fbpx
Wikipedia

Conatus

In the philosophy of Baruch Spinoza, conatus (/kˈntəs/; wikt:conatus; Latin for "effort; endeavor; impulse, inclination, tendency; undertaking; striving") is an innate inclination of a thing to continue to exist and enhance itself. This "thing" may be mind, matter, or a combination of both, and is often associated with God's will in a pantheist view of nature. The conatus may refer to the instinctive "will to live" of living organisms or to various metaphysical theories of motion and inertia. Today, conatus is rarely used in the technical sense, since classical mechanics uses concepts such as inertia and conservation of momentum that have superseded it. It has, however, been a notable influence on later thinkers such as Arthur Schopenhauer and Friedrich Nietzsche.

Conatus is, for Baruch Spinoza, where "each thing, as far as it lies in itself, strives to persevere in its being."[a]

Definition and origin

 
René Descartes used the term conatus in his mechanistic theory of motion.

The Latin cōnātus comes from the verb cōnor, which is usually translated into English as, "to endeavor"; used as an abstract noun, conatus is an innate inclination of a thing to continue to exist and enhance itself. Although the term is most central to Spinoza's philosophy, many other early modern philosophers including René Descartes, Gottfried Leibniz, and Thomas Hobbes made significant contributions, each developing the term differently.[1]

Whereas the medieval Scholastic philosophers such as Jean Buridan developed a notion of impetus as a mysterious intrinsic property of things,[2] René Descartes (1596–1650) developed a more modern, mechanistic concept of motion which he called the conatus.[3] For Descartes, in contrast to Buridan, motion and rest are properties of the interactions of matter according to eternally fixed mechanical laws, not dispositions and intentions, nor as inherent properties or "forces" of things, but rather as a unifying, external characteristic of the physical universe itself.[4] Descartes specifies two varieties of the conatus: conatus a centro,[b] or a theory of gravity and conatus recedendi[c] which represents centrifugal forces.[5] Descartes, in developing his First Law of Nature, also invokes the idea of a conatus se movendi, or "conatus of self-preservation".a generalization of the principle of inertia, which was formalized by Isaac Newton and made into the first of his three Laws of Motion fifty years after the death of Descartes." [6]

Thomas Hobbes criticized previous definitions of conatus for failing to explain the origin of motion, defining conatus to be the infinitesimal unit at the beginning of motion: an inclination in a specified direction. [7] Furthermore, Hobbes uses conatus to describe cognition functions in the mind,[8] describing emotion as the beginning of motion and the will as the sum of all emotions, which forms the conatus of a body and its physical manifestation is the perceived "will to survive".[1] In a notion similar that of Hobbes, Gottfried Leibniz differentiates between the conatus of the body and soul,[9] primarily focusing however on the concept of a conatus of body in developing the principles of integral calculus to explain Zeno's paradoxes of motion.[10] Leibniz later defines the term monadic conatus, as the "state of change" through which his monads perpetually advance.[11] This conatus is a sort of instantaneous or "virtual" motion that all things possess, even when they are static. Motion, meanwhile, is just the summation of all the conatuses that a thing has, along with the interactions of things. By summing an infinity of such conatuses (i.e., what is now called integration), Leibniz could measure the effect of a continuous force.[12]

