fbpx
Wikipedia

Wild animal suffering

Wild animal suffering is the suffering experienced by nonhuman animals living outside of direct human control, due to harms such as disease, injury, parasitism, starvation and malnutrition, dehydration, weather conditions, natural disasters, and killings by other animals,[1][2] as well as psychological stress.[3] Some estimates indicate that these individual animals make up the vast majority of animals in existence.[4] An extensive amount of natural suffering has been described as an unavoidable consequence of Darwinian evolution[5] and the pervasiveness of reproductive strategies which favor producing large numbers of offspring, with a low amount of parental care and of which only a small number survive to adulthood, the rest dying in painful ways, has led some to argue that suffering dominates happiness in nature.[1][6][7]

The topic has historically been discussed in the context of the philosophy of religion as an instance of the problem of evil.[8] More recently, starting in the 19th century, a number of writers have considered the subject from a secular standpoint as a general moral issue, that humans might be able to take actions toward preventing.[9] There is considerable disagreement around taking such actions, as many believe that human interventions in nature, for this reason, should not take place because of practicality,[10] valuing ecological preservation over the well-being and interests of individual animals,[11] considering any obligation to reduce wild animal suffering implied by animal rights to be absurd,[12] or viewing nature as an idyllic place where happiness is widespread.[6] Some have argued that such interventions would be an example of human hubris, or playing God and use examples of how human interventions, for other reasons, have unintentionally caused harm.[13] Others, including animal rights writers, have defended variants of a laissez-faire position, which argues that humans should not harm wild animals, but that humans should not intervene to reduce natural harms that they experience.[14][15]

Advocates of such interventions argue that animal rights and welfare positions imply an obligation to help animals suffering in the wild due to natural processes. Some have asserted that refusing to help animals in situations where humans would consider it wrong not to help humans is an example of speciesism.[2] Others argue that humans intervene in nature constantly—sometimes in very substantial ways—for their own interests and to further environmentalist goals.[16] Human responsibility for enhancing existing natural harms has also been cited as a reason for intervention.[17] Some advocates argue that humans already successfully help animals in the wild, such as vaccinating and healing injured and sick animals, rescuing animals in fires and other natural disasters, feeding hungry animals, providing thirsty animals with water, and caring for orphaned animals.[18] They also assert that although wide-scale interventions may not be possible with our current level of understanding, they could become feasible in the future with improved knowledge and technologies.[19][20] For these reasons, they claim it is important to raise awareness about the issue of wild animal suffering, spread the idea that humans should help animals suffering in these situations and encourage research into effective measures which can be taken in the future to reduce the suffering of these individuals, without causing greater harms.[6][16]

Extent of suffering in nature

Sources of harm

Disease

 
Dead limosa harlequin frog showing symptoms of chytridiomycosis.

Animals in the wild may suffer from diseases which circulate similarly to human colds and flus, as well as epizootics, which are analogous to human epidemics; epizootics are relatively understudied in the scientific literature.[21] Some well-studied examples include chronic wasting disease in elk and deer, white-nose syndrome in bats, devil facial tumour disease in Tasmanian devils and Newcastle disease in birds.[21] Examples of other diseases include myxomatosis and viral haemorrhagic disease in rabbits,[22] ringworm and cutaneous fibroma in deer,[23] and chytridiomycosis in amphibians.[24] Diseases, combined with parasitism, "may induce listlessness, shivering, ulcers, pneumonia, starvation, violent behavior, or other gruesome symptoms over the course of days or weeks leading up to death."[1]

Poor health may dispose wild animals to increased risk of infection, which in turn reduces the health of the animal, further increasing the risk of infection.[25] The terminal investment hypothesis holds that infection can lead some animals to focus their limited remaining resources on increasing the number of offspring they produce.[26]

Injury

Wild animals can experience injury from a variety of causes such as predation; intraspecific competition; accidents, which can cause fractures, crushing injuries, eye injuries and wing tears; self-amputation; molting, a common source of injury for arthropods; extreme weather conditions, such as storms, extreme heat or cold weather; and natural disasters. Such injuries may be extremely painful, which can lead to behaviors which further negatively affect the well-being of the injured animal. Injuries can also make animals susceptible to diseases and other injuries, as well as parasitic infections. Additionally, the affected animal may find it harder to eat and drink and struggle to escape from predators and attacks from other members of their species.[27]

Parasitism

 
Tongue-eating lice are parasites who destroy and replace the tongues of fish.

Many wild animals, particularly larger ones, have been found to be infected with at least one parasite. Parasites can negatively affect the well-being of their hosts by redirecting their host's resources to themselves, destroying their host's tissue and increasing their host's susceptibility to predation.[21] As a result, parasites may reduce the movement, reproduction and survival of their hosts.[28] Parasites can alter the phenotype of their hosts; limb malformations in amphibians caused by Ribeiroia ondatrae, is one example.[29] Some parasites have the capacity to manipulate the cognitive function of their hosts, such as worms which make crickets kill themselves by directing them to drown themselves in water for the purpose of reproduction in an aquatic environment, as well as caterpillars using dopamine containing secretions that manipulate ants to act as bodyguards for protecting the caterpillar from parasites.[30] It is rare that parasites directly cause the death of their host, rather, they may increase the chances of their host's death by other means;[21] one meta-study found that mortality was 2.65 times higher in animals affected by parasites, than those that weren't.[31]

