fbpx
Wikipedia

Real number

In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, continuous means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences.[a] Every real number can be almost uniquely represented by an infinite decimal expansion.[b][1]

A symbol for the set of real numbers

The real numbers are fundamental in calculus (and more generally in all mathematics), in particular by their role in the classical definitions of limits, continuity and derivatives.[c]

The set of real numbers is denoted R or [2] and is sometimes called "the reals".[3] The adjective real, used in the 17th century by René Descartes, distinguishes real numbers from imaginary numbers such as the square roots of −1.[4]

The real numbers include the rational numbers, such as the integer −5 and the fraction 4 / 3. The rest of the real numbers are called irrational numbers, and include algebraic numbers (such as the square root 2 = 1.414...) and transcendental numbers (such as π = 3.1415...).[4]

Real numbers can be thought of as all points on a line called the number line or real line, where the points corresponding to integers (..., −2, −1, 0, 1, 2, ...) are equally spaced.

Conversely, analytic geometry is the association of points on lines (especially axis lines) to real numbers such that geometric displacements are proportional to differences between corresponding numbers.

The informal descriptions above of the real numbers are not sufficient for ensuring the correctness of proofs of theorems involving real numbers. The realization that a better definition was needed, and the elaboration of such a definition was a major development of 19th-century mathematics and is the foundation of real analysis, the study of real functions and real-valued sequences. A current axiomatic definition is that real numbers form the unique (up to an isomorphism) Dedekind-complete ordered field.[d] Other common definitions of real numbers include equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences (of rational numbers), Dedekind cuts, and infinite decimal representations. All these definitions satisfy the axiomatic definition and are thus equivalent.

Characterizing properties

Real numbers are completely characterized by their fundamental properties that can be summarized by saying that they form an ordered field that is Dedekind complete. Here, "completely characterized" means that there a unique isomorphism between any two Dedekind complete ordered fields, and thus that their elements have exactly the same properties. This implies that one can manipulate real numbers and computing with them, without knowing how they can be defined; this is what mathematicians and physicists did during several centuries before the first formal definition were provided in the second half of the 19th century. See Construction of the real numbers for details about these formal definitions and the proof of their equivalence.

Arithmetic

The real numbers form an ordered field. Intuitively, this means that methods and rules of elementary arithmetic apply to them. More precisely, there are two binary operations, addition and multiplication, and a total order that have the following properties.

  • The addition of two real numbers a and b produce a real number denoted   which is the sum of a and b.
  • The multiplication of two real numbers a and b produce a real number denoted     or   which is the product of a and b.
  • Addition and multiplication are both commutative, which means that   and   for every real numbers a and b.
  • Addition and multiplication are both associative, which means that   and   for every real numbers a, b and c, and that parentheses may be omitted in both cases.
  • Multiplication is distributive over addition, which means that   for every real numbers a, b and c.
  • There is a real number called zero and denoted 0 which is an additive identity, which means that   for every real number a.
  • There is a real number denoted 1 which is an multiplicative identity, which means that   for every real number a.
  • Every real number a has an additive inverse denoted   This means that   for every real number a.
  • Every nonzero real number a has a multiplicative inverse denoted   or   This means that   for every nonzero real number a.
  • The total order is denoted   being that it is a total order means two properties: given two real numbers a and b, exactly one of     or   is true; and if   and   then one has also  
  • The order is compatible with addition and multiplication, which means that   implies   for every real number c, and   is implied by   and  

Many other properties can be deduced from the above ones. In particular:

  •   for every real number a
  •  
  •   for every nonzero real number a

Auxiliary operations

Several other operations are commonly used, which can be deduced from the above ones.

  • Subtraction: the subtraction of two real numbers a and b results in the sum of a and the additive inverse b of b; that is,
     
  • Division: the division of a real number a by a nonzero real number b is denoted   or   and defined as the multiplication of a with the multiplicative inverse of b; that is,
     
  • Absolute value: the absolute value of a real number a, denoted   measures its distance from zero, and is defined as
     

Auxiliary order relations

The total order that is considered above is denoted   and read as "a is less than b". Three other order relations are also commonly used:

  • Greater than:   read as "a is greater than b", is defined as   if and only if  
  • Less than or equal to:   read as "a is less than or equal to b" or "a is not greater than b", is defined as   or equivalently as  
  • Greater than or equal to:   read as "a is greater than or equal to b" or "a is not less than b", is defined as   or equivalently as  

Dedekind completeness

Previous properties do not distinguish real numbers from rational numbers. This distinction is provided by Dedekind completeness, which states that every upper bounded set of real numbers admits a least upper bound. This means the following. A set of real numbers   is upper bounded if there is a real number   such that   for all   such a   is called a upper bound of   So, Dedekind completeness means that, if S is upper bounded, it has a upper bound that is less than any other upper bound.

Dedekind completeness implies other sorts of completeness (see below), but also has some important consequences.

  • Archimedean property: for every real number x, there is an integer n such that   (take,   where   is the least upper bound of the integers less than n).
  • Equivalently, if x is a positive real number, there is a positive integer n such that  .
  • Every positive real number x has a positive square root, that is, there exist a positive real number   such that  
  • Every univariate polynomial of odd degree with real coefficients has at least one real root (if the leading coefficient is positive, take the least upper bound of real numbers for which the value of the polynomial is negative).

The last two properties are summarized by saying that the real numbers form a real closed field. This implies the real version of the fundamental theorem of algebra, namely that every polynomial with real coefficients can be factored into polynomials with real coefficients of degree at most two.

Topological completeness

A main reason for using real numbers is so that many sequences have limits. More formally, the reals are complete (in the sense of metric spaces or uniform spaces, which is a different sense than the Dedekind completeness of the order in the previous section):

A sequence (xn) of real numbers is called a Cauchy sequence if for any ε > 0 there exists an integer N (possibly depending on ε) such that the distance |xnxm| is less than ε for all n and m that are both greater than N. This definition, originally provided by Cauchy, formalizes the fact that the xn eventually come and remain arbitrarily close to each other.

A sequence (xn) converges to the limit x if its elements eventually come and remain arbitrarily close to x, that is, if for any ε > 0 there exists an integer N (possibly depending on ε) such that the distance |xnx| is less than ε for n greater than N.

Every convergent sequence is a Cauchy sequence, and the converse is true for real numbers, and this means that the topological space of the real numbers is complete.

The set of rational numbers is not complete. For example, the sequence (1; 1.4; 1.41; 1.414; 1.4142; 1.41421; ...), where each term adds a digit of the decimal expansion of the positive square root of 2, is Cauchy but it does not converge to a rational number (in the real numbers, in contrast, it converges to the positive square root of 2).

The completeness property of the reals is the basis on which calculus, and, more generally mathematical analysis are built. In particular, the test that a sequence is a Cauchy sequence allows proving that a sequence has a limit, without computing it, and even without knowing it.

For example, the standard series of the exponential function

 

converges to a real number for every x, because the sums

 

can be made arbitrarily small (independently of M) by choosing N sufficiently large. This proves that the sequence is Cauchy, and thus converges, showing that   is well defined for every x.

"The complete ordered field"

The real numbers are often described as "the complete ordered field", a phrase that can be interpreted in several ways.

First, an order can be lattice-complete. It is easy to see that no ordered field can be lattice-complete, because it can have no largest element (given any element z, z + 1 is larger).

Additionally, an order can be Dedekind-complete, see § Axiomatic approach. The uniqueness result at the end of that section justifies using the word "the" in the phrase "complete ordered field" when this is the sense of "complete" that is meant. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Dedekind cuts, since that construction starts from an ordered field (the rationals) and then forms the Dedekind-completion of it in a standard way.