In Spinoza's philosophy

Conatus is a central theme in the philosophy of Benedict de Spinoza (1632–1677), which is derived from principles that Hobbes and Descartes developed.[13] Contrary to most philosophers of his time, Spinoza rejects the dualistic assumption that mind, intentionality, ethics, and freedom are to be treated as things separate from the natural world of physical objects and events.[14] One significant change he makes to Hobbes' theory is his belief that the conatus ad motum, (conatus to motion), is not mental, but material.[8] Spinoza also uses conatus to refer to rudimentary concepts of inertia, as Descartes had earlier.[1] According to Spinoza, "each thing, as far as it lies in itself, strives to persevere in its being" (Ethics, part 3, prop. 6). Since a thing cannot be destroyed without the action of external forces, motion and rest, too, exist indefinitely until disturbed.[15] His goal is to provide a unified explanation of all these things within a naturalistic framework, man and nature must be unified under a consistent set of laws; God and nature are one, and there is no free will. For example, an action is "free", for Spinoza, only if it arises from the essence and conatus of an entity. However, an action can still be free in the sense that it is not constrained or otherwise subject to external forces.[16] Human beings are thus an integral part of nature.[15] Spinoza explains seemingly irregular human behaviour as really "natural" and rational and motivated by this principle of the conatus.[15] Some have argued that the conatus consists of happiness and the perpetual drive toward perfection.[17] Conversely, a person is saddened by anything that opposes his conatus. Others have associated "desire", a primary affect, with the conatus principle of Spinoza. Desire is then controlled by the other affects, pleasure and pain, and thus the conatus strives towards that which causes joy and avoids that which produces pain.[8]

Later usages and related concepts

After the development of Classical mechanics, the concept of a conatus, in the sense used by philosophers other than Spinoza,"[8] an intrinsic property of all physical bodies, was largely superseded by the principle of inertia and conservation of momentum. Similarly, Conatus recendendi became centrifugal force, and conatus a centro became gravity.[5] However, Giambattista Vico, inspired by Neoplatonism, explicitly rejected the principle of inertia and the laws of motion of the new physics. For him, conatus was the essence of human society,[18] and also, in a more traditional, hylozoistic sense, as the generating power of movement which pervades all of nature,[19] which was composed neither of atoms, as in the dominant view, nor of extension, as in Descartes, but of metaphysical points animated by a conatus principle provoked by God.[20] Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) developed a principle notably similar to that of Spinoza's conatus.[1][21] This principle, Wille zum Leben, or of a "Will to Live", described the specific phenomenon of an organism's self-preservation instinct.[22] Schopenhauer qualified this, however, by suggesting that the Will to Live is not limited in duration, but rather, "the will wills absolutely and for all time", across generations.[23] Rejecting the primacy of Schopenhauer's Will to Live, Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) developed a separate principle the Will to Power, which comes out of a rejection of such notions of self-preservation.[24] In systems theory, the Spinozistic conception of a conatus has been related to modern theories of autopoiesis in biological systems.[25] However, the scope of the idea is definitely narrower today, being explained in terms of chemistry and neurology where, before, it was a matter of metaphysics and theurgy.[26]

Notes

  1. ^ Ethics, part 3, prop. 6
  2. ^ "tendency towards the center"
  3. ^ "tendency away from the center"
  1. ^ a b c d LeBuffe 2006
  2. ^ Grant 1964, pp. 265–292
  3. ^ Garber 1992, pp. 150, 154
  4. ^ Garber 1992, pp. 180, 184
  5. ^ a b Kollerstrom 1999, pp. 331–356
  6. ^ Wolfson 1934, pp. 197–202.
  7. ^ Hobbes 1998, III, xiv, 2
  8. ^ a b c d Bidney 1962, p. 87-93.
  9. ^ Arthur 1998.
  10. ^ Leibniz 1988, p. 135
  11. ^ Arthur 1994, sec. 3
  12. ^ Gillispie 1971, pp. 159–161
  13. ^ Morgan 2006, p. ix
  14. ^ Jarrett 1991, pp. 470–475
  15. ^ a b c Allison 1975, p. 124-125.
  16. ^ Lachterman 1978
  17. ^ DeBrabander 2007, pp. 20–1
  18. ^ Goulding 2005, p. 22040
  19. ^ Vico 1710, pp. 180–186
  20. ^ Landucci 2004, pp. 1174, 1175
  21. ^ Schopenhauer 1958, p. 357
  22. ^ Rabenort 1911, p. 16
  23. ^ Schopenhauer 1958, p. 568
  24. ^ Durant & Durant 1963, chp. IX
  25. ^ Sandywell 1996, pp. 144–5
  26. ^ Mathews 1991, p. 110

