fbpx
Wikipedia

Ethics (Spinoza book)

Ethics, Demonstrated in Geometrical Order (Latin: Ethica, ordine geometrico demonstrata), usually known as the Ethics, is a philosophical treatise written in Latin by Baruch Spinoza (Benedictus de Spinoza). It was written between 1661 and 1675[1] and was first published posthumously in 1677.

The opening page of Spinoza's magnum opus, Ethics, in the posthumous Latin first edition
A manuscript of Baruch de Spinoza: Ethica in the Biblioteca Vaticana, Vat. lat. 12838. Part 1, theorems 5 (the ending), 6-8. Prop. = Theorem, Dem. = Proof.
Benedictus de Spinoza: Ethica part 2. Ethices Pars secunda, De Naturâ & Origine mentis, 1677. "On the nature and origin of the Mind".

The book is perhaps the most ambitious attempt to apply the method of Euclid in philosophy. Spinoza puts forward a small number of definitions and axioms from which he attempts to derive hundreds of propositions and corollaries, such as "When the Mind imagines its own lack of power, it is saddened by it",[2] "A free man thinks of nothing less than of death",[3] and "The human Mind cannot be absolutely destroyed with the Body, but something of it remains which is eternal."[4]

Summary edit

Part I: Of God edit

The first part of the book addresses the relationship between God and the universe. Spinoza was engaging with a tradition that held: God exists outside of the universe; God created the universe for a reason; and God could have created a different universe according to his will. Spinoza denies each point. According to Spinoza, God is the natural world. Spinoza concludes the following: God is the substance comprising the universe, with God existing in itself, not somehow outside of the universe; and the universe exists as it does from necessity, not because of a divine theological reason or will.

Spinoza argues through propositions. He holds the perspective that the conclusion he presents is merely the necessary logical result of combining the provided Definitions and Axioms. He starts with the proposition that "there cannot exist in the universe two or more substances having the same nature or attribute."[5] He follows this by arguing that objects and events must not merely be caused if they occur, but be prevented if they do not. By a logical contradiction, if something is non-contradictory, there is no reason that it should not exist. Spinoza builds from these starting ideas. If substance exists it must be infinite,[6] because if not infinite another finite substance would have to exist to take up the remaining parts of its finite attributes, something which is impossible according to an earlier proposition. Spinoza then uses the Ontological Argument as justification for the existence of God and argues that God (which should be read as "nature", rather than traditional deity) must possess all attributes infinitely. Since no two things can share attributes, "besides God no substance can be granted or conceived."[7]

As with many of Spinoza's claims, what this means is a matter of dispute. Spinoza claims that the things that make up the universe, including human beings, are God's "modes". This means that everything is, in some sense, dependent upon God. The nature of this dependence is disputed. Some scholars say that the modes are properties of God in the traditional sense. Others say that modes are effects of God. Either way, the modes are also logically dependent on God's essence, in this sense: everything that happens follows from the nature of God, just like how it follows from the nature of a triangle that its angles are equal to two right angles. Since God had to exist with the nature he has, nothing that has happened could have been avoided, and if God has fixed a particular fate for a particular mode, there is no escaping it. As Spinoza puts it, "A thing which has been determined by God to produce an effect cannot render itself undetermined."

 
Logical structure of the first six propositions of Spinoza's Ethics

Part II: Of the Nature & Origin of the Mind edit

The second part focuses on the human mind and body. Spinoza attacks several Cartesian positions: (1) that the mind and body are distinct substances that can affect one another; (2) that we know our minds better than we know our bodies; (3) that our senses may be trusted; (4) that despite being created by God we can make mistakes, namely, when we affirm, of our own free will, an idea that is not clear and distinct. Spinoza denies each of Descartes's points. Regarding (1), Spinoza argues that the mind and the body are a single thing that is being thought of in two different ways. The whole of nature can be fully described in terms of thoughts or in terms of bodies. However, we cannot mix these two ways of describing things, as Descartes does, and say that the mind affects the body or vice versa. Moreover, the mind's self-knowledge is not fundamental: it cannot know its own thoughts better than it knows the ways in which its body is acted upon by other bodies.

Further, there is no difference between contemplating an idea and thinking that it is true, and there is no freedom of the will at all. Sensory perception, which Spinoza calls "knowledge of the first kind", is entirely inaccurate, since it reflects how our own bodies work more than how things really are. We can also have a kind of accurate knowledge called "knowledge of the second kind", or "reason". This encompasses knowledge of the features common to all things, and includes principles of physics and geometry. We can also have "knowledge of the third kind", or "intuitive knowledge". This is a sort of knowledge that, somehow, relates particular things to the nature of God.

Part III: Of the Origin & Nature of Emotions edit

In the third part of the Ethics, Spinoza argues that all things, including human beings, strive to persevere their perfection of power in being unaffected.[8] Spinoza states that virtue is equal to power (i.e., self-control).[9]

Spinoza explains how this desire ("conatus") underlies the movement and complexity of our emotions and passions (i.e., joy and sadness that are building blocks for all other emotions).[10] Our mind is in certain cases active, and in certain cases passive. In so far as it has adequate ideas it is necessarily active, and in so far as it has inadequate ideas, it is necessarily passive.

(+) refers to pleasure [...] (-) refers to pain [...] (f) and (i) refer respectively, to feeling and imagining [...]

Proposition 19 would translate:

He who imagines that the loved object (+) is being destroyed (-) feels pain (-). If the loved object (+) is preserved (+), he will feel pleasure (+). Symbolically, this reduces to two equations:

1) [(+) (i)] (-) = [(f) (-)];

2) [(+) (i)] (+) = [(f) (+)].

— Ian S. Miller[11]

Definitions of the Affects edit

Term affect Definition affect Definition / object
Joy[10] passage from a lesser to a greater perfection.
Sadness[10] passage from a greater to a lesser perfection.
Wonder[10] an imagination of a thing in which the mind remains fixed because this singular imagination has no connection with the others.
Disdain[10] an imagination of a thing which touches the mind so little that the thing's presence moves the mind to imagining more what is not than what is.
Love[10] a joy accompanied by the idea of an external cause.
Hate[10] a sadness accompanied by the idea of an external cause.
Inclination[10] a joy accompanied by the idea of a thing which is the accidental cause of joy
Aversion[10] a sadness accompanied by the idea of something which is the accidental cause of sadness.
Devotion[10] a love of one whom we wonder at.
Mockery[10] a joy born of the fact that we imagine something we disdain in a thing we hate.
Hope[10] an inconstant joy born out of the idea of a future or past thing whose outcome we to some extent doubt.
Fear[10] an inconstant sadness born of the idea of a future or past thing whose outcome we to some extent doubt.
Confidence[10] a joy born of the idea of a future or past thing, concerning which the cause of doubting has been removed.
Despair[10] a sadness born of the idea of a future or past thing concerning which the cause of doubting has been removed.
Gladness[10] a joy accompanied by the idea of a past thing which has turned out better than we had hoped.
Remorse[10] a sadness accompanied by the idea of a past thing which has turned out worse than we had hoped.
Pity[10] a sadness accompanied by the idea of an evil which has happened to another whom we imagine to be like us.
Favor[10] a love toward someone who has benefited another.
Indignation[10] a hate toward someone who has done evil to another.
Overestimation[10] out of love thinking more highly of someone than is just.
Scorn[10] out of hate thinking less highly of someone than is just.
Envy[10] hate insofar as it so affects a human that they are saddened by another's happiness and, conversely, glad at another's ill fortune.
Compassion[10] love insofar as it so affects a human that they are glad at another's good fortune and saddened by another's ill fortune.
Self-esteem[10] a joy born of the fact that a human considers itself and its own power of acting
Humility[10] a sadness born of the fact that a human considers its own lack of power and weakness.
Repentance[10] a sadness accompanied by the idea of some deed we believe ourselves to have done from a free decision of the mind.
Pride[10] out of love of oneself thinking more highly of oneself than is just
Despondency[10] out of sadness thinking less highly of oneself than is just
Love of esteem[10] a joy accompanied by the idea of some action of ours which we imagine that others praise.
Shame[10] a sadness accompanied by the idea of some action of ours which we imagine that others blame.
Longing[10] a desire / appetite / sadness to possess something which is encouraged by the memory of that thing while concurrently restrained by the memory of other things which exclude the existence of the thing wanted.
Emulation[10] a desire for a thing which is generated in us because we imagine that others have the same desire.
Gratitude[10] a desire / eagerness for love by which we strive to benefit one who has benefited us from a like affect of love.
Benevolence[10] a desire to benefit one whom we pity.
Anger[10] a desire by which we are spurred
Vengeance[10] a desire by which, from reciprocal hate, we are roused to do evil to one who, from a like affect, has injured us.
Cruelty[10] a desire by which someone is roused to do evil to one whom we love or pity.
Timidity[10] a desire to avoid a greater evil, which we fear, by a lesser one.
Daring[10] a desire by, which someone is spurred to do something dangerous which one's equals fear to take on themselves
Cowardice[10] desire is restrained by timidity in fear of some evil which most people do not usually fear.
Consternation[10] one whose desire to avoid an evil is restrained by wonder at the evil they fear.
Courtesy[10] a desire to do what pleases others and not do what displeases oneself.
Ambition[10] an excessive desire for esteem
Gluttony[10] an immoderate desire for and love of eating.
Drunkenness[10] an immoderate desire for and love of drinking.
Greed[10] an immoderate desire for and love of wealth.
Lust[10] a desire for and love of joining one body to another.