These two notions of completeness ignore the field structure. However, an ordered group (in this case, the additive group of the field) defines a uniform structure, and uniform structures have a notion of completeness; the description in § Completeness is a special case. (We refer to the notion of completeness in uniform spaces rather than the related and better known notion for metric spaces, since the definition of metric space relies on already having a characterization of the real numbers.) It is not true that   is the only uniformly complete ordered field, but it is the only uniformly complete Archimedean field, and indeed one often hears the phrase "complete Archimedean field" instead of "complete ordered field". Every uniformly complete Archimedean field must also be Dedekind-complete (and vice versa), justifying using "the" in the phrase "the complete Archimedean field". This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Cauchy sequences (the construction carried out in full in this article), since it starts with an Archimedean field (the rationals) and forms the uniform completion of it in a standard way.

But the original use of the phrase "complete Archimedean field" was by David Hilbert, who meant still something else by it. He meant that the real numbers form the largest Archimedean field in the sense that every other Archimedean field is a subfield of  . Thus   is "complete" in the sense that nothing further can be added to it without making it no longer an Archimedean field. This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from surreal numbers, since that construction starts with a proper class that contains every ordered field (the surreals) and then selects from it the largest Archimedean subfield.

Cardinality

The set of all real numbers is uncountable, in the sense that while both the set of all natural numbers {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} and the set of all real numbers are infinite sets, there can be no one-to-one function from the real numbers to the natural numbers. The cardinality of the set of all real numbers is denoted by   and called the cardinality of the continuum. It is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers (denoted   and called 'aleph-naught'), and equals the cardinality of the power set of the set of the natural numbers.

The statement that there is no subset of the reals with cardinality strictly greater than   and strictly smaller than   is known as the continuum hypothesis (CH). It is neither provable nor refutable using the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory including the axiom of choice (ZFC)—the standard foundation of modern mathematics. In fact, some models of ZFC satisfy CH, while others violate it.[5]

Other properties

As a topological space, the real numbers are separable. This is because the set of rationals, which is countable, is dense in the real numbers. The irrational numbers are also dense in the real numbers, however they are uncountable and have the same cardinality as the reals.

The real numbers form a metric space: the distance between x and y is defined as the absolute value |xy|. By virtue of being a totally ordered set, they also carry an order topology; the topology arising from the metric and the one arising from the order are identical, but yield different presentations for the topology—in the order topology as ordered intervals, in the metric topology as epsilon-balls. The Dedekind cuts construction uses the order topology presentation, while the Cauchy sequences construction uses the metric topology presentation. The reals form a contractible (hence connected and simply connected), separable and complete metric space of Hausdorff dimension 1. The real numbers are locally compact but not compact. There are various properties that uniquely specify them; for instance, all unbounded, connected, and separable order topologies are necessarily homeomorphic to the reals.

Every nonnegative real number has a square root in  , although no negative number does. This shows that the order on   is determined by its algebraic structure. Also, every polynomial of odd degree admits at least one real root: these two properties make   the premier example of a real closed field. Proving this is the first half of one proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra.

The reals carry a canonical measure, the Lebesgue measure, which is the Haar measure on their structure as a topological group normalized such that the unit interval [0;1] has measure 1. There exist sets of real numbers that are not Lebesgue measurable, e.g. Vitali sets.

The supremum axiom of the reals refers to subsets of the reals and is therefore a second-order logical statement. It is not possible to characterize the reals with first-order logic alone: the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem implies that there exists a countable dense subset of the real numbers satisfying exactly the same sentences in first-order logic as the real numbers themselves. The set of hyperreal numbers satisfies the same first order sentences as  . Ordered fields that satisfy the same first-order sentences as   are called nonstandard models of  . This is what makes nonstandard analysis work; by proving a first-order statement in some nonstandard model (which may be easier than proving it in  ), we know that the same statement must also be true of  .

The field   of real numbers is an extension field of the field   of rational numbers, and   can therefore be seen as a vector space over  . Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice guarantees the existence of a basis of this vector space: there exists a set B of real numbers such that every real number can be written uniquely as a finite linear combination of elements of this set, using rational coefficients only, and such that no element of B is a rational linear combination of the others. However, this existence theorem is purely theoretical, as such a base has never been explicitly described.

The well-ordering theorem implies that the real numbers can be well-ordered if the axiom of choice is assumed: there exists a total order on   with the property that every nonempty subset of   has a least element in this ordering. (The standard ordering ≤ of the real numbers is not a well-ordering since e.g. an open interval does not contain a least element in this ordering.) Again, the existence of such a well-ordering is purely theoretical, as it has not been explicitly described. If V=L is assumed in addition to the axioms of ZF, a well ordering of the real numbers can be shown to be explicitly definable by a formula.[6]

A real number may be either computable or uncomputable; either algorithmically random or not; and either arithmetically random or not.

History

 
Real numbers   include the rational numbers  , which include the integers  , which in turn include the natural numbers  

Simple fractions were used by the Egyptians around 1000 BC; the Vedic "Shulba Sutras" ("The rules of chords") in c. 600 BC include what may be the first "use" of irrational numbers. The concept of irrationality was implicitly accepted by early Indian mathematicians such as Manava (c. 750–690 BC), who was aware that the square roots of certain numbers, such as 2 and 61, could not be exactly determined.[7] Around 500 BC, the Greek mathematicians led by Pythagoras also realized that the square root of 2 is irrational.

The Middle Ages brought about the acceptance of zero, negative numbers, integers, and fractional numbers, first by Indian and Chinese mathematicians, and then by Arabic mathematicians, who were also the first to treat irrational numbers as algebraic objects (the latter being made possible by the development of algebra).[8] Arabic mathematicians merged the concepts of "number" and "magnitude" into a more general idea of real numbers.[9] The Egyptian mathematician Abū Kāmil Shujā ibn Aslam (c. 850–930) was the first to accept irrational numbers as solutions to quadratic equations, or as coefficients in an equation (often in the form of square roots, cube roots and fourth roots).[10] In Europe, such numbers, not commensurable with the numerical unit, were called irrational or surd ("deaf").

In the 16th century, Simon Stevin created the basis for modern decimal notation, and insisted that there is no difference between rational and irrational numbers in this regard.

In the 17th century, Descartes introduced the term "real" to describe roots of a polynomial, distinguishing them from "imaginary" ones.

In the 18th and 19th centuries, there was much work on irrational and transcendental numbers. Lambert (1761) gave a flawed proof that π cannot be rational; Legendre (1794) completed the proof[11] and showed that π is not the square root of a rational number.[12] Liouville (1840) showed that neither e nor e2 can be a root of an integer quadratic equation, and then established the existence of transcendental numbers; Cantor (1873) extended and greatly simplified this proof.[13] Hermite (1873) proved that e is transcendental, and Lindemann (1882), showed that π is transcendental. Lindemann's proof was much simplified by Weierstrass (1885), Hilbert (1893), Hurwitz,[14] and Gordan.[15]

The developers of calculus used real numbers without having defined them rigorously. The first rigorous definition was published by Cantor in 1871. In 1874, he showed that the set of all real numbers is uncountably infinite, but the set of all algebraic numbers is countably infinite. Cantor's first uncountability proof was different from his famous diagonal argument published in 1891.