References

  • Allison, Henry E. (1975), Benedict de Spinoza, San Diego: Twayne Publishers, ISBN 978-0-8057-2853-8
  • Arthur, Richard (1994), "Space and relativity in Newton and Leibniz", The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45 (1): 219–240, doi:10.1093/bjps/45.1.219, Thomson Gale Document Number:A16109468
  • Arthur, Richard (1998), "Cohesion, Division and Harmony: Physical Aspects of Leibniz's Continuum Problem (1671–1686)", Perspectives on Science, 6 (1): 110–135, doi:10.1162/posc_a_00546, S2CID 141579187, Thomson Gale Document Number:A54601187
  • Bidney, David (1962), The Psychology and Ethics of Spinoza: A Study in the History and Logic of Ideas, New York: Russell & Russell
  • DeBrabander, Firmin (March 15, 2007), Spinoza and the Stoics: Power, Politics and the Passions, London; New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, ISBN 978-0-8264-9393-4
  • Duchesneau, Francois (Spring–Summer 1998), "Leibniz's Theoretical Shift in the Phoranomus and Dynamica de Potentia", Perspectives on Science, 6 (2): 77–109, doi:10.1162/posc_a_00545, S2CID 141935224, Thomson Gale Document Number: A54601186
  • Durant, Will; Durant, Ariel (1963), , The Story of Civilization, vol. 8, New York: Simon & Schuster, archived from the original on 2007-04-23, retrieved 2007-03-29
  • Dutton, Blake D. (2006), "Benedict De Spinoza", The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 2007-01-15
  • Garber, Daniel (1992), Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, ISBN 978-0-226-28217-6
  • Gillispie, Charles Coulston, ed. (1971), "Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm", Dictionary of Scientific Biography, New York, retrieved 2007-03-27
  • Goulding, Jay (2005), Horowitz, Maryanne (ed.), "Society", New Dictionary of the History of Ideas, Detroit: Charles Scribner's Sons, 5, Thomson Gale Document Number:CX3424300736
  • Grant, Edward (1964), "Motion in the Void and the Principle of Inertia in the Middle Ages", Isis, 55 (3): 265–292, doi:10.1086/349862, S2CID 120402625
  • Hobbes, Thomas (1998), De Corpore, New York: Oxford Publishing Company, ISBN 978-0-19-283682-3
  • Jarrett, Charles (1991), "Spinoza's Denial of Mind-Body Interaction and the Explanation of Human Action", The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 29 (4): 465–486, doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.1991.tb00604.x
  • Jesseph, Doug (2006), (PDF), Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, 3, ISBN 978-0-19-920394-9, archived from the original (PDF) on 2006-11-07, retrieved 2007-03-10
  • Kollerstrom, Nicholas (1999), "The Path of Halley's Comet, and Newton's Late Apprehension of the Law of Gravity", Annals of Science, 59 (4): 331–356, doi:10.1080/000337999296328
  • Lachterman, D. (1978), Robert Shahan; J.I. Biro. (eds.), The Physics of Spinoza's Ethics in Spinoza: New Perspectives, Norman: University of Oklahoma Press
  • Landucci, Sergio (2004), "Vico, Giambattista", in Gianni Vattimo (ed.), Enciclopedia Garzantine della Filosofia, Milan: Garzanti Editore, ISBN 978-88-11-50515-0
  • LeBuffe, Michael (2006-03-20), "Spinoza's Psychological Theory", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), retrieved 2007-01-15
  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Freiherr von (December 31, 1988) [1695], "Exposition and Defence of the New System", in Morris, Mary, M.A. (ed.), Leibniz: Philosophical Writings, J.M. Dent & Sons, p. 136, ISBN 978-0-460-87045-0
  • Mathews, Freya (1991), The Ecological Self, Routledge, ISBN 978-0-415-10797-6
  • Morgan, Michael L. (2006), The Essential Spinoza, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., p. ix, ISBN 978-0-87220-803-2
  • Osler, Margaret J. (2001), "Whose ends? Teleology in early modern natural philosophy", Osiris, 16 (1): 151–168, doi:10.1086/649343, S2CID 143776874, Thomson Gale Document Number:A80401149
  • Polt, Richard (1996), "German Ideology: From France to Germany and Back", The Review of Metaphysics, 49 (3), Thomson Gale Document Number:A18262679
  • Rabenort, William Louis (1911), Spinoza as Educator, New York City: Teachers College, Columbia University
  • Sandywell, Barry (1996), Reflexivity and the Crisis of Western Reason, vol. 1: Logological Investigations, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 144–5, ISBN 978-0-415-08756-8
  • Schmitter, Amy M. (2006), "Hobbes on the Emotions", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retrieved 2006-03-04
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur (1958), Payne, E.F.J. (ed.), The World as Will and Representation, vol. 1, Clinton, Massachusetts: The Colonial Press Inc.
  • Vico, Giambattista (1710), L.M. Palmer (ed.), De antiquissima Italiorum sapientia ex linguae originibus eruenda librir tres, Ithaca: Cornell University Press
  • Wolfson, Harry Austryn (1934). The philosophy of Spinoza : unfolding the latent processes of his reasoning. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-66595-8.
  • Ziemke, Tom (2007), "What's life got to do with it?", in Chella, A.; Manzotti, R. (eds.), Artificial Consciousness, Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, ISBN 9781845406783

