Russell was substantially responsible for helping to make correspondence theory widely known under this name Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Correspondence Theory of Truth auth Arthur N Prior pp 223 24 Macmillan 1969 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Correspondence Theory of Truth auth Arthur N Prior Macmillan 1969 p 224 Correspondence Theory of Truth in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived 2019 10 31 at the Wayback Machine Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae I Q 16 A 2 arg 2 Correspondence Theory of Truth in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived 2019 10 31 at the Wayback Machine citing De Veritate Q 1 A 1 3 and Summa Theologiae I Q 16 See e g Bradley F H On Truth and Copying in Blackburn et al eds 1999 Truth 31 45 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Correspondence Theory of Truth auth Arthur N Prior pp 223 ff Macmillan 1969 See especially section on Moore s Correspondence Theory 225 26 Russell s Correspondence Theory 226 27 Remsey and Later Wittgenstein 228 29 Tarski s Semantic Theory 230 31 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Correspondence Theory of Truth auth Arthur N Prior pp 223 ff Macmillan 1969 See the section on Tarski s Semantic Theory 230 31 Immanuel Kant for instance assembled a controversial but quite coherent system in the early 19th century whose validity and usefulness continues to be debated even today Similarly the systems of Leibniz and Spinoza are characteristic systems that are internally coherent but controversial in terms of their utility and validity Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Coherence Theory of Truth auth Alan R White pp 130 31 Macmillan 1969 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Coherence Theory of Truth auth Alan R White pp 131 33 see esp section on Epistemological assumptions Macmillan 1969 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Coherence Theory of Truth auth Alan R White p 130 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 5 Pragmatic Theory of Truth 427 Macmillan 1969 a b Peirce C S 1901 Truth and Falsity and Error in part pp 716 20 in James Mark Baldwin ed Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology v 2 Peirce s section is entitled Logical beginning on p 718 column 1 and ending on p 720 with the initials C S P see Google Books Eprint Reprinted Collected Papers v 5 pp 565 73 a b James William The Meaning of Truth A Sequel to Pragmatism 1909 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 2 Dewey John auth Richard J Bernstein p 383 Macmillan 1969 Sahakian W S amp Sahakian M L Ideas of the Great Philosophers New York Barnes amp Noble 1966 LCCN 66 23155 a b Feynman The Character of Physical Law New York Random House 1994 978 0 679 60127 2 Feynman The Character of Physical Law p 150 May Todd 1993 Between Genealogy and Epistemology Psychology Politics and Knowledge in the Thought of Michel Foucault University Park Pennsylvania State University Press ISBN 978 0271027821 OCLC 26553016 See e g Habermas Jurgen Knowledge and Human Interests English translation 1972 See e g Habermas Jurgen Knowledge and Human Interests English translation 1972 esp Part III pp 187 ff Rescher Nicholas Pluralism Against the Demand for Consensus 1995 Blackburn Simon and Simmons Keith eds 1999 Truth in the Introductory section of the book Richard Kirkham Theories of Truth A Critical Introduction MIT Press 1992 J L Austin How to Do Things With Words Cambridge Harvard University Press 1975 Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 6 Performative Theory of Truth auth Gertrude Ezorsky p 88 Macmillan 1969 Ramsey F P 1927 Facts and Propositions Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7 153 70 Reprinted pp 34 51 in F P Ramsey Philosophical Papers David Hugh Mellor ed Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1990 Le Morvan Pierre 2004 Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey The British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 4 pp 705 18 Popkin R H The History of Skepticism from Erasmus to Descartes rev ed 1968 C L Stough Greek Skepticism 1969 M Burnyeat ed The Skeptical Tradition 1983 B Stroud The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism 1984 Archived from the original on 2012 07 13 Retrieved 2018 06 04 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Philosophical views are typically classed as skeptical when they involve advancing some degree of doubt regarding claims that are elsewhere taken for granted utm edu Archived 2009 01 13 at the Wayback Machine Greco John 2008 The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism Oxford University Press US ISBN 978 0 19 518321 4 Definition of SKEPTICISM Merriam Webster Archived from the original on 2019 04 24 Retrieved 2016 02 05 Truth and Objectivity Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press 1992 Truth as One and Many Oxford Oxford University Press 2009 Ludwig Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico Philosophicus Kretzmann Norman 1968 IV section 2 Infinitely Many and Finitely Many William of Sherwood s Treatise on Syncategorematic Words University of Minnesota Press ISBN 978 0 8166 5805 3 Smith Nicholas J J 2010 Article 2 6 PDF Many Valued Logics Routledge Archived PDF from the original on 2018 04 08 Retrieved 2018 05 25 Mancosu Paolo Zach Richard Badesa Calixto 2004 7 2 Many valued logics 9 The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski 1900 1935 Oxford University Press pp 418 20 ISBN 978 0 19 972272 3 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Garrido Angel 2012 A Brief History of Fuzzy Logic Revista EduSoft Archived from the original on 2018 05 17 Retrieved 2018 05 25 Editorial Rescher Nicholas 1968 Many Valued Logic Topics in Philosophical Logic Humanities Press Synthese Library volume 17 pp 54 125 doi 10 1007 978 94 017 3546 9 6 ISBN 978 90 481 8331 9 Penelope Maddy Realism in Mathematics Series Clarendon Paperbacks Paperback 216 pages Publisher Oxford University Press US 1992 978 0 19 824035 8 Elliott Mendelson Introduction to Mathematical Logic Series Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications Hardcover 469 pages Publisher Chapman and Hall CRC 5 edition August 11 2009 978 1 58488 876 5 See e g Chaitin Gregory L The Limits of Mathematics 1997 esp 89 ff M Davis Hilbert s Tenth Problem is Unsolvable American Mathematical Monthly 80 pp 233 69 1973 Yandell Benjamin H The Honors Class Hilbert s Problems and Their Solvers 2002 Chaitin Gregory L The Limits of Mathematics 1997 1 28 89 ff Ravitch Harold 1998 On Godel s Philosophy of Mathematics Archived from the original on 2018 02 28 Retrieved 2018 05 25 Solomon Martin 1998 On Kurt Godel s Philosophy of Mathematics Archived from the original on 2016 03 04 Retrieved 2018 05 25 Wang Hao 1997 A Logical Journey From Godel to Philosophy The MIT Press A discussion of Godel s views on logical intuition is woven throughout the book the quote appears on page 75 Kripke Saul Outline of a Theory of Truth Journal of Philosophy 72 1975 690 716 Keith Simmons Universality and the Liar An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1993 Goldblatt Robert 1983 Topoi the categorial analysis of logic revised ed Amsterdam Sole distributors for the U S A and Canada Elsevier North Holland ISBN 0 444 86711 2 OCLC 9622076 Scharp Kevin 2013 6 What is the Use Replacing truth First ed Oxford Oxford Univ Press ISBN 978 0 19 965385 0 truth philosophy and logic Encyclopedia Britannica Archived from the original on 5 June 2019 Retrieved 28 July 2017 Truth is important Believing what is not true is apt to spoil a person s plans and may even cost him his life Telling what is not true may result in legal and social penalties Wellman Henry M David Cross and Julanne Watson Meta analysis of theory of mind development the truth about false belief Child development 72 3 2001 655 84 Lynch Michael P Alethic functionalism and our folk theory of truth Synthese 