Part IV: Of the Servitude of Humanity, or the Strength of the Emotions edit

The fourth part analyzes human passions, which Spinoza sees as aspects of the mind that direct us outwards to seek what gives pleasure and shun what gives pain. The "bondage" he refers to is domination by these passions or "affects" as he calls them. Spinoza considers how the affects, ungoverned, can torment people and make it impossible for mankind to live in harmony with one another.

Part V: Of the Power of the Intellect, or the Liberty of Humanity edit

The fifth part argues that reason can govern the affects in the pursuit of virtue, which for Spinoza is self-preservation: only with the aid of reason can humans distinguish the passions that truly aid virtue from those that are ultimately harmful. By reason, we can see things as they truly are, sub specie aeternitatis, "under the aspect of eternity," and because Spinoza treats God and nature as indistinguishable, by knowing things as they are we improve our knowledge of God. Seeing that all things are determined by nature to be as they are, we can achieve the rational tranquility that best promotes our happiness, and liberate ourselves from being driven by our passions.

Themes edit

God or Nature edit

According to Spinoza, God is Nature and Nature is God (Deus sive Natura). This is his pantheism. In his previous book, Theologico-Political Treatise, Spinoza discussed the inconsistencies that result when God is assumed to have human characteristics. In the third chapter of that book, he stated that the word "God" means the same as the word "Nature". He wrote: "Whether we say ... that all things happen according to the laws of nature, or are ordered by the decree and direction of God, we say the same thing." He later qualified this statement in his letter to Oldenburg[12] by abjuring materialism.[13] Nature, to Spinoza, is a metaphysical substance, not physical matter.[14] In this posthumously published book Ethics, he equated God with nature by writing "God or Nature" four times.[15] "For Spinoza, God or Nature—being one and the same thing—is the whole, infinite, eternal, necessarily existing, active system of the universe within which absolutely everything exists. This is the fundamental principle of the Ethics...."[16]

Spinoza holds that everything that exists is part of nature, and everything in nature follows the same basic laws. In this perspective, human beings are part of nature, and hence they can be explained and understood in the same way as everything else in nature. This aspect of Spinoza's philosophy — his naturalism — was radical for its time, and perhaps even for today. In the preface to Part III of Ethics (relating to emotions), he writes:

Most writers on the emotions and on human conduct seem to be treating rather of matters outside nature than of natural phenomena following nature's general laws. They appear to conceive man to be situated in nature as a kingdom within a kingdom: for they believe that he disturbs rather than follows nature's order, that he has absolute control over his actions, and that he is determined solely by himself. However, my argument is this. Nothing comes to pass in nature, which can be set down to a flaw therein; for nature is always the same, and everywhere one and the same in her efficacy and power of action; that is, nature's laws and ordinances, whereby all things come to pass and change from one form to another, are everywhere and always the same; so that there should be one and the same method of understanding the nature of all things whatsoever, namely, through nature's universal laws and rules.

— Ethics, Part 3

Therefore, Spinoza affirms that the passions of hatred, anger, envy, and so on, considered in themselves, "follow from this same necessity and efficacy of nature; they answer to certain definite causes, through which they are understood, and possess certain properties as worthy of being known as the properties of anything else". Humans are not different in kind from the rest of the natural world; they are part of it.[17]

Spinoza's naturalism can be seen as deriving from his firm commitment to the principle of sufficient reason (psr), which is the thesis that everything has an explanation. He articulates the psr in a strong fashion, as he applies it not only to everything that is, but also to everything that is not:

Of everything whatsoever a cause or reason must be assigned, either for its existence, or for its non-existence — e.g. if a triangle exists, a reason or cause must be granted for its existence; if, on the contrary, it does not exist, a cause must also be granted, which prevents it from existing, or annuls its existence.

— Ethics, Part 1, XI (emphasis added)

And to continue with Spinoza's triangle example, here is one claim he makes about God:

From God's supreme power, or infinite nature, an infinite number of things – that is, all things have necessarily flowed forth in an infinite number of ways, or always flow from the same necessity; in the same way as from the nature of a triangle it follows from eternity and for eternity, that its three interior angles are equal to two right angles.

— Ethics, Part 1, XVII

Spinoza rejected the idea of an external Creator suddenly, and apparently capriciously, creating the world at one particular time rather than another, and creating it out of nothing. The solution appeared to him more perplexing than the problem, and rather unscientific in spirit as involving a break in continuity. He preferred to think of the entire system of reality as its own ground. This view was simpler; it avoided the impossible conception of creation out of nothing; and it was religiously more satisfying by bringing God and man into closer relationship. Instead of Nature, on the one hand, and a supernatural God, on the other, he posited one world of reality, at once Nature and God, and leaving no room for the supernatural. This so-called naturalism of Spinoza is only distorted if one starts with a crude materialistic idea of Nature and supposes that Spinoza degraded God. The truth is that he raised Nature to the rank of God by conceiving Nature as the fulness of reality, as the One and All. He rejected the specious simplicity obtainable by denying the reality of Matter, or of Mind, or of God. The cosmic system comprehends them all. In fact, God and Nature become identical when each is conceived as the Perfect Self-Existent. This constitutes Spinoza's Pantheism.[17][18]

Structure of reality edit

 
Spinoza's original text of Ethica, Part 1

According to Spinoza, God has "attributes". One attribute is 'extension', another attribute is 'thought', and there are infinitely many such attributes. Since Spinoza holds that to exist is to act, some readers take 'extension' to refer to an activity characteristic of bodies (for example, the active process of taking up space, exercising physical power, or resisting a change of place or shape). They take 'thought' to refer to the activity that is characteristic of minds, namely thinking, the exercise of mental power. Each attribute has modes. All bodies are modes of extension, and all ideas are modes of thought.[18]

Substance, attributes, modes edit

Spinoza's ideas relating to the character and structure of reality are expressed by him in terms of substance, attributes, and modes. These terms are very old and familiar, but not in the sense in which Spinoza employs them. To understand Spinoza, it is necessary to lay aside all preconceptions[19] about them, and follow Spinoza closely.[18][20] Spinoza found it impossible to understand the finite, dependent, transient objects and events of experience without assuming some reality not dependent on anything else but self-existent, not produced by anything else but eternal, not restricted or limited by anything else but infinite. Such an uncaused, self-sustaining reality he called substance. So, for instance, he could not understand the reality of material objects and physical events without assuming the reality of a self-existing, infinite and eternal physical force which expresses itself in all the movements and changes which occur, as we say, in space.

This physical force he called extension, and described it, at first, as a substance, in the sense just explained. Similarly, he could not understand the various dependent, transient mental experiences with which we are familiar without assuming the reality of a self-existing, infinite and eternal consciousness, mental force, or mind-energy, which expresses itself in all these finite experiences of perceiving and understanding, of feeling and striving. This consciousness or mind-energy he called thought, and described it also, at first, as a substance.[21] Each of these "substances" he regarded as infinite of its kind (that is, as exhaustive of all the events of its own kind), and as irreducible to the other, or any other, substance. But in view of the intimate way in which Extension and Thought express themselves conjointly in the life of man, Spinoza considered it necessary to conceive of Extension and Thought not as detached realities, but as constituting one organic whole or system. And in order to express this idea, he then described Extension and Thought as attributes, reserving the term Substance for the system which they constitute between them. This change of description was not intended to deny that Extension and Thought are substances in the sense of being self-existent, etc. It was only intended to express their coherence in one system. The system of course would be more than any one attribute. For each attribute is only infinite of its kind; the system of all attributes is absolutely infinite, that is, exhausts the whole of reality. Spinoza, accordingly, now restricted the term "substance" to the complete system, though he occasionally continued to use the phrase "substance or attribute", or described Extension as a substance.[21]

As commonly used, especially since the time of Locke, the term substance is contrasted with its attributes or qualities as their substratum or bearer. But this meaning must not be read into Spinoza. For Spinoza, Substance is not the support or bearer of the Attributes, but the system of Attributes — he actually uses the expression "Substance or the Attributes."[18] If there is any difference at all between "Substance" and "the Attributes", as Spinoza uses these terms, it is only the difference between the Attributes conceived as an organic system and the Attributes conceived (but not by Spinoza) as a mere sum of detached forces. Something is still necessary to complete the account of Spinoza's conception of Substance. So far only the two Attributes have been considered, namely, Extension and Thought. Spinoza, however, realised that there may be other Attributes, unknown to man. If so, they are part of the one Substance or cosmic system. And using the term "infinite" in the sense of "complete" or "exhaustive", he ascribed to Substance an infinity of Attributes, that is, all the attributes there are, whether known to man or not.[18][21]

Now reality, for Spinoza, is activity. Substance is incessantly active, each Attribute exercising its kind of energy in all possible ways. Thus the various objects and events of the material world come into being as modes (modifications or states) of the attribute Extension; and the various minds and mental experiences come into being as modes of the attribute Thought (or Consciousness). These modes are not external creations of the Attributes, but immanent results — they are not "thrown off" by the Attributes, but are states (or modifications) of them, as air-waves are states of the air. Each Attribute, however, expresses itself in its finite modes not immediately (or directly) but mediately (or indirectly), at least in the sense to be explained now. Galilean physics tended to regard the whole world of physical phenomena as the result of differences of motion or momentum. And, though erroneously conceived, the Cartesian conception of a constant quantity of motion in the world led Spinoza to conceive of all physical phenomena as so many varying expressions of that store of motion (or motion and rest).