Unlike parasites, parasitoids—which include species of worms, wasps, beetles and flies—kill their hosts, who are generally other invertebrates.[32] Parasitoids specialize in attacking one particular species. Different methods are used by parasitoids to infect their hosts: laying their eggs on plants which are frequently visited by their host, laying their eggs on or close to the host's eggs or young and stinging adult hosts so that they are paralyzed, then laying their eggs near or on them.[32] The larvae of parasitoids grow by feeding on the internal organs and bodily fluids of their hosts,[33] which eventually leads to the death of their host when their organs have ceased to function, or they have lost all of their bodily fluids.[32] Superparasitism is a phenomenon where multiple different parasitoid species simultaneously infect the same host.[34] Parasitoid wasps have been described as having the largest number of species of any other animal species.[35]

Starvation and malnutrition

Starvation and malnutrition particularly affect young, old, sick and weak animals, and can be caused by injury, disease, poor teeth and environmental conditions, with winter being particularly associated with an increased risk.[36] It is argued that because food availability limits the size of wild animal populations, that this means that a huge number of individuals die as a result of starvation; such deaths are described as prolonged and marked by extreme distress as the animal's bodily functions shut down.[37]: 67  Within days of hatching, fish larvae may experience hydrodynamic starvation, whereby the motion of fluids in their environment limits their ability to feed; this can lead to mortality of greater than 99%.[38]

Dehydration

Dehydration is associated with high mortality in wild animals. Drought can cause many animals in larger populations to die of thirst. Thirst can also expose animals to an increased risk of being preyed upon; they may remain hidden in safe spaces to avoid this. However, their need for water may eventually force them to leave these spaces; being in a weakened state, this makes them easier targets for predatory animals. Animals who remain hidden cannot move due to dehydration and may end up dying of thirst. When dehydration is combined with starvation, the process of dehydration can be accelerated.[39] Diseases, such as chytridiomycosis, can also increase the risk of dehydration.[40]

Weather conditions

 
Mountain cottontail in the snow; approximately 60% of these rabbits die during the winter.[41]

Weather has a strong influence on the health and survival of wild animals. Weather phenomena such as heavy snow, flooding and droughts can directly harm animals.[42] and indirectly harm them by increasing the risks of other forms of suffering, such as starvation and disease.[42] Extreme weather can cause the deaths of animals by destroying their habitats and directly killing animals;[43] hailstorms are known to kill thousands of birds.[44][45] Certain weather conditions may maintain large numbers of individuals over many generations; such conditions, while conducive to survival, may still cause suffering for animals. Humidity or lack thereof can be beneficial or harmful depending on an individual animals' needs.[42]

Deaths of large numbers of animals—particularly cold-blooded ones such as amphibians, reptiles, fishes and invertebrates—can take place as a result of temperature fluctuations, with young animals being particularly susceptible. Temperature may not be a problem for parts of the year, but can be a problem in especially hot summers or cold winters.[42] Extreme heat and lack of rainfall are also associated with suffering and increased mortality by increasing susceptibility to disease and causing vegetation that insects and other animals rely upon to dry out; this drying out can also make animals who rely on plants as hiding places more susceptible to predation. Amphibians who rely on moisture to breathe and stay cool may die when water sources dry up.[46] Hot temperatures can cause fish to die by making it hard for them to breathe.[47] Climate change and associated warming and drying is making certain habitats intolerable for some animals through heat stress and reducing available water sources.[48] Mass mortality is particularly linked with winter weather due to low temperatures, lack of food and bodies of water where animals live, such as frogs, freezing over;[49] a study on cottontail rabbits indicates that only 32% of them survive the winter.[41] Fluctuating environmental conditions in the winter months is also associated with increased mortality.[50]

Natural disasters

Fires, volcanic eruptions, earthquakes, tsunamis, hurricanes, storms, floods and other natural disasters are sources of extensive short- and long-term harm for wild animals, causing death, injury, illness and malnutrition, as well as poisoning by contaminating food and water sources.[51] Such disasters can also alter the physical environment of individual animals in ways which are harmful to them;[52] fires and large volcanic eruptions can affect the weather and marine animals may die due to disasters affecting water temperature and salinity.[51]

Killing by other animals

Predation has been described as the act of one animal capturing and killing another animal to consume part or all of their body.[53] Jeff McMahan, a moral philosopher, asserts that: "Wherever there is animal life, predators are stalking, chasing, capturing, killing, and devouring their prey. Agonized suffering and violent death are ubiquitous and continuous."[54] Preyed upon animals die in a variety of different ways, with the time taking for them to die, which can be lengthy, depending on the method that the predatory animal uses to kill them; some animals are swallowed and digested while still being alive.[55] Other preyed upon animals are paralysed with venom before being eaten; venom can also be used to start digesting the animal.[56]

Animals may be killed by members of their own species due to territorial disputes, competition for mates and social status, as well as cannibalism, infanticide and siblicide.[57]

Psychological stress

It has been argued that animals in the wild do not appear to be happier than domestic animals, based on findings that these individuals have greater levels of cortisol and elevated stress responses relative to domestic animals; additionally, unlike domestic animals, wild animals do not have their needs provided for them by human caretakers.[3] Sources of stress for these individuals include illness and infection, predation avoidance, nutritional stress and social interactions; these stressors can begin before birth and continue as the individual develops.[58]

A framework known as the ecology of fear conceptualises the psychological impact that the fear of predatory animals can have on the individuals that they predate, such as altering their behavior and reducing their survival chances.[59][60] Fear-inducing interactions with predators may cause lasting effects on behavior and PTSD-like changes in the brains of animals in the wild.[61] These interactions can also cause a spike in stress hormones, such as cortisol, which can increase the risk of both the individual's death and their offspring.[62]

Number of affected individuals

 
Marine arthropods, such as this Northern krill, are the largest estimated group of individual wild animals.