145 1 2005 29 43 Bueno Otavio and Mark Colyvan Logical non apriorism and the law of non contradiction The law of non contradiction New philosophical essays 2004 156 75 a b c d David Marion 2005 Correspondence Theory of Truth Archived 2014 02 25 at the Wayback Machine in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Asmis Elizabeth 2009 Epicurean empiricism In Warren James ed The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism Cambridge University Press p 84 O Keefe Tim 2010 Epicureanism University of California Press pp 97 98 Osman Amin 2007 Influence of Muslim Philosophy on the West Monthly Renaissance 17 11 Jan A Aertsen 1988 Nature and Creature Thomas Aquinas s Way of Thought p 152 Brill 978 90 04 08451 3 Simone van Riet Liber de philosophia prima sive Scientia divina in Latin p 413 Avicenna The Metaphysics of The Healing Michael E Marmura Brigham Young University Press 2005 p 284 ISBN 978 0 934893 77 0 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint others link Disputed Questions on Truth 1 2 c reply to Obj 1 Trans Mulligan McGlynn Schmidt Truth vol I pp 10 12 Veritas supra ens fundatur Truth is founded on being Disputed Questions on Truth 10 2 reply to Obj 3 Rock Catherine A 2006 Forsworn and Fordone Arcite as Oath Breaker in the Knight s Tale The Chaucer Review 40 4 416 32 doi 10 1353 cr 2006 0009 JSTOR 25094334 S2CID 159853483 Pearsall Derek 2004 Medieval Literature and Historical Enquiry Modern Language Review 99 4 xxxi xlii doi 10 2307 3738608 JSTOR 3738608 S2CID 155446847 Fowler Elizabeth 2003 Rev of Green A Crisis of Truth Speculum 78 1 179 82 doi 10 1017 S0038713400099310 JSTOR 3301477 Kant Immanuel 1781 1787 Critique of Pure Reason Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W Wood Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1998 A58 B82 a b Kant Immanuel 1801 The Jasche Logic in Lectures on Logic Translated and edited by J Michael Young Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1992 pp 557 58 Alberto Vanzo Kant on the Nominal Definition of Truth Kant Studien 101 2010 pp 147 66 Die Wahrheit ist die Bewegung ihrer an ihr selbst The Phenomenology of Spirit Preface 48 On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 29 33 Kierkegaard Soren Concluding Unscientific Postscript Princeton Princeton University Press 1992 Watts Michael Kierkegaard Oxford Oneworld Publications 2003 Robert Wicks Friedrich Nietzsche Early Writings 1872 1876 Archived 2018 09 04 at the Wayback Machine The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2008 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Nietzsche Friedrich Williams Bernard Nauckhoff Josefine 2001 Nietzsche The Gay Science With a Prelude in German Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 63645 2 via Google Books Nietzsche Friedrich 2006 Nietzsche On the Genealogy of Morality and Other Writings Student Edition Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 46121 4 via Google Books Nietzsche Friedrich 1997 Beyond Good and Evil Dover Publications p 46 ISBN 978 0486298689 Nietzsche Friedrich 1976 The Portable Nietzsche Penguin Books p 46 ISBN 978 0140150629 Nietzsche Friedrich 1887 On the Genealogy of Morality Oxford University Press p 73 ISBN 978 0199537082 Nietzsche Friedrich 1883 Thus Spoke Zarathustra Penguin UK p 46 ISBN 9780140441185 Nietzsche Friedrich 1883 Thus Spoke Zarathustra Penguin UK p 121 ISBN 9780140441185 Heidegger Martin On the Essence of Truth PDF aphelis net Retrieved 3 October 2023 Martin Heidegger on Aletheia Truth as Unconcealment Archived from the original on 2015 06 26 Retrieved 2010 08 13 Heidegger Martin 1962 Being and Time 1st ed Oxford Basil Blackswell pp 256 274 Sartre Jean Paul 1956 Being and Nothingness An Essay on Phenomenological Ontolgoy 1st ed New York Philosophical Library Sartre Jean Paul 2004 The imaginary a phenomenological psychology of the imagination Arlette Elkaim Sartre Jonathan Webber London Routledge ISBN 0 203 64410 7 OCLC 56549324 Wilder Kathleen 1995 Truth and existence