fbpx
Wikipedia

Crime

In ordinary language, a crime is an unlawful act punishable by a state or other authority.[1] The term crime does not, in modern criminal law, have any simple and universally accepted definition,[2] though statutory definitions have been provided for certain purposes.[3] The most popular view is that crime is a category created by law; in other words, something is a crime if declared as such by the relevant and applicable law.[2] One proposed definition is that a crime or offence (or criminal offence) is an act harmful not only to some individual but also to a community, society, or the state ("a public wrong"). Such acts are forbidden and punishable by law.[1][4]

The notion that acts such as murder, rape, and theft are to be prohibited exists worldwide.[5] What precisely is a criminal offence is defined by the criminal law of each relevant jurisdiction. While many have a catalogue of crimes called the criminal code, in some common law nations no such comprehensive statute exists.

The state (government) has the power to severely restrict one's liberty for committing a crime. In modern societies, there are procedures to which investigations and trials must adhere. If found guilty, an offender may be sentenced to a form of reparation such as a community sentence, or, depending on the nature of their offence, to undergo imprisonment, life imprisonment or, in some jurisdictions, death. Some jurisdictions sentence individuals to programs to emphasize or provide for their rehabilitation while most jurisdictions sentence individuals with the goal of punishing them or a mix of the aforementioned practices.[citation needed]

Usually, to be classified as a crime, the "act of doing something criminal" (actus reus) must – with certain exceptions – be accompanied by the "intention to do something criminal" (mens rea).[4]

While every crime violates the law, not every violation of the law counts as a crime. Breaches of private law (torts and breaches of contract) are not automatically punished by the state, but can be enforced through civil procedure.

Overview

When informal relationships prove insufficient to establish and maintain a desired social order, a government or a state may impose more formalized or stricter systems of social control. With institutional and legal machinery at their disposal, agents of the state can compel populations to conform to codes and can opt to punish or attempt to reform those who do not conform.

Authorities employ various mechanisms to regulate (encouraging or discouraging) certain behaviors in general. Governing or administering agencies may for example codify rules into laws, police citizens and visitors to ensure that they comply with those laws, and implement other policies and practices that legislators or administrators have prescribed with the aim of discouraging or preventing crime. In addition, authorities provide remedies and sanctions, and collectively these constitute a criminal justice system. Legal sanctions vary widely in their severity; they may include (for example) incarceration of temporary character aimed at reforming the convict. Some jurisdictions have penal codes written to inflict permanent harsh punishments: legal mutilation, capital punishment, or life without parole.

Usually, a natural person perpetrates a crime, but legal persons may also commit crimes. Historically, several premodern societies believed that non-human animals were capable of committing crimes, and prosecuted and punished them accordingly.[6]

The sociologist Richard Quinney has written about the relationship between society and crime. When Quinney states "crime is a social phenomenon" he envisages both how individuals conceive crime and how populations perceive it, based on societal norms.[7]

Etymology

The word crime is derived from the Latin root cernō, meaning "I decide, I give judgment". Originally the Latin word crīmen meant "charge" or "cry of distress".[8] The Ancient Greek word κρίμα, krima, with which the Latin crimen is cognate, typically referred to an intellectual mistake or an offense against the community, rather than a private or moral wrong.[9]

In 13th century English crime meant "sinfulness", according to the Online Etymology Dictionary. It was probably brought to England as Old French crimne (12th century form of Modern French crime), from Latin crimen (in the genitive case: criminis). In Latin, crimen could have signified any one of the following: "charge, indictment, accusation; crime, fault, offense".

The word may derive from the Latin cernere – "to decide, to sift" (see crisis, mapped on Kairos and Chronos). But Ernest Klein (citing Karl Brugmann) rejects this and suggests *cri-men, which originally would have meant "cry of distress". Thomas G. Tucker suggests a root in "cry" words and refers to English plaint, plaintiff, and so on. The meaning "offense punishable by law" dates from the late 14th century. The Latin word is glossed in Old English by facen, also "deceit, fraud, treachery", [cf. fake]. Crime wave is first attested in 1893 in American English.

Definition

Legalism

In the scope of law, crime is defined by the criminal law of a given jurisdiction, including all actions that are subject to criminal procedure. There is no limit to what can be considered a crime in a legal system, so there may not be a unifying principle used to determine whether an action should be designated as a crime.[10]

Legislatures can pass laws (called mala prohibita) that define crimes against social norms. These laws vary from time to time and from place to place: note variations in gambling laws, for example, and the prohibition or encouragement of duelling in history. Other crimes, called mala in se, count as outlawed in almost all societies, (murder, theft and rape, for example).

English criminal law and the related criminal law of Commonwealth countries can define offences that the courts alone have developed over the years, without any actual legislation: common law offences. The courts used the concept of malum in se to develop various common law offences.[11]

In the military sphere, authorities can prosecute both regular crimes and specific acts (such as mutiny or desertion) under martial-law codes that either supplant or extend civil codes in times of (for example) war. Many constitutions contain provisions to curtail freedoms and criminalize otherwise tolerated behaviors under a state of emergency in case of war, natural disaster or civil unrest. Undesired activities at such times may include assembly in the streets, violation of curfew, or possession of firearms.

Sociology

A normative definition views crime as deviant behavior that violates prevailing norms – cultural standards prescribing how humans ought to behave normally. This approach considers the complex realities surrounding the concept of crime and seeks to understand how changing social, political, psychological, and economic conditions may affect changing definitions of crime and the form of the legal, law-enforcement, and penal responses made by society.

These structural realities remain fluid and often contentious. For example: as cultures change and the political environment shifts, societies may criminalise or decriminalise certain behaviours, which directly affects the statistical crime rates, influence the allocation of resources for the enforcement of laws, and (re-)influence the general public opinion.

Similarly, changes in the collection and/or calculation of data on crime may affect the public perceptions of the extent of any given "crime problem". All such adjustments to crime statistics, allied with the experience of people in their everyday lives, shape attitudes on the extent to which the state should use law or social engineering to enforce or encourage any particular social norm. Behaviour can be controlled and influenced by a society in many ways without having to resort to the criminal justice system.

Indeed, in those cases where no clear consensus exists on a given norm, the drafting of criminal law by the group in power to prohibit the behaviour of another group may seem to some observers an improper limitation of the second group's freedom, and the ordinary members of society have less respect for the law or laws in general – whether the authorities actually enforce the disputed law or not.

Foundational systems

Natural-law theory

Justifying the state's use of force to coerce compliance with its laws has proven a consistent theoretical problem. One of the earliest justifications involved the theory of natural law. This posits that the nature of the world or of human beings underlies the standards of morality or constructs them. Thomas Aquinas wrote in the 13th century: "the rule and measure of human acts is the reason, which is the first principle of human acts".[12] He regarded people as by nature rational beings, concluding that it becomes morally appropriate that they should behave in a way that conforms to their rational nature. Thus, to be valid, any law must conform to natural law and coercing people to conform to that law is morally acceptable. In the 1760s, William Blackstone described the thesis:[13]

"This law of nature, being co-eval with mankind and dictated by God himself, is of course superior in obligation to any other. It is binding over all the globe, in all countries, and at all times: no human laws are of any validity, if contrary to this; and such of them as are valid derive all their force, and all their authority, mediately or immediately, from this original."

But John Austin (1790–1859), an early positivist, applied utilitarianism in accepting the calculating nature of human beings and the existence of an objective morality. He denied that the legal validity of a norm depends on whether its content conforms to morality. Thus in Austinian terms, a moral code can objectively determine what people ought to do, the law can embody whatever norms the legislature decrees to achieve social utility, but every individual remains free to choose what to do. Similarly, H.L.A. Hart saw the law as an aspect of sovereignty, with lawmakers able to adopt any law as a means to a moral end.[14]

Thus the necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of a proposition of law involved internal logic and consistency, and that the state's agents used state power with responsibility. Ronald Dworkin rejects Hart's theory and proposes that all individuals should expect the equal respect and concern of those who govern them as a fundamental political right. He offers a theory of compliance overlaid by a theory of deference (the citizen's duty to obey the law) and a theory of enforcement, which identifies the legitimate goals of enforcement and punishment. Legislation must conform to a theory of legitimacy, which describes the circumstances under which a particular person or group is entitled to make law, and a theory of legislative justice, which describes the law they are entitled or obliged to make.[15]

There are natural-law theorists who have accepted the idea of enforcing the prevailing morality as a primary function of the law.[16] This view entails the problem that it makes any moral criticism of the law impossible: if conformity with natural law forms a necessary condition for legal validity, all valid law must, by definition, count as morally just. Thus, on this line of reasoning, the legal validity of a norm necessarily entails its moral justice.[17]

One can solve this problem by granting some degree of moral relativism and accepting that norms may evolve over time and, therefore, one can criticize the continued enforcement of old laws in the light of the current norms. People may find such law acceptable, but the use of state power to coerce citizens to comply with that law lacks moral justification. More recent conceptions of the theory characterise crime as the violation of individual rights.