Formal definitions

The real number system   can be defined axiomatically up to an isomorphism, which is described hereinafter. There are also many ways to construct "the" real number system, and a popular approach involves starting from natural numbers, then defining rational numbers algebraically, and finally defining real numbers as equivalence classes of their Cauchy sequences or as Dedekind cuts, which are certain subsets of rational numbers.[16] Another approach is to start from some rigorous axiomatization of Euclidean geometry (say of Hilbert or of Tarski), and then define the real number system geometrically. All these constructions of the real numbers have been shown to be equivalent, in the sense that the resulting number systems are isomorphic.

Axiomatic approach

Let   denote the set of all real numbers, then:

  • The set   is a field, meaning that addition and multiplication are defined and have the usual properties.
  • The field   is ordered, meaning that there is a total order ≥ such that for all real numbers x, y and z:
    • if xy, then x + zy + z;
    • if x ≥ 0 and y ≥ 0, then xy ≥ 0.
  • The order is Dedekind-complete, meaning that every nonempty subset S of   with an upper bound in   has a least upper bound (a.k.a., supremum) in  .

The last property is what differentiates the real numbers from the rational numbers (and from other more exotic ordered fields). For example,   has a rational upper bound (e.g., 1.42), but no least rational upper bound, because   is not rational.

These properties imply the Archimedean property (which is not implied by other definitions of completeness), which states that the set of integers has no upper bound in the reals. In fact, if this were false, then the integers would have a least upper bound N; then, N – 1 would not be an upper bound, and there would be an integer n such that n > N – 1, and thus n + 1 > N, which is a contradiction with the upper-bound property of N.

The real numbers are uniquely specified by the above properties. More precisely, given any two Dedekind-complete ordered fields   and  , there exists a unique field isomorphism from   to  . This uniqueness allows us to think of them as essentially the same mathematical object.

For another axiomatization of  , see Tarski's axiomatization of the reals.

Construction from the rational numbers

The real numbers can be constructed as a completion of the rational numbers, in such a way that a sequence defined by a decimal or binary expansion like (3; 3.1; 3.14; 3.141; 3.1415; ...) converges to a unique real number—in this case π. For details and other constructions of real numbers, see construction of the real numbers.

Applications and connections

Physics

In the physical sciences, most physical constants such as the universal gravitational constant, and physical variables, such as position, mass, speed, and electric charge, are modeled using real numbers. In fact, the fundamental physical theories such as classical mechanics, electromagnetism, quantum mechanics, general relativity and the standard model are described using mathematical structures, typically smooth manifolds or Hilbert spaces, that are based on the real numbers, although actual measurements of physical quantities are of finite accuracy and precision.

Physicists have occasionally suggested that a more fundamental theory would replace the real numbers with quantities that do not form a continuum, but such proposals remain speculative.[17]

Logic

The real numbers are most often formalized using the Zermelo–Fraenkel axiomatization of set theory, but some mathematicians study the real numbers with other logical foundations of mathematics. In particular, the real numbers are also studied in reverse mathematics and in constructive mathematics.[18]

The hyperreal numbers as developed by Edwin Hewitt, Abraham Robinson and others extend the set of the real numbers by introducing infinitesimal and infinite numbers, allowing for building infinitesimal calculus in a way closer to the original intuitions of Leibniz, Euler, Cauchy and others.

Edward Nelson's internal set theory enriches the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory syntactically by introducing a unary predicate "standard". In this approach, infinitesimals are (non-"standard") elements of the set of the real numbers (rather than being elements of an extension thereof, as in Robinson's theory).

The continuum hypothesis posits that the cardinality of the set of the real numbers is  ; i.e. the smallest infinite cardinal number after  , the cardinality of the integers. Paul Cohen proved in 1963 that it is an axiom independent of the other axioms of set theory; that is: one may choose either the continuum hypothesis or its negation as an axiom of set theory, without contradiction.

Computation

Electronic calculators and computers cannot operate on arbitrary real numbers, because finite computers cannot directly store infinitely many digits or other infinite representations. Nor do they usually even operate on arbitrary definable real numbers, which are inconvenient to manipulate.

Instead, computers typically work with finite-precision approximations called floating-point numbers, a representation similar to scientific notation. The achievable precision is limited by the data storage space allocated for each number, whether as fixed-point, floating-point, or arbitrary-precision numbers, or some other representation. Most scientific computation uses binary floating-point arithmetic, often a 64-bit representation with around 16 decimal digits of precision. Real numbers satisfy the usual rules of arithmetic, but floating-point numbers do not. The field of numerical analysis studies the stability and accuracy of numerical algorithms implemented with approximate arithmetic.

Alternately, computer algebra systems can operate on irrational quantities exactly by manipulating symbolic formulas for them (such as     or  ) rather than their rational or decimal approximation.[19] But exact and symbolic arithmetic also have limitations: for instance, they are computationally more expensive; it is not in general possible to determine whether two symbolic expressions are equal (the constant problem); and arithmetic operations can cause exponential explosion in the size of representation of a single number (for instance, squaring a rational number roughly doubles the number of digits in its numerator and denominator, and squaring a polynomial roughly doubles its number of terms), overwhelming finite computer storage.[20]

A real number is called computable if there exists an algorithm that yields its digits. Because there are only countably many algorithms,[21] but an uncountable number of reals, almost all real numbers fail to be computable. Moreover, the equality of two computable numbers is an undecidable problem. Some constructivists accept the existence of only those reals that are computable. The set of definable numbers is broader, but still only countable.

Set theory

In set theory, specifically descriptive set theory, the Baire space is used as a surrogate for the real numbers since the latter have some topological properties (connectedness) that are a technical inconvenience. Elements of Baire space are referred to as "reals".

Vocabulary and notation

The set of all real numbers is denoted   (blackboard bold) or R (upright bold). As it is naturally endowed with the structure of a field, the expression field of real numbers is frequently used when its algebraic properties are under consideration.

The sets of positive real numbers and negative real numbers are often noted   and  ,[22] respectively;   and   are also used.[23] The non-negative real numbers can be noted   but one often sees this set noted  [22] In French mathematics, the positive real numbers and negative real numbers commonly include zero, and these sets are noted respectively   and  [23] In this understanding, the respective sets without zero are called strictly positive real numbers and strictly negative real numbers, and are noted   and  [23]

The notation   refers to the set of the n-tuples of elements of   (real coordinate space), which can be identified to the Cartesian product of n copies of   It is an n-dimensional vector space over the field of the real numbers, often called the coordinate space of dimension n; this space may be identified to the n-dimensional Euclidean space as soon as a Cartesian coordinate system has been chosen in the latter. In this identification, a point of the Euclidean space is identified with the tuple of its Cartesian coordinates.

In mathematics, real is used as an adjective, meaning that the underlying field is the field of the real numbers (or the real field). For example, real matrix, real polynomial and real Lie algebra. The word is also used as a noun, meaning a real number (as in "the set of all reals").

Generalizations and extensions

The real numbers can be generalized and extended in several different directions:

  • The complex numbers contain solutions to all polynomial equations and hence are an algebraically closed field unlike the real numbers. However, the complex numbers are not an ordered field.
  • The affinely extended real number system adds two elements +∞ and −∞. It is a compact space. It is no longer a field, or even an additive group, but it still has a total order; moreover, it is a complete lattice.
  • The real projective line adds only one value . It is also a compact space. Again, it is no longer a field, or even an additive group. However, it allows division of a nonzero element by zero. It has cyclic order described by a separation relation.
  • The long real line pastes together 1* + ℵ1 copies of the real line plus a single point (here 1* denotes the reversed ordering of 1) to create an ordered set that is "locally" identical to the real numbers, but somehow longer; for instance, there is an order-preserving embedding of 1 in the long real line but not in the real numbers. The long real line is the largest ordered set that is complete and locally Archimedean. As with the previous two examples, this set is no longer a field or additive group.
  • Ordered fields extending the reals are the hyperreal numbers and the surreal numbers; both of them contain infinitesimal and infinitely large numbers and are therefore non-Archimedean ordered fields.
  • Self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space (for example, self-adjoint square complex matrices) generalize the reals in many respects: they can be ordered (though not totally ordered), they are complete, all their eigenvalues are real and they form a real associative algebra. Positive-definite operators correspond to the positive reals and normal operators correspond to the complex numbers.