Spinoza might, of course, have identified Extension with energy of motion. But, with his usual caution, he appears to have suspected that motion may be only one of several types of physical energy. So he described motion simply as a mode of Extension, but as an infinite mode (because complete or exhaustive of all finite modes of motion) and as an immediate mode (as a direct expression of Extension). Again, the physical world (or "the face of the world as a whole", as Spinoza calls it)[21] retains a certain sameness in spite of the innumerable changes in detail that are going on. Accordingly, Spinoza described also the physical world as a whole as an infinite mode of extension ("infinite" because exhaustive of all facts and events that can be reduced to motion), but as a mediate (or indirect) mode, because he regarded it as the outcome of the conservation of motion (itself a mode, though an immediate mode). The physical things and events of ordinary experience are finite modes. In essence each of them is part of the Attribute Extension, which is active in each of them. But the finiteness of each of them is due to the fact that it is restrained or hedged in, so to say, by other finite modes. This limitation or determination is negation in the sense that each finite mode is not the whole attribute Extension; it is not the other finite modes. But each mode is positively real and ultimate as part of the Attribute.[18][21]

In the same kind of way the Attribute Thought exercises its activity in various mental processes, and in such systems of mental process as are called minds or souls. But in this case, as in the case of Extension, Spinoza conceives of the finite modes of Thought as mediated by infinite modes. The immediate infinite mode of Thought he describes as "the idea of God"; the mediate infinite mode he calls "the infinite idea" or "the idea of all things". The other Attributes (if any) must be conceived in an analogous manner. And the whole Universe or Substance is conceived as one dynamic system of which the various Attributes are the several world-lines along which it expresses itself in all the infinite variety of events.[18][22]

Given the persistent misinterpretation of Spinozism it is worth emphasizing the dynamic character of reality as Spinoza conceived it. The cosmic system is certainly a logical or rational system, according to Spinoza, for Thought is a constitutive part of it; but it is not merely a logical system — it is dynamic as well as logical. His frequent use of geometrical illustrations affords no evidence at all in support of a purely logico-mathematical interpretation of his philosophy; for Spinoza regarded geometrical figures, not in a Platonic or static manner, but as things traced out by moving particles or lines, etc., that is, dynamically.[21][23]

Moral philosophy edit

 
Portrait of Baruch Spinoza, 1665.

Without intelligence there is not rational life: and things are only good, in so far as they aid man in his enjoyment of the intellectual life, which is defined by intelligence. Contrariwise, whatsoever things hinder man's perfecting of his reason, and capability to enjoy the rational life, are alone called evil.

— Ethics, Part IV, Appendix V

For Spinoza, reality means activity, and the reality of anything expresses itself in a tendency to self-preservation — to exist is to persist. In the lowest kinds of things, in so-called inanimate matter, this tendency shows itself as a "will to live". Regarded physiologically the effort is called appetite; when we are conscious of it, it is called desire. The moral categories, good and evil, are intimately connected with desire, though not in the way commonly supposed. Man does not desire a thing because he thinks it is good, or shun it because he considers it bad; rather he considers anything good if he desires it, and regards it as bad if he has an aversion for it. Now whatever is felt to heighten vital activity gives pleasure; whatever is felt to lower such activity causes pain. Pleasure coupled with a consciousness of its external cause is called love, and pain coupled with a consciousness of its external cause is called hate — "love" and "hate" being used in the wide sense of "like" and "dislike". All human feelings are derived from pleasure, pain and desire. Their great variety is due to the differences in the kinds of external objects which give rise to them, and to the differences in the inner conditions of the individual experiencing them.[18]

Spinoza gives a detailed analysis of the whole gamut of human feelings, and his account is one of the classics of psychology.[24] For the present purpose the most important distinction is that between "active" feelings and "passive" feelings (or "passions"). Man, according to Spinoza, is active or free in so far as any experience is the outcome solely of his own nature; he is passive, or a bondsman, in so far as any experience is due to other causes besides his own nature. The active feelings are all of them forms of self-realisation, of heightened activity, of strength of mind, and are therefore always pleasurable. It is the passive feelings (or "passions") which are responsible for all the ills of life, for they are induced largely by things outside us and frequently cause that lowered vitality which means pain. Spinoza next links up his ethics with his theory of knowledge, and correlates the moral progress of man with his intellectual progress. At the lowest stage of knowledge, that of "opinion", man is under the dominant influence of things outside himself, and so is in the bondage of the passions. At the next stage, the stage of "reason", the characteristic feature of the human mind, its intelligence, asserts itself, and helps to emancipate him from his bondage to the senses and external allurements. The insight gained into the nature of the passions helps to free man from their domination. A better understanding of his own place in the cosmic system and of the place of all the objects of his likes and dislikes, and his insight into the necessity which rules all things, tend to cure him of his resentments, regrets and disappointments. He grows reconciled to things, and wins peace of mind. In this way reason teaches acquiescence in the universal order, and elevates the mind above the turmoil of passion. At the highest stage of knowledge, that of "intuitive knowledge", the mind apprehends all things as expressions of the eternal cosmos. It sees all things in God, and God in all things. It feels itself as part of the eternal order, identifying its thoughts with cosmic thought and its interests with cosmic interests. Thereby it becomes eternal as one of the eternal ideas in which the Attribute Thought expresses itself, and attains to that "blessedness" which "is not the reward of virtue, but virtue itself", that is, the perfect joy which characterises perfect self-activity. This is not an easy or a common achievement. "But", says Spinoza, "everything excellent is as difficult as it is rare."[18][25][26]

Reception edit

Shortly after his death in 1677, Spinoza's works were placed on the Catholic Church's Index of Banned Books. Condemnations soon appeared, such as Aubert de Versé's L'impie convaincu (1685). According to its subtitle, in this work "the foundations of [Spinoza's] atheism are refuted". In June 1678 —just over a year after Spinoza's death—the States of Holland banned his entire works, since they “contain very many profane, blasphemous and atheistic propositions.” The prohibition included the owning, reading, distribution, copying, and restating of Spinoza's books, and even the reworking of his fundamental ideas.[27]

For the next hundred years, if European philosophers read this so-called heretic, they did so almost entirely in secret. How much forbidden Spinozism they were sneaking into their diets remains a subject of continual intrigue. Locke, Hume, Leibniz and Kant all stand accused by later scholars of indulging in periods of closeted Spinozism.[28] At the close of the 18th century, a controversy centering on the Ethics scandalized the German philosophy scene.

The first known translation of the Ethics into English was completed in 1856 by the novelist George Eliot, though not published until much later. The book next appeared in English in 1883, by the hand of the novelist Hale White. Spinoza rose clearly into view for anglophone metaphysicians in the late nineteenth century, during the British craze for Hegel. In his admiration for Spinoza, Hegel was joined in this period by his countrymen Schelling, Goethe, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. In the twentieth century, the ghost of Spinoza continued to show itself, for example in the writings of Russell, Wittgenstein, Davidson, and Deleuze. Among writers of fiction and poetry, the influential thinkers inspired by Spinoza include Coleridge, George Eliot, Melville, Borges, and Malamud.

The first published Dutch translations were by the poet Herman Gorter (1895)[29] and by Willem Meyer (1896).[30]

Criticism edit

Number of attributes edit

Spinoza's contemporary, Simon de Vries, raised the objection that Spinoza fails to prove that substances may possess multiple attributes, but that if substances have only a single attribute, "where there are two different attributes, there are also different substances".[31] This is a serious weakness in Spinoza's logic, which has yet to be conclusively resolved. Some have attempted to resolve this conflict, such as Linda Trompetter, who writes that "attributes are singly essential properties, which together constitute the one essence of a substance",[32] but this interpretation is not universal, and Spinoza did not clarify the issue in his response to de Vries.[33] On the other hand, Stanley Martens states that "an attribute of a substance is that substance; it is that substance insofar as it has a certain nature"[34] in an analysis of Spinoza's ideas of attributes.

Misuse of words edit

Schopenhauer claimed that Spinoza misused words. "Thus he calls 'God' that which is everywhere called 'the world'; 'justice' that which is everywhere called 'power'; and 'will' that which is everywhere called 'judgement'."[35] Also, "that concept of substance...with the definition of which Spinoza accordingly begins...appears on close and honest investigation to be a higher yet unjustified abstraction of the concept matter."[36] In spite of his repeated objections and critical remarks, Schopenhauer incorporated some of Spinoza's fundamental concepts into his system, especially concerning the theory of emotions; there was also a striking similarity between Schopenhauer's will and Spinoza's substance.[37]

Critical influence edit

In fact, within the German philosophical sphere, Spinoza's influence on German idealism was remarkable.[38] He was both a challenge and inspiration for the three major figures of this movement: Hegel, Schelling and Fichte — who all sought to define their own philosophical positions in relation to his. Schopenhauer, who detested these three philosophers to varying degrees of intensity,[39] also had a similarly ambivalent relation to the Dutch philosopher. How Spinoza came to influence Schopenhauer is not clear, but one might speculate: it could have come from his exposure to Fichte's lectures, from his conversations with Goethe or simply from being caught up in the post-Kantian attempt to rethink the critical philosophy. Still, his engagement with Spinozism is evident throughout his writings and attentive readers of his chief work may indeed note his ambivalence toward Spinoza's philosophy. He sees in Spinoza an ally against the feverish culture of the West. For example, in the context of a rather favourable account of "the standpoint of affirmation" he notes that "[T]he philosophy of Bruno and that of Spinoza might also bring to this standpoint the person whose conviction was not shaken or weakened by their errors and imperfections".[40] Moreover, in discussing Spinoza and Giordano Bruno, Schopenhauer also affirms that:

They do not belong either to their age or to their part of the globe, which rewarded the one with death, and the other with persecution and ignominy. Their miserable existence and death in this Western world are like that of a tropical plant in Europe. The banks of the Ganges were their spiritual home; there they would have led a peaceful and honoured life among men of like mind.