The number of individual animals in the wild is relatively unexplored in the scientific literature and estimates vary considerably.[63] An analysis, undertaken in 2018, estimates (not including wild mammals) that there are 1015 fish, 1011 wild birds, 1018 terrestrial arthropods and 1020 marine arthropods, 1018 annelids, 1018 molluscs and 1016 cnidarians, for a total of 1021 wild animals.[64] It has been estimated that there are 2.25 times more wild mammals than wild birds in Britain, but the authors of this estimate assert that this calculation would likely be a severe underestimate when applied to the number of individual wild mammals in other continents.[65] A 2022 study estimated that there are 20 quadrillion individual ants across the world.[66]

Based on some of these estimates, it has been argued that the number of individual wild animals in existence is considerably higher, by an order of magnitude, than the number of animals humans kill for food each year,[4] with individuals in the wild making up over 99% of all sentient beings in existence.[67]

Natural selection

In his autobiography, the naturalist and biologist Charles Darwin acknowledged that the existence of extensive suffering in nature was fully compatible with the workings of natural selection, yet maintained that pleasure was the main driver of fitness-increasing behavior in organisms.[68] Evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins challenged Darwin's claim in his book River Out of Eden, wherein he argued that wild animal suffering must be extensive due to the interplay of the following evolutionary mechanisms:[5]

  • Selfish genes – genes are wholly indifferent to the well-being of individual organisms as long as DNA is passed on.
  • The struggle for existence – competition over limited resources results in the majority of organisms dying before passing on their genes.
  • Malthusian checks – even bountiful periods within a given ecosystem eventually lead to overpopulation and subsequent population crashes.

From this, Dawkins concludes that the natural world must necessarily contain enormous amounts of animal suffering as an inevitable consequence of Darwinian evolution.[5] To illustrate this he writes:[69]

The total amount of suffering per year in the natural world is beyond all decent contemplation. During the minute that it takes me to compose this sentence, thousands of animals are being eaten alive, many others are running for their lives, whimpering with fear, others are slowly being devoured from within by rasping parasites, thousands of all kinds are dying of starvation, thirst, and disease. It must be so. If there ever is a time of plenty, this very fact will automatically lead to an increase in the population until the natural state of starvation and misery is restored.

Reproductive strategies and population dynamics

 
A litter of rats with their mother. The reproduction of rats follows an r-selection strategy, with many offspring, short gestation, less parental care, and a short time until sexual maturity.

Some writers have argued that the prevalence of r-selected animals in the wild—who produce large numbers of offspring, with a low amount of parental care, and of which only a small number, in a stable population, will survive to adulthood—indicates that the average life of these individuals is likely to be very short and end in a painful death.[6][7] The pathologist Keith Simpson described this as follows:[70]

In the wild, plagues of excess population are a rarity. The seas are not crowded with sunfish; the ponds are not brimming with toads; elephants do not stand shoulder to shoulder over the land. With few exceptions, animal populations are remarkably stable. On average, of each pair's offspring, only sufficient survive to replace the parents when they die. Surplus young die, and birth rates are balanced by death rates. In the case of spawners and egg layers, some young are killed before hatching. Almost half of all blackbird eggs are taken by jays, but even so, each pair usually manages to fledge about four young. By the end of summer, however, an average of under two are still alive. Since one parent will probably die or be killed during the winter, only one of the young will survive to breed the following summer. The high mortality rate among young animals is an inevitable consequence of high fecundity. Of the millions of fry produced by a pair of sunfish, only one or two escape starvation, disease or predators. Half the young of house mice living on the Welsh island of Skokholm are lost before weaning. Even in large mammals, the lives of the young can be pathetically brief and the killing wholesale. During the calving season, many young wildebeeste, still wet, feeble and bewildered, are seized and torn apart by jackals, hyenas and lions within minutes of emerging from their mothers' bellies. Three out of every four die violently within six months.

According to this view, the lives of the majority of animals in the wild likely contain more suffering than happiness, since a painful death would outweigh any short-lived moments of happiness experienced in their short lives.[6][71][72]

Welfare economist Yew-Kwang Ng has argued that evolutionary dynamics can lead to welfare outcomes that are worse than necessary for a given population equilibrium.[71] A 2019 follow-up challenged the conclusions of Ng's original paper.[73]

History of concern for wild animals

Religious views

Problem of evil

 
Charles Darwin referred to the Ichneumonidae feeding inside the living bodies of caterpillars as an example of the problem of evil.

The idea that suffering is common in nature has been observed by several writers historically who engaged with the problem of evil. In his notebooks (written between 1487 and 1505), Italian polymath Leonardo da Vinci described the suffering experienced by animals in the wild due to predation and reproduction, questioning: "Why did nature not ordain that one animal should not live by the death of another?"[74] In his 1779 posthumous work Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, the philosopher David Hume described the antagonism inflicted by animals upon each other and the psychological impact experienced by the victims, observing: "The stronger prey upon the weaker, and keep them in perpetual terror and anxiety."[75]

In Natural Theology, published in 1802, Christian philosopher William Paley argued that animals in the wild die as a result of violence, decay, disease, starvation and malnutrition, and that they exist in a state of suffering and misery; their suffering unaided by their fellow animals. He compared this to humans, who even when they can't relieve the suffering of their fellow humans, at least provide them with necessities. Paley also engaged with the reader of his book, asking whether, based on these observations, "you would alter the present system of pursuit and prey?"[76]: 261–262  Additionally, he argued that "the subject ... of animals devouring one another, forms the chief, if not the only instance, in the works of the Deity ... in which the character of utility can be called in question."[76]: 265  However, he defended predation as being a part of God's design by asserting that it was a solution to the problem of superfecundity;[77] animals producing more offspring than can possibly survive.[76]: 264  Paley also contended that venom is a merciful way for poisonous animals to kill the animals that they predate.[77]