The idealism in Sartre s theory of truth International Journal of Philosophical Studies 3 1 91 109 doi 10 1080 09672559508570805 Sartre Jean Paul 1963 Search for a Method 1st ed New York Knopf Skirke Christian 2014 04 28 Jean Paul Sartre Philosophy Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 obo 9780195396577 0192 ISBN 978 0 19 539657 7 retrieved 2023 02 25 Sartre Jean Paul 2004 Critique of Dialectical Reason London Verso pp 15 41 Camus Albert 2020 The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays 1st ed London Penguin Group pp 14 16 Camus Albert 2013 The Rebel 3rd ed London Penguin Group p 180 Camus Albert 2013 The Rebel 3rd ed London Penguin Group p 90 Alfred North Whitehead Dialogues 1954 Prologue How to Make Our Ideas Clear Archived from the original on 2018 10 03 Retrieved 2015 08 31 John Maraldo Nishida Kitaro Self Awareness Archived 2010 12 04 at the Wayback Machine in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2005 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Foucault M The Order of Things London Vintage Books 1970 1966 a b Jean Baudrillard Simulacra and Simulation Michigan Michigan University Press 1994 Baudrillard Jean Simulacra and Simulations in Selected Writings Archived 2004 02 09 at the Wayback Machine ed Mark Poster Stanford University Press 1988 166 ff Baudrillard s attribution of this quote to Ecclesiastes is deliberately fictional Baudrillard attributes this quote to Ecclesiastes However the quote is a fabrication see Jean Baudrillard Cool Memories III 1991 95 London Verso 1997 Editor s note In Fragments Conversations With Francois L Yvonnet New York Routledge 2004 11 Baudrillard acknowledges this Borges like fabrication Cited in footnote 4 in Smith Richard G Lights Camera Action Baudrillard and the Performance of Representations Archived 2018 04 25 at the Wayback Machine International Journal of Baudrillard Studies Volume 2 Number 1 January 2005 Asay Jamin Truthmaker Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2020 11 24 Retrieved 2020 11 28 Beebee Helen Dodd Julian 2005 Truthmakers The Contemporary Debate Clarendon Press pp 13 14 Archived from the original on 2020 12 06 Retrieved 2020 11 28 References editAristotle The Categories Harold P Cooke trans pp 1 109 in Aristotle Volume 1 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London 1938 Aristotle On Interpretation Harold P Cooke trans pp 111 79 in Aristotle Volume 1 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London 1938 Aristotle Prior Analytics Hugh Tredennick trans pp 181 531 in Aristotle Volume 1 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London 1938 Aristotle On the Soul De Anima W S Hett trans pp 1 203 in Aristotle Volume 8 Loeb Classical Library William Heinemann London 1936 Audi Robert ed 1999 The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1995 2nd edition 1999 Cited as CDP Baldwin James Mark ed 1901 1905 Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology 3 volumes in 4 Macmillan New York Baylis Charles A 1962 Truth pp 321 22 in Dagobert D Runes ed Dictionary of Philosophy Littlefield Adams and Company Totowa NJ Benjamin A Cornelius 1962 Coherence Theory of Truth p 58 in Dagobert D Runes ed Dictionary of Philosophy Littlefield Adams and Company Totowa NJ Blackburn Simon and Simmons Keith eds 1999 Truth Oxford University Press Oxford Includes papers by James Ramsey Russell Tarski and more recent work Chandrasekhar Subrahmanyan 1987 Truth and Beauty Aesthetics and Motivations in Science University of Chicago Press Chicago IL Chang C C and Keisler H J Model Theory North Holland Amsterdam Netherlands 1973 Chomsky Noam 1995 The Minimalist Program MIT Press Cambridge Massachusetts Church Alonzo 1962a Name Relation or Meaning Relation p 204 in Dagobert D Runes ed Dictionary of Philosophy Littlefield Adams and Company Totowa NJ Church Alonzo 1962b Truth Semantical p 322 in Dagobert D Runes ed Dictionary of Philosophy Littlefield Adams and Company Totowa NJ Clifford W K 1877 