See also

Number systems
Complex  
Real  
Rational  
Integer  
Natural  
Negative integers
Imaginary

Notes

  1. ^ This is not sufficient for distinguishing the real numbers from the rational numbers; a property of completeness is also required.
  2. ^ The terminating rational numbers may have two decimal expansions (see 0.999...); the other real numbers have exactly one decimal expansion.
  3. ^ Limits and continuity can be defined in general topology without reference to real numbers, but these generalizations are relatively recent, and used only in very specific cases.
  4. ^ More precisely, given two complete totally ordered fields, there is a unique isomorphism between them. This implies that the identity is the unique field automorphism of the reals that is compatible with the ordering.

References

Citations

  1. ^ "Real number". Oxford Reference. 2011-08-03.
  2. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Real Number". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
  3. ^ "real". Oxford English Dictionary (3rd ed.). 2008. 'real', n.2, B.4. Mathematics. A real number. Usually in plural
  4. ^ a b "Real number". Encyclopedia Britannica.
  5. ^ Koellner, Peter (2013). "The Continuum Hypothesis". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University.
  6. ^ Moschovakis, Yiannis N. (1980), "5. The Constructible Universe", Descriptive Set Theory, North-Holland, pp. 274–285, ISBN 978-0-444-85305-9
  7. ^ T. K. Puttaswamy, "The Accomplishments of Ancient Indian Mathematicians", pp. 410–11. In: Selin, Helaine; D'Ambrosio, Ubiratan, eds. (2000), Mathematics Across Cultures: The History of Non-western Mathematics, Springer, ISBN 978-1-4020-0260-1.
  8. ^ O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F. (1999), "Arabic mathematics: forgotten brilliance?", MacTutor History of Mathematics archive, University of St Andrews
  9. ^ Matvievskaya, Galina (1987), "The Theory of Quadratic Irrationals in Medieval Oriental Mathematics", Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 500 (1): 253–77 [254], Bibcode:1987NYASA.500..253M, doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.1987.tb37206.x, S2CID 121416910
  10. ^ Jacques Sesiano, "Islamic mathematics", p. 148, in Selin, Helaine; D'Ambrosio, Ubiratan (2000), Mathematics Across Cultures: The History of Non-western Mathematics, Springer, ISBN 978-1-4020-0260-1
  11. ^ Beckmann, Petr (1971). A History of π (PI). St. Martin's Press. p. 170. ISBN 9780312381851.
  12. ^ Arndt, Jörg; Haenel, Christoph (2001), Pi Unleashed, Springer, p. 192, ISBN 978-3-540-66572-4, retrieved 2015-11-15.
  13. ^ Dunham, William (2015), The Calculus Gallery: Masterpieces from Newton to Lebesgue, Princeton University Press, p. 127, ISBN 978-1-4008-6679-3, retrieved 2015-02-17, Cantor found a remarkable shortcut to reach Liouville's conclusion with a fraction of the work
  14. ^ Hurwitz, Adolf (1893). "Beweis der Transendenz der Zahl e". Mathematische Annalen (43): 134–35.
  15. ^ Gordan, Paul (1893). "Transcendenz von e und π". Mathematische Annalen. 43 (2–3): 222–224. doi:10.1007/bf01443647. S2CID 123203471.
  16. ^ "Lecture #1" (PDF). 18.095 Lecture Series in Mathematics. 2015-01-05.
  17. ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (1986). "Hermann Weyl and the Unity of Knowledge: In the linkage of four mysteries—the "how come" of existence, time, the mathematical continuum, and the discontinuous yes-or-no of quantum physics—may lie the key to deep new insight". American Scientist. 74 (4): 366–75. Bibcode:1986AmSci..74..366W. JSTOR 27854250.
    Bengtsson, Ingemar (2017). "The Number Behind the Simplest SIC-POVM". Foundations of Physics. 47 (8): 1031–41. arXiv:1611.09087. Bibcode:2017FoPh...47.1031B. doi:10.1007/s10701-017-0078-3. S2CID 118954904.
  18. ^ Bishop, Errett; Bridges, Douglas (1985), Constructive analysis, Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften [Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences], vol. 279, Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag, ISBN 978-3-540-15066-4, chapter 2.
  19. ^ Cohen, Joel S. (2002), Computer algebra and symbolic computation: elementary algorithms, vol. 1, A K Peters, p. 32, ISBN 978-1-56881-158-1
  20. ^ Trefethen, Lloyd N. (2007). "Computing numerically with functions instead of numbers" (PDF). Mathematics in Computer Science. 1 (1): 9–19. doi:10.1007/s11786-007-0001-y.
  21. ^ Hein, James L. (2010), "14.1.1", Discrete Structures, Logic, and Computability (3 ed.), Sudbury, MA: Jones and Bartlett Publishers, ISBN 97-80763772062, retrieved 2015-11-15
  22. ^ a b Schumacher, Carol (1996). Chapter Zero: Fundamental Notions of Abstract Mathematics. Addison-Wesley. pp. 114–115. ISBN 9780201826531.
  23. ^ a b c École Normale Supérieure of Paris, "Nombres réels" ("Real numbers") 2014-05-08 at the Wayback Machine, p. 6