The problem of evil has also been extended to include the suffering of animals in the context of evolution.[78][79] In Phytologia, or the Philosophy of Agriculture and Gardening, published in 1800, Erasmus Darwin, a physician and the grandfather of Charles Darwin, aimed to vindicate the goodness of God allowing the consumption of "lower" animals by "higher" ones, by asserting that "more pleasurable sensation exists in the world, as the organic matter is taken from a state of less irritability and less sensibility and converted into a greater"; he claimed that this process secures the greatest happiness for sentient beings. Writing in response, in 1894, Edward Payson Evans, a linguist and early advocate for animal rights, argued that evolution, which regards the antagonism between animals purely as events within the context of a "universal struggle for existence", has disregarded this kind of theodicy and ended "teleological attempts to infer from the nature and operations of creation the moral character of the Creator".[80]

In an 1856 letter to Joseph Dalton Hooker, Charles Darwin remarked sarcastically on the cruelty and wastefulness of nature, describing it as something that a "Devil's chaplain" could write about.[81] Writing in 1860, to Asa Gray, Darwin asserted that he could not reconcile an omnibenevolent and omnipotent God with the intentional existence of the Ichneumonidae, a parasitoid wasp family, the larvae of which feed internally on the living bodies of caterpillars.[82] In his autobiography, published in 1887, Darwin described a feeling of revolt at the idea that God's benevolence is limited, stating: "for what advantage can there be in the sufferings of millions of the lower animals throughout almost endless time?"[83]

Eastern perspectives

Philosopher Ole Martin Moen argues that unlike Western, Judeo-Christian views, Jainism, Buddhism and Hinduism "all hold that the natural world is filled with suffering, that suffering is bad for all who endure it, and that our ultimate aim should be to bring suffering to an end."[84]

Buddhism

In Buddhist doctrine, rebirth as an animal is regarded as evil because of the different forms of suffering that animals experience due to humans and natural processes.[85] Buddhists may also regard the suffering experienced by animals in nature as evidence for the truth of dukkha.[86][87]

The Buddhist scripture Aṅguttara Nikāya describes the lives of wild animals as "so cruel, so harsh, so painful".[87]

The Indian Buddhist sutra, Saddharmasmṛtyupasthānasūtra, written in the first half of the first millennium, categorises the different forms of suffering experienced by the animals living in the water, on the earth and in the sky and draws attention to certain animals who can be liberated from their suffering through consciousness: "There are those [animals] who—[though] fearful of predation, of threats, beatings, cold, heat, and bad weather—if capable, disregard their trembling and, just for a moment, arouse a mind of faith towards the Buddha, the Dharma, and the Saṅgha."[88]

Around 700 AD, the Indian Buddhist monk and scholar Shantideva wrote in his Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra:

     And may the stooping animals be freed
     From fear of being preyed upon, each other's food.[89]

Patrul Rinpoche, a 19th-century Tibetan Buddhist teacher, described animals in the ocean as experiencing "immense suffering", as a result of predation, as well as parasites burrowing inside them and eating them alive. He also described animals on land as existing in a state of continuous fear and of killing and being killed.[90]

Hinduism

Hindu literature has been described as holding the lives and welfare of wild animals as equal with that of humans.[91]

18th century

In Histoire Naturelle, published in 1753, the naturalist Buffon described wild animals as suffering much want in the winter, focusing specifically on the plight of stags who are exhausted by the rutting season, which in turn leads to the breeding of parasites under their skin, further adding to their misery.[92]: 53  Later in the book, he described predation as necessary to prevent the superabundance of animals who produce vast numbers of offspring, who if not killed would have their fecundity diminished due to a lack of food and would die as a result of disease and starvation. Buffon concluded that "violent deaths seem to be equally as necessary as natural ones; they are both modes of destruction and renovation; the one serves to preserve nature in a perpetual spring, and the other maintains the order of her productions, and limits the number of each species."[92]: 116–117 

Herder, a philosopher and theologian, in Ideen zur Philosphie der Geschichte der Menschheit, published between 1784 and 1791, argued that animals exist in a state of constant striving, needing to provide for their own subsistence and to defend their lives. He contended that nature ensured peace in creation by creating an equilibrium of animals with different instincts and belonging to different species who live opposed to each other.[93]

19th century

 
Lewis Gompertz argued that both humans and animals in their natural state suffer similarly and that both should be assisted.

In 1824, Lewis Gompertz, an early vegan and animal rights activist, published Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes, in which he advocated for an egalitarian view towards animals and aiding animals suffering in the wild.[4] Gompertz asserted that humans and animals in their natural state both suffer similarly:[94]: 47 

[B]oth of them being miserably subject to almost every evil, destitute of the means of palliating them; living in the continual apprehension of immediate starvation, of destruction by their enemies, which swarm around them; of receiving dreadful injuries from the revengeful and malicious feelings of their associates, uncontrolled by laws or by education, and acting as their strength alone dictates; without proper shelter from the inclemencies of the weather; without proper attention and medical or surgical aid in sickness; destitute frequently of fire, of candle-light, and (in man) also of clothing; without amusements or occupations, excepting a few, the chief of which are immediately necessary for their existence, and subject to all the ill consequences arising from the want of them.

