fbpx
Wikipedia

Infinity (philosophy)

In philosophy and theology, infinity is explored in articles under headings such as the Absolute, God, and Zeno's paradoxes.

In Greek philosophy, for example in Anaximander, 'the Boundless' is the origin of all that is. He took the beginning or first principle to be an endless, unlimited primordial mass (ἄπειρον, apeiron). The Jain metaphysics and mathematics were the first to define and delineate different "types" of infinities.[1] The work of the mathematician Georg Cantor first placed infinity into a coherent mathematical framework. Keenly aware of his departure from traditional wisdom, Cantor also presented a comprehensive historical and philosophical discussion of infinity.[2] In Christian theology, for example in the work of Duns Scotus, the infinite nature of God invokes a sense of being without constraint, rather than a sense of being unlimited in quantity.

Early thinking edit

Egyptian edit

...how sad is the descent in the land of silence, the wakeful sleeps, he who did not slumber at night lies still forever. The scorners say: The dwelling place of the inhabitants of the West is deep and dark, it has no door, no window, no light to illuminate it, no north wind to refresh the heart, the sun does not rise there, but they lie every day in darkness - the guardian has been taken away to the land of infinity...

— an Egyptian mourner [3]

Greek edit

Anaximander edit

An early engagement with the idea of infinity was made by Anaximander who considered infinity to be a foundational and primitive basis of reality.[4] Anaximander was the first in the Greek philosophical tradition to propose that the universe was infinite.[5]

Anaxagoras edit

Anaxagoras (500–428 BCE) was of the opinion that matter of the universe had an innate capacity for infinite division.[6]

The Atomists edit

A group of thinkers of ancient Greece (later identified as the Atomists) all similarly considered matter to be made of an infinite number of structures as considered by imagining dividing or separating matter from itself an infinite number of times.[7]

Aristotle and after edit

Aristotle, alive for the period 384–322 BCE, is credited with being the root of a field of thought, in his influence of succeeding thinking for a period spanning more than one subsequent millennium, by his rejection of the idea of actual infinity.[8]

In Book 3 of the work entitled Physics, written by Aristotle, Aristotle deals with the concept of infinity in terms of his notion of actuality and of potentiality.[9][10][11]

... It is always possible to think of a larger number: for the number of times a magnitude can be bisected is infinite. Hence the infinite is potential, never actual; the number of parts that can be taken always surpasses any assigned number.

— Physics 207b8

This is often called potential infinity; however, there are two ideas mixed up with this. One is that it is always possible to find a number of things that surpasses any given number, even if there are not actually such things. The other is that we may quantify over infinite sets without restriction. For example,  , which reads, "for any integer n, there exists an integer m > n such that P(m)". The second view is found in a clearer form by medieval writers such as William of Ockham:

Sed omne continuum est actualiter existens. Igitur quaelibet pars sua est vere existens in rerum natura. Sed partes continui sunt infinitae quia non tot quin plures, igitur partes infinitae sunt actualiter existentes.

But every continuum is actually existent. Therefore any of its parts is really existent in nature. But the parts of the continuum are infinite because there are not so many that there are not more, and therefore the infinite parts are actually existent.

The parts are actually there, in some sense. However, on this view, no infinite magnitude can have a number, for whatever number we can imagine, there is always a larger one: "There are not so many (in number) that there are no more."

Aristotle's views on the continuum foreshadow some topological aspects of modern mathematical theories of the continuum. Aristotle's emphasis on the connectedness of the continuum may have inspired—in different ways—modern philosophers and mathematicians such as Charles Sanders Peirce, Cantor, and LEJ Brouwer.[12][13]

Among the scholastics, Aquinas also argued against the idea that infinity could be in any sense complete or a totality.

Aristotle deals with infinity in the context of the prime mover, in Book 7 of the same work, the reasoning of which was later studied and commented on by Simplicius.[14]

Roman edit

Plotinus edit

Plotinus considered infinity, while he was alive, during the 3rd century A.D.[4]

Simplicius edit

Simplicius,[15] alive circa 490 to 560 AD,[16] thought the concept "Mind" was infinite.[15]

Augustine edit

Augustine thought infinity to be "incomprehensible for the human mind".[15]

Early Indian thinking edit

The Jain upanga āgama Surya Prajnapti (c. 400 BC) classifies all numbers into three sets: enumerable, innumerable, and infinite. Each of these was further subdivided into three orders:

  • Enumerable: lowest, intermediate and highest
  • Innumerable: nearly innumerable, truly innumerable and innumerably innumerable
  • Infinite: nearly infinite, truly infinite, infinitely infinite
 
Jain theory of numbers (See IIIrd section for various infinities)

The Jains were the first to discard the idea that all infinities were the same or equal. They recognized different types of infinities: infinite in length (one dimension), infinite in area (two dimensions), infinite in volume (three dimensions), and infinite perpetually (infinite number of dimensions).