Sources

External links

real, number, real, numbers, used, descriptive, theory, baire, space, theory, mathematics, real, number, number, that, used, measure, continuous, dimensional, quantity, such, distance, duration, temperature, here, continuous, means, that, pairs, values, have, . For the real numbers used in descriptive set theory see Baire space set theory In mathematics a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one dimensional quantity such as a distance duration or temperature Here continuous means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences a Every real number can be almost uniquely represented by an infinite decimal expansion b 1 A symbol for the set of real numbers The real numbers are fundamental in calculus and more generally in all mathematics in particular by their role in the classical definitions of limits continuity and derivatives c The set of real numbers is denoted R or R displaystyle mathbb R 2 and is sometimes called the reals 3 The adjective real used in the 17th century by Rene Descartes distinguishes real numbers from imaginary numbers such as the square roots of 1 4 The real numbers include the rational numbers such as the integer 5 and the fraction 4 3 The rest of the real numbers are called irrational numbers and include algebraic numbers such as the square root 2 1 414 and transcendental numbers such as p 3 1415 4 Real numbers can be thought of as all points on a line called the number line or real line where the points corresponding to integers 2 1 0 1 2 are equally spaced Conversely analytic geometry is the association of points on lines especially axis lines to real numbers such that geometric displacements are proportional to differences between corresponding numbers The informal descriptions above of the real numbers are not sufficient for ensuring the correctness of proofs of theorems involving real numbers The realization that a better definition was needed and the elaboration of such a definition was a major development of 19th century mathematics and is the foundation of real analysis the study of real functions and real valued sequences A current axiomatic definition is that real numbers form the unique up to an isomorphism Dedekind complete ordered field d Other common definitions of real numbers include equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rational numbers Dedekind cuts and infinite decimal representations All these definitions satisfy the axiomatic definition and are thus equivalent Contents 1 Characterizing properties 2 Arithmetic 2 1 Auxiliary operations 2 2 Auxiliary order relations 3 Dedekind completeness 4 Topological completeness 4 1 The complete ordered field 5 Cardinality 6 Other properties 7 History 8 Formal definitions 8 1 Axiomatic approach 8 2 Construction from the rational numbers 9 Applications and connections 9 1 Physics 9 2 Logic 9 3 Computation 9 4 Set theory 10 Vocabulary and notation 11 Generalizations and extensions 12 See also 13 Notes 14 References 14 1 Citations 14 2 Sources 15 External linksCharacterizing properties EditReal numbers are completely characterized by their fundamental properties that can be summarized by saying that they form an ordered field that is Dedekind complete Here completely characterized means that there a unique isomorphism between any two Dedekind complete ordered fields and thus that their elements have exactly the same properties This implies that one can manipulate real numbers and computing with them without knowing how they can be defined this is what mathematicians and physicists did during several centuries before the first formal definition were provided in the second half of the 19th century See Construction of the real numbers for details about these formal definitions and the proof of their equivalence Arithmetic EditThe real numbers form an ordered field Intuitively this means that methods and rules of elementary arithmetic apply to them More precisely there are two binary operations addition and multiplication and a total order that have the following properties The addition of two real numbers a and b produce a real number denoted a b displaystyle a b which is the sum of a and b The multiplication of two real numbers a and b produce a real number denoted a b displaystyle ab a b displaystyle a cdot b or a b displaystyle a times b which is the product of a and b Addition and multiplication are both commutative which means that a b b a displaystyle a b b a and a b b a displaystyle ab ba for every real numbers a and b Addition and multiplication are both associative which means that a b c a b c displaystyle a b c a b c and a b c a b c displaystyle ab c a bc for every real numbers a b and c and that parentheses may be omitted in both cases Multiplication is distributive over addition which means that a b c a b a c displaystyle a b c ab ac for every real numbers a b and c There is a real number called zero and denoted 0 which is an additive identity which means that a 0 a displaystyle a 0 a for every real number a There is a real number denoted 1 which is an multiplicative identity which means that a 1 a displaystyle a times 1 a for every real number a Every real number a has an additive inverse denoted a displaystyle a This means that a a 0 displaystyle a a 0 for every real number a Every nonzero real number a has a multiplicative inverse denoted a 1 displaystyle a 1 or 1 a displaystyle frac 1 a This means that a a 1 1 displaystyle aa 1 1 for every nonzero real number a The total order is denoted a lt b displaystyle a lt b being that it is a total order means two properties given two real numbers a and b exactly one of a lt b displaystyle a lt b a b displaystyle a b or b lt a displaystyle b lt a is true and if a lt b displaystyle a lt b and b lt c displaystyle b lt c then one has also a lt c displaystyle a lt c The order is compatible with addition and multiplication which means that a lt b displaystyle a lt b implies a c lt b c displaystyle a c lt b c for every real number c and 0 lt a b displaystyle 0 lt ab is implied by 0 lt a displaystyle 0 lt a and 0 lt b displaystyle 0 lt b Many other properties can be deduced from the above ones In particular 0 a 0 displaystyle 0 cdot a 0 for every real number a 0 lt 1 displaystyle 0 lt 1 0 lt a 2 displaystyle 0 lt a 2 for every nonzero real number aAuxiliary operations Edit Several other operations are commonly used which can be deduced from the above ones Subtraction the subtraction of two real numbers a and b results in the sum of a and the additive inverse b of b that is a b a b displaystyle a b a b Division the division of a real number a by a nonzero real number b is denoted a b textstyle frac a b or a b displaystyle a b and defined as the multiplication of a with the multiplicative inverse of b that is a b a b 1 displaystyle frac a b ab 1 Absolute value the absolute value of a real number a denoted a displaystyle a measures its distance from zero and is defined as a max a a displaystyle a max a a Auxiliary order relations Edit The total order that is considered above is denoted a lt b displaystyle a lt b and read as a is less than b Three other order relations are also commonly used Greater than a gt b displaystyle a gt b read as a is greater than b is defined as a gt b displaystyle a gt b if and only if b lt a displaystyle b lt a Less than or equal to a b displaystyle a leq b read as a is less than or equal to b or a is not greater than b is defined as a lt b or a b displaystyle a lt b text or a b or equivalently as not b lt a displaystyle text not b lt a Greater than or equal to a b displaystyle a geq b read as a is greater than or equal to b or a is not less than b is defined as b lt a or a b displaystyle b lt a text or a b or equivalently as not a lt b displaystyle text not a lt b Dedekind completeness EditPrevious properties do not distinguish real numbers from rational numbers This distinction is provided by Dedekind completeness which states that every upper bounded set of real numbers admits a least upper bound This means the following A set of real numbers S displaystyle S is upper bounded if there is a real number u displaystyle u such that s u displaystyle s leq u for all s S displaystyle s in S such a u displaystyle u is called a upper bound of S displaystyle S So Dedekind completeness means that if S is upper bounded it has a upper bound that is less than any other upper bound Dedekind completeness implies other sorts of completeness see below but also has some important consequences Archimedean property for every real number x there is an integer n such that x lt n displaystyle x lt n take n u 1 displaystyle n u 1 where u displaystyle u is the least upper bound of the integers less than n Equivalently if x is a positive real number there is a positive integer n such that 0 lt 1 n lt x displaystyle 0 lt frac 1 n lt x Every positive real number x has a positive square root that is there exist a positive real number r displaystyle r such that r 2 x displaystyle r 2 x Every univariate polynomial of odd degree with real coefficients has at least one real root if the leading coefficient is positive take the least upper bound of real numbers for which the value of the polynomial is negative The last two properties are summarized by saying that the real numbers form a real closed field This implies the real version of the fundamental theorem of algebra namely that every polynomial with real coefficients can be factored into polynomials with real coefficients of degree at most two Topological completeness EditMain article Completeness of the real numbers A main reason for using real numbers is so that many sequences have limits More formally the reals are complete in the sense of metric spaces or uniform spaces which is a different sense than the Dedekind completeness of the order in the previous section A sequence xn of real numbers is called a Cauchy sequence if for any e gt 0 there exists an integer N possibly depending on e such that