Since society considers so many rights as natural (hence the term right) rather than man-made, what constitutes a crime also counts as natural, in contrast to laws (seen as man-made). Adam Smith illustrates this view, saying that a smuggler would be an excellent citizen, "...had not the laws of his country made that a crime which nature never meant to be so."

Natural-law theory therefore distinguishes between "criminality" (which derives from human nature) and "illegality" (which originates with the interests of those in power). Lawyers sometimes express the two concepts with the phrases malum in se and malum prohibitum respectively. They regard a "crime malum in se" as inherently criminal; whereas a "crime malum prohibitum" (the argument goes) counts as criminal only because the law has decreed it so.

It follows from this view that one can perform an illegal act without committing a crime, while a criminal act could be perfectly legal. Many Enlightenment thinkers (such as Adam Smith and the American Founding Fathers) subscribed to this view to some extent, and it remains influential among so-called classical liberals[citation needed] and libertarians.[citation needed]

Religion

 
Religious sentiment often becomes a contributory factor of crime. In the 1819 anti-Jewish Hep-Hep riots in Würzburg, rioters attacked Jewish businesses and destroyed property.

Different religious traditions may promote distinct norms of behaviour, and these in turn may clash or harmonise with the perceived interests of a state. Socially accepted or imposed religious morality has influenced secular jurisdictions on issues that may otherwise concern only an individual's conscience. Activities sometimes criminalized on religious grounds include (for example) alcohol consumption (prohibition), abortion and stem-cell research. In various historical and present-day societies, institutionalized religions have established systems of earthly justice that punish crimes against the divine will and against specific devotional, organizational and other rules under specific codes, such as Roman Catholic canon law and Islamic Shariah Law.

Criminalization

 
The spiked heads of executed criminals once adorned the gatehouse of the medieval London Bridge.

One can view criminalization as a procedure deployed by society as a preemptive harm-reduction device, using the threat of punishment as a deterrent to anyone proposing to engage in the behavior causing harm. The state becomes involved because governing entities can become convinced that the costs of not criminalizing (through allowing the harms to continue unabated) outweigh the costs of criminalizing it (restricting individual liberty, for example, to minimize harm to others).[citation needed]

States control the process of criminalization because:

  • Even if victims recognize their own role as victims, they may not have the resources to investigate and seek legal redress for the injuries suffered: the enforcers formally appointed by the state often have better access to expertise and resources.
  • The victims may only want compensation for the injuries suffered, while remaining indifferent to a possible desire for deterrence.[18]
  • Fear of retaliation may deter victims or witnesses of crimes from taking any action. Even in policed societies, fear may inhibit from reporting incidents or from co-operating in a trial.
  • Victims, on their own, may lack the economies of scale that could allow them to administer a penal system, let alone to collect any fines levied by a court.[19] Garoupa and Klerman (2002) warn that a rent-seeking government has as its primary motivation to maximize revenue and so, if offenders have sufficient wealth, a rent-seeking government will act more aggressively than a social-welfare-maximizing government in enforcing laws against minor crimes (usually with a fixed penalty such as parking and routine traffic violations), but more laxly in enforcing laws against major crimes.
  • As a result of the crime, victims may die or become incapacitated.

Labelling theory

The label of "crime" and the accompanying social stigma normally confine their scope to those activities seen as injurious to the general population or to the state, including some that cause serious loss or damage to individuals. Those who apply the labels of "crime" or "criminal" intend to assert the hegemony of a dominant population, or to reflect a consensus of condemnation for the identified behavior and to justify any punishments prescribed by the state (if standard processing tries and convicts an accused person of a crime).

History

Some religious communities regard sin as a crime; some may even highlight the crime of sin very early in legendary or mythological accounts of origins – note the tale of Adam and Eve and the theory of original sin. What one group considers a crime may cause or ignite war or conflict. However, the earliest known civilizations had codes of law, containing both civil and penal rules mixed together, though not always in recorded form.

Ancient Near East

The Sumerians produced the earliest surviving written codes.[20] Urukagina (reigned c. 2380 BC – c. 2360 BC, short chronology) had an early code that has not survived; a later king, Ur-Nammu, left the earliest extant written law system, the Code of Ur-Nammu (c. 2100 – c. 2050 BC), which prescribed a formal system of penalties for specific cases in 57 articles. The Sumerians later issued other codes, including the "code of Lipit-Ishtar". This code, from the 20th century BCE, contains some fifty articles, and scholars have reconstructed it by comparing several sources.

The Sumerian was deeply conscious of his personal rights and resented any encroachment on them, whether by his King, his superior, or his equal. No wonder that the Sumerians were the first to compile laws and law codes.

— Kramer[21]

Successive legal codes in Babylon, including the code of Hammurabi (c. 1790 BC), reflected Mesopotamian society's belief that law derived from the will of the gods (see Babylonian law).[22][23] Many states at this time functioned as theocracies, with codes of conduct largely religious in origin or reference. In the Sanskrit texts of Dharmaśāstra (c. 1250 BC), issues such as legal and religious duties, code of conduct, penalties and remedies, etc. have been discussed and forms one of the elaborate and earliest source of legal code.[24][25]

Sir Henry Maine studied the ancient codes available in his day, and failed to find any criminal law in the "modern" sense of the word.[26] While modern systems distinguish between offences against the "state" or "community", and offences against the "individual", the so-called penal law of ancient communities did not deal with "crimes" (Latin: crimina), but with "wrongs" (Latin: delicta). Thus the Hellenic laws treated all forms of theft, assault, rape, and murder as private wrongs, and left action for enforcement up to the victims or their survivors. The earliest systems seem to have lacked formal courts.[27][28]

Rome and its legacy in Europe

The Romans systematized law and applied their system across the Roman Empire. Again, the initial rules of Roman law regarded assaults as a matter of private compensation. The most significant Roman law concept involved dominion.[29] The pater familias owned all the family and its property (including slaves); the pater enforced matters involving interference with any property. The Commentaries of Gaius (written between 130 and 180 AD) on the Twelve Tables treated furtum (in modern parlance: "theft") as a tort.

Similarly, assault and violent robbery involved trespass as to the pater's property (so, for example, the rape of a slave could become the subject of compensation to the pater as having trespassed on his "property"), and breach of such laws created a vinculum juris (an obligation of law) that only the payment of monetary compensation (modern "damages") could discharge. Similarly, the consolidated Teutonic laws of the Germanic tribes,[30] included a complex system of monetary compensations for what courts would now consider the complete[citation needed] range of criminal offences against the person, from murder down.

Even though Rome abandoned its Britannic provinces around 400 AD, the Germanic mercenaries – who had largely become instrumental in enforcing Roman rule in Britannia – acquired ownership of land there and continued to use a mixture of Roman and Teutonic Law, with much written down under the early Anglo-Saxon kings.[31] But only when a more centralized English monarchy emerged following the Norman invasion, and when the kings of England attempted to assert power over the land and its peoples, did the modern concept emerge, namely of a crime not only as an offence against the "individual", but also as a wrong against the "state".[32]

This idea came from common law, and the earliest conception of a criminal act involved events of such major significance that the "state" had to usurp the usual functions of the civil tribunals, and direct a special law or privilegium against the perpetrator. All the earliest English criminal trials involved wholly extraordinary and arbitrary courts without any settled law to apply, whereas the civil (delictual) law operated in a highly developed and consistent manner (except where a king wanted to raise money by selling a new form of writ). The development of the idea that the "state" dispenses justice in a court only emerges in parallel with or after the emergence of the concept of sovereignty.