Further reading

  • Bove, Laurent (1992), L'affirmation absolue d'une existence : essai sur la stratégie du conatus Spinoziste, Université de Lille III: Lille, OCLC 57584015
  • Duff, Robert Alexander (1903), Spinoza's Political and Ethical Philosophy, J. Maclehose and Sons, ISBN 9780678006153, retrieved 2007-03-19
  • Tuusvuori, Jarkko S. (March 2000), Nietzsche & Nihilism: Exploring a Revolutionary Conception of Philosophical Conceptuality, University of Helsinki, ISBN 978-951-45-9135-8
  • Wendell, Rich (1997), Spinoza's Conatus doctrine: existence, being, and suicide, Waltham, Mass., OCLC 37542442

conatus, this, article, about, term, philosophy, zola, jesus, album, album, journal, philosophy, journal, philosophy, baruch, spinoza, conatus, wikt, conatus, latin, effort, endeavor, impulse, inclination, tendency, undertaking, striving, innate, inclination, . This article is about a term in philosophy For the Zola Jesus album see Conatus album For Conatus Journal of Philosophy see Conatus journal In the philosophy of Baruch Spinoza conatus k oʊ ˈ n eɪ t e s wikt conatus Latin for effort endeavor impulse inclination tendency undertaking striving is an innate inclination of a thing to continue to exist and enhance itself This thing may be mind matter or a combination of both and is often associated with God s will in a pantheist view of nature The conatus may refer to the instinctive will to live of living organisms or to various metaphysical theories of motion and inertia Today conatus is rarely used in the technical sense since classical mechanics uses concepts such as inertia and conservation of momentum that have superseded it It has however been a notable influence on later thinkers such as Arthur Schopenhauer and Friedrich Nietzsche Conatus is for Baruch Spinoza where each thing as far as it lies in itself strives to persevere in its being a Contents 1 Definition and origin 2 In Spinoza s philosophy 3 Later usages and related concepts 4 Notes 5 References 6 Further readingDefinition and origin Edit Rene Descartes used the term conatus in his mechanistic theory of motion The Latin cōnatus comes from the verb cōnor which is usually translated into English as to endeavor used as an abstract noun conatus is an innate inclination of a thing to continue to exist and enhance itself Although the term is most central to Spinoza s philosophy many other early modern philosophers including Rene Descartes Gottfried Leibniz and Thomas Hobbes made significant contributions each developing the term differently 1 Whereas the medieval Scholastic philosophers such as Jean Buridan developed a notion of impetus as a mysterious intrinsic property of things 2 Rene Descartes 1596 1650 developed a more modern mechanistic concept of motion which he called the conatus 3 For Descartes in contrast to Buridan motion and rest are properties of the interactions of matter according to eternally fixed mechanical laws not dispositions and intentions nor as inherent properties or forces of things but rather as a unifying external characteristic of the physical universe itself 4 Descartes specifies two varieties of the conatus conatus a centro b or a theory of gravity and conatus recedendi c which represents centrifugal forces 5 Descartes in developing his First Law of Nature also invokes the idea of a conatus se movendi or conatus of self preservation a generalization of the principle of inertia which was formalized by Isaac Newton and made into the first of his three Laws of Motion fifty years after the death of Descartes 6 Thomas Hobbes criticized previous definitions of conatus for failing to explain the origin of motion defining