According to Singh (1987), Joseph (2000) and Agrawal (2000), the highest enumerable number N of the Jains corresponds to the modern concept of aleph-null   (the cardinal number of the infinite set of integers 1, 2, ...), the smallest cardinal transfinite number. The Jains also defined a whole system of infinite cardinal numbers, of which the highest enumerable number N is the smallest.

In the Jaina work on the theory of sets, two basic types of infinite numbers are distinguished. On both physical and ontological grounds, a distinction was made between asaṃkhyāta ("countless, innumerable") and ananta ("endless, unlimited"), between rigidly bounded and loosely bounded infinities.

Views from the Renaissance to modern times edit

Galileo edit

Galileo Galilei (February 1564 - January 1642 [17]) discussed the example of comparing the square numbers {1, 4, 9, 16, ...} with the natural numbers {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} as follows:

1 → 1
2 → 4
3 → 9
4 → 16

It appeared by this reasoning as though a "set" (Galileo did not use the terminology) which is naturally smaller than the "set" of which it is a part (since it does not contain all the members) is in some sense the same "size". Galileo found no way around this problem:

So far as I see we can only infer that the totality of all numbers is infinite, that the number of squares is infinite, and that the number of their roots is infinite; neither is the number of squares less than the totality of all numbers, nor the latter greater than the former; and finally the attributes "equal," "greater," and "less," are not applicable to infinite, but only to finite, quantities.

— On two New Sciences, 1638

The idea that size can be measured by one-to-one correspondence is today known as Hume's principle, although Hume, like Galileo, believed the principle could not be applied to the infinite. The same concept, applied by Georg Cantor, is used in relation to infinite sets.

Thomas Hobbes edit

Famously, the ultra-empiricist Hobbes ( April 1588 - December 1679 [18]) tried to defend the idea of a potential infinity in light of the discovery, by Evangelista Torricelli, of a figure (Gabriel's Horn) whose surface area is infinite, but whose volume is finite. Not reported, this motivation of Hobbes came too late as curves having infinite length yet bounding finite areas were known much before.

John Locke edit

Locke ( August 1632 - October 1704 [19]) in common with most of the empiricist philosophers, also believed that we can have no proper idea of the infinite. They believed all our ideas were derived from sense data or "impressions," and since all sensory impressions are inherently finite, so too are our thoughts and ideas. Our idea of infinity is merely negative or privative.

Whatever positive ideas we have in our minds of any space, duration, or number, let them be never so great, they are still finite; but when we suppose an inexhaustible remainder, from which we remove all bounds, and wherein we allow the mind an endless progression of thought, without ever completing the idea, there we have our idea of infinity... yet when we would frame in our minds the idea of an infinite space or duration, that idea is very obscure and confused, because it is made up of two parts very different, if not inconsistent. For let a man frame in his mind an idea of any space or number, as great as he will, it is plain the mind rests and terminates in that idea; which is contrary to the idea of infinity, which consists in a supposed endless progression.

— Essay, II. xvii. 7., author's emphasis

He considered that in considerations on the subject of eternity, which he classified as an infinity, humans are likely to make mistakes.[20]

Modern philosophical views edit

Modern discussion of the infinite is now regarded as part of set theory and mathematics. Contemporary philosophers of mathematics engage with the topic of infinity and generally acknowledge its role in mathematical practice. But, although set theory is now widely accepted, this was not always so. Influenced by L.E.J Brouwer and verificationism in part, Wittgenstein (April 1889 Vienna - April 1951 Cambridge, England [21]), made an impassioned attack upon axiomatic set theory, and upon the idea of the actual infinite, during his "middle period".[22]

Does the relation   correlate the class of all numbers with one of its subclasses? No. It correlates any arbitrary number with another, and in that way we arrive at infinitely many pairs of classes, of which one is correlated with the other, but which are never related as class and subclass. Neither is this infinite process itself in some sense or other such a pair of classes... In the superstition that   correlates a class with its subclass, we merely have yet another case of ambiguous grammar.