— World, I, 422, n. 2

Given Schopenhauer's respect for Hindu philosophy, comments like these indicate that he too felt intellectual kinship with Spinoza. Elsewhere, Schopenhauer points to more fundamental affinities, but he also criticizes Spinoza. These criticisms deal with fundamental disagreements about the ultimate nature of reality and whether it is to be affirmed or denied.[41]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Genevieve Lloyd, Routledge philosophy guidebook to Spinoza and The ethics, Routledge, 2002, p. 24.
  2. ^ Part 3, proposition 55.
  3. ^ Part 4, proposition 67.
  4. ^ Part 5, proposition 23.
  5. ^ Part 1, Proposition 5
  6. ^ Part 1, Proposition 8
  7. ^ Part 1, Proposition 14
  8. ^ Deleuze, Gilles (1988) [1970]. Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. Translated by Hurley, Robert. City Lights Books. pp. 58, 59, 62, 97. ISBN 978-0-87286-218-0. Conatus. Cf. Power. Desire. Cf. Consciousness, Power [...] all power is inseparable from a capacity for being affected
  9. ^ Spinoza, Benedict (1994). Curley, Edwin (ed.). A Spinoza Reader: the Ethcs and other works. Translated by Curley, Edwin. Princeton University Press. p. 201. ISBN 0-691-00067-0.
  10. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao ap aq ar as at au av Spinoza, Benedict (1994). Curley, Edwin (ed.). A Spinoza Reader: the Ethcs and other works. Translated by Curley, Edwin. Princeton University Press. pp. 189–196. ISBN 0-691-00067-0.
  11. ^ Miller, Ian S. (2022). Clinical Spinoza: Integrating His Philosophy with Contemporary Therapeutic Practice. Psychoanalysis in a New Key Book Series. Routledge. p. 239. doi:10.4324/9781003246404-11. ISBN 978-1-032-15934-8.
  12. ^ Letter XXI (Van Vloten LXXIII)
  13. ^ "The supposition of some, that I endeavor to prove in the Tractatus Theologico–Politicus the unity of God and Nature (meaning by the latter a certain mass or corporeal matter), is wholly erroneous."
  14. ^ "Having established that Nature is an indivisible, infinite, uncaused, substantial whole—in fact, the only substantial whole; that outside of Nature there is nothing; and that everything that exists is a part of Nature and is brought into being by and within Nature with a deterministic necessity through Nature's laws," Spinoza concludes that "God and Nature—the substantial, unique, unified, active, infinitely powerful, necessary cause of everything—are one and the same thing." (A Book Forged in Hell, Steven Nadler, ch.4 [the page number should also be added])
  15. ^ Twice in Part IV, Preface (Deum seu Naturam, Deus seu Natura); twice in Part IV, Proposition IV, Proof (Dei sive Naturæ, Dei seu Naturæ).
  16. ^ Cf. Steven Nadler, A Book Forged in Hell: Spinoza's Scandalous Treatise, Princeton University Press, 2011, ch. 5.
  17. ^ a b Cf. "Introduction to Spinoza's Ethics" 2015-02-26 at the Wayback Machine, by Geoff Pynn, Northern Illinois University, Spring 2012.
  18. ^ a b c d e f g h i Pringle-Pattison, Andrew Seth (1911). "Spinoza, Baruch" . In Chisholm, Hugh (ed.). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 20 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 687–691.
  19. ^ See also "Spinoza's Modal Metaphysics", on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, cit., publ. 21/08/2007.
  20. ^ See also A. Wolf's, "Spinoza, the Man and His Thought", 1933; Antonio Damasio, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain, William Heinemann, 2003, esp. ch. 6, 224–261; Richard McKeon, The Philosophy of Spinoza: The Unity of His Thought, Ox Bow Pr., 1928; Ray Monk & Frederic Raphael, The Great Philosophers. Phoenix, 2000, s.v. "Spinoza", pp. 135–174. See also the very useful Olli Koistinen (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza's Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 2009, esp. ch. 7, by Diane Steinberg, pp. 140–166.
  21. ^ a b c d e f Especially valuable for these specific sections of Spinoza's thought as expounded in his Ethics, have been the online pages by the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy at these four links [1], [2], [3], [4] — which respectively represent an interpretation and commentary of the philosopher's stance on "Modal Metaphysics", "Theory of Attributes", "Psychological Theory", "Physical Theory", and are currently cited as a reference within the present text.
  22. ^ See also The Short Treatise on God, Man and his Well-being, London: A. & C. Black, 2006 – scanned, University of Toronto, Internet Archive.
  23. ^ Cf. Marcello Colitti, Etica e politica di Baruch Spinoza, Aliberti, 2010, esp. s.v. "Etica". (in Italian)
  24. ^ For this and other affirmations about Spinoza's "psychology", cf. esp. "Spinoza's Psychological Theory", on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, cit., rev. 09/08/2010.
  25. ^ Cf. Frédéric Manzini, Spinoza, Points, 2010, esp. Pt. 2, pp. 227–306; Pt. 3, pp. 489–550. (in French)
  26. ^ Cf. also The correspondence of Spinoza, G. Allen & Unwin ltd., 1928, p. 289. See also John Laird, Journal of Philosophical Studies, Vol. 3, No. 12 (Oct., 1928), pp. 544–545.
  27. ^ See: Jonathan Israel, “The Banning of Spinoza's Works in the Dutch Republic (1670–1678)”, in: Wiep van Bunge and Wim Klever (eds.) Disguised and Overt Spinozism around 1700 (Leiden, 1996), 3-14 (online).
  28. ^ See for example Boehm, Omri. 2014. Kant's Critique of Spinoza. New York: Oxford University Press.
  29. ^ publ. Loman en Funke, The Hague, 1895
  30. ^ publ. Van Looy, Amsterdam, 1896
  31. ^ Letter VIII
  32. ^ TROMPETTER, LINDA (January 1981). "Spinoza: A Response to De Vries". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 11 (3): 525–537. doi:10.1080/00455091.1981.10716319. ISSN 0045-5091. S2CID 171006804.
  33. ^ Letter IX
  34. ^ Martens, Stanley C. (January 1978). "Spinoza on attributes". Synthese. 37 (1): 107–111. doi:10.1007/bf00869442. ISSN 0039-7857. S2CID 46971533.
  35. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, vol. I, "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real", p. 13
  36. ^ Parerga and Paralipomena, vol. I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", § 12, p. 76
  37. ^ Cf. Henry Walter Brann, Philosophy and History Archived 2013-04-15 at archive.today, on "Schopenhauer and Spinoza", Vol. 4, Issue 1, 1971, pp. 17–18.
  38. ^ A very detailed examination of Spinoza's influence on German Idealism is given in Jean-Marie Vaysse, Totalité et Subjectivité: Spinoza dans l'Idealisme Allemand, Vrin, 1994.
  39. ^ His vicious attacks on Hegel stand out: once he called him "a commonplace, inane, loathsome, repulsive and ignorant charlatan...""Archived copy". Archived from the original on October 7, 2009. Retrieved June 19, 2015.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  40. ^ Cf. Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, trans. E.F.G. Payne, Dover Books, 1958 [Voll. I & II originally published in 1819 and 1844, respectively], Vol. I, 284.
  41. ^ Cf. essay by Bela Egyed, "Spinoza, Schopenhauer and the Standpoint of Affirmation", on PhaenEx 2, no. 1 (spring/summer 2007): pp. 110–131. The author argues that "Schopenhauer's ambivalence toward Spinoza's philosophy is a reflection of an inner tension within his own doctrine of the denial of the will-to-live, and that his criticisms of Spinoza are related to his rejection of the standpoint of affirmation. In addition ... if this tension is resolved in favour of the standpoint of affirmation, Schopenhauer's own ethics turns out to be closer to Spinoza's than he takes it to be." Egyed also offers a suggestion about the possible relation of Schopenhauer's philosophy to two different strains of Buddhist philosophy: Theravada and Mahayana Buddhism.