the distance xn xm is less than e for all n and m that are both greater than N This definition originally provided by Cauchy formalizes the fact that the xn eventually come and remain arbitrarily close to each other A sequence xn converges to the limit x if its elements eventually come and remain arbitrarily close to x that is if for any e gt 0 there exists an integer N possibly depending on e such that the distance xn x is less than e for n greater than N Every convergent sequence is a Cauchy sequence and the converse is true for real numbers and this means that the topological space of the real numbers is complete The set of rational numbers is not complete For example the sequence 1 1 4 1 41 1 414 1 4142 1 41421 where each term adds a digit of the decimal expansion of the positive square root of 2 is Cauchy but it does not converge to a rational number in the real numbers in contrast it converges to the positive square root of 2 The completeness property of the reals is the basis on which calculus and more generally mathematical analysis are built In particular the test that a sequence is a Cauchy sequence allows proving that a sequence has a limit without computing it and even without knowing it For example the standard series of the exponential function e x n 0 x n n displaystyle e x sum n 0 infty frac x n n converges to a real number for every x because the sums n N M x n n displaystyle sum n N M frac x n n can be made arbitrarily small independently of M by choosing N sufficiently large This proves that the sequence is Cauchy and thus converges showing that e x displaystyle e x is well defined for every x The complete ordered field Edit The real numbers are often described as the complete ordered field a phrase that can be interpreted in several ways First an order can be lattice complete It is easy to see that no ordered field can be lattice complete because it can have no largest element given any element z z 1 is larger Additionally an order can be Dedekind complete see Axiomatic approach The uniqueness result at the end of that section justifies using the word the in the phrase complete ordered field when this is the sense of complete that is meant This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Dedekind cuts since that construction starts from an ordered field the rationals and then forms the Dedekind completion of it in a standard way These two notions of completeness ignore the field structure However an ordered group in this case the additive group of the field defines a uniform structure and uniform structures have a notion of completeness the description in Completeness is a special case We refer to the notion of completeness in uniform spaces rather than the related and better known notion for metric spaces since the definition of metric space relies on already having a characterization of the real numbers It is not true that R displaystyle mathbb R is the only uniformly complete ordered field but it is the only uniformly complete Archimedean field and indeed one often hears the phrase complete Archimedean field instead of complete ordered field Every uniformly complete Archimedean field must also be Dedekind complete and vice versa justifying using the in the phrase the complete Archimedean field This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from Cauchy sequences the construction carried out in full in this article since it starts with an Archimedean field the rationals and forms the uniform completion of it in a standard way But the original use of the phrase complete Archimedean field was by David Hilbert who meant still something else by it He meant that the real numbers form the largest Archimedean field in the sense that every other Archimedean field is a subfield of R displaystyle mathbb R Thus R displaystyle mathbb R is complete in the sense that nothing further can be added to it without making it no longer an Archimedean field This sense of completeness is most closely related to the construction of the reals from surreal numbers since that construction starts with a proper class that contains every ordered field the surreals and then selects from it the largest Archimedean subfield Cardinality EditThe set of all real numbers is uncountable in the sense that while both the set of all natural numbers 1 2 3 4 and the set of all real numbers are infinite sets there can be no one to one function from the real numbers to the natural numbers The cardinality of the set of all real numbers is denoted by c displaystyle mathfrak c and called the cardinality of the continuum It is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers denoted ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 and called aleph naught and equals the cardinality of the power set of the set of the natural numbers The statement that there is no subset of the reals with cardinality strictly greater than ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 and strictly smaller than c displaystyle mathfrak c is known as the continuum hypothesis CH It is neither provable nor refutable using the axioms of Zermelo Fraenkel set theory including the axiom of choice ZFC the standard foundation of modern mathematics In fact some models of ZFC satisfy CH while others violate it 5 Other properties EditSee also Real line As a topological space the real numbers are separable This is because the set of rationals which is countable is dense in the real numbers The irrational numbers are also dense in the real numbers however they are uncountable and have the same cardinality as the reals The real numbers form a metric space the distance between x and y is defined as the absolute value x y By virtue of being a totally ordered set they also carry an order topology the topology arising from the metric and the one arising from the order are identical but yield different presentations for the topology in the order topology as ordered intervals in the metric topology as epsilon balls The Dedekind cuts construction uses the order topology presentation while the Cauchy sequences construction uses the metric topology presentation The reals form a contractible hence connected and simply connected separable and complete metric space of Hausdorff dimension 1 The real numbers are locally compact but not compact There are various properties that uniquely specify them for instance all unbounded connected and separable order topologies are necessarily homeomorphic to the reals Every nonnegative real number has a square root in R displaystyle mathbb R although no negative number does This shows that the order on R displaystyle mathbb R is determined by its algebraic structure Also every polynomial of odd degree admits at least one real root these two properties make R displaystyle mathbb R the premier example of a real closed field Proving this is the first half of one proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra The reals carry a canonical measure the Lebesgue measure which is the Haar measure on their structure as a topological group normalized such that the unit interval 0 1 has measure 1 There exist sets of real numbers that are not Lebesgue measurable e g Vitali sets The supremum axiom of the reals refers to subsets of the reals and is therefore a second order logical statement It is not possible to characterize the reals with first order logic alone the Lowenheim Skolem theorem implies that there exists a countable dense subset of the real numbers satisfying exactly the same sentences in first order logic as the real numbers themselves The set of hyperreal numbers satisfies the same first order sentences as R displaystyle mathbb R Ordered fields that satisfy the same first order sentences as R displaystyle mathbb R are called nonstandard models of R displaystyle mathbb R This is what makes nonstandard analysis work by proving a first order statement in some nonstandard model which may be easier than proving it in R displaystyle mathbb R we know that the same statement must also be true of R displaystyle mathbb R The field R displaystyle mathbb R of real numbers is an extension field of the field Q displaystyle mathbb Q of rational numbers and R displaystyle mathbb R can therefore be seen as a vector space over Q displaystyle mathbb Q Zermelo Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice guarantees the existence of a basis of this vector space there exists a set B of real numbers such that every real number can be written uniquely as a finite linear combination of elements of this set using rational coefficients only and such that no element of B is a rational linear combination of the others However this existence theorem is purely theoretical as such a base has never been explicitly described The well ordering theorem implies that the real numbers can be well ordered if the axiom of choice is assumed there exists a total order on R displaystyle mathbb R with the property that every nonempty subset of R displaystyle mathbb R has a least element in this ordering The standard ordering of the real numbers is not a well ordering since e g an open interval does not contain a least element in this ordering Again the existence of such a well ordering is purely theoretical as it has not been explicitly described If V L is assumed in addition to the axioms of ZF a well ordering of the real numbers can be shown to be explicitly definable by a formula 6 A real number may be either computable or uncomputable either algorithmically random or not and either arithmetically random or not History Edit Real numbers R displaystyle mathbb R include the rational numbers Q displaystyle mathbb Q which include the integers Z displaystyle mathbb Z which in turn include the natural numbers N displaystyle mathbb N Simple fractions were used by the Egyptians around 1000 BC the Vedic Shulba Sutras The rules of chords in c 600 BC include what may be the first use of irrational numbers The concept of irrationality was implicitly accepted by early