— Philosophical Remarks § 141, cf Philosophical Grammar p. 465

Unlike the traditional empiricists, he thought that the infinite was in some way given to sense experience.

... I can see in space the possibility of any finite experience... we recognize [the] essential infinity of space in its smallest part." "[Time] is infinite in the same sense as the three-dimensional space of sight and movement is infinite, even if in fact I can only see as far as the walls of my room.

... what is infinite about endlessness is only the endlessness itself.

Emmanuel Levinas edit

The philosopher Emmanuel Levinas ( January 1906, Lithuania - December 25 1995, Paris [23] ) uses infinity to designate that which cannot be defined or reduced to knowledge or power. In Levinas' magnum opus Totality and Infinity he says :

...infinity is produced in the relationship of the same with the other, and how the particular and the personal, which are unsurpassable, as it were magnetize the very field in which the production of infinity is enacted...

The idea of infinity is not an incidental notion forged by a subjectivity to reflect the case of an entity encountering on the outside nothing that limits it, overflowing every limit, and thereby infinite. The production of the infinite entity is inseparable from the idea of infinity, for it is precisely in the disproportion between the idea of infinity and the infinity of which it is the idea that this exceeding of limits is produced. The idea of infinity is the mode of being, the infinition, of infinity... All knowing qua intentionality already presupposes the idea of infinity, which is preeminently non-adequation.

— p. 26-27

Levinas also wrote a work entitled Philosophy and the Idea of Infinity, which was published during 1957.[24]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Stewart, Ian (2017). Infinity: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875523-4.
  2. ^ Newstead, A. (2009). "Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind" (PDF). American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. 83 (4): 533–553. doi:10.5840/acpq200983444.
  3. ^ Henri Frankfort citing Kees, Zeitschrift für aegyptische Sprache in - Ancient Egyptian Religion: An Interpretation, p.108, Courier Corporation, 22 June 2012, ISBN 048614495X Consulted 2017-06-May
  4. ^ a b F. LeRon Shults (2005-11-01). Reforming the Doctrine of God (footnote 4. of page 99). Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing, 326 pages. ISBN 9780802829887. Retrieved 2015-06-26.
  5. ^ A.A. Long (1999-05-28). The Cambridge companion to Early Greek philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 127. ISBN 978-0521446679. Retrieved 2016-03-18.
  6. ^ James Fieser (2008). The History of Philosophy: A Short Survey. The University of Tennessee at Martin. Retrieved 2016-03-14.
  7. ^ J.J. O'Connor, E.F. Robertson (February 2002). Infinity. School of Computer Science - University of St Andrews. Retrieved 2016-03-13.
  8. ^ Rudy Rucker. Infinity: Mathematics. Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 2016-03-13.
  9. ^ Wolfgang Achtner (2011-02-07). Infinity: New Research Frontiers - Chapter 1 : Infinity as a Transformative concept in Science and Theology (p.22). Cambridge University Press, 7 Feb 2011, edited by Revd Dr Michael Heller, Dr W. Hugh Woodin. ISBN 978-1107003873. Retrieved 2015-06-21.
  10. ^ Z. Bechler (1995). Aristotle's Theory of Actuality (p.119). SUNY Press, 1995, 270 pages, SUNY series in ancient Greek philosophy. ISBN 978-0791422403. Retrieved 2015-06-21.
  11. ^ John Bowin. Aristotelian Infinity (PDF). University of California - Santa Cruz. Retrieved 2015-06-24.
  12. ^ Newstead, A.G.J. (2001). Aristotle and modern mathematical theories of the continuum, in Aristotle and Contemporary Science II. Frankfurt: Peter Lang. pp. 113–129.
  13. ^ White, Michael (1992). The Continuous and the Discrete. Oxford University Press.
  14. ^ R. Sorabji (C. Hagen) (2014-04-10). Simplicius: On Aristotle Physics 7 (page 1.). A&C Black, 10 Apr 2014, 202 pages, Ancient Commentators on Aristotle. ISBN 978-0801429927. Retrieved 2015-06-25.
  15. ^ a b c Dr Adam Drozdek (2013-05-28). Greek Philosophers as Theologians: The Divine Arche. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd. ISBN 978-1409477570.
  16. ^ J.J. O'Connor and E.F. Robertson (April 1999). Simplicius.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  17. ^ J.J. O'Connor, E.F. Robertson (2002). "Galileo Galilei". St Andrews University. Retrieved 2016-04-21.
  18. ^ T. Sorell (30 October 2014). "Thomas Hobbes (English philosopher)". Britannica. Retrieved 2016-04-21.
  19. ^ G.A.J. Rogers (2015-12-14). "John Locke, English philosopher". Britannica. Retrieved 2016-04-21.
  20. ^ Philosophical beauties selected from the works of John Locke - p.237 T.Hurst 1802 [Retrieved 2015-3-28](ed. Locke writes: And hence it is, that in disputes and reasonings concerning eternity, or any other infinite, we are apt to blunder, and involve ourselves in manifest absurdities...)
  21. ^ R. Monk (8 April 2016). "Ludwig Wittgenstein, British philosopher". Britannica. Retrieved 2016-04-21.
  22. ^ See also Asenjo, F. G.; Tamburino, J. (1975). "Logic of antinomies". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 16: 17–44. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093891610.
  23. ^ Bergo, Bettina (23 July 2006). "Emmanual Levinas". Stanford University. Retrieved 2016-04-21.
  24. ^ E. Levinas - Collected Philosophical Papers (p.47) (Translated by A. Lingis) Springer Science & Business Media, 31 March 1987 ISBN 9024733952 [Retrieved 2015-05-01]