conatus to be the infinitesimal unit at the beginning of motion an inclination in a specified direction 7 Furthermore Hobbes uses conatus to describe cognition functions in the mind 8 describing emotion as the beginning of motion and the will as the sum of all emotions which forms the conatus of a body and its physical manifestation is the perceived will to survive 1 In a notion similar that of Hobbes Gottfried Leibniz differentiates between the conatus of the body and soul 9 primarily focusing however on the concept of a conatus of body in developing the principles of integral calculus to explain Zeno s paradoxes of motion 10 Leibniz later defines the term monadic conatus as the state of change through which his monads perpetually advance 11 This conatus is a sort of instantaneous or virtual motion that all things possess even when they are static Motion meanwhile is just the summation of all the conatuses that a thing has along with the interactions of things By summing an infinity of such conatuses i e what is now called integration Leibniz could measure the effect of a continuous force 12 In Spinoza s philosophy EditMain article Philosophy of Baruch Spinoza Conatus is a central theme in the philosophy of Benedict de Spinoza 1632 1677 which is derived from principles that Hobbes and Descartes developed 13 Contrary to most philosophers of his time Spinoza rejects the dualistic assumption that mind intentionality ethics and freedom are to be treated as things separate from the natural world of physical objects and events 14 One significant change he makes to Hobbes theory is his belief that the conatus ad motum conatus to motion is not mental but material 8 Spinoza also uses conatus to refer to rudimentary concepts of inertia as Descartes had earlier 1 According to Spinoza each thing as far as it lies in itself strives to persevere in its being Ethics part 3 prop 6 Since a thing cannot be destroyed without the action of external forces motion and rest too exist indefinitely until disturbed 15 His goal is to provide a unified explanation of all these things within a naturalistic framework man and nature must be unified under a consistent set of laws God and nature are one and there is no free will For example an action is free for Spinoza only if it arises from the essence and conatus of an entity However an action can still be free in the sense that it is not constrained or otherwise subject to external forces 16 Human beings are thus an integral part of nature 15 Spinoza explains seemingly irregular human behaviour as really natural and rational and motivated by this principle of the conatus 15 Some have argued that the conatus consists of happiness and the perpetual drive toward perfection 17 Conversely a person is saddened by anything that opposes his conatus Others have associated desire a primary affect with the conatus principle of Spinoza Desire is then controlled by the other affects pleasure and pain and thus the conatus strives towards that which causes joy and avoids that which produces pain 8 Later usages and related concepts EditAfter the development of Classical mechanics the concept of a conatus in the sense used by philosophers other than Spinoza 8 an intrinsic property of all physical bodies was largely superseded by the principle of inertia and conservation of momentum Similarly Conatus recendendi became centrifugal force and conatus a centro became gravity 5 However Giambattista Vico inspired by Neoplatonism explicitly rejected the principle of inertia and the laws of motion of the new physics For him conatus was the essence of human society 18 and also in a more traditional