Further reading edit

  • Bennett, Jonathan (July 1984). A Study of Spinoza's 'Ethics'. CUP Archive. ISBN 978-0-521-27742-6.
  • Carlisle, Clare. Spinoza's Religion: A New Reading of the 'Ethics'. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2021. ISBN 9780691224190
  • Carlisle, Clare, ed. Spinoza's 'Ethics', translated by George Eliot. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2020.
  • Curley, Edwin (ed.). The Collected Works of Spinoza. vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press 1985.
  • ________. (ed.). The Collected Works of Spinoza. vol. 2. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2016.
  • Curley, Edwin M. Behind the Geometrical Method. A Reading of Spinoza's Ethics, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988.
  • Della Rocca, Michael, (ed.), 2018. The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza. Oxford University Press.
  • Israel, Jonathan, 2023. Spinoza: Life and Legacy. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198857488
  • Kisner, Matthew J. (ed.). Spinoza: Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order. trans. Michael Silverthorne and Matthew J. Kisner. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2018.
  • Krop, H. A., 2002, Spinoza Ethica, Amsterdam: Bert Bakker. Later editions, 2017, Amsterdam: Prometheus. In Dutch with Latin text by Spinoza.
  • Lloyd, Genevieve, 1996. Spinoza and the Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-10781-5, 978-0-415-10782-2
  • Lord, Beth. Spinoza's 'Ethics': An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide. Ediburgh University Press 2010.
  • Nadler, Steven. Spinoza, A Life. 2nd Edition. Cambridge University Press 2018.
  • ______, Spinoza's Ethics: An Introduction, 2006 (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-83620-3).

External links edit

  • The 1883 translation of the Ethics into English by R. H. M. Elwes is available in two places:
    • Wikisource
    • Project Gutenberg
  • Original Latin text on Wikisource
  • EthicaDB hosts translations in several languages.
  • EarlyModernTexts contains a simplified and abridged translation of the Ethics, by Jonathan Bennett
  •   The Ethics public domain audiobook at LibriVox