The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays Prometheus Books 1999 infidels org Archived 2009 12 03 at the Wayback Machine Dewey John 1900 1901 Lectures on Ethics 1900 1901 Donald F Koch ed Southern Illinois University Press Carbondale and Edwardsville IL Dewey John 1932 Theory of the Moral Life Part 2 of John Dewey and James H Tufts Ethics Henry Holt and Company New York 1908 2nd edition Holt Rinehart and Winston 1932 Reprinted Arnold Isenberg ed Victor Kestenbaum pref Irvingtion Publishers New York 1980 Dewey John 1938 Logic The Theory of Inquiry 1938 Holt and Company New York Reprinted John Dewey The Later Works 1925 1953 Volume 12 1938 Jo Ann Boydston ed Southern Illinois University Press Carbondale and Edwardsville IL 1986 Field Hartry 2001 Truth and the Absence of Fact Oxford University Press Oxford Foucault Michel 1997 Essential Works of Foucault 1954 1984 Volume 1 Ethics Subjectivity and Truth Paul Rabinow ed Robert Hurley et al trans The New Press New York Garfield Jay L and Kiteley Murray 1991 Meaning and Truth The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics Paragon House New York Gupta Anil 2001 Truth in Lou Goble ed The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic Blackwell Publishers Oxford Gupta Anil and Belnap Nuel 1993 The Revision Theory of Truth MIT Press Haack Susan 1993 Evidence and Inquiry Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology Blackwell Publishers Oxford Habermas Jurgen 1976 What Is Universal Pragmatics 1st published Was heisst Universalpragmatik Sprachpragmatik und Philosophie Karl Otto Apel ed Suhrkamp Verlag Frankfurt am Main Reprinted pp 1 68 in Jurgen Habermas Communication and the Evolution of Society Thomas McCarthy trans Beacon Press Boston 1979 Habermas Jurgen 1990 Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen trans Thomas McCarthy intro MIT Press Cambridge Massachusetts Habermas Jurgen 2003 Truth and Justification Barbara Fultner trans MIT Press Cambridge Massachusetts Hegel Georg 1977 The Phenomenology of Spirit Oxford University Press Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 824597 1 Horwich Paul 1988 Truth 2nd edition Oxford University Press Oxford James William 1904 A World of Pure Experience James William 1907 Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking Popular Lectures on Philosophy Longmans Green and Company New York James William 1909 The Meaning of Truth A Sequel to Pragmatism Longmans Green and Company New York James William 1912 Essays in Radical Empiricism Cf Chapt 3 The Thing and its Relations pp 92 122 James William 2014 William James on Habit Will Truth and the Meaning of Life James Sloan Allen ed Frederic C Beil Publisher Savannah GA Kant Immanuel 1800 Introduction to Logic Reprinted Thomas Kingsmill Abbott trans Dennis Sweet intro Barnes and Noble New York 2005 Kirkham Richard L 1992 Theories of Truth A Critical Introduction MIT Press Cambridge Massachusetts Kneale W and Kneale M 1962 The Development of Logic Oxford University Press London 1962 Reprinted with corrections 1975 Kreitler Hans and Kreitler Shulamith 1972 Psychology of the Arts Duke University Press Durham NC Le Morvan Pierre 2004 Ramsey on Truth and Truth on Ramsey British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 4 2004 705 18 PDF Archived 2017 08 29 at the Wayback Machine Peirce C S Bibliography Peirce C S Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce vols 1 6 Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds vols 7 8 Arthur W Burks ed Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts 1931 1935 1958 Cited as CP vol para Peirce C S 1877 The Fixation of Belief Popular Science Monthly 12 1877 1 15 Reprinted CP 5 358 387 CE 3 242 257 EP 1 109 123 Eprint Archived 2020 12 11 at the Wayback Machine Peirce C S 1901 Truth and Falsity and Error in part pp 718 20 in J M Baldwin ed Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology vol 2 Reprinted CP 5 565 573 Polanyi Michael 1966 The Tacit Dimension Doubleday and