In continental Europe, Roman law persisted, but with a stronger influence from the Christian Church.[33] Coupled with the more diffuse political structure based on smaller feudal units, various legal traditions emerged, remaining more strongly rooted in Roman jurisprudence, but modified to meet the prevailing political climate.

In Scandinavia the effect of Roman law did not become apparent until the 17th century, and the courts grew out of the things – the assemblies of the people. The people decided the cases (usually with largest freeholders dominating). This system later gradually developed into a system with a royal judge nominating a number of the most esteemed men of the parish as his board, fulfilling the function of "the people" of yore.

From the Hellenic system onwards, the policy rationale for requiring the payment of monetary compensation for wrongs committed has involved the avoidance of feuding between clans and families.[34] If compensation could mollify families' feelings, this would help to keep the peace. On the other hand, the institution of oaths also played down the threat of feudal warfare. Both in archaic Greece and in medieval Scandinavia, an accused person walked free if he could get a sufficient number of male relatives to swear him not guilty. (Compare the United Nations Security Council, in which the veto power of the permanent members ensures that the organization does not become involved in crises where it could not enforce its decisions.)

These means of restraining private feuds did not always work, and sometimes prevented the fulfillment of justice. But in the earliest times the "state" did not always provide an independent policing force. Thus criminal law grew out of what 21st-century lawyers would call torts; and, in real terms, many acts and omissions classified as crimes actually overlap with civil-law concepts.

The development of sociological thought from the 19th century onwards prompted some fresh views on crime and criminality, and fostered the beginnings of criminology as a study of crime in society. Nietzsche noted a link between crime and creativity – in The Birth of Tragedy he asserted:[needs context] "The best and brightest that man can acquire he must obtain by crime". In the 20th century, Michel Foucault in Discipline and Punish made a study of criminalization as a coercive method of state control.

Types

The following classes of offences are used, or have been used, as legal terms:

Researchers and commentators have classified crimes into the following categories, in addition to those above:

Classification

By penalty

One can categorise crimes depending on the related punishment, with sentencing tariffs prescribed in line with the perceived seriousness of the offence. Thus fines and noncustodial sentences may address the crimes seen as least serious, with lengthy imprisonment or (in some jurisdictions) capital punishment reserved for the most serious.

Common law

Under the common law of England, crimes were classified as either treason, felony or misdemeanour, with treason sometimes being included with the felonies. This system was based on the perceived seriousness of the offence. It is still used in the United States but the distinction between felony and misdemeanour is abolished in England, Wales and Northern Ireland.

By mode of trial

The following classes of offence are based on mode of trial:

By origin

In common law countries, crimes may be categorised into common law offences and statutory offences. In the US, Australia and Canada (in particular), they are divided into federal crimes and under state crimes.

Reports, studies and organizations

There are several national and International organizations offering studies and statistics about global and local crime activity, such as United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime, the United States of America Overseas Security Advisory Council (OSAC) safety report or national reports generated by the law-enforcement authorities of EU state member reported to the Europol.

"Offence" in common law jurisdictions

In England and Wales, as well as in Hong Kong, the term "offence" means the same thing as "crime",[50] They are further split into:

Causes and correlates

Many different causes and correlates of crime have been proposed with varying degree of empirical support. They include socioeconomic, psychological, biological, and behavioral factors. Controversial topics include media violence research and effects of gun politics.

Emotional state (both chronic and current) have a tremendous impact on individual thought processes and, as a result, can be linked to criminal activities. The positive psychology concept of Broaden and Build posits that cognitive functioning expands when an individual is in a good-feeling emotional state and contracts as emotional state declines.[51] In positive emotional states an individual is able to consider more possible solutions to problems, but in lower emotional states fewer solutions can be ascertained. The narrowed thought-action repertoires can result in the only paths perceptible to an individual being ones they would never use if they saw an alternative, but if they can't conceive of the alternatives that carry less risk they will choose one that they can see. Criminals who commit even the most horrendous of crimes, such as mass murders, did not see another solution.[52]

International

 
Kang Kek Iew before the Cambodian Genocide Tribunal on July 20, 2009

Crimes defined by treaty as crimes against international law include:

From the point of view of state-centric law, extraordinary procedures (international courts or national courts operating with universal jurisdiction) may prosecute such crimes. Note the role of the International Criminal Court at The Hague in the Netherlands.[citation needed]

Occupational

Two common types of employee crime exist: embezzlement and wage theft.

The complexity and anonymity of computer systems may help criminal employees camouflage their operations. The victims of the most costly scams include banks, brokerage houses, insurance companies, and other large financial institutions.[53]

In the United States, it is estimated[by whom?] that $40 billion to $60 billion are lost annually due to all forms of wage theft.[54] This compares to national annual losses of $340 million due to robbery, $4.1 billion due to burglary, $5.3 billion due to larceny, and $3.8 billion due to auto theft in 2012.[55] In Singapore, as in the United States, wage theft was found to be widespread and severe. In a 2014 survey it was found that as many as one-third of low wage male foreign workers in Singapore, or about 130,000, were affected by wage theft from partial to full denial of pay.[56]