ethics, spinoza, book, ethics, demonstrated, geometrical, order, latin, ethica, ordine, geometrico, demonstrata, usually, known, ethics, philosophical, treatise, written, latin, baruch, spinoza, benedictus, spinoza, written, between, 1661, 1675, first, publish. Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Latin Ethica ordine geometrico demonstrata usually known as the Ethics is a philosophical treatise written in Latin by Baruch Spinoza Benedictus de Spinoza It was written between 1661 and 1675 1 and was first published posthumously in 1677 The opening page of Spinoza s magnum opus Ethics in the posthumous Latin first editionA manuscript of Baruch de Spinoza Ethica in the Biblioteca Vaticana Vat lat 12838 Part 1 theorems 5 the ending 6 8 Prop Theorem Dem Proof Benedictus de Spinoza Ethica part 2 Ethices Pars secunda De Natura amp Origine mentis 1677 On the nature and origin of the Mind The book is perhaps the most ambitious attempt to apply the method of Euclid in philosophy Spinoza puts forward a small number of definitions and axioms from which he attempts to derive hundreds of propositions and corollaries such as When the Mind imagines its own lack of power it is saddened by it 2 A free man thinks of nothing less than of death 3 and The human Mind cannot be absolutely destroyed with the Body but something of it remains which is eternal 4 Contents 1 Summary 1 1 Part I Of God 1 2 Part II Of the Nature amp Origin of the Mind 1 3 Part III Of the Origin amp Nature of Emotions 1 3 1 Definitions of the Affects 1 4 Part IV Of the Servitude of Humanity or the Strength of the Emotions 1 5 Part V Of the Power of the Intellect or the Liberty of Humanity 2 Themes 2 1 God or Nature 2 2 Structure of reality 2 2 1 Substance attributes modes 2 3 Moral philosophy 3 Reception 4 Criticism 4 1 Number of attributes 4 2 Misuse of words 4 3 Critical influence 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksSummary editThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Ethics Spinoza book news newspapers books scholar JSTOR November 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Part I Of God edit The first part of the book addresses the relationship between God and the universe Spinoza was engaging with a tradition that held God exists outside of the universe God created the universe for a reason and God could have created a different universe according to his will Spinoza denies each point According to Spinoza God is the natural world Spinoza concludes the following God is the substance comprising the universe with God existing in itself not somehow outside of the universe and the universe exists as it does from necessity not because of a divine theological reason or will Spinoza argues through propositions He holds the perspective that the conclusion he presents is merely the necessary logical result of combining the provided Definitions and Axioms He starts with the proposition that there cannot exist in the universe two or more substances having the same nature or attribute 5 He follows this by arguing that objects and events must not merely be caused if they occur but be prevented if they do not By a logical contradiction if something is non contradictory there is no reason that it should not exist Spinoza builds from these starting ideas If substance exists it must be infinite 6 because if not infinite another finite substance would have to exist to take up the remaining parts of its finite attributes something which is impossible according to an earlier proposition Spinoza then uses the Ontological Argument as justification for the existence of God and argues that God which should be read as nature rather than traditional deity must possess all attributes infinitely Since no two things can share attributes besides God no substance can be granted or conceived 7 As with many of Spinoza s claims what this means is a matter of dispute Spinoza claims that the things that make up the universe including human beings are God s modes This means that everything is in some sense dependent upon God The nature of this dependence is disputed Some scholars say that the modes are properties of God in the traditional sense Others say that modes are effects of God Either way the modes are also logically dependent on God s essence in this sense everything that happens follows from the nature of God just like how it follows from the nature of a triangle that its angles are equal to two right angles Since God had to exist with the nature he has nothing that has happened could have been avoided and if God has fixed a particular fate for a particular mode there is no escaping it As Spinoza puts it A thing which has been determined by God to produce an effect cannot render itself undetermined nbsp Logical structure of the first six propositions of Spinoza s EthicsPart II Of the Nature amp Origin of the Mind edit The second part focuses on the human mind and body Spinoza attacks several Cartesian positions 1 that the mind and body are distinct substances that can affect one another 2 that we know our minds better than we know our bodies 3 that our senses may be trusted 4 that despite being created by God we can make mistakes namely when we affirm of our own free will an idea that is not clear and distinct Spinoza denies each of Descartes s points Regarding 1 Spinoza argues that the mind and the body are a single thing that is being thought of in two different ways The whole of nature can be fully described in terms of thoughts or in terms of bodies However we cannot mix these two ways of describing things as Descartes does and say that the mind affects the body or vice versa Moreover the mind s self knowledge is not fundamental it cannot know its own thoughts better than it knows the ways in which its body is acted upon by other bodies Further there is no difference between contemplating an idea and thinking that it is true and there is no freedom of the will at all Sensory perception which Spinoza calls knowledge of the first kind is entirely inaccurate since it reflects how our own bodies work more than how things really are We can also have a kind of accurate knowledge called knowledge of the second kind or reason This encompasses knowledge of the features common to all things and includes principles of physics and geometry We can also have knowledge of the third kind or intuitive knowledge This is a sort of knowledge that somehow relates particular things to the nature of God Part III Of the Origin amp Nature of Emotions edit Main articles Affect philosophy and Conatus For broader coverage of this topic see Spinoza Practical Philosophy and Stoicism See also Cognitive behavioral therapy Object relations theory and Psychodynamic psychotherapy In the third part of the Ethics Spinoza argues that all things including human beings strive to persevere their perfection of power in being unaffected 8 Spinoza states that virtue is equal to power i e self control 9 Spinoza explains how this desire conatus underlies the movement and complexity of our emotions and passions i e joy and sadness that are building blocks for all other emotions 10 Our mind is in certain cases active and in certain cases passive In so far as it has adequate ideas it is necessarily active and in so far as it has inadequate ideas it is necessarily passive refers to pleasure refers to pain f and i refer respectively to feeling and imagining Proposition 19 would translate He who imagines that the loved object is being destroyed feels pain If the loved object is preserved he will feel pleasure Symbolically this reduces to two equations 1 i f 2 i f Ian S Miller 11 Definitions of the Affects edit Main article Affect psychology For broader coverage of this topic see Temporality Passion emotion and Passions philosophy See also Beyond Good and Evil and Determinism Term affect Definition affect Definition objectJoy 10 passage from a lesser to a greater perfection Sadness 10 passage from a greater to a lesser perfection Wonder 10 an imagination of a thing in which the mind remains fixed because this singular imagination has no connection with the others Disdain 10 an imagination of a thing which touches the mind so little that the thing s presence moves the mind to imagining more what is not than what is Love 10 a joy accompanied by the idea of an external cause Hate 10 a sadness accompanied by the idea of an external cause Inclination 10 a joy accompanied by the idea of a thing which is the accidental cause of joyAversion 10 a sadness accompanied by the idea of something which is the accidental cause of sadness Devotion 10 a love of one whom we wonder at Mockery 10 a joy born of the fact that we imagine something we disdain in a thing we hate Hope 10 an inconstant joy born out of the idea of a future or past thing whose outcome we to some extent doubt Fear 10 an inconstant sadness born of the idea of a future or past thing whose outcome we to some extent doubt Confidence 10 a joy born of the idea of a future or past thing concerning which the cause of doubting has been removed Despair 10 a sadness born of the idea of a future or past thing concerning which the cause of doubting has been removed Gladness 10 a joy accompanied by the idea of a past thing which has turned out better than we had hoped Remorse 10 a sadness accompanied by the idea of a past thing which has turned out worse than we had hoped Pity 10 a sadness accompanied by the idea of an evil which has happened to another whom we imagine to be like us Favor 10 a love toward someone who has benefited another Indignation 10 a hate toward someone who has done evil to another Overestimation 10 out of love thinking more highly of someone than is just Scorn 10 out of hate thinking less highly of someone than is just Envy 10 hate insofar as it so affects a human that they are saddened by another s happiness and conversely glad at another s ill fortune Compassion 10 love insofar as it so affects a human that they are glad at another s good fortune and saddened by another s ill fortune Self esteem 10 a joy born of the fact that a human considers itself and its own power of actingHumility 10 a sadness born of the fact that a human considers its own lack of power and weakness Repentance 10 a sadness accompanied by the idea of some deed we believe ourselves to have done from a free decision of the mind Pride 10 out of love of oneself thinking more highly of oneself than is justDespondency 10 out of sadness thinking less highly of oneself than is justLove of esteem 10 a joy accompanied by the idea of some action of ours which we imagine that others praise Shame 10 a sadness accompanied by the idea of some action of ours which we imagine that others blame Longing 10 a desire appetite sadness to possess something which is encouraged by the memory of that thing while concurrently restrained by the memory of other things which exclude the existence of the thing wanted Emulation 10 a desire for a thing which is generated in us because we imagine that others have the same desire Gratitude 10 a desire eagerness for love by which we strive to benefit one who has benefited us from a like affect of love Benevolence 10 a desire to benefit one whom we pity Anger 10 a desire by which we are spurredVengeance 10 a desire by which from reciprocal hate we are roused to do evil to one who from a like affect has injured us Cruelty 10 a desire by which someone is roused to do evil to one whom we love or pity Timidity 10 a desire to avoid a greater evil which we fear by a lesser one Daring 10 a desire by which someone is spurred to do something dangerous which one s equals fear to take on themselvesCowardice 10 desire is restrained by timidity in fear of some evil which most people do not usually fear Consternation 10 one whose desire to avoid an evil is restrained by wonder at the evil they fear Courtesy 10 a desire to do what pleases others and not do what displeases oneself Ambition 10 an excessive desire for esteemGluttony 10 an immoderate desire for and love of eating Drunkenness 10 an immoderate desire for and love of drinking Greed 10 an immoderate desire for and love of wealth Lust 10 a desire for and love of joining one body to another Part IV Of the Servitude of Humanity or the Strength of the Emotions edit The fourth part analyzes human passions which Spinoza sees as aspects of the mind that direct us outwards to seek what gives pleasure and shun what gives pain The bondage he refers to is domination by these passions or affects as he calls them Spinoza considers how the affects ungoverned can torment people and make it impossible for mankind to live in harmony with one another Part V Of the Power of the Intellect or the Liberty of Humanity edit The fifth part argues that reason can govern the affects in the pursuit of virtue which for Spinoza is self preservation only with the aid of reason can humans distinguish the passions that truly aid virtue from those that are ultimately harmful By reason we can see things as they truly are sub specie aeternitatis under the aspect of eternity and because Spinoza treats God and nature as indistinguishable by knowing things as they are we improve our knowledge of God Seeing that all things are determined by nature to be as they are we can achieve the rational tranquility that best promotes our happiness and liberate ourselves from being driven by our passions Themes editGod or Nature edit According to Spinoza God is Nature and Nature is God Deus sive Natura This is his pantheism In his previous book Theologico Political Treatise Spinoza discussed the inconsistencies that result when God is assumed to have human characteristics In the third chapter of that book he stated that the word God means the same as the word Nature He wrote Whether we say that all things happen according to the laws of nature or are ordered by the decree and direction of God we say the same thing He later qualified this statement in his letter to Oldenburg 12 by abjuring materialism 13 Nature to Spinoza is a metaphysical substance not physical matter 14 In this posthumously published book Ethics he equated God with nature by writing God or Nature four times 15 For Spinoza God or Nature being one and the same thing is the whole infinite eternal necessarily existing active system of the universe within which absolutely everything exists This is the fundamental principle of the Ethics 16 Spinoza holds that everything that exists is part of nature and everything in nature follows the same basic laws In this perspective human beings are part of nature and hence they can be explained and understood in the same way as everything else in nature This aspect of Spinoza s philosophy his naturalism was radical for its time and perhaps even for today In the preface to Part III of Ethics relating to emotions he writes Most writers on the emotions and on human conduct seem to be treating rather of matters outside nature than of natural phenomena following nature s general laws They appear to conceive man to be situated in nature as a kingdom within a kingdom for they believe that he disturbs rather than follows nature s order that he has absolute control over his actions and