References edit

External links edit

  • Thomas Taylor - A Dissertation on the Philosophy of Aristotle, in Four Books. In which his principle physical and metaphysical dogmas are unfolded, and it is shown, from undubitable evidence, that his philosophy has not been accurately known since the destruction of the Greeks. The insufficiency also of the philosophy that has been substituted by the moderns for that of Aristotle, is demonstrated published by Robert Wilks, London 1812

infinity, philosophy, this, article, about, philosophical, concept, mathematical, concept, infinity, other, uses, infinity, disambiguation, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, . This article is about the philosophical concept For the mathematical concept see Infinity For other uses see Infinity disambiguation This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations February 2012 Learn how and when to remove this message This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Infinity philosophy news newspapers books scholar JSTOR June 2007 Learn how and when to remove this message Learn how and when to remove this message In philosophy and theology infinity is explored in articles under headings such as the Absolute God and Zeno s paradoxes In Greek philosophy for example in Anaximander the Boundless is the origin of all that is He took the beginning or first principle to be an endless unlimited primordial mass ἄpeiron apeiron The Jain metaphysics and mathematics were the first to define and delineate different types of infinities 1 The work of the mathematician Georg Cantor first placed infinity into a coherent mathematical framework Keenly aware of his departure from traditional wisdom Cantor also presented a comprehensive historical and philosophical discussion of infinity 2 In Christian theology for example in the work of Duns Scotus the infinite nature of God invokes a sense of being without constraint rather than a sense of being unlimited in quantity Contents 1 Early thinking 1 1 Egyptian 1 2 Greek 1 2 1 Anaximander 1 2 2 Anaxagoras 1 2 3 The Atomists 1 2 4 Aristotle and after 1 3 Roman 1 3 1 Plotinus 1 3 2 Simplicius 1 3 3 Augustine 1 4 Early Indian thinking 2 Views from the Renaissance to modern times 2 1 Galileo 2 2 Thomas Hobbes 2 3 John Locke 3 Modern philosophical views 3 1 Emmanuel Levinas 4 See also 5 Notes 6 References 7 External linksEarly thinking editFurther information History of infinity Egyptian edit Main article Heh god This section needs expansion You can help by adding to it November 2019 how sad is the descent in the land of silence the wakeful sleeps he who did not slumber at night lies still forever The scorners say The dwelling place of the inhabitants of the West is deep and dark it has no door no window no light to illuminate it no north wind to refresh the heart the sun does not rise there but they lie every day in darkness the guardian has been taken away to the land of infinity an Egyptian mourner 3 Greek edit Anaximander edit An early engagement with the idea of infinity was made by Anaximander who considered infinity to be a foundational and primitive basis of reality 4 Anaximander was the first in the Greek philosophical tradition to propose that the universe was infinite 5 Anaxagoras edit Anaxagoras 500 428 BCE was of the opinion that matter of the universe had an innate capacity for infinite division 6 The Atomists edit A group of thinkers of ancient Greece later identified as the Atomists all similarly considered matter to be made of an infinite number of structures as considered by imagining dividing or separating matter from itself an infinite number of times 7 Aristotle and after edit Aristotle alive for the period 384 322 BCE is credited with being the root of a field of thought in his influence of succeeding thinking for a period spanning more than one subsequent millennium by his rejection of the idea of actual infinity 8 In Book 3 of the work entitled Physics written by Aristotle Aristotle deals with the concept of infinity in terms of his notion of actuality and of potentiality 9 10 11 It is always possible to think of a larger number for the number of times a magnitude can be bisected is infinite Hence the infinite is potential never actual the number of parts that can be taken always surpasses any assigned number Physics 207b8 This is often called potential infinity however there are two ideas mixed up with this One is that it is always possible to find a number of things that surpasses any given number even if there are not actually such things The other is that we may quantify over infinite sets without restriction For example n Z m Z