Liability

If a crime is committed, the individual responsible is considered to be liable for the crime. For liability to exist, the individual must be capable of understanding the criminal process and the relevant authority must have legitimate power to establish what constitutes a crime.[57]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b "Crime". Oxford English Dictionary Second Edition on CD-ROM. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2009.
  2. ^ a b Farmer, Lindsay: "Crime, definitions of", in Cane and Conoghan (editors), The New Oxford Companion to Law, Oxford University Press, 2008 (ISBN 978-0-19-929054-3), p. 263 (Google Books 2016-06-04 at the Wayback Machine).
  3. ^ In the United Kingdom, for instance, the definitions provided by section 243(2) of the Trade Union and Labour Relations (Consolidation) Act 1992 and by the Schedule to the Prevention of Crimes Act 1871.
  4. ^ a b Elizabeth A. Martin (2003). Oxford Dictionary of Law (7 ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-860756-4.
  5. ^ Easton, Mark (17 June 2010). "What is crime?". BBC News. from the original on 27 February 2013. Retrieved 10 June 2013.
  6. ^ Girgen, Jen (2003). "The Historical and Contemporary Prosecution and Punishment of Animals". Animal Law Journal. 9: 97. from the original on 29 December 2019. Retrieved 1 October 2017.
  7. ^ Quinney, Richard, "Structural Characteristics, Population Areas, and Crime Rates in the United States," The Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology and Police Science, 57(1), pp. 45–52
  8. ^ Ernest Klein, Klein's Comprehensive Etymological Dictionary of the English Language 2016-03-22 at the Wayback Machine
  9. ^ Bakaoukas, Michael. "The conceptualisation of 'Crime' in Classical Greek Antiquity: From the ancient Greek 'crime' (krima) as an intellectual error to the christian 'crime' (crimen) as a moral sin." ERCES ( European and International research group on crime, Social Philosophy and Ethics). 2005. . Archived from the original on 2011-09-28. Retrieved 2011-06-27.
  10. ^ Lamond, G. (2007-01-01). "What is a Crime?". Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. 27 (4): 609–632. doi:10.1093/ojls/gqm018. ISSN 0143-6503.
  11. ^ Canadian Law Dictionary, John A. Yogis, Q.C., Barrons: 2003
  12. ^ Thomas, Aquinas, Saint, 1225?-1274. (2002). On law, morality, and politics. Regan, Richard J., Baumgarth, William P. (2nd ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. ISBN 0872206637. OCLC 50423002.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  13. ^ Blackstone, William, 1723-1780. (1979). Commentaries on the laws of England. William Blackstone Collection (Library of Congress). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 41. ISBN 0226055361. OCLC 4832359.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  14. ^ Hart, H. L. A. (Herbert Lionel Adolphus), 1907-1992. (1994). The concept of law (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 0198761228. OCLC 31410701.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  15. ^ Dworkin, Ronald. (1978). Taking rights seriously : [with a new appendix, a response to critics]. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ISBN 0674867114. OCLC 4313351.
  16. ^ Finnis, John (2015). Natural Law & Natural Rights. 3.2 Natural law & (purely) positive law as concurrent dimensions of legal reasoning. OUP. ISBN 978-0199599141. from the original on 2019-08-06. Retrieved 2019-07-17. The moral standards...which Dworkin (in line with natural law theory) treats as capable of being morally objective & true, thus function as a direct source of law and...as already law, except when their fit with the whole set of social-fact sources in the relevant community is so weak that it would be more accurate (according to Dworkin) to say that judges who apply them are applying morality not law.
  17. ^ Bix, Brian H. (August 2015). "Kelsen, Hart, & legal normativity". 3.3 Law and morality. Revus - OpenEdition Journals. 34 (34). doi:10.4000/revus.3984. ...it was part of the task of a legal theorist to explain the 'normativity' or 'authority' of law, by which they meant 'our sense that 'legal' norms provide agents with special reasons for acting, reasons they would not have if the norm were not a 'legal' one'...this may be a matter calling more for a psychological or sociological explanation, rather than a philosophical one.
  18. ^ See Polinsky & Shavell (1997) on the fundamental divergence between the private and the social motivation for using the legal system.
  19. ^ See Polinsky (1980) on the enforcement of fines
  20. ^ Oppenheim (1964)
  21. ^ Kramer (1971: 4)
  22. ^ Driver and Mills (1952–55) and Skaist (1994)
  23. ^ The Babylonian laws. Driver, G. R. (Godfrey Rolles), 1892–1975; Miles, John C. (John Charles), Sir, 1870–1963. Eugene, Oregon: Wipf & Stock Pub. April 2007. ISBN 978-1556352294. OCLC 320934300.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  24. ^ Anuradha Jaiswal, Criminal Justice Tenets of Manusmriti – A Critique of the Ancient Hindu Code
  25. ^ Olivelle, Patrick. 2004. The Law Code of Manu. New York: Oxford UP.
  26. ^ Maine, Henry Sumner, 1822–1888 (1861). Ancient law : its connection with the early history of society, and its relation to modern ideas. Tucson. ISBN 0816510067. OCLC 13358229.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  27. ^ Gagarin, Michael. (1986). Early Greek law. London: University of California Press. ISBN 9780520909168. OCLC 43477491.
  28. ^ Garner, Richard, 1953- (1987). Law & society in classical Athens. New York: St. Martin's Press. ISBN 0312008562. OCLC 15365822.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  29. ^ Daube, David. (1969). Roman law: linguistic, social and philosophical aspects. Edinburgh: Edinburgh U.P. ISBN 0852240511. OCLC 22054.
  30. ^ Guterman, Simeon L. (Simeon Leonard), 1907- (1990). The principle of the personality of law in the Germanic kingdoms of western Europe from the fifth to the eleventh century. New York: P. Lang. ISBN 0820407313. OCLC 17731409.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  31. ^ Attenborough: 1963
  32. ^ Kern: 1948; Blythe: 1992; and Pennington: 1993
  33. ^ Vinogradoff (1909); Tierney: 1964, 1979
  34. ^ The concept of the pater familias acted as a unifying factor in extended kin groups, and the later practice of wergild functioned in this context.[citation needed]
  35. ^ a b For example, by the Visiting Forces Act 1952
  36. ^ a b For example, by section 31(1) of the Criminal Justice Act 1991, and by the Criminal Justice Act 2003
  37. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 22
  38. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 24
  39. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 25
  40. ^ E.g. Card, Cross and Jones: Criminal Law, 12th ed, 1992, chapter 17
  41. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 26
  42. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 27
  43. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 28
  44. ^ E.g. Card, Cross and Jones: Criminal Law, 12th ed, 1992, chapter 16
  45. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 29
  46. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 30
  47. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 31
  48. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 32
  49. ^ E.g. Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, chapter 33
  50. ^ Glanville Williams, Learning the Law, Eleventh Edition, Stevens, 1982, p. 3
  51. ^ Fredrickson, B.L. (2005). Positive Emotions broaden the scope of attention and though-action repertoires. Cognition and Emotion, 19: 313–332.
  52. ^ Baumeister, R.F. (2012). Human Evil: The myth of pure evil and the true causes of violence. In A.P. Association, M. Mikulincer, & P.R. Shaver (Eds.), The social psychology of morality: Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 367–380). Washington, DC
  53. ^ Sara Baase, A Gift of Fire: Social, Legal, and Ethical Issues for Computing and The Internet. Third Ed. "Employee Crime" (2008)
  54. ^ Michael De Groote, Michael De Groote (24 June 2014). . Desert News National. Archived from the original on 2 July 2014. Retrieved July 1, 2014.
  55. ^ "Crime in the United States 2012, Table 23". Uniform Crime Reports. Federal Bureau of Investigation. from the original on 2016-06-05.
  56. ^ Choo, Irene (1 September 2014). "Cheap foreign labour to spur economic growth – think deeper and harder". The Online Citizen. from the original on 14 October 2014.
  57. ^ Duff, R. (1998-06-01). "Law, language and community: some preconditions of criminal liability". Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. 18 (2): 189–206. doi:10.1093/ojls/18.2.189. ISSN 0143-6503.

References and further reading

  • Attenborough, F.L. (ed. and trans.) (1922). . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprint March 2006. The Lawbook Exchange, Ltd. ISBN 1-58477-583-1
  • Blythe, James M. (1992). Ideal Government and the Mixed Constitution in the Middle Ages. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-03167-3
  • Cohen, Stanley (1985). Visions of Social Control: Crime, Punishment, and Classification. Polity Press. ISBN 0-7456-0021-2
  • Foucault, Michel (1975). Discipline and Punish: the Birth of the Prison, New York: Random House.
  • Garoupa, Nuno & Klerman, Daniel. (2002). "Optimal Law Enforcement with a Rent-Seeking Government". American Law and Economics Review Vol. 4, No. 1. pp. 116–140.
  • Hart, H.L.A. (1972). Law, Liberty and Morality. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ISBN 0-8047-0154-7
  • Hitchins, Peter. A Brief History of Crime (2003) 2nd edition was issued as he Abolition of Liberty: The Decline of Order and Justice in England (2004)
  • Kalifa, Dominique. Vice, Crime, and Poverty: How the Western Imagination Invented the Underworld (Columbia University Press, 2019)
  • Kern, Fritz. (1948). Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages. Reprint edition (1985), Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
  • Kramer, Samuel Noah. (1971). The Sumerians: Their History, Culture, and Character. Chicago: University of Chicago. ISBN 0-226-45238-7
  • Maine, Henry Sumner. (1861). Ancient Law: Its Connection with the Early History of Society, and Its Relation to Modern Ideas. Reprint edition (1986). Tucson: University of Arizona Press. ISBN 0-8165-1006-7
  • Oppenheim, A. Leo (and Reiner, Erica as editor). (1964). Ancient Mesopotamia: Portrait of a Dead Civilization. Revised edition (September 15, 1977). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-63187-7
  • Pennington, Kenneth. (1993). The Prince and the Law, 1200–1600: Sovereignty and Rights in the Western Legal Tradition. Berkeley: University of California Press. ISBN 0-520-07995-7
  • Polinsky, A. Mitchell. (1980). "Private versus Public Enforcement of Fines". The Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. IX, No. 1, (January), pp. 105–127.
  • Polinsky, A. Mitchell & Shavell, Steven. (1997). On the Disutility and Discounting of Imprisonment and the Theory of Deterrence, NBER Working Papers 6259, National Bureau of Economic Research, Inc.
  • Skaist, Aaron Jacob. (1994). The Old Babylonian Loan Contract: Its History and Geography. Ramat Gan, Israel: Bar-Ilan University Press. ISBN 965-226-161-0
  • Théry, Julien. (2011). "Atrocitas/enormitas. Esquisse pour une histoire de la catégorie de 'crime énorme' du Moyen Âge à l'époque moderne", Clio@Themis, Revue électronique d'histoire du droit, n. 4 2015-02-08 at the Wayback Machine
  • Tierney, Brian. (1979). Church Law and Constitutional Thought in the Middle Ages. London: Variorum Reprints. ISBN 0-86078-036-8
  • Tierney, Brian (1988) [1964]. The Crisis of Church and State, 1050–1300: with selected documents (Reprint ed.). Toronto: University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-0-8020-6701-2.
  • Vinogradoff, Paul. (1909). Roman Law in Medieval Europe. Reprint edition (2004). Kessinger Publishing Co. ISBN 1-4179-4909-0