that he is determined solely by himself However my argument is this Nothing comes to pass in nature which can be set down to a flaw therein for nature is always the same and everywhere one and the same in her efficacy and power of action that is nature s laws and ordinances whereby all things come to pass and change from one form to another are everywhere and always the same so that there should be one and the same method of understanding the nature of all things whatsoever namely through nature s universal laws and rules Ethics Part 3 Therefore Spinoza affirms that the passions of hatred anger envy and so on considered in themselves follow from this same necessity and efficacy of nature they answer to certain definite causes through which they are understood and possess certain properties as worthy of being known as the properties of anything else Humans are not different in kind from the rest of the natural world they are part of it 17 Spinoza s naturalism can be seen as deriving from his firm commitment to the principle of sufficient reason psr which is the thesis that everything has an explanation He articulates the psr in a strong fashion as he applies it not only to everything that is but also to everything that is not Of everything whatsoever a cause or reason must be assigned either for its existence or for its non existence e g if a triangle exists a reason or cause must be granted for its existence if on the contrary it does not exist a cause must also be granted which prevents it from existing or annuls its existence Ethics Part 1 XI emphasis added And to continue with Spinoza s triangle example here is one claim he makes about God From God s supreme power or infinite nature an infinite number of things that is all things have necessarily flowed forth in an infinite number of ways or always flow from the same necessity in the same way as from the nature of a triangle it follows from eternity and for eternity that its three interior angles are equal to two right angles Ethics Part 1 XVII Spinoza rejected the idea of an external Creator suddenly and apparently capriciously creating the world at one particular time rather than another and creating it out of nothing The solution appeared to him more perplexing than the problem and rather unscientific in spirit as involving a break in continuity He preferred to think of the entire system of reality as its own ground This view was simpler it avoided the impossible conception of creation out of nothing and it was religiously more satisfying by bringing God and man into closer relationship Instead of Nature on the one hand and a supernatural God on the other he posited one world of reality at once Nature and God and leaving no room for the supernatural This so called naturalism of Spinoza is only distorted if one starts with a crude materialistic idea of Nature and supposes that Spinoza degraded God The truth is that he raised Nature to the rank of God by conceiving Nature as the fulness of reality as the One and All He rejected the specious simplicity obtainable by denying the reality of Matter or of Mind or of God The cosmic system comprehends them all In fact God and Nature become identical when each is conceived as the Perfect Self Existent This constitutes Spinoza s Pantheism 17 18 Structure of reality edit nbsp Spinoza s original text of Ethica Part 1According to Spinoza God has attributes One attribute is extension another attribute is thought and there are infinitely many such attributes Since Spinoza holds that to exist is to act some readers take extension to refer to an activity characteristic of bodies for example the active process of taking up space exercising physical power or resisting a change of place or shape They take thought to refer to the activity that is characteristic of minds namely thinking the exercise of mental power Each attribute has modes All bodies are modes of extension and all ideas are modes of thought 18 Substance attributes modes edit Spinoza s ideas relating to the character and structure of reality are expressed by him in terms of substance attributes and modes These terms are very old and familiar but not in the sense in which Spinoza employs them To understand Spinoza it is necessary to lay aside all preconceptions 19 about them and follow Spinoza closely 18 20 Spinoza found it impossible to understand the finite dependent transient objects and events of experience without assuming some reality not dependent on anything else but self existent not produced by anything else but eternal not restricted or limited by anything else but infinite Such an uncaused self sustaining reality he called substance So for instance he could not understand the reality of material objects and physical events without assuming the reality of a self existing infinite and eternal physical force which expresses itself in all the movements and changes which occur as we say in space This physical force he called extension and described it at first as a substance in the sense just explained Similarly he could not understand the various dependent transient mental experiences with which we are familiar without assuming the reality of a self existing infinite and eternal consciousness mental force or mind energy which expresses itself in all these finite experiences of perceiving and understanding of feeling and striving This consciousness or mind energy he called thought and described it also at first as a substance 21 Each of these substances he regarded as infinite of its kind that is as exhaustive of all the events of its own kind and as irreducible to the other or any other substance But in view of the intimate way in which Extension and Thought express themselves conjointly in the life of man Spinoza considered it necessary to conceive of Extension and Thought not as detached realities but as constituting one organic whole or system And in order to express this idea he then described Extension and Thought as attributes reserving the term Substance for the system which they constitute between them This change of description was not intended to deny that Extension and Thought are substances in the sense of being self existent etc It was only intended to express their coherence in one system The system of course would be more than any one attribute For each attribute is only infinite of its kind the system of all attributes is absolutely infinite that is exhausts the whole of reality Spinoza accordingly now restricted the term substance to the complete system though he occasionally continued to use the phrase substance or attribute or described Extension as a substance 21 As commonly used especially since the time of Locke the term substance is contrasted with its attributes or qualities as their substratum or bearer But this meaning must not be read into Spinoza For Spinoza Substance is not the support or bearer of the Attributes but the system of Attributes he actually uses the expression Substance or the Attributes 18 If there is any difference at all between Substance and the Attributes as Spinoza uses these terms it is only the difference between the Attributes conceived as an organic system and the Attributes conceived but not by Spinoza as a mere sum of detached forces Something is still necessary to complete the account of Spinoza s conception of Substance So far only the two Attributes have been considered namely Extension and Thought Spinoza however realised that there may be other Attributes unknown to man If so they are part of the one Substance or cosmic system And using the term infinite in the sense of complete or exhaustive he ascribed to Substance an infinity of Attributes that is all the attributes there are whether known to man or not 18 21 Now reality for Spinoza is activity Substance is incessantly active each Attribute exercising its kind of energy in all possible ways Thus the various objects and events of the material world come into being as modes modifications or states of the attribute Extension and the various minds and mental experiences come into being as modes of the attribute Thought or Consciousness These modes are not external creations of the Attributes but immanent results they are not thrown off by the Attributes but are states or modifications of them as air waves are states of the air Each Attribute however expresses itself in its finite modes not immediately or directly but mediately or indirectly at least in the sense to be explained now Galilean physics tended to regard the whole world of physical phenomena as the result of differences of motion or momentum And though erroneously conceived the Cartesian conception of a constant quantity of motion in the world led Spinoza to conceive of all physical phenomena as so many varying expressions of that store of motion or motion and rest Spinoza might of course have identified Extension with energy of motion But with his usual caution he appears to have suspected that motion may be only one of several types of physical energy So he described motion simply as a mode of Extension but as an infinite mode because complete or exhaustive of all finite modes of motion and as an immediate mode as a direct expression of Extension Again the physical world or the face of the world as a whole as Spinoza calls it 21 retains a certain sameness in spite of the innumerable changes in detail that are going on Accordingly Spinoza described also the physical world as a whole as an infinite mode of extension infinite because exhaustive of all facts and events that can be reduced to motion but as a mediate or indirect mode because he regarded it as the outcome of the conservation of motion itself a mode though an immediate mode The physical things and events of ordinary experience are finite modes In essence each of them is part of the Attribute Extension which is active in each of them But the finiteness of each of them is due to the fact that it is restrained or hedged in so to say by other finite modes This limitation or determination is negation in the sense that each finite mode is not the whole attribute Extension it is not the other finite modes But each mode is positively real and ultimate as part of the Attribute 18 21 In the same kind of way the Attribute Thought exercises its activity in various mental processes and in such systems of mental process as are called minds or souls But in this case as in the case of Extension Spinoza conceives of the finite modes of Thought as mediated by infinite modes The immediate infinite mode of Thought he describes as the idea of God the mediate infinite mode he calls the infinite idea or the idea of all things The other Attributes if any must be conceived in an analogous manner And the whole Universe or Substance is conceived as one dynamic system of which the various Attributes are the several world lines along which it expresses itself in all the infinite variety of events 18 22 Given the persistent misinterpretation of Spinozism it is worth emphasizing the dynamic character of reality as Spinoza conceived it The cosmic system is certainly a logical or rational system according to Spinoza for Thought is a constitutive part of it but it is not merely a logical system it is dynamic as well as logical His frequent use of geometrical illustrations affords no evidence at all in support of a purely logico mathematical interpretation of his philosophy for Spinoza regarded geometrical figures not in a Platonic or static manner but as things traced out by moving particles or lines etc that is dynamically 21 23 Moral philosophy edit nbsp Portrait of Baruch Spinoza 1665 Without intelligence there is not rational life and things are only good in so far as they aid man in his enjoyment of the intellectual life which is defined by intelligence Contrariwise whatsoever things hinder man s perfecting of his reason and capability to enjoy the rational life are alone called evil Ethics Part IV Appendix V For Spinoza reality means activity and the reality of anything expresses itself in a tendency to self preservation to exist is to persist In the lowest kinds of things in so called inanimate matter this tendency shows itself as a will to live Regarded physiologically the effort is called appetite when we are conscious of it it is called desire The moral categories good and evil are intimately connected with desire though not in the way commonly supposed Man does not desire a thing because he thinks it is good or shun it because he considers it bad rather he considers anything good if he desires it and regards it as bad if he has an aversion for it Now whatever is felt to heighten vital activity gives pleasure whatever is felt to lower such activity causes pain Pleasure coupled with a consciousness of its external cause is called love and pain coupled with a consciousness of its external cause is called hate love and hate being used in the wide sense of like and dislike All human feelings are derived from pleasure pain and desire Their great variety is due to the differences in the kinds of external objects which give rise to them and to the differences in the inner conditions of the individual experiencing them 18 Spinoza gives a detailed analysis of the whole gamut of human feelings and his account is one of the classics of psychology 24 For the present purpose the most important distinction is that between active feelings and passive feelings or passions Man according to Spinoza is active or free in so far as any experience is the outcome solely of his own nature he is passive or a bondsman in so far as any experience is due to other causes besides his own nature The active feelings are all of them forms of self realisation of heightened activity of strength of mind and are therefore always pleasurable It is the passive feelings or passions which are responsible for all the ills of life for they are induced largely by things outside us and frequently cause that lowered vitality which means pain Spinoza next links up his ethics with his theory of knowledge and correlates the moral progress of man with his intellectual progress At the lowest stage of knowledge that of opinion man is under the dominant influence of things outside himself and so is in the bondage of the passions At the next stage the stage of reason the characteristic feature of the human mind its intelligence asserts itself and helps to emancipate him from his bondage to the senses and external allurements The insight gained into the nature of the passions helps to free man from their domination A better understanding of his own place in the cosmic system and of the place of all the objects of his likes and dislikes and his insight into the necessity which rules all things tend to cure him of his resentments regrets and disappointments He grows reconciled to things and wins peace of mind In this way reason teaches acquiescence in the universal order and elevates the mind above the turmoil of passion At the highest stage of knowledge that of intuitive knowledge the mind apprehends all things as expressions of the eternal cosmos It sees all things in God and God in all things It feels itself as part of the eternal order identifying