m gt n P m displaystyle forall n in mathbb Z exists m in mathbb Z m gt n wedge P m nbsp which reads for any integer n there exists an integer m gt n such that P m The second view is found in a clearer form by medieval writers such as William of Ockham Sed omne continuum est actualiter existens Igitur quaelibet pars sua est vere existens in rerum natura Sed partes continui sunt infinitae quia non tot quin plures igitur partes infinitae sunt actualiter existentes But every continuum is actually existent Therefore any of its parts is really existent in nature But the parts of the continuum are infinite because there are not so many that there are not more and therefore the infinite parts are actually existent The parts are actually there in some sense However on this view no infinite magnitude can have a number for whatever number we can imagine there is always a larger one There are not so many in number that there are no more Aristotle s views on the continuum foreshadow some topological aspects of modern mathematical theories of the continuum Aristotle s emphasis on the connectedness of the continuum may have inspired in different ways modern philosophers and mathematicians such as Charles Sanders Peirce Cantor and LEJ Brouwer 12 13 Among the scholastics Aquinas also argued against the idea that infinity could be in any sense complete or a totality Aristotle deals with infinity in the context of the prime mover in Book 7 of the same work the reasoning of which was later studied and commented on by Simplicius 14 Roman edit Plotinus edit Plotinus considered infinity while he was alive during the 3rd century A D 4 Simplicius edit Simplicius 15 alive circa 490 to 560 AD 16 thought the concept Mind was infinite 15 Augustine edit Augustine thought infinity to be incomprehensible for the human mind 15 Early Indian thinking edit The Jain upanga agama Surya Prajnapti c 400 BC classifies all numbers into three sets enumerable innumerable and infinite Each of these was further subdivided into three orders Enumerable lowest intermediate and highest Innumerable nearly innumerable truly innumerable and innumerably innumerable Infinite nearly infinite truly infinite infinitely infinite nbsp Jain theory of numbers See IIIrd section for various infinities The Jains were the first to discard the idea that all infinities were the same or equal They recognized different types of infinities infinite in length one dimension infinite in area two dimensions infinite in volume three dimensions and infinite perpetually infinite number of dimensions According to Singh 1987 Joseph 2000 and Agrawal 2000 the highest enumerable number N of the Jains corresponds to the modern concept of aleph null ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 nbsp the cardinal number of the infinite set of integers 1 2 the smallest cardinal transfinite number The Jains also defined a whole system of infinite cardinal numbers of which the highest enumerable number N is the smallest In the Jaina work on the theory of sets two basic types of infinite numbers are distinguished On both physical and ontological grounds a distinction was made between asaṃkhyata countless innumerable and ananta endless unlimited between rigidly bounded and loosely bounded infinities Views from the Renaissance to modern times editGalileo edit Main article Galileo s paradox Galileo Galilei February 1564 January 1642 17 discussed the example of comparing the square numbers 1 4 9 16 with the natural numbers 1 2 3 4 as follows 1 1 2 4 3 9 4 16 It appeared by this reasoning as though a set Galileo did not use the terminology which is naturally smaller than the set of which it is a part since it does not contain all the members is in some sense the same size Galileo found no way around this problem So far as I see we can only infer that the totality of all numbers is infinite that the number of squares is infinite and that the number of their roots is infinite neither is the number of squares less than the totality of all numbers nor the latter greater than the former and finally the attributes equal greater and less are not applicable to infinite but only to finite quantities On two New Sciences 1638 The idea that size can be measured by one to one correspondence is today known as Hume s principle although Hume like Galileo believed the principle could not be applied to the infinite The same concept applied by Georg Cantor is used in relation to infinite sets Thomas Hobbes edit Famously the ultra empiricist Hobbes April 1588 December 1679 18 tried to defend the idea of a potential infinity in light of the discovery by Evangelista Torricelli of a figure