External links

crime, other, uses, disambiguation, criminal, disambiguation, criminals, disambiguation, ordinary, language, crime, unlawful, punishable, state, other, authority, term, crime, does, modern, criminal, have, simple, universally, accepted, definition, though, sta. For other uses see Crime disambiguation Criminal disambiguation and Criminals disambiguation In ordinary language a crime is an unlawful act punishable by a state or other authority 1 The term crime does not in modern criminal law have any simple and universally accepted definition 2 though statutory definitions have been provided for certain purposes 3 The most popular view is that crime is a category created by law in other words something is a crime if declared as such by the relevant and applicable law 2 One proposed definition is that a crime or offence or criminal offence is an act harmful not only to some individual but also to a community society or the state a public wrong Such acts are forbidden and punishable by law 1 4 The notion that acts such as murder rape and theft are to be prohibited exists worldwide 5 What precisely is a criminal offence is defined by the criminal law of each relevant jurisdiction While many have a catalogue of crimes called the criminal code in some common law nations no such comprehensive statute exists The state government has the power to severely restrict one s liberty for committing a crime In modern societies there are procedures to which investigations and trials must adhere If found guilty an offender may be sentenced to a form of reparation such as a community sentence or depending on the nature of their offence to undergo imprisonment life imprisonment or in some jurisdictions death Some jurisdictions sentence individuals to programs to emphasize or provide for their rehabilitation while most jurisdictions sentence individuals with the goal of punishing them or a mix of the aforementioned practices citation needed Usually to be classified as a crime the act of doing something criminal actus reus must with certain exceptions be accompanied by the intention to do something criminal mens rea 4 While every crime violates the law not every violation of the law counts as a crime Breaches of private law torts and breaches of contract are not automatically punished by the state but can be enforced through civil procedure Contents 1 Overview 2 Etymology 3 Definition 3 1 Legalism 3 2 Sociology 4 Foundational systems 4 1 Natural law theory 4 2 Religion 5 Criminalization 6 Labelling theory 7 History 7 1 Ancient Near East 7 2 Rome and its legacy in Europe 8 Types 9 Classification 9 1 By penalty 9 2 Common law 9 3 By mode of trial 9 4 By origin 10 Reports studies and organizations 11 Offence in common law jurisdictions 12 Causes and correlates 13 International 14 Occupational 15 Liability 16 See also 17 Notes 18 References and further reading 19 External linksOverviewWhen informal relationships prove insufficient to establish and maintain a desired social order a government or a state may impose more formalized or stricter systems of social control With institutional and legal machinery at their disposal agents of the state can compel populations to conform to codes and can opt to punish or attempt to reform those who do not conform Authorities employ various mechanisms to regulate encouraging or discouraging certain behaviors in general Governing or administering agencies may for example codify rules into laws police citizens and visitors to ensure that they comply with those laws and implement other policies and practices that legislators or administrators have prescribed with the aim of discouraging or preventing crime In addition authorities provide remedies and sanctions and collectively these constitute a criminal justice system Legal sanctions vary widely in their severity they may include for example incarceration of temporary character aimed at reforming the convict Some jurisdictions have penal codes written to inflict permanent harsh punishments legal mutilation capital punishment or life without parole Usually a natural person perpetrates a crime but legal persons may also commit crimes Historically several premodern societies believed that non human animals were capable of committing crimes and prosecuted and punished them accordingly 6 The sociologist Richard Quinney has written about the relationship between society and crime When Quinney states crime is a social phenomenon he envisages both how individuals conceive crime and how populations perceive it based on societal norms 7 EtymologyThe word crime is derived from the Latin root cernō meaning I decide I give judgment Originally the Latin word crimen meant charge or cry of distress 8 The Ancient Greek word krima krima with which the Latin crimen is cognate typically referred to an intellectual mistake or an offense against the community rather than a private or moral wrong 9 In 13th century English crime meant sinfulness according to the Online Etymology Dictionary It was probably brought to England as Old French crimne 12th century form of Modern French crime from Latin crimen in the genitive case criminis In Latin crimen could have signified any one of the following charge indictment accusation crime fault offense The word may derive from the Latin cernere to decide to sift see crisis mapped on Kairos and Chronos But Ernest Klein citing Karl Brugmann rejects this and suggests cri men which originally would have meant cry of distress Thomas G Tucker suggests a root in cry words and refers to English plaint plaintiff and so on The meaning offense punishable by law dates from the late 14th century The Latin word is glossed in Old English by facen also deceit fraud treachery cf fake Crime wave is first attested in 1893 in American English DefinitionLegalism Main article Legalism Western philosophy In the scope of law crime is defined by the criminal law of a given jurisdiction including all actions that are subject to criminal procedure There is no limit to what can be considered a crime in a legal system so there may not be a unifying principle used to determine whether an action should be designated as a crime 10 Legislatures can pass laws called mala prohibita that define crimes against social norms These laws vary from time to time and from place to place note variations in gambling laws for example and the prohibition or encouragement of duelling in history Other crimes called mala in se count as outlawed in almost all societies murder theft and rape for example English criminal law and the related criminal law of Commonwealth countries can define offences that the courts alone have developed over the years without any actual legislation common law offences The courts used the concept of malum in se to develop various common law offences 11 In the military sphere authorities can prosecute both regular crimes and specific acts such as mutiny or desertion under martial law codes that either supplant or extend civil codes in times of for example war Many constitutions contain provisions to curtail freedoms and criminalize otherwise tolerated behaviors under a state of emergency in case of war natural disaster or civil unrest Undesired activities at such times may include assembly in the streets violation of curfew or possession of firearms Sociology A normative definition views crime as deviant behavior that violates prevailing norms cultural standards prescribing how humans ought to behave normally This approach considers the complex realities surrounding the concept of crime and seeks to understand how changing social political psychological and economic conditions may affect changing definitions of crime and the form of the legal law enforcement and penal responses made by society These structural realities remain fluid and often contentious For example as cultures change and the political environment shifts societies may criminalise or decriminalise certain behaviours which directly affects the statistical crime rates influence the allocation of resources for the enforcement of laws and re influence the general public opinion Similarly changes in the collection and or calculation of data on crime may affect the public perceptions of the extent of any given crime problem All such adjustments to crime statistics allied with the experience of people in their everyday lives shape attitudes on the extent to which the state should use law or social engineering to enforce or encourage any particular social norm Behaviour can be controlled and influenced by a society in many ways without having to resort to the criminal justice system Indeed in those cases where no clear consensus exists on a given norm the drafting of criminal law by the group in power to prohibit the behaviour of another group may seem to some observers an improper limitation of the second group s freedom and the ordinary members of society have less respect for the law or laws in general whether the authorities actually enforce the disputed law or not Foundational systemsNatural law theory Justifying the state s use of force to coerce compliance with its laws has proven a consistent theoretical problem One of the earliest justifications involved the theory of natural law This posits that the nature of the world or of human beings underlies the standards of morality or constructs them Thomas Aquinas wrote in the 13th century the rule and measure of human acts is the reason which is the first principle of human acts 12 He regarded people as by nature rational beings concluding that it becomes morally appropriate that they should behave in a way that conforms to their rational nature Thus to be valid any law must conform to natural law and coercing people to conform to that law is morally acceptable In the 1760s William Blackstone described the thesis 13 This law of nature being co eval with mankind and dictated by God himself is of course superior in obligation to any other It is binding over all the globe in all countries and at all times no human laws are of any validity if contrary to this and such of them as are valid derive all their force and all their authority mediately or immediately from this original But John Austin 1790 1859 an early positivist applied utilitarianism in accepting the calculating nature