Indian mathematicians such as Manava c 750 690 BC who was aware that the square roots of certain numbers such as 2 and 61 could not be exactly determined 7 Around 500 BC the Greek mathematicians led by Pythagoras also realized that the square root of 2 is irrational The Middle Ages brought about the acceptance of zero negative numbers integers and fractional numbers first by Indian and Chinese mathematicians and then by Arabic mathematicians who were also the first to treat irrational numbers as algebraic objects the latter being made possible by the development of algebra 8 Arabic mathematicians merged the concepts of number and magnitude into a more general idea of real numbers 9 The Egyptian mathematician Abu Kamil Shuja ibn Aslam c 850 930 was the first to accept irrational numbers as solutions to quadratic equations or as coefficients in an equation often in the form of square roots cube roots and fourth roots 10 In Europe such numbers not commensurable with the numerical unit were called irrational or surd deaf In the 16th century Simon Stevin created the basis for modern decimal notation and insisted that there is no difference between rational and irrational numbers in this regard In the 17th century Descartes introduced the term real to describe roots of a polynomial distinguishing them from imaginary ones In the 18th and 19th centuries there was much work on irrational and transcendental numbers Lambert 1761 gave a flawed proof that p cannot be rational Legendre 1794 completed the proof 11 and showed that p is not the square root of a rational number 12 Liouville 1840 showed that neither e nor e2 can be a root of an integer quadratic equation and then established the existence of transcendental numbers Cantor 1873 extended and greatly simplified this proof 13 Hermite 1873 proved that e is transcendental and Lindemann 1882 showed that p is transcendental Lindemann s proof was much simplified by Weierstrass 1885 Hilbert 1893 Hurwitz 14 and Gordan 15 The developers of calculus used real numbers without having defined them rigorously The first rigorous definition was published by Cantor in 1871 In 1874 he showed that the set of all real numbers is uncountably infinite but the set of all algebraic numbers is countably infinite Cantor s first uncountability proof was different from his famous diagonal argument published in 1891 Formal definitions EditMain article Construction of the real numbers The real number system R lt displaystyle mathbb R cdot lt can be defined axiomatically up to an isomorphism which is described hereinafter There are also many ways to construct the real number system and a popular approach involves starting from natural numbers then defining rational numbers algebraically and finally defining real numbers as equivalence classes of their Cauchy sequences or as Dedekind cuts which are certain subsets of rational numbers 16 Another approach is to start from some rigorous axiomatization of Euclidean geometry say of Hilbert or of Tarski and then define the real number system geometrically All these constructions of the real numbers have been shown to be equivalent in the sense that the resulting number systems are isomorphic Axiomatic approach Edit Let R displaystyle mathbb R denote the set of all real numbers then The set R displaystyle mathbb R is a field meaning that addition and multiplication are defined and have the usual properties The field R displaystyle mathbb R is ordered meaning that there is a total order such that for all real numbers x y and z if x y then x z y z if x 0 and y 0 then xy 0 The order is Dedekind complete meaning that every nonempty subset S of R displaystyle mathbb R with an upper bound in R displaystyle mathbb R has a least upper bound a k a supremum in R displaystyle mathbb R The last property is what differentiates the real numbers from the rational numbers and from other more exotic ordered fields For example x Q x 2 lt 2 displaystyle x in mathbb Q x 2 lt 2 has a rational upper bound e g 1 42 but no least rational upper bound because 2 displaystyle sqrt 2 is not rational These properties imply the Archimedean property which is not implied by other definitions of completeness which states that the set of integers has no upper bound in the reals In fact if this were false then the integers would have a least upper bound N then N 1 would not be an upper bound and there would be an integer n such that n gt N 1 and thus n 1 gt N which is a contradiction with the upper bound property of N The real numbers are uniquely specified by the above properties More precisely given any two Dedekind complete ordered fields R 1 displaystyle mathbb R 1 and R 2 displaystyle mathbb R 2 there exists a unique field isomorphism from R 1 displaystyle mathbb R 1 to R 2 displaystyle mathbb R 2 This uniqueness allows us to think of them as essentially the same mathematical object For another axiomatization of R displaystyle mathbb R see Tarski s axiomatization of the reals Construction from the rational numbers Edit The real numbers can be constructed as a completion of the rational numbers in such a way that a sequence defined by a decimal or binary expansion like 3 3 1 3 14 3 141 3 1415 converges to a unique real number in this case p For details and other constructions of real numbers see construction of the real numbers Applications and connections EditPhysics Edit In the physical sciences most physical constants such as the universal gravitational constant and physical variables such as position mass speed and electric charge are modeled using real numbers In fact the fundamental physical theories such as classical mechanics electromagnetism quantum mechanics general relativity and the standard model are described using mathematical structures typically smooth manifolds or Hilbert spaces that are based on the real numbers although actual measurements of physical quantities are of finite accuracy and precision Physicists have occasionally suggested that a more fundamental theory would replace the real numbers with quantities that do not form a continuum but such proposals remain speculative 17 Logic Edit The real numbers are most often formalized using the Zermelo Fraenkel axiomatization of set theory but some mathematicians study the real numbers with other logical foundations of mathematics In particular the real numbers are also studied in reverse mathematics and in constructive mathematics 18 The hyperreal numbers as developed by Edwin Hewitt Abraham Robinson and others extend the set of the real numbers by introducing infinitesimal and infinite numbers allowing for building infinitesimal calculus in a way closer to the original intuitions of Leibniz Euler Cauchy and others Edward Nelson s internal set theory enriches the Zermelo Fraenkel set theory syntactically by introducing a unary predicate standard In this approach infinitesimals are non standard elements of the set of the real numbers rather than being elements of an extension thereof as in Robinson s theory The continuum hypothesis posits that the cardinality of the set of the real numbers is ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 i e the smallest infinite cardinal number after ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 the cardinality of the integers Paul Cohen proved in 1963 that it is an axiom independent of the other axioms of set theory that is one may choose either the continuum hypothesis or its negation as an axiom of set theory without contradiction Computation Edit Electronic calculators and computers cannot operate on arbitrary real numbers because finite computers cannot directly store infinitely many digits or other infinite representations Nor do they usually even operate on arbitrary definable real numbers which are inconvenient to manipulate Instead computers typically work with finite precision approximations called floating point numbers a representation similar to scientific notation The achievable precision is limited by the data storage space allocated for each number whether as fixed point floating point or arbitrary precision numbers or some other representation Most scientific computation uses binary floating point arithmetic often a 64 bit representation with around 16 decimal digits of precision Real numbers satisfy the usual rules of arithmetic but floating point numbers do not The field of numerical analysis studies the stability and accuracy of numerical algorithms implemented with approximate arithmetic Alternately computer algebra systems can operate on irrational quantities exactly by manipulating symbolic formulas for them such as 2 textstyle sqrt 2 arctan 5 textstyle arctan 5 or 0 1 x x d x textstyle int 0 1 x x dx rather than their rational or decimal approximation 19 But exact and symbolic arithmetic also have limitations for instance they are computationally more expensive it is not in general possible to determine whether two symbolic expressions are equal the constant problem and arithmetic operations can cause exponential explosion in the size of representation of a single number for instance squaring a rational number roughly doubles the number of digits in its numerator and denominator and squaring a polynomial roughly doubles its number of terms overwhelming finite computer storage 20 A real number is called computable if there exists an algorithm that yields its digits Because there are only countably many algorithms 21 but an uncountable number of reals almost all real numbers fail to be computable Moreover the equality of two computable numbers is an undecidable problem Some constructivists accept the existence of only those reals that are computable The set of definable numbers is broader but still only countable Set theory Edit In set theory specifically descriptive set theory the Baire space is used as a surrogate for the real numbers since the latter have some topological properties connectedness that are a technical inconvenience Elements of Baire space are referred