Gompertz also argued that as much as animals suffer in the wild, that they suffer much more at the hands of humans because, in their natural state, they have the capacity to also experience periods of much enjoyment.[94]: 52  Additionally, he contended that if he was to encounter a situation where an animal was eating another, that he would intervene to help the animal being attacked, even if "this might probably be wrong."[94]: 93–94  In his 1852 book Fragments in Defence of Animals, and Essays on Morals, Soul, and Future State, Gompertz compared the suffering of animals in the wild to the suffering inflicted by humans, stating: "Much as animals suffer in a natural state, much more do they seem to suffer when under the dominion of the generality of men. What suffering in the former can be supposed to equal the constant torture of a hackney-coach horse?"[95]

Philosopher and poet Giacomo Leopardi in his 1824 "Dialogue between Nature and an Icelander", from Operette morali, used images of animal predation, which he rejected as having value, to represent nature's cycles of creation and destruction.[96] Writing in his notebooks, Zibaldone di pensieri, published posthumously in 1898, Leopardi asserted that predation is a leading example of the evil design of nature.[97]

In 1851, the philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer commented on the vast amount of suffering in nature, drawing attention to the asymmetry between the pleasure experienced by a carnivorous animal and the suffering of the animal that they are consuming, stating: "Whoever wants summarily to test the assertion that the pleasure in the world outweighs the pain, or at any rate that the two balance each other, should compare the feelings of an animal that is devouring another with those of that other".[98]

In the 1874 posthumous essay "Nature", utilitarian philosopher John Stuart Mill wrote about suffering in nature and the imperative of struggling against it:[99]

In sober truth, nearly all the things which men are hanged or imprisoned for doing to one another, are nature's every day performances. ... The phrases which ascribe perfection to the course of nature can only be considered as the exaggerations of poetic or devotional feeling, not intended to stand the test of a sober examination. No one, either religious or irreligious, believes that the hurtful agencies of nature, considered as a whole, promote good purposes, in any other way than by inciting human rational creatures to rise up and struggle against them. ... Whatsoever, in nature, gives indication of beneficent design proves this beneficence to be armed only with limited power; and the duty of man is to cooperate with the beneficent powers, not by imitating, but by perpetually striving to amend, the course of nature—and bringing that part of it over which we can exercise control more nearly into conformity with a high standard of justice and goodness.

In his 1892 book Animals' Rights: Considered in Relation to Social Progress, the writer and early activist for animal rights Henry Stephens Salt focused an entire chapter on the plight of wild animals, "The Case of Wild Animals". Salt wrote that the rights of animals should not be dependent on the rights of being property and that sympathy and protection should be extended to non-owned animals too.[100] He also argued that humans are justified in killing wild animals in self-defense, but that neither unnecessary killing nor torturing harmless beings is justified.[100]

20th century

 
J. Howard Moore speculated whether a sufficiently sympathetic human, if only given the chance, could significantly improve the situation of animals suffering in the wild.

In the 1906 book The Universal Kinship, the zoologist and utilitarian philosopher J. Howard Moore argued that the egoism of sentient beings—a product of natural selection—which leads them to exploit their sentient fellows, was the "most mournful and immense fact in the phenomena of conscious life", and speculated whether an ordinary human who was sufficiently sympathetic to the welfare of the world could significantly improve this situation if only given the opportunity.[101] In Ethics and Education, published in 1912, Moore critiqued the human conception of animals in the wild: "Many of these non-human beings are so remote from human beings in language, appearance, interests, and ways of life, as to be nothing but 'wild animals.' These 'wild things' have, of course, no rights whatever in the eyes of men."[102]: 71  Later in the book, he described them as independent beings who suffer and enjoy in the same way humans do and have their "own ends and justifications of life."[102]: 157 

In his 1952 article "Which Shall We Protect? Thoughts on the Ethics of the Treatment of Free Life", Alexander Skutch, a naturalist and writer, explored five ethical principles that humans could follow when considering their relationship with animals in the wild, including the principle of only considering human interests; the laissez-faire, or "hands-off" principle; the do no harm, ahimsa principle; the principle of favoring the "higher animals", which are most similar to ourselves; the principle of "harmonious association", whereby humans and animals in the wild could live symbiotically, with each providing benefits to the other and individuals who disrupt this harmony, such as predators, are removed. Skutch endorsed a combination of the laissez-faire, ahimsa and harmonious association approaches as the way to create the ultimate harmony between humans and animals in the wild.[103]

Moral philosopher Peter Singer, in 1973, responded to a question on whether humans have a moral obligation to prevent predation, arguing that intervening in this way may cause more suffering in the long-term, but asserting that he would support actions if the long-term outcome was positive.[104]

In 1979, the animal rights philosopher Stephen R. L. Clark, published "The Rights of Wild Things", in which he argued that humans should protect animals in the wild from particularly large dangers, but that humans do not have an obligation to regulate all of their relationships.[105] The following year, J. Baird Callicott, an environmental ethicist, published "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair", in which he compared the ethical underpinnings of the animal liberation movement, asserting that it is based on Benthamite principles, and Aldo Leopold's land ethic, which he used as a model for environmental ethics. Callicott concluded that intractable differences exist between the two ethical positions when it comes to the issue of wild animal suffering.[106]

In his 1987 book, Morals, Reason, and Animals, animal rights philosopher Steve F. Sapontzis argued that from an antispeciesist perspective, humans should aid animals suffering in the wild, as long as a greater harm is not inflicted overall.[107]