its thoughts with cosmic thought and its interests with cosmic interests Thereby it becomes eternal as one of the eternal ideas in which the Attribute Thought expresses itself and attains to that blessedness which is not the reward of virtue but virtue itself that is the perfect joy which characterises perfect self activity This is not an easy or a common achievement But says Spinoza everything excellent is as difficult as it is rare 18 25 26 Reception editMain article Spinozism Shortly after his death in 1677 Spinoza s works were placed on the Catholic Church s Index of Banned Books Condemnations soon appeared such as Aubert de Verse s L impie convaincu 1685 According to its subtitle in this work the foundations of Spinoza s atheism are refuted In June 1678 just over a year after Spinoza s death the States of Holland banned his entire works since they contain very many profane blasphemous and atheistic propositions The prohibition included the owning reading distribution copying and restating of Spinoza s books and even the reworking of his fundamental ideas 27 For the next hundred years if European philosophers read this so called heretic they did so almost entirely in secret How much forbidden Spinozism they were sneaking into their diets remains a subject of continual intrigue Locke Hume Leibniz and Kant all stand accused by later scholars of indulging in periods of closeted Spinozism 28 At the close of the 18th century a controversy centering on the Ethics scandalized the German philosophy scene The first known translation of the Ethics into English was completed in 1856 by the novelist George Eliot though not published until much later The book next appeared in English in 1883 by the hand of the novelist Hale White Spinoza rose clearly into view for anglophone metaphysicians in the late nineteenth century during the British craze for Hegel In his admiration for Spinoza Hegel was joined in this period by his countrymen Schelling Goethe Schopenhauer and Nietzsche In the twentieth century the ghost of Spinoza continued to show itself for example in the writings of Russell Wittgenstein Davidson and Deleuze Among writers of fiction and poetry the influential thinkers inspired by Spinoza include Coleridge George Eliot Melville Borges and Malamud The first published Dutch translations were by the poet Herman Gorter 1895 29 and by Willem Meyer 1896 30 Criticism editThis section contains information of unclear or questionable importance or relevance to the article s subject Please help improve this section by clarifying or removing indiscriminate details Non important content should likely be moved to another article or removed January 2020 Learn how and when to remove this template message Number of attributes edit Spinoza s contemporary Simon de Vries raised the objection that Spinoza fails to prove that substances may possess multiple attributes but that if substances have only a single attribute where there are two different attributes there are also different substances 31 This is a serious weakness in Spinoza s logic which has yet to be conclusively resolved Some have attempted to resolve this conflict such as Linda Trompetter who writes that attributes are singly essential properties which together constitute the one essence of a substance 32 but this interpretation is not universal and Spinoza did not clarify the issue in his response to de Vries 33 On the other hand Stanley Martens states that an attribute of a substance is that substance it is that substance insofar as it has a certain nature 34 in an analysis of Spinoza s ideas of attributes Misuse of words edit Schopenhauer claimed that Spinoza misused words Thus he calls God that which is everywhere called the world justice that which is everywhere called power and will that which is everywhere called judgement 35 Also that concept of substance with the definition of which Spinoza accordingly begins appears on close and honest investigation to be a higher yet unjustified abstraction of the concept matter 36 In spite of his repeated objections and critical remarks Schopenhauer incorporated some of Spinoza s fundamental concepts into his system especially concerning the theory of emotions there was also a striking similarity between Schopenhauer s will and Spinoza s substance 37 Critical influence edit In fact within the German philosophical sphere Spinoza s influence on German idealism was remarkable 38 He was both a challenge and inspiration for the three major figures of this movement Hegel Schelling and Fichte who all sought to define their own philosophical positions in relation to his Schopenhauer who detested these three philosophers to varying degrees of intensity 39 also had a similarly ambivalent relation to the Dutch philosopher How Spinoza came to influence Schopenhauer is not clear but one might speculate it could have come from his exposure to Fichte s lectures from his conversations with Goethe or simply from being caught up in the post Kantian attempt to rethink the critical philosophy Still his engagement with Spinozism is evident throughout his writings and attentive readers of his chief work may indeed note his ambivalence toward Spinoza s philosophy He sees in Spinoza an ally against the feverish culture of the West For example in the context of a rather favourable account of the standpoint of affirmation he notes that T he philosophy of Bruno and that of Spinoza might also bring to this standpoint the person whose conviction was not shaken or weakened by their errors and imperfections 40 Moreover in discussing Spinoza and Giordano Bruno Schopenhauer also affirms that They do not belong either to their age or to their part of the globe which rewarded the one with death and the other with persecution and ignominy Their miserable existence and death in this Western world are like that of a tropical plant in Europe The banks of the Ganges were their spiritual home there they would have led a peaceful and honoured life among men of like mind World I 422 n 2 Given Schopenhauer s respect for Hindu philosophy comments like these indicate that he too felt intellectual kinship with Spinoza Elsewhere Schopenhauer points to more fundamental affinities but he also criticizes Spinoza These criticisms deal with fundamental disagreements about the ultimate nature of reality and whether it is to be affirmed or denied 41 See also editNatura naturans Natura naturata Nature connectedness Opera Posthuma Pantheism Philosophy of SpinozaReferences edit Genevieve Lloyd Routledge philosophy guidebook to Spinoza and The ethics Routledge 2002 p 24 Part 3 proposition 55 Part 4 proposition 67 Part 5 proposition 23 Part 1 Proposition 5 Part 1 Proposition 8 Part 1 Proposition 14 Deleuze Gilles 1988 1970 Spinoza Practical Philosophy Translated by Hurley Robert City Lights Books pp 58 59 62 97 ISBN 978 0 87286 218 0 Conatus Cf Power Desire Cf Consciousness Power all power is inseparable from a capacity for being affected Spinoza Benedict 1994 Curley Edwin ed A Spinoza Reader the Ethcs and other works Translated by Curley Edwin Princeton University Press p 201 ISBN 0 691 00067 0 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao ap aq ar as at au av Spinoza Benedict 1994 Curley Edwin ed A Spinoza Reader the Ethcs and other works Translated by Curley Edwin Princeton University Press pp 189 196 ISBN 0 691 00067 0 Miller Ian S 2022 Clinical Spinoza Integrating His Philosophy with Contemporary Therapeutic Practice Psychoanalysis in a New Key Book Series Routledge p 239 doi 10 4324 9781003246404 11 ISBN 978 1 032 15934 8 Letter XXI Van Vloten LXXIII The supposition of some that I endeavor to prove in the Tractatus Theologico Politicus the unity of God and Nature meaning by the latter a certain mass or corporeal matter is wholly erroneous Having established that Nature is an indivisible infinite uncaused substantial whole in fact the only substantial whole that outside of Nature there is nothing and that everything that exists is a part of Nature and is brought into being by and within Nature with a deterministic necessity through Nature s laws Spinoza concludes that God and Nature the substantial unique unified active infinitely powerful necessary cause of everything are one and the same thing A Book Forged in Hell Steven Nadler ch 4 the page number should also be added Twice in Part IV Preface Deum seu Naturam Deus seu Natura twice in Part IV Proposition IV Proof Dei sive Naturae Dei seu Naturae Cf Steven Nadler A Book Forged in Hell Spinoza s Scandalous Treatise Princeton University Press 2011 ch 5 a b Cf Introduction to Spinoza s Ethics Archived 2015 02 26 at the Wayback Machine by Geoff Pynn Northern Illinois University Spring 2012 a b c d e f g h i Pringle Pattison Andrew Seth 1911 Spinoza Baruch In Chisholm Hugh ed Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 20 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 687 691 See also Spinoza s Modal Metaphysics on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy cit publ 21 08 2007 See also A Wolf s Spinoza the Man and His Thought 1933 Antonio Damasio Looking for Spinoza Joy Sorrow and the Feeling Brain William Heinemann 2003 esp ch 6 224 261 Richard McKeon The Philosophy of Spinoza The Unity of His Thought Ox Bow Pr 1928 Ray Monk amp Frederic Raphael The Great Philosophers Phoenix 2000 s v Spinoza pp 135 174 See also the very useful Olli Koistinen ed The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza s Ethics Cambridge University Press 2009 esp ch 7 by Diane Steinberg pp 140 166 a b c d e f Especially valuable for these specific sections of Spinoza s thought as expounded in his Ethics have been the online pages by the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy at these four links 1 2 3 4 which respectively represent an interpretation and commentary of the philosopher s stance on Modal Metaphysics Theory of Attributes Psychological Theory Physical Theory and are currently cited as a reference within the present text See also The Short Treatise on God Man and his Well being London A amp C Black 2006 scanned University of Toronto Internet Archive Cf Marcello Colitti Etica e politica di Baruch Spinoza Aliberti 2010 esp s v Etica in Italian For this and other affirmations about Spinoza s psychology cf esp Spinoza s Psychological Theory on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy cit rev 09 08 2010 Cf Frederic Manzini Spinoza Points 2010 esp Pt 2 pp 227 306 Pt 3 pp 489 550 in French Cf also The correspondence of Spinoza G Allen amp Unwin ltd 1928 p 289 See also John Laird Journal of Philosophical Studies Vol 3 No 12 Oct 1928 pp 544 545 See Jonathan Israel The Banning of Spinoza s Works in the Dutch Republic 1670 1678 in Wiep van Bunge and Wim Klever eds Disguised and Overt Spinozism around 1700 Leiden 1996 3 14 online See for example Boehm Omri 2014 Kant s Critique of Spinoza New York Oxford University Press publ Loman en Funke The Hague 1895 publ Van Looy Amsterdam 1896 Letter VIII TROMPETTER LINDA January 1981 Spinoza A Response to De Vries Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 3 525 537 doi 10 1080 00455091 1981 10716319 ISSN 0045 5091 S2CID 171006804 Letter IX Martens Stanley C January 1978 Spinoza on attributes Synthese 37 1 107 111 doi 10 1007 bf00869442 ISSN 0039 7857 S2CID 46971533 Parerga and Paralipomena vol I Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real p 13 Parerga and Paralipomena vol I Fragments for the History of Philosophy 12 p 76 Cf Henry Walter Brann Philosophy and History Archived 2013 04 15 at archive today on Schopenhauer and Spinoza Vol 4 Issue 1 1971 pp 17 18 A very detailed examination of Spinoza s influence on German Idealism is given in Jean Marie Vaysse Totalite et Subjectivite Spinoza dans l Idealisme Allemand Vrin 1994 His vicious attacks on Hegel stand out once he called him a commonplace inane loathsome repulsive and ignorant charlatan Archived copy Archived from the original on October 7 2009 Retrieved June 19 2015 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link Cf Schopenhauer The World as Will and Representation trans E F G Payne Dover Books 1958 Voll I amp II originally published in 1819 and 1844 respectively Vol I 284 Cf essay by Bela Egyed Spinoza Schopenhauer and the Standpoint of Affirmation on PhaenEx 2 no 1 spring summer 2007 pp 110 131 The author argues that Schopenhauer s ambivalence toward Spinoza s philosophy is a reflection of an inner tension within his own doctrine of the denial of the will to live and that his criticisms of Spinoza are related to his rejection of the standpoint of affirmation In addition if this tension is resolved in favour of the standpoint of affirmation Schopenhauer s own ethics turns out to be closer to Spinoza s than he takes it to be Egyed also offers a suggestion about the possible relation of Schopenhauer s philosophy to two different strains of Buddhist philosophy Theravada and Mahayana Buddhism Further reading editBennett Jonathan July 1984 A Study of Spinoza s Ethics CUP Archive ISBN 978 0 521 27742 6 Carlisle Clare Spinoza s Religion A New Reading of the Ethics Princeton Princeton University Press 2021 ISBN 9780691224190 Carlisle Clare ed Spinoza s Ethics translated by George Eliot Princeton Princeton University Press 2020 Curley Edwin ed The Collected Works of Spinoza vol 1 Princeton Princeton University Press 1985 ed The Collected Works of Spinoza vol 2 Princeton Princeton University Press 2016 Curley Edwin M Behind the Geometrical Method A Reading of Spinoza s Ethics Princeton Princeton University Press 1988 Della Rocca Michael ed 2018 The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza Oxford University Press Israel Jonathan 2023 Spinoza Life and Legacy New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198857488 Kisner Matthew J ed Spinoza Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order trans Michael Silverthorne and Matthew J Kisner Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2018 Krop H A 2002 Spinoza Ethica Amsterdam Bert Bakker Later editions 2017 Amsterdam Prometheus In Dutch with Latin text by Spinoza Lloyd Genevieve 1996 Spinoza and the Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 10781 5 978 0 415 10782 2 Lord Beth Spinoza s Ethics An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide Ediburgh University Press 2010 Nadler Steven Spinoza A Life 2nd Edition Cambridge University Press 2018 Spinoza s Ethics An Introduction 2006 Cambridge England Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 83620 3 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Ethics Spinoza book nbsp Wikisource has original text related to this article Ethics Spinoza The 1883 translation of the Ethics into English by R H M Elwes is available in two places Wikisource Project Gutenberg Original Latin text on Wikisource EthicaDB hosts translations in several languages EarlyModernTexts contains a simplified and abridged translation of the Ethics by Jonathan Bennett nbsp The Ethics public domain audiobook at LibriVox Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Ethics Spinoza book amp oldid 1184332405 God or Nature, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.