of human beings and the existence of an objective morality He denied that the legal validity of a norm depends on whether its content conforms to morality Thus in Austinian terms a moral code can objectively determine what people ought to do the law can embody whatever norms the legislature decrees to achieve social utility but every individual remains free to choose what to do Similarly H L A Hart saw the law as an aspect of sovereignty with lawmakers able to adopt any law as a means to a moral end 14 Thus the necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of a proposition of law involved internal logic and consistency and that the state s agents used state power with responsibility Ronald Dworkin rejects Hart s theory and proposes that all individuals should expect the equal respect and concern of those who govern them as a fundamental political right He offers a theory of compliance overlaid by a theory of deference the citizen s duty to obey the law and a theory of enforcement which identifies the legitimate goals of enforcement and punishment Legislation must conform to a theory of legitimacy which describes the circumstances under which a particular person or group is entitled to make law and a theory of legislative justice which describes the law they are entitled or obliged to make 15 There are natural law theorists who have accepted the idea of enforcing the prevailing morality as a primary function of the law 16 This view entails the problem that it makes any moral criticism of the law impossible if conformity with natural law forms a necessary condition for legal validity all valid law must by definition count as morally just Thus on this line of reasoning the legal validity of a norm necessarily entails its moral justice 17 One can solve this problem by granting some degree of moral relativism and accepting that norms may evolve over time and therefore one can criticize the continued enforcement of old laws in the light of the current norms People may find such law acceptable but the use of state power to coerce citizens to comply with that law lacks moral justification More recent conceptions of the theory characterise crime as the violation of individual rights Since society considers so many rights as natural hence the term right rather than man made what constitutes a crime also counts as natural in contrast to laws seen as man made Adam Smith illustrates this view saying that a smuggler would be an excellent citizen had not the laws of his country made that a crime which nature never meant to be so Natural law theory therefore distinguishes between criminality which derives from human nature and illegality which originates with the interests of those in power Lawyers sometimes express the two concepts with the phrases malum in se and malum prohibitum respectively They regard a crime malum in se as inherently criminal whereas a crime malum prohibitum the argument goes counts as criminal only because the law has decreed it so It follows from this view that one can perform an illegal act without committing a crime while a criminal act could be perfectly legal Many Enlightenment thinkers such as Adam Smith and the American Founding Fathers subscribed to this view to some extent and it remains influential among so called classical liberals citation needed and libertarians citation needed Religion Main article Religious law See also Category Crimes in religion Religious sentiment often becomes a contributory factor of crime In the 1819 anti Jewish Hep Hep riots in Wurzburg rioters attacked Jewish businesses and destroyed property Different religious traditions may promote distinct norms of behaviour and these in turn may clash or harmonise with the perceived interests of a state Socially accepted or imposed religious morality has influenced secular jurisdictions on issues that may otherwise concern only an individual s conscience Activities sometimes criminalized on religious grounds include for example alcohol consumption prohibition abortion and stem cell research In various historical and present day societies institutionalized religions have established systems of earthly justice that punish crimes against the divine will and against specific devotional organizational and other rules under specific codes such as Roman Catholic canon law and Islamic Shariah Law CriminalizationMain article Criminalization The spiked heads of executed criminals once adorned the gatehouse of the medieval London Bridge One can view criminalization as a procedure deployed by society as a preemptive harm reduction device using the threat of punishment as a deterrent to anyone proposing to engage in the behavior causing harm The state becomes involved because governing entities can become convinced that the costs of not criminalizing through allowing the harms to continue unabated outweigh the costs of criminalizing it restricting individual liberty for example to minimize harm to others citation needed States control the process of criminalization because Even if victims recognize their own role as victims they may not have the resources to investigate and seek legal redress for the injuries suffered the enforcers formally appointed by the state often have better access to expertise and resources The victims may only want compensation for the injuries suffered while remaining indifferent to a possible desire for deterrence 18 Fear of retaliation may deter victims or witnesses of crimes from taking any action Even in policed societies fear may inhibit from reporting incidents or from co operating in a trial Victims on their own may lack the economies of scale that could allow them to administer a penal system let alone to collect any fines levied by a court 19 Garoupa and Klerman 2002 warn that a rent seeking government has as its primary motivation to maximize revenue and so if offenders have sufficient wealth a rent seeking government will act more aggressively than a social welfare maximizing government in enforcing laws against minor crimes usually with a fixed penalty such as parking and routine traffic violations but more laxly in enforcing laws against major crimes As a result of the crime victims may die or become incapacitated Labelling theoryFurther information Labeling theory The criminal The label of crime and the accompanying social stigma normally confine their scope to those activities seen as injurious to the general population or to the state including some that cause serious loss or damage to individuals Those who apply the labels of crime or criminal intend to assert the hegemony of a dominant population or to reflect a consensus of condemnation for the identified behavior and to justify any punishments prescribed by the state if standard processing tries and convicts an accused person of a crime HistorySome religious communities regard sin as a crime some may even highlight the crime of sin very early in legendary or mythological accounts of origins note the tale of Adam and Eve and the theory of original sin What one group considers a crime may cause or ignite war or conflict However the earliest known civilizations had codes of law containing both civil and penal rules mixed together though not always in recorded form Ancient Near EastThe Sumerians produced the earliest surviving written codes 20 Urukagina reigned c 2380 BC c 2360 BC short chronology had an early code that has not survived a later king Ur Nammu left the earliest extant written law system the Code of Ur Nammu c 2100 c 2050 BC which prescribed a formal system of penalties for specific cases in 57 articles The Sumerians later issued other codes including the code of Lipit Ishtar This code from the 20th century BCE contains some fifty articles and scholars have reconstructed it by comparing several sources The Sumerian was deeply conscious of his personal rights and resented any encroachment on them whether by his King his superior or his equal No wonder that the Sumerians were the first to compile laws and law codes Kramer 21 Successive legal codes in Babylon including the code of Hammurabi c 1790 BC reflected Mesopotamian society s belief that law derived from the will of the gods see Babylonian law 22 23 Many states at this time functioned as theocracies with codes of conduct largely religious in origin or reference In the Sanskrit texts of Dharmasastra c 1250 BC issues such as legal and religious duties code of conduct penalties and remedies etc have been discussed and forms one of the elaborate and earliest source of legal code 24 25 Sir Henry Maine studied the ancient codes available in his day and failed to find any criminal law in the modern sense of the word 26 While modern systems distinguish between offences against the state or community and offences against the individual the so called penal law of ancient communities did not deal with crimes Latin crimina but with wrongs Latin delicta Thus the Hellenic laws treated all forms of theft assault rape and murder as private wrongs and left action for enforcement up to the victims or their survivors The earliest systems seem to have lacked formal courts 27 28 Rome and its legacy in Europe This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Crime news newspapers books scholar JSTOR June 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message The Romans systematized law and applied their system across the Roman Empire Again the initial rules of Roman law regarded assaults as a matter of private compensation The most significant Roman law concept involved dominion 29 The pater familias owned all the family and its property including slaves the pater enforced matters involving interference with any property The Commentaries of Gaius written between 130 and 180 AD on the Twelve Tables treated furtum in modern parlance theft as a tort Similarly assault and violent robbery involved trespass as to the pater s property so for example the rape of a slave could become the subject of compensation to the pater as having trespassed on his property and breach of such laws created a vinculum juris an obligation of law that only the payment of monetary compensation modern damages could discharge Similarly the consolidated Teutonic laws of the Germanic tribes 30 included a complex system of monetary compensations for