In 1991, the environmental philosopher Arne Næss critiqued what he termed the "cult of nature" of contemporary and historical attitudes of indifference towards suffering in nature. He argued that humans should confront the reality of the wilderness, including disturbing natural processes—when feasible—to relieve suffering.[108]

In his 1993 article "Pourquoi je ne suis pas écologiste" ("Why I am not an environmentalist"), published in the antispeciesist journal Cahiers antispécistes, the animal rights philosopher David Olivier argued that he is opposed to environmentalists because they consider predation to be good because of the preservation of species and "natural balance", while Olivier gives consideration to the suffering of the individual animal being predated. He also asserted that if the environmentalists were themselves at risk of being predated, they wouldn't follow the "order of nature". Olivier concluded: "I don't want to turn the universe into a planned, man-made world. Synthetic food for foxes, contraception for hares, I only half like that. I have a problem that I do not know how to solve, and I am unlikely to find a solution, even theoretical, as long as I am (almost) alone looking for one."[109]

21st century

Publications

 
Brian Tomasik argues that animal advocates should promote concern for wild animal suffering and highlights the risk of human descendants astronomically multiplying such suffering.

In 2009, essayist Brian Tomasik published the essay, "The Importance of Wild-Animal Suffering". In the essay, Tomasik makes the case that the number of individual wild animals in existence is significantly larger than the number of non-human animals used by humans and that, as a result, animal advocates should focus on promoting concern for the suffering experienced by animals in their natural environments. He also makes the point that as much as there is a vast amount of suffering existing in the present, that human descendants could increase the amount of wild animal suffering in existence astronomically, if these descendants chose to multiply wild animal suffering, rather than preventing it.[110] In 2015, a version of the essay was published in the journal Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism,[1] in the special two-volume issue "Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature", which collected contributions from a number of authors on the topic of wild animal suffering.[111][112]

Jeff McMahan's 2010 essay "The Meat Eaters" was published by The New York Times, in which he argued in favor of taking steps to reduce animal suffering in the wild, particularly by reducing predation.[113] In the same year, McMahan published "Predators: A Response", a reply to the criticism he received for his original article.[114]

Vox has published multiple articles on the topic of wild animal suffering. In 2015, it published sociologist Jacy Reese Anthis's article "Wild animals endure illness, injury, and starvation. We should help.";[115] in his 2018 book The End of Animal Farming, Anthis discusses expanding the circle of human moral concern to include invertebrates and animals suffering in the wild.[116] In 2021, Vox published the journalist Dylan Matthews's article "The wild frontier of animal welfare", which analyzed the views of various philosophers and scientists on the topic.[117]

The digital magazine Aeon has published essays by philosophers which discuss wild animal suffering, "We have an ethical obligation to relieve individual animal suffering" (2018)[118] and "All we owe to animals" (2020).[17]

Philosopher Catia Faria, in 2016, successfully defended her Ph.D. thesis, Animal Ethics Goes Wild: The Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature; the first thesis of its kind to argue that humans have an obligation to help animals in the wild.[119] In 2022, she is expected to publish a book on the topic, Animal Ethics in the Wild: Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature.[120]

In 2020, philosopher Kyle Johannsen published Wild Animal Ethics: The Moral and Political Problem of Wild Animal Suffering. The book argues that wild animal suffering is a pressing moral issue and that humans have a collective moral duty to intervene in nature to reduce suffering.[121] In the same year, a symposium was held at Queen's University on Johannsen's book.[122]

Animal rights activist and philosopher Oscar Horta published Making a Stand for Animals, in 2022, which includes a chapter titled "In defense of animals!", which argues that giving moral consideration to animals implies aiding them when they suffer due to natural processes.[123]

Organizations

In response to arguments for the moral and political importance of wild animal suffering, a number of organizations have been created to research and address the issue. Two of these, Utility Farm and Wild-Animal Suffering Research merged in 2019 to form Wild Animal Initiative.[124] The nonprofit organization Animal Ethics also researches wild animal suffering and advocates on behalf of wild animals, among other populations.[125] Rethink Priorities is a research organization which, among other topics, has conducted research on wild animal suffering, particularly around invertebrate sentience and invertebrate welfare.[126][127]

The Wildlife Disaster Network was founded in 2020 with the intention of helping wild animals suffering in natural disasters. Jamie Payton, who works for the network, challenges the view that wild animals in disasters situations manage best when left alone, stating: "Without human interference, these animals will suffer and succumb, due not only to their injuries but also to the loss of food, water and habitat. It is our obligation to provide the missing link for the wildlife that share our home."[128]

Philosophical status

Predation as a moral problem

Predation has been considered a moral problem by some philosophers, who argue that humans have an obligation to prevent it,[12][129] while others argue that intervention is not ethically required.[130][131] Others have argued that humans shouldn't do anything about it right now because there's a chance we'll unwittingly cause serious harm, but that with better information and technology, it may be possible to take meaningful action in the future.[132] An obligation to prevent predation has been considered untenable or absurd by some writers, who have used the position as a reductio ad absurdum to reject the concept of animal rights altogether.[133][134] Others have argued that attempting to reduce it would be environmentally harmful.[135]

Arguments for intervention

Animal rights and welfare perspectives

 
Oscar Horta argues that animals in the wild experience vast amounts of suffering due to natural processes and that, taking a nonspeciesist perspective, there is a moral obligation to reduce the suffering of these individuals.

Some theorists have reflected on whether the harms animals suffer in the wild should be accepted or if something should be done to mitigate them.[6] The moral basis for interventions aimed at reducing wild animal suffering can be rights or welfare based. Advocates of such interventions argue that non-intervention is inconsistent with either of these approaches.