to as reals Vocabulary and notation EditThe set of all real numbers is denoted R displaystyle mathbb R blackboard bold or R upright bold As it is naturally endowed with the structure of a field the expression field of real numbers is frequently used when its algebraic properties are under consideration The sets of positive real numbers and negative real numbers are often noted R displaystyle mathbb R and R displaystyle mathbb R 22 respectively R displaystyle mathbb R and R displaystyle mathbb R are also used 23 The non negative real numbers can be noted R 0 displaystyle mathbb R geq 0 but one often sees this set noted R 0 displaystyle mathbb R cup 0 22 In French mathematics the positive real numbers and negative real numbers commonly include zero and these sets are noted respectively R displaystyle mathbb R and R displaystyle mathbb R 23 In this understanding the respective sets without zero are called strictly positive real numbers and strictly negative real numbers and are noted R displaystyle mathbb R and R displaystyle mathbb R 23 The notation R n displaystyle mathbb R n refers to the set of the n tuples of elements of R displaystyle mathbb R real coordinate space which can be identified to the Cartesian product of n copies of R displaystyle mathbb R It is an n dimensional vector space over the field of the real numbers often called the coordinate space of dimension n this space may be identified to the n dimensional Euclidean space as soon as a Cartesian coordinate system has been chosen in the latter In this identification a point of the Euclidean space is identified with the tuple of its Cartesian coordinates In mathematics real is used as an adjective meaning that the underlying field is the field of the real numbers or the real field For example real matrix real polynomial and real Lie algebra The word is also used as a noun meaning a real number as in the set of all reals Generalizations and extensions EditThe real numbers can be generalized and extended in several different directions The complex numbers contain solutions to all polynomial equations and hence are an algebraically closed field unlike the real numbers However the complex numbers are not an ordered field The affinely extended real number system adds two elements and It is a compact space It is no longer a field or even an additive group but it still has a total order moreover it is a complete lattice The real projective line adds only one value It is also a compact space Again it is no longer a field or even an additive group However it allows division of a nonzero element by zero It has cyclic order described by a separation relation The long real line pastes together ℵ1 ℵ1 copies of the real line plus a single point here ℵ1 denotes the reversed ordering of ℵ1 to create an ordered set that is locally identical to the real numbers but somehow longer for instance there is an order preserving embedding of ℵ1 in the long real line but not in the real numbers The long real line is the largest ordered set that is complete and locally Archimedean As with the previous two examples this set is no longer a field or additive group Ordered fields extending the reals are the hyperreal numbers and the surreal numbers both of them contain infinitesimal and infinitely large numbers and are therefore non Archimedean ordered fields Self adjoint operators on a Hilbert space for example self adjoint square complex matrices generalize the reals in many respects they can be ordered though not totally ordered they are complete all their eigenvalues are real and they form a real associative algebra Positive definite operators correspond to the positive reals and normal operators correspond to the complex numbers See also Edit Mathematics portalCompleteness of the real numbers Continued fraction Definable real numbers Positive real numbers Real analysisNumber systems Complex C displaystyle mathbb C Real R displaystyle mathbb R Rational Q displaystyle mathbb Q Integer Z displaystyle mathbb Z Natural N displaystyle mathbb N Zero 0One 1Prime numbersComposite numbersNegative integersFraction Finite decimalDyadic finite binary Repeating decimalIrrational Algebraic irrationalTranscendentalImaginaryNotes Edit This is not sufficient for distinguishing the real numbers from the rational numbers a property of completeness is also required The terminating rational numbers may have two decimal expansions see 0 999 the other real numbers have exactly one decimal expansion Limits and continuity can be defined in general topology without reference to real numbers but these generalizations are relatively recent and used only in very specific cases More precisely given two complete totally ordered fields there is a unique isomorphism between them This implies that the identity is the unique field automorphism of the reals that is compatible with the ordering References EditCitations Edit Real number Oxford Reference 2011 08 03 Weisstein Eric W Real Number mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2020 08 11 real Oxford English Dictionary 3rd ed 2008 real n 2 B 4 Mathematics A real number Usually in plural a b Real number Encyclopedia Britannica Koellner Peter 2013 The Continuum Hypothesis In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Moschovakis Yiannis N 1980 5 The Constructible Universe Descriptive Set Theory North Holland pp 274 285 ISBN 978 0 444 85305 9 T K Puttaswamy The Accomplishments of Ancient Indian Mathematicians pp 410 11 In Selin Helaine D Ambrosio Ubiratan eds 2000 Mathematics Across Cultures The History of Non western Mathematics Springer ISBN 978 1 4020 0260 1 O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F 1999 Arabic mathematics forgotten brilliance MacTutor History of Mathematics archive University of St Andrews Matvievskaya Galina 1987 The Theory of Quadratic Irrationals in Medieval Oriental Mathematics Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 500 1 253 77 254 Bibcode 1987NYASA 500 253M doi 10 1111 j 1749 6632 1987 tb37206 x S2CID 121416910 Jacques Sesiano Islamic mathematics p 148 in Selin Helaine D Ambrosio Ubiratan 2000 Mathematics Across Cultures The History of Non western Mathematics Springer ISBN 978 1 4020 0260 1 Beckmann Petr 1971 A History of p PI St Martin s Press p 170 ISBN 9780312381851 Arndt Jorg Haenel Christoph 2001 Pi Unleashed Springer p 192 ISBN 978 3 540 66572 4 retrieved 2015 11 15 Dunham William 2015 The Calculus Gallery Masterpieces from Newton to Lebesgue Princeton University Press p 127 ISBN 978 1 4008 6679 3 retrieved 2015 02 17 Cantor found a remarkable shortcut to reach Liouville s conclusion with a fraction of the work Hurwitz Adolf 1893 Beweis der Transendenz der Zahl e Mathematische Annalen 43 134 35 Gordan Paul 1893 Transcendenz von e und p Mathematische Annalen 43 2 3 222 224 doi 10 1007 bf01443647 S2CID 123203471 Lecture 1 PDF 18 095 Lecture Series in Mathematics 2015 01 05 Wheeler John Archibald 1986 Hermann Weyl and the Unity of Knowledge In the linkage of four mysteries the how come of existence time the mathematical continuum and the discontinuous yes or no of quantum physics may lie the key to deep new insight American Scientist 74 4 366 75 Bibcode 1986AmSci 74 366W JSTOR 27854250 Bengtsson Ingemar 2017 The Number Behind the Simplest SIC POVM Foundations of Physics 47 8 1031 41 arXiv 1611 09087 Bibcode 2017FoPh 47 1031B doi 10 1007 s10701 017 0078 3 S2CID 118954904 Bishop Errett Bridges Douglas 1985 Constructive analysis Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften Fundamental Principles of Mathematical Sciences vol 279 Berlin New York Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 540 15066 4 chapter 2 Cohen Joel S 2002 Computer algebra and symbolic computation elementary algorithms vol 1 A K Peters p 32 ISBN 978 1 56881 158 1 Trefethen Lloyd N 2007 Computing numerically with functions instead of numbers PDF Mathematics in Computer Science 1 1 9 19 doi 10 1007 s11786 007 0001 y Hein James L 2010 14 1 1 Discrete Structures Logic and Computability 3 ed Sudbury MA Jones and Bartlett Publishers ISBN 97 80763772062 retrieved 2015 11 15 a b Schumacher Carol 1996 Chapter Zero Fundamental Notions of Abstract Mathematics Addison Wesley pp 114 115 ISBN 9780201826531 a b c Ecole Normale Superieure of Paris Nombres reels Real numbers Archived 2014 05 08 at the Wayback Machine p 6 Sources Edit Bos Henk J M 2001 Redefining Geometrical Exactness Descartes Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Springer doi 10 1007 978 1 4613 0087 8 ISBN 978 1 4612 6521 4 Bottazzini Umberto 1986 The Higher Calculus A History of Real and Complex Analysis from Euler to Weierstrass Springer ISBN 9780387963020 Cantor Georg 1874 Uber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen On a property of the collection of all real algebraic numbers Crelle s Journal in German 77 258 62 Dieudonne Jean 1960 Foundations of Modern Analysis Academic Press Feferman Solomon 1964 The Number Systems Foundations of Algebra and Analysis Addison Wesley Howie John M 2001 Real Analysis Springer Undergraduate Mathematics Series Springer doi 10 1007 978 1 4471 0341 7 ISBN 978 1 85233 314 0 Katz Robert 1964 Axiomatic Analysis Heath Krantz David H Luce R Duncan Suppes Patrick Tversky Amos 1971 Foundations of Measurement Vol 1 Academic Press ISBN 9780124254015 Vol 2 1989 Vol 3 1990 Mac Lane Saunders 1986 4 Real Numbers Mathematics Form and Function Springer ISBN 9780387962177 Landau Edmund 1966 Foundations of Analysis 3rd ed Chelsea ISBN 9780828400794 Translated from the German Grundlagen der Analysis 1930 Stevenson Frederick W 2000 Exploring the Real Numbers Prentice Hall ISBN 9780130402615 Stillwell John 2013 The Real Numbers An Introduction to Set Theory and Analysis Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 319 01577 4 ISBN 978 3 319 01576 7 External links Edit Real number Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Real number amp oldid 1154165614, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.