Gabriel s Horn whose surface area is infinite but whose volume is finite Not reported this motivation of Hobbes came too late as curves having infinite length yet bounding finite areas were known much before John Locke edit Locke August 1632 October 1704 19 in common with most of the empiricist philosophers also believed that we can have no proper idea of the infinite They believed all our ideas were derived from sense data or impressions and since all sensory impressions are inherently finite so too are our thoughts and ideas Our idea of infinity is merely negative or privative Whatever positive ideas we have in our minds of any space duration or number let them be never so great they are still finite but when we suppose an inexhaustible remainder from which we remove all bounds and wherein we allow the mind an endless progression of thought without ever completing the idea there we have our idea of infinity yet when we would frame in our minds the idea of an infinite space or duration that idea is very obscure and confused because it is made up of two parts very different if not inconsistent For let a man frame in his mind an idea of any space or number as great as he will it is plain the mind rests and terminates in that idea which is contrary to the idea of infinity which consists in a supposed endless progression Essay II xvii 7 author s emphasis He considered that in considerations on the subject of eternity which he classified as an infinity humans are likely to make mistakes 20 Modern philosophical views editModern discussion of the infinite is now regarded as part of set theory and mathematics Contemporary philosophers of mathematics engage with the topic of infinity and generally acknowledge its role in mathematical practice But although set theory is now widely accepted this was not always so Influenced by L E J Brouwer and verificationism in part Wittgenstein April 1889 Vienna April 1951 Cambridge England 21 made an impassioned attack upon axiomatic set theory and upon the idea of the actual infinite during his middle period 22 Does the relation m 2 n displaystyle m 2n nbsp correlate the class of all numbers with one of its subclasses No It correlates any arbitrary number with another and in that way we arrive at infinitely many pairs of classes of which one is correlated with the other but which are never related as class and subclass Neither is this infinite process itself in some sense or other such a pair of classes In the superstition that m 2 n displaystyle m 2n nbsp correlates a class with its subclass we merely have yet another case of ambiguous grammar Philosophical Remarks 141 cf Philosophical Grammar p 465 Unlike the traditional empiricists he thought that the infinite was in some way given to sense experience I can see in space the possibility of any finite experience we recognize the essential infinity of space in its smallest part Time is infinite in the same sense as the three dimensional space of sight and movement is infinite even if in fact I can only see as far as the walls of my room what is infinite about endlessness is only the endlessness itself Emmanuel Levinas edit The philosopher Emmanuel Levinas January 1906 Lithuania December 25 1995 Paris 23 uses infinity to designate that which cannot be defined or reduced to knowledge or power In Levinas magnum opus Totality and Infinity he says infinity is produced in the relationship of the same with the other and how the particular and the personal which are unsurpassable as it were magnetize the very field in which the production of infinity is enacted The idea of infinity is not an incidental notion forged by a subjectivity to reflect the case of an entity encountering on the outside nothing that limits it overflowing every limit and thereby infinite The production of the infinite entity is inseparable from the idea of infinity for it is precisely in the disproportion between the idea of infinity and the infinity of which it is the idea that this exceeding of limits is produced The idea of infinity is the mode of being the infinition of infinity All knowing qua intentionality already presupposes the idea of infinity which is preeminently non adequation p 26 27 Levinas also wrote a work entitled Philosophy and the Idea of Infinity which was published during 1957 24 See also editInfinite monkey theorem Measure problem cosmology Philosophy of space and timeNotes edit Stewart Ian 2017 Infinity A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 875523 4 Newstead A 2009 Cantor on Infinity in Nature Number and the Divine Mind PDF American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 83 4 533 553 doi 10 