Company Garden City NY Quine W V 1956 Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes Journal of Philosophy 53 1956 Reprinted pp 185 96 in Quine 1976 Ways of Paradox Quine W V 1976 The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays 1st edition 1966 Revised and enlarged edition Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts 1976 Quine W V 1980 a From a Logical Point of View Logico Philosophical Essays 2nd edition Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts Quine W V 1980 b Reference and Modality pp 139 59 in Quine 1980 a From a Logical Point of View Rajchman John and West Cornel ed 1985 Post Analytic Philosophy Columbia University Press New York Ramsey F P 1927 Facts and Propositions Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 7 153 70 Reprinted pp 34 51 in F P Ramsey Philosophical Papers David Hugh Mellor ed Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1990 Ramsey F P 1990 Philosophical Papers David Hugh Mellor ed Cambridge University Press Cambridge Rawls John 2000 Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy Barbara Herman ed Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts Rorty R 1979 Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature Princeton University Press Princeton NJ Russell Bertrand 1912 The Problems of Philosophy 1st published 1912 Reprinted Galaxy Book Oxford University Press New York 1959 Reprinted Prometheus Books Buffalo NY 1988 Russell Bertrand 1918 The Philosophy of Logical Atomism The Monist 1918 Reprinted pp 177 281 in Logic and Knowledge Essays 1901 1950 Robert Charles Marsh ed Unwin Hyman London 1956 Reprinted pp 35 155 in The Philosophy of Logical Atomism David Pears ed Open Court La Salle IL 1985 Russell Bertrand 1956 Logic and Knowledge Essays 1901 1950 Robert Charles Marsh ed Unwin Hyman London 1956 Reprinted Routledge London 1992 Russell Bertrand 1985 The Philosophy of Logical Atomism David Pears ed Open Court La Salle IL Schopenhauer Arthur 1974 On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason Open Court La Salle IL ISBN 978 0 87548 187 6 Smart Ninian 1969 The Religious Experience of Mankind Charles Scribner s Sons New York Tarski A Logic Semantics Metamathematics Papers from 1923 to 1938 J H Woodger trans Oxford University Press Oxford 1956 2nd edition John Corcoran ed Hackett Publishing Indianapolis IN 1983 Wallace Anthony F C 1966 Religion An Anthropological View Random House New York Reference works edit Audi Robert ed 1999 The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Cambridge University Press Cambridge 1995 2nd edition 1999 Cited as CDP Blackburn Simon 1996 The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press Oxford 1994 Paperback edition with new Chronology 1996 Cited as ODP Runes Dagobert D ed Dictionary of Philosophy Littlefield Adams and Company Totowa NJ 1962 Webster s New International Dictionary of the English Language Second Edition Unabridged 1950 W A Neilson T A Knott P W Carhart eds G amp C Merriam Company Springfield MA Cited as MWU Webster s Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary 1983 Frederick C Mish ed Merriam Webster Inc Springfield MA Cited as MWC External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Truth nbsp Look up truth in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Truth An Introduction to Truth by Paul Newall aimed at beginners Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Truth Pluralist Theories of Truth Truthmaker Theory Prosentential Theory of Truth Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Truth Coherence theory of truth Correspondence theory of truth Deflationary theory of truth Identity theory of truth Revision theory of truth Tarski s definition of truth Axiomatic theories of truth Heidegger on Truth Aletheia as Unconcealment History of Truth The Greek Aletheia History of Truth The Latin Veritas Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Truth amp oldid 1221025627, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.