hylozoistic sense as the generating power of movement which pervades all of nature 19 which was composed neither of atoms as in the dominant view nor of extension as in Descartes but of metaphysical points animated by a conatus principle provoked by God 20 Arthur Schopenhauer 1788 1860 developed a principle notably similar to that of Spinoza s conatus 1 21 This principle Wille zum Leben or of a Will to Live described the specific phenomenon of an organism s self preservation instinct 22 Schopenhauer qualified this however by suggesting that the Will to Live is not limited in duration but rather the will wills absolutely and for all time across generations 23 Rejecting the primacy of Schopenhauer s Will to Live Friedrich Nietzsche 1844 1900 developed a separate principle the Will to Power which comes out of a rejection of such notions of self preservation 24 In systems theory the Spinozistic conception of a conatus has been related to modern theories of autopoiesis in biological systems 25 However the scope of the idea is definitely narrower today being explained in terms of chemistry and neurology where before it was a matter of metaphysics and theurgy 26 Notes Edit Ethics part 3 prop 6 tendency towards the center tendency away from the center a b c d LeBuffe 2006 Grant 1964 pp 265 292 Garber 1992 pp 150 154 Garber 1992 pp 180 184 a b Kollerstrom 1999 pp 331 356 Wolfson 1934 pp 197 202 Hobbes 1998 III xiv 2 a b c d Bidney 1962 p 87 93 Arthur 1998 Leibniz 1988 p 135 Arthur 1994 sec 3 Gillispie 1971 pp 159 161 Morgan 2006 p ix Jarrett 1991 pp 470 475 a b c Allison 1975 p 124 125 Lachterman 1978 DeBrabander 2007 pp 20 1 Goulding 2005 p 22040 Vico 1710 pp 180 186 Landucci 2004 pp 1174 1175 Schopenhauer 1958 p 357 Rabenort 1911 p 16 Schopenhauer 1958 p 568 Durant amp Durant 1963 chp IX Sandywell 1996 pp 144 5 Mathews 1991 p 110References EditAllison Henry E 1975 Benedict de Spinoza San Diego Twayne Publishers ISBN 978 0 8057 2853 8 Arthur Richard 1994 Space and relativity in Newton and Leibniz The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 1 219 240 doi 10 1093 bjps 45 1 219 Thomson Gale Document Number A16109468 Arthur Richard 1998 Cohesion Division and Harmony Physical Aspects of Leibniz s Continuum Problem 1671 1686 Perspectives on Science 6 1 110 135 doi 10 1162 posc a 00546 S2CID 141579187 Thomson Gale Document Number A54601187 Bidney David 1962 The Psychology and Ethics of Spinoza A Study in the History and Logic of Ideas New York Russell amp Russell DeBrabander Firmin March 15 2007 Spinoza and the Stoics Power Politics and the Passions London New York Continuum International Publishing Group ISBN 978 0 8264 9393 4 Duchesneau Francois Spring Summer 1998 Leibniz s Theoretical Shift in the Phoranomus and Dynamica de Potentia Perspectives on Science 6 2 77 109 doi 10 1162 posc a 00545 S2CID 141935224 Thomson Gale Document Number A54601186 Durant Will Durant Ariel 1963 XXII Spinoza 1632 77 The Story of Civilization vol 8 New York Simon amp Schuster archived from the original on 2007 04 23 retrieved 2007 03 29 Dutton Blake D 2006 Benedict De Spinoza The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy retrieved 2007 01 15 Garber Daniel 1992 Descartes Metaphysical Physics Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 28217 6 Gillispie Charles Coulston ed 1971 Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm Dictionary of Scientific Biography New York retrieved 2007 03 27 Goulding Jay 2005 Horowitz Maryanne ed Society New Dictionary of the History of Ideas Detroit Charles Scribner s Sons 5 Thomson Gale Document Number CX3424300736 Grant Edward 1964 Motion in the Void and the Principle