From a rights-based perspective, if animals have a moral right to life or bodily integrity, intervention may be required to prevent such rights from being violated by other animals.[136] Animal rights philosopher Tom Regan was critical of this view; he argued that because animals aren't moral agents, in the sense of being morally responsible for their actions, they can't violate each other's rights. Based on this, he concluded that humans don't need to concern themselves with preventing suffering of this kind, unless such interactions were strongly influenced by humans.[137]: 14–15 

Oscar Horta argues that it is a mistaken perception that the animal rights position implies a respect for natural processes because of the assumption that animals in the wild live easy and happy lives, when in reality, they live short and painful lives full of suffering.[6] It has also been argued that a non-speciesist legal system would mean animals in the wild would be entitled to positive rights—similar to what humans are entitled to by their species-membership—which would give them the legal right to food, shelter, healthcare and protection.[138]

From a welfare-based perspective, a requirement to intervene may arise insofar as it is possible to prevent some of the suffering experienced by wild animals without causing even more suffering.[139] Katie McShane argues that biodiversity is not a good proxy for wild animal welfare: "A region with high biodiversity is full of lots of different kinds of individuals. They might be suffering; their lives might be barely worth living. But if they are alive, they count positively toward biodiversity."[140]

Non-intervention as a form of speciesism

Some writers have argued that humans refusing to aid animals suffering in the wild, when they would help humans suffering in a similar situation, is an example of speciesism;[2] the differential treatment or moral consideration of individuals based on their species membership.[141] Jamie Mayerfeld contends that a duty to relive suffering which is blind to species membership implies an obligation to relieve the suffering of animals due to natural processes.[142] Stijn Bruers argues that even long-term animal rights activists sometimes hold speciesist views when it comes to this specific topic, which he calls a "moral blind spot".[143] His view is echoed by Eze Paez, who asserts that advocates who disregard the interests of animals purely because they live in the wild are responsible for the same form of discrimination used by those who justify the exploitation of animals by humans.[144] Oscar Horta argues that spreading awareness of speciesism will in turn increase concern for the plight of animals in the wild.[145]

Humans already intervene to further human interests

Oscar Horta asserts that humans are constantly intervening in nature, in significant ways, to further human interests, such as furthering environmentalist ideals. He criticizes how interventions are considered to be realistic, safe or acceptable when their aims favor humans, but not when they focus on helping wild animals. He argues that humans should shift the aim of these interventions to consider the interests of sentient beings; not just humans.[16]

Human responsibility for enhancing natural harms

Philosopher Martha Nussbaum asserts that humans continually "affect the habitats of animals, determining opportunities for nutrition, free movement, and other aspects of flourishing" and contends that the pervasive human involvement in natural processes means that humans have a moral responsibility to help individuals affected by our actions. She also argues that humans may have the capacity to help animals suffering due to entirely natural processes, such as diseases and natural disasters and asserts that way may have duties to provide care in these cases.[146]: 374 

Jeff Sebo, a philosopher, argues that animals in the wild suffer as a result of natural processes, as well as human-caused harms. He asserts that climate change is making existing harms more severe and creating new harms for these individuals. From this, he concludes that there are two reasons to help individual animals in the wild: "they are suffering and dying, and we are either partly or wholly responsible".[17] Similarly, philosopher Steven Nadler argues that climate change means "that the scope of actions that are proscribed – and, especially, prescribed – by a consideration of animal suffering should be broadened".[118] However, Nadler goes further, asserting that humans have a moral obligation to help individual animals suffering in the wild regardless of human responsibility.[118]

Arguments against intervention

Practicality of intervening in nature

 
Peter Singer argues that, in theory, intervention would be justified if one could be reasonably assured that this would greatly reduce wild animal suffering in the long term; he cautions against such interventions in practice.

A common objection to intervening in nature is that it would be impractical, either because of the amount of work involved or because the complexity of ecosystems would make it difficult to know whether or not an intervention would be net beneficial on balance.[114] Aaron Simmons argues that humans should not intervene to save animals in nature because doing so would result in unintended consequences such as damaging ecosystems, interfering with human projects, or resulting in more animal deaths overall.[12] Nicolas Delon and Duncan Purves argue that the "nature of ecosystems leaves us with no reason to predict that interventions would reduce, rather than exacerbate, suffering".[10] Peter Singer has argued that intervention in nature would be justified if one could be reasonably confident that this would greatly reduce wild animal suffering and death in the long run. In practice, however, Singer cautions against interfering with ecosystems because he fears that doing so would cause more harm than good.[104][147]

Other authors dispute Singer's empirical claim about the likely consequences of intervening in the natural world and argue that some types of intervention can be expected to produce good consequences overall. Economist Tyler Cowen cites examples of animal species whose extinction is not generally regarded as having been on balance bad for the world. Cowen also notes that insofar as humans are already intervening in nature, the relevant practical question is not whether there should be intervention, but what particular forms of intervention should be favored.[139] Oscar Horta similarly writes that there are already many cases in which humans intervene in nature for other reasons, such as for human interest in nature and environmental preservation as something valuable in their own rights.[6] Horta has also proposed that courses of action aiming at helping wild animals should be carried out and adequately monitored first in urban, suburban, industrial, or agricultural areas.[148] Likewise, Jeff McMahan argues that since humans "are already causing massive, precipitate changes in the natural world," humans should favor those changes that would promote the survival "of herbivorous rather than carnivorous species."[114] Peter Vallentyne, a philosopher, suggests that, while humans should not eliminate predators in nature, they can intervene to help prey in more limited ways. In the same way that humans help humans in need when the cost to us is small, humans might help some wild animals at least in limited circumstances.[149]