what courts would now update consider the complete citation needed range of criminal offences against the person from murder down Even though Rome abandoned its Britannic provinces around 400 AD the Germanic mercenaries who had largely become instrumental in enforcing Roman rule in Britannia acquired ownership of land there and continued to use a mixture of Roman and Teutonic Law with much written down under the early Anglo Saxon kings 31 But only when a more centralized English monarchy emerged following the Norman invasion and when the kings of England attempted to assert power over the land and its peoples did the modern concept emerge namely of a crime not only as an offence against the individual but also as a wrong against the state 32 This idea came from common law and the earliest conception of a criminal act involved events of such major significance that the state had to usurp the usual functions of the civil tribunals and direct a special law or privilegium against the perpetrator All the earliest English criminal trials involved wholly extraordinary and arbitrary courts without any settled law to apply whereas the civil delictual law operated in a highly developed and consistent manner except where a king wanted to raise money by selling a new form of writ The development of the idea that the state dispenses justice in a court only emerges in parallel with or after the emergence of the concept of sovereignty In continental Europe Roman law persisted but with a stronger influence from the Christian Church 33 Coupled with the more diffuse political structure based on smaller feudal units various legal traditions emerged remaining more strongly rooted in Roman jurisprudence but modified to meet the prevailing political climate In Scandinavia the effect of Roman law did not become apparent until the 17th century and the courts grew out of the things the assemblies of the people The people decided the cases usually with largest freeholders dominating This system later gradually developed into a system with a royal judge nominating a number of the most esteemed men of the parish as his board fulfilling the function of the people of yore From the Hellenic system onwards the policy rationale for requiring the payment of monetary compensation for wrongs committed has involved the avoidance of feuding between clans and families 34 If compensation could mollify families feelings this would help to keep the peace On the other hand the institution of oaths also played down the threat of feudal warfare Both in archaic Greece and in medieval Scandinavia an accused person walked free if he could get a sufficient number of male relatives to swear him not guilty Compare the United Nations Security Council in which the veto power of the permanent members ensures that the organization does not become involved in crises where it could not enforce its decisions These means of restraining private feuds did not always work and sometimes prevented the fulfillment of justice But in the earliest times the state did not always provide an independent policing force Thus criminal law grew out of what 21st century lawyers would call torts and in real terms many acts and omissions classified as crimes actually overlap with civil law concepts The development of sociological thought from the 19th century onwards prompted some fresh views on crime and criminality and fostered the beginnings of criminology as a study of crime in society Nietzsche noted a link between crime and creativity in The Birth of Tragedy he asserted needs context The best and brightest that man can acquire he must obtain by crime In the 20th century Michel Foucault in Discipline and Punish made a study of criminalization as a coercive method of state control TypesThe following classes of offences are used or have been used as legal terms Offence against the person 35 Violent offence 36 Sexual offence 36 Offence against property 35 Researchers and commentators have classified crimes into the following categories in addition to those above Forgery personation and cheating 37 Firearms and offensive weapons 38 Offences against the state offences against the Crown and Government 39 or political offences 40 Harmful or dangerous drugs 41 Offences against religion and public worship 42 Offences against public justice 43 or offences against the administration of public justice 44 Public order offence 45 Commerce financial markets and insolvency 46 Offences against public morals and public policy 47 Motor vehicle offences 48 Conspiracy incitement and attempt to commit crime 49 Inchoate offence Juvenile delinquency Victimless crimeClassificationBy penalty One can categorise crimes depending on the related punishment with sentencing tariffs prescribed in line with the perceived seriousness of the offence Thus fines and noncustodial sentences may address the crimes seen as least serious with lengthy imprisonment or in some jurisdictions capital punishment reserved for the most serious Common law Under the common law of England crimes were classified as either treason felony or misdemeanour with treason sometimes being included with the felonies This system was based on the perceived seriousness of the offence It is still used in the United States but the distinction between felony and misdemeanour is abolished in England Wales and Northern Ireland By mode of trial The following classes of offence are based on mode of trial Indictable only offence Indictable offence Hybrid offence a k a either way offence in England and Wales Summary offence a k a infraction in the USBy origin In common law countries crimes may be categorised into common law offences and statutory offences In the US Australia and Canada in particular they are divided into federal crimes and under state crimes Reports studies and organizationsThere are several national and International organizations offering studies and statistics about global and local crime activity such as United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime the United States of America Overseas Security Advisory Council OSAC safety report or national reports generated by the law enforcement authorities of EU state member reported to the Europol Offence in common law jurisdictionsIn England and Wales as well as in Hong Kong the term offence means the same thing as crime 50 They are further split into Summary offences Indictable offencesCauses and correlatesMain article Causes and correlates of crime Many different causes and correlates of crime have been proposed with varying degree of empirical support They include socioeconomic psychological biological and behavioral factors Controversial topics include media violence research and effects of gun politics Emotional state both chronic and current have a tremendous impact on individual thought processes and as a result can be linked to criminal activities The positive psychology concept of Broaden and Build posits that cognitive functioning expands when an individual is in a good feeling emotional state and contracts as emotional state declines 51 In positive emotional states an individual is able to consider more possible solutions to problems but in lower emotional states fewer solutions can be ascertained The narrowed thought action repertoires can result in the only paths perceptible to an individual being ones they would never use if they saw an alternative but if they can t conceive of the alternatives that carry less risk they will choose one that they can see Criminals who commit even the most horrendous of crimes such as mass murders did not see another solution 52 InternationalMain article International criminal law Kang Kek Iew before the Cambodian Genocide Tribunal on July 20 2009 Crimes defined by treaty as crimes against international law include Crimes against peace Crimes of apartheid Forced disappearance Genocide Incitement to genocide Piracy Sexual slavery Slavery Torture Waging a war of aggression War crimesFrom the point of view of state centric law extraordinary procedures international courts or national courts operating with universal jurisdiction may prosecute such crimes Note the role of the International Criminal Court at The Hague in the Netherlands citation needed OccupationalMain article Occupational crime Two common types of employee crime exist embezzlement and wage theft The complexity and anonymity of computer systems may help criminal employees camouflage their operations The victims of the most costly scams include banks brokerage houses insurance companies and other large financial institutions 53 In the United States it is estimated by whom that 40 billion to 60 billion are lost annually due to all forms of wage theft 54 This compares to national annual losses of 340 million due to robbery 4 1 billion due to burglary 5 3 billion due to larceny and 3 8 billion due to auto theft in 2012 55 In Singapore as in the United States wage theft was found to be widespread and severe In a 2014 survey it was found that as many as one third of low wage male foreign workers in Singapore or about 130 000 were affected by wage theft from partial to full denial of pay 56 LiabilityMain article Legal liability If a crime is committed the individual responsible is considered to be liable for the crime For liability to exist the individual must be capable of understanding the criminal process and the relevant authority must have legitimate power to establish what constitutes a crime 57 See also Law portalCrime displacement Crime science Federal Crime Law and order politics National Museum of Crime amp Punishment in Washington DC Organized crime also knows as the criminal underworld Category Age of criminal responsibilityNotes a b Crime Oxford English Dictionary Second Edition on CD ROM Oxford Oxford University Press 2009 a b Farmer Lindsay Crime definitions of in Cane and Conoghan editors The New Oxford Companion to Law Oxford University Press 2008 ISBN 978 0 19 929054 3 p 263 Google Books Archived 2016 06 04 at the Wayback Machine In the United Kingdom for instance the definitions provided by section 243 2 of the Trade Union and Labour Relations Consolidation Act 1992 and by the Schedule to the Prevention of Crimes Act 1871 a b Elizabeth A Martin 2003 Oxford Dictionary of Law 7 