of Inertia in the Middle Ages Isis 55 3 265 292 doi 10 1086 349862 S2CID 120402625 Hobbes Thomas 1998 De Corpore New York Oxford Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 19 283682 3 Jarrett Charles 1991 Spinoza s Denial of Mind Body Interaction and the Explanation of Human Action The Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 4 465 486 doi 10 1111 j 2041 6962 1991 tb00604 x Jesseph Doug 2006 Hobbesian Mechanics PDF Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 3 ISBN 978 0 19 920394 9 archived from the original PDF on 2006 11 07 retrieved 2007 03 10 Kollerstrom Nicholas 1999 The Path of Halley s Comet and Newton s Late Apprehension of the Law of Gravity Annals of Science 59 4 331 356 doi 10 1080 000337999296328 Lachterman D 1978 Robert Shahan J I Biro eds The Physics of Spinoza s Ethics in Spinoza New Perspectives Norman University of Oklahoma Press Landucci Sergio 2004 Vico Giambattista in Gianni Vattimo ed Enciclopedia Garzantine della Filosofia Milan Garzanti Editore ISBN 978 88 11 50515 0 LeBuffe Michael 2006 03 20 Spinoza s Psychological Theory Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Edward N Zalta ed retrieved 2007 01 15 Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm Freiherr von December 31 1988 1695 Exposition and Defence of the New System in Morris Mary M A ed Leibniz Philosophical Writings J M Dent amp Sons p 136 ISBN 978 0 460 87045 0 Mathews Freya 1991 The Ecological Self Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 10797 6 Morgan Michael L 2006 The Essential Spinoza Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company Inc p ix ISBN 978 0 87220 803 2 Osler Margaret J 2001 Whose ends Teleology in early modern natural philosophy Osiris 16 1 151 168 doi 10 1086 649343 S2CID 143776874 Thomson Gale Document Number A80401149 Polt Richard 1996 German Ideology From France to Germany and Back The Review of Metaphysics 49 3 Thomson Gale Document Number A18262679 Rabenort William Louis 1911 Spinoza as Educator New York City Teachers College Columbia University Sandywell Barry 1996 Reflexivity and the Crisis of Western Reason vol 1 Logological Investigations London and New York Routledge pp 144 5 ISBN 978 0 415 08756 8 Schmitter Amy M 2006 Hobbes on the Emotions Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy retrieved 2006 03 04 Schopenhauer Arthur 1958 Payne E F J ed The World as Will and Representation vol 1 Clinton Massachusetts The Colonial Press Inc Vico Giambattista 1710 L M Palmer ed De antiquissima Italiorum sapientia ex linguae originibus eruenda librir tres Ithaca Cornell University Press Wolfson Harry Austryn 1934 The philosophy of Spinoza unfolding the latent processes of his reasoning Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 66595 8 Ziemke Tom 2007 What s life got to do with it in Chella A Manzotti R eds Artificial Consciousness Exeter UK Imprint Academic ISBN 9781845406783Further reading Edit Look up conatus in Wiktionary the free dictionary Bove Laurent 1992 L affirmation absolue d une existence essai sur la strategie du conatus Spinoziste Universite de Lille III Lille OCLC 57584015 Duff Robert Alexander 1903 Spinoza s Political and Ethical Philosophy J Maclehose and Sons ISBN 9780678006153 retrieved 2007 03 19 Tuusvuori Jarkko S March 2000 Nietzsche amp Nihilism Exploring a Revolutionary Conception of Philosophical Conceptuality University of Helsinki ISBN 978 951 45 9135 8 Wendell Rich 1997 Spinoza s Conatus doctrine existence being and suicide Waltham Mass OCLC 37542442 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Conatus amp oldid 1139624396, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.