Potential conflict between animal rights and environmentalism

It has been argued that the environmentalist goal of preserving certain abstract entities such as species and ecosystems and a policy of non-interference in regard to natural processes is incompatible with animal rights views, which place the welfare and interests of individual animals at the center of concern.[150][151][152] Examples include environmentalists supporting hunting for species population control, while animal rights advocates oppose it;[72] animal rights advocates arguing for the extinction or reengineering of carnivores or r-strategist species, while deep ecologists defend their right to be and flourish as they are;[132][153] animal rights advocates defending the reduction of wildlife habitats or arguing against their expansion out of concern that most animal suffering takes place within them, while environmentalists want to safeguard and expand them.[154][155] Oscar Horta argues that there are instances where environmentalists and animal rights advocates may both support approaches that would consequently reduce wild animal suffering.[155]

Intrinsic value of ecological processes, wilderness and wildness

Some writers, such as the environmental ethicist Holmes Rolston III, argue that natural animal suffering is valuable because it serves an ecological purpose and that only animal suffering due to non-natural processes is morally bad and, as a result, humans do not have a duty to intervene in cases of suffering caused by natural processes.[156][page needed] Rolston celebrates carnivores in nature because of the significant ecological role they play.[153] Others argue that the reason that humans have a duty to protect other humans from predation, but not wild animals, is that humans are part of the cultural world rather than the natural world and so different rules apply to them in these situations.[153][157] Some writers assert that animals who are preyed upon are fulfilling their natural function, and thus flourishing when they are preyed upon or otherwise die, since this allows natural selection to work.[136]

Yves Bonnardel, an animal rights philosopher, has criticized this view, as well as the concept of nature, which he describes as an "ideological tool" that places humans in a superior position above other animals, who exist only to perform certain ecosystem functions, such as a rabbit being food for a wolf. Bonnardel compares this with the religious idea that a slaves exist for their masters, or that woman exists for the sake of man. He argues that animals as individuals all have an interest in living.[158]

Wilderness advocates argue that wilderness is intrinsically valuable; the biologist E. O. Wilson wrote that "wilderness has virtue unto itself and needs no extraneous justification".[159] Joshua Duclos describes the moral argument against preserving wilderness because of the suffering experienced by wild animals who live in them as the "objection from welfare".[160]

Jack Walker argues that the "intrinsic value of wildness cannot be used to oppose large-scale interventions to reduce [wild animal suffering]".[161] Joshua Duclos that wilderness is given intrinsic value of from a narrow anthropocentric perspective, with a religio-spiritual dimension.[162]

Nature as idyllic

The idyllic view of nature is described as the widely-held view that happiness in nature is widespread.[6][7] Oscar Horta argues that even though many people are aware of the harms that animals in the wild experience, such as predation, starvation and disease, as well as recognizing that these animals may suffer as a result of these harms, they don't conclude from this that wild animals have bad enough lives to imply that nature is not a happy place. Horta also contends that a romantic conception of nature has significant implications for attitudes people have towards animals in the wild, as holders of the view may oppose interventions to reduce suffering.[6]

Bob Fischer argues that many wild animals may have "net negative" lives (experiencing more pain than pleasure), even in the absence of human activity. However, Fischer argues that if many animals have net negative lives, then what is good for the animal, as an individual, may not be good for its species, other species, the climate or the preservation of biodiversity; for example, some animals may have to have their populations massively reduced and controlled and some species, such as parasites or predators, eliminated entirely.[163]

Intervention as hubris

Some writers have argued that interventions to reduce wild animal suffering would be an example of arrogance, hubris, or playing God, as such interventions could potentially have disastrous unforeseen consequences. They are also sceptical of the competence of humans when it comes to making correct moral judgements, as well as human fallibility. Additionally, they contend that the moral stance of humans and moral agency can lead to the imposition of anthropocentric or paternalistic values on others. To support these claims, they use the history of human negative impacts on nature, including species extinctions, wilderness and resource depletion, as well as climate change. From this, they conclude that the best way that humans can help animals in the wild is through the preservation of larger wilderness areas and by reducing the human sphere of influence on nature.[13]

Critics of this position, such as Beril Sözmen, argue that human negative impacts are not inevitable and that, until recently, interventions were not undertaken with the goal of improving the well-being of individual animals in the wild. Furthermore, she contends that such examples of anthropogenic harms are not the consequence of misguided human intervention gone awry, but are actually the result of human agriculture and industry, which do not consider, or do not care, about their impact on nature and animals in the wild. Sözmen also asserts that the holders of this position may view that nature as exists in a delicate state of balance and have an overly romantic view of the lives of animals in the wild and, that she contends, actually contain vast amounts of suffering.[13] Martha Nussbaum argues that because humans are constantly intervening in nature, the central question should be what form should these interventions take, rather than whether interventions should take place, arguing that "intelligently respectful paternalism is vastly superior to neglect".[146]: 377 

Laissez-faire

A laissez-faire view, which holds that humans should not harm animals in the wild, but do not have an obligation to aid these individuals when in need, has been defended by Tom Regan, Elisa Aaltola, Clare Palmer and Ned Hettinger. Regan argued that the suffering animals inflict on each other should not be a concern of ethically motivated wildlife management and that these wildlife managers should instead focus on letting animals in the wild exist as they are, with no human predation, and to "carve out their own destiny".[14] Aaltola similarly argues that predators should be left to flourish, despite the suffering that they cause to the animals that they predate.[15] Palmer endorses a variant of this position, which claims that