ed Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 860756 4 Easton Mark 17 June 2010 What is crime BBC News Archived from the original on 27 February 2013 Retrieved 10 June 2013 Girgen Jen 2003 The Historical and Contemporary Prosecution and Punishment of Animals Animal Law Journal 9 97 Archived from the original on 29 December 2019 Retrieved 1 October 2017 Quinney Richard Structural Characteristics Population Areas and Crime Rates in the United States The Journal of Criminal Law Criminology and Police Science 57 1 pp 45 52 Ernest Klein Klein s Comprehensive Etymological Dictionary of the English Language Archived 2016 03 22 at the Wayback Machine Bakaoukas Michael The conceptualisation of Crime in Classical Greek Antiquity From the ancient Greek crime krima as an intellectual error to the christian crime crimen as a moral sin ERCES European and International research group on crime Social Philosophy and Ethics 2005 Ercesoqr Archived from the original on 2011 09 28 Retrieved 2011 06 27 Lamond G 2007 01 01 What is a Crime Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 4 609 632 doi 10 1093 ojls gqm018 ISSN 0143 6503 Canadian Law Dictionary John A Yogis Q C Barrons 2003 Thomas Aquinas Saint 1225 1274 2002 On law morality and politics Regan Richard J Baumgarth William P 2nd ed Indianapolis Hackett Pub ISBN 0872206637 OCLC 50423002 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Blackstone William 1723 1780 1979 Commentaries on the laws of England William Blackstone Collection Library of Congress Chicago University of Chicago Press p 41 ISBN 0226055361 OCLC 4832359 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Hart H L A Herbert Lionel Adolphus 1907 1992 1994 The concept of law 2nd ed Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN 0198761228 OCLC 31410701 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Dworkin Ronald 1978 Taking rights seriously with a new appendix a response to critics Cambridge Harvard University Press ISBN 0674867114 OCLC 4313351 Finnis John 2015 Natural Law amp Natural Rights 3 2 Natural law amp purely positive law as concurrent dimensions of legal reasoning OUP ISBN 978 0199599141 Archived from the original on 2019 08 06 Retrieved 2019 07 17 The moral standards which Dworkin in line with natural law theory treats as capable of being morally objective amp true thus function as a direct source of law and as already law except when their fit with the whole set of social fact sources in the relevant community is so weak that it would be more accurate according to Dworkin to say that judges who apply them are applying morality not law Bix Brian H August 2015 Kelsen Hart amp legal normativity 3 3 Law and morality Revus OpenEdition Journals 34 34 doi 10 4000 revus 3984 it was part of the task of a legal theorist to explain the normativity or authority of law by which they meant our sense that legal norms provide agents with special reasons for acting reasons they would not have if the norm were not a legal one this may be a matter calling more for a psychological or sociological explanation rather than a philosophical one See Polinsky amp Shavell 1997 on the fundamental divergence between the private and the social motivation for using the legal system See Polinsky 1980 on the enforcement of fines Oppenheim 1964 Kramer 1971 4 Driver and Mills 1952 55 and Skaist 1994 The Babylonian laws Driver G R Godfrey Rolles 1892 1975 Miles John C John Charles Sir 1870 1963 Eugene Oregon Wipf amp Stock Pub April 2007 ISBN 978 1556352294 OCLC 320934300 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint others link Anuradha Jaiswal Criminal Justice Tenets of Manusmriti A Critique of the Ancient Hindu Code Olivelle Patrick 2004 The Law Code of Manu New York Oxford UP Maine Henry Sumner 1822 1888 1861 Ancient law its connection with the early history of society and its relation to modern ideas Tucson ISBN 0816510067 OCLC 13358229 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Gagarin Michael 1986 Early Greek law London University of California Press ISBN 9780520909168 OCLC 43477491 Garner Richard 1953 1987 Law amp society in classical Athens New York St Martin s Press ISBN 0312008562 OCLC 15365822 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Daube David 1969 Roman law linguistic social and philosophical aspects Edinburgh Edinburgh U P ISBN 0852240511 OCLC 22054 Guterman Simeon L Simeon Leonard 1907 1990 The principle of the personality of law in the Germanic kingdoms of western Europe from the fifth to the eleventh century New York P Lang ISBN 0820407313 OCLC 17731409 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Attenborough 1963 Kern 1948 Blythe 1992 and Pennington 1993 Vinogradoff 1909 Tierney 1964 1979 The concept of the pater familias acted as a unifying factor in extended kin groups and the later practice of wergild functioned in this context citation needed a b For example by the Visiting Forces Act 1952 a b For example by section 31 1 of the Criminal Justice Act 1991 and by the Criminal Justice Act 2003 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 22 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 24 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 25 E g Card Cross and Jones Criminal Law 12th ed 1992 chapter 17 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 26 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 27 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 28 E g Card Cross and Jones Criminal Law 12th ed 1992 chapter 16 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 29 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 30 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 31 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 32 E g Archbold Criminal Pleading Evidence and Practice 1999 chapter 33 Glanville Williams Learning the Law Eleventh Edition Stevens 1982 p 3 Fredrickson B L 2005 Positive Emotions broaden the scope of attention and though action repertoires Cognition and Emotion 19 313 332 Baumeister R F 2012 Human Evil The myth of pure evil and the true causes of violence In A P Association M Mikulincer amp P R Shaver Eds The social psychology of morality Exploring the causes of good and evil pp 367 380 Washington DC Sara Baase A Gift of Fire Social Legal and Ethical Issues for Computing and The Internet Third Ed Employee Crime 2008 Michael De Groote Michael De Groote 24 June 2014 Wage theft How employers steal millions from workers every week Desert News National Archived from the original on 2 July 2014 Retrieved July 1 2014 Crime in the United States 2012 Table 23 Uniform Crime Reports Federal Bureau of Investigation Archived from the original on 2016 06 05 Choo Irene 1 September 2014 Cheap foreign labour to spur economic growth think deeper and harder The Online Citizen Archived from the original on 14 October 2014 Duff R 1998 06 01 Law language and community some preconditions of criminal liability Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 2 189 206 doi 10 1093 ojls 18 2 189 ISSN 0143 6503 References and further readingAttenborough F L ed and trans 1922 The Laws of the Earliest English Kings Cambridge Cambridge University Press Reprint March 2006 The Lawbook Exchange Ltd ISBN 1 58477 583 1 Blythe James M 1992 Ideal Government and the Mixed Constitution in the Middle Ages Princeton Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 03167 3 Cohen Stanley 1985 Visions of Social Control Crime Punishment and Classification Polity Press ISBN 0 7456 0021 2 Foucault Michel 1975 Discipline and Punish the Birth of the Prison New York Random House Garoupa Nuno amp Klerman Daniel 2002 Optimal Law Enforcement with a Rent Seeking Government American Law and Economics Review Vol 4 No 1 pp 116 140 Hart H L A 1972 Law Liberty and Morality Stanford Stanford University Press ISBN 0 8047 0154 7 Hitchins Peter A Brief History of Crime 2003 2nd edition was issued as he Abolition of Liberty The Decline of Order and Justice in England 2004 Kalifa Dominique Vice Crime and Poverty How the Western Imagination Invented the Underworld Columbia University Press 2019 Kern Fritz 1948 Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages Reprint edition 1985 Westport Conn Greenwood Press Kramer Samuel Noah 1971 The Sumerians Their History Culture and Character Chicago University of Chicago ISBN 0 226 45238 7 Maine Henry Sumner 1861 Ancient Law Its Connection with the Early History of Society and Its Relation to Modern Ideas Reprint edition 1986 Tucson University of Arizona Press ISBN 0 8165 1006 7 Oppenheim A Leo and Reiner Erica as editor 1964 Ancient Mesopotamia Portrait of a Dead Civilization Revised edition September 15 1977 Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 0 226 63187 7 Pennington Kenneth 1993 The Prince and the Law 1200 1600 Sovereignty and Rights in the Western Legal Tradition Berkeley University of California Press ISBN 0 520 07995 7 Polinsky A Mitchell 1980 Private versus Public Enforcement of Fines The Journal of Legal Studies Vol IX No 1 January pp 105 127 Polinsky A Mitchell amp Shavell Steven 1997 On the Disutility and Discounting of Imprisonment and the Theory of Deterrence NBER Working Papers 6259 National Bureau of Economic Research Inc Skaist Aaron Jacob 1994 The Old Babylonian Loan Contract Its History and Geography Ramat Gan Israel Bar Ilan University Press ISBN 965 226 161 0 Thery Julien 2011 Atrocitas enormitas Esquisse pour une histoire de la categorie de crime enorme du Moyen Age a l epoque moderne Clio Themis Revue electronique d histoire du droit n 4 Archived 2015 02 08 at the Wayback Machine Tierney Brian 1979 Church Law and Constitutional Thought in the Middle Ages London Variorum Reprints ISBN 0 86078 036 8 Tierney Brian 1988 1964 The Crisis of Church and State 1050 1300 with selected documents Reprint ed Toronto University of Toronto Press ISBN 978 0 8020 6701 2 Vinogradoff Paul 1909 Roman Law in Medieval Europe Reprint edition 2004 Kessinger Publishing Co ISBN 1 4179 4909 0External links Wikiquote has quotations related to Crime Look up crime in Wiktionary the free dictionary Wikimedia Commons has media related to Crimes Wikivoyage has travel information for crime Crime at Curlie Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Crime amp oldid 1130111401, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.