5840 acpq200983444 Henri Frankfort citing Kees Zeitschrift fur aegyptische Sprache in Ancient Egyptian Religion An Interpretation p 108 Courier Corporation 22 June 2012 ISBN 048614495X Consulted 2017 06 May a b F LeRon Shults 2005 11 01 Reforming the Doctrine of God footnote 4 of page 99 Wm B Eerdmans Publishing 326 pages ISBN 9780802829887 Retrieved 2015 06 26 A A Long 1999 05 28 The Cambridge companion to Early Greek philosophy Cambridge University Press p 127 ISBN 978 0521446679 Retrieved 2016 03 18 James Fieser 2008 The History of Philosophy A Short Survey The University of Tennessee at Martin Retrieved 2016 03 14 J J O Connor E F Robertson February 2002 Infinity School of Computer Science University of St Andrews Retrieved 2016 03 13 Rudy Rucker Infinity Mathematics Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 2016 03 13 Wolfgang Achtner 2011 02 07 Infinity New Research Frontiers Chapter 1 Infinity as a Transformative concept in Science and Theology p 22 Cambridge University Press 7 Feb 2011 edited by Revd Dr Michael Heller Dr W Hugh Woodin ISBN 978 1107003873 Retrieved 2015 06 21 Z Bechler 1995 Aristotle s Theory of Actuality p 119 SUNY Press 1995 270 pages SUNY series in ancient Greek philosophy ISBN 978 0791422403 Retrieved 2015 06 21 John Bowin Aristotelian Infinity PDF University of California Santa Cruz Retrieved 2015 06 24 Newstead A G J 2001 Aristotle and modern mathematical theories of the continuum in Aristotle and Contemporary Science II Frankfurt Peter Lang pp 113 129 White Michael 1992 The Continuous and the Discrete Oxford University Press R Sorabji C Hagen 2014 04 10 Simplicius On Aristotle Physics 7 page 1 A amp C Black 10 Apr 2014 202 pages Ancient Commentators on Aristotle ISBN 978 0801429927 Retrieved 2015 06 25 a b c Dr Adam Drozdek 2013 05 28 Greek Philosophers as Theologians The Divine Arche Ashgate Publishing Ltd ISBN 978 1409477570 J J O Connor and E F Robertson April 1999 Simplicius a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint numeric names authors list link J J O Connor E F Robertson 2002 Galileo Galilei St Andrews University Retrieved 2016 04 21 T Sorell 30 October 2014 Thomas Hobbes English philosopher Britannica Retrieved 2016 04 21 G A J Rogers 2015 12 14 John Locke English philosopher Britannica Retrieved 2016 04 21 Philosophical beauties selected from the works of John Locke p 237 T Hurst 1802 Retrieved 2015 3 28 ed Locke writes And hence it is that in disputes and reasonings concerning eternity or any other infinite we are apt to blunder and involve ourselves in manifest absurdities R Monk 8 April 2016 Ludwig Wittgenstein British philosopher Britannica Retrieved 2016 04 21 See also Asenjo F G Tamburino J 1975 Logic of antinomies Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16 17 44 doi 10 1305 ndjfl 1093891610 Bergo Bettina 23 July 2006 Emmanual Levinas Stanford University Retrieved 2016 04 21 E Levinas Collected Philosophical Papers p 47 Translated by A Lingis Springer Science amp Business Media 31 March 1987 ISBN 9024733952 Retrieved 2015 05 01 References editD P Agrawal 2000 Ancient Jaina Mathematics an Introduction Infinity Foundation L C Jain 1973 Set theory in the Jaina school of mathematics Indian Journal of History of Science George G Joseph 2000 The Crest of the Peacock Non European Roots of Mathematics 2nd ed Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 14 027778 4 A Newstead 2001 Aristotle and Modern Mathematical Theories of the Continuum in Aristotle and Contemporary Science II D Sfendoni Mentzou J Hattiangadi and D M Johnson eds Frankfurt Peter Lang 2001 113 129 ISBN 0820441473 A Newstead 2009 Cantor on Infinity in Nature Number and the Divine Mind American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 83 4 533 553 O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F Jaina mathematics MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews Ian Pearce 2002 Jainism MacTutor History of Mathematics archive N Singh 1988 Jaina Theory of Actual Infinity and Transfinite Numbers Journal of Asiatic Society Vol 30 External links editThomas Taylor A Dissertation on the Philosophy of Aristotle in Four Books In which his principle physical and metaphysical dogmas are unfolded and it is shown from undubitable evidence that his philosophy has not been accurately known since the destruction of the Greeks The insufficiency also of the philosophy that has been substituted by the moderns for that of Aristotle is demonstrated published by Robert Wilks London 1812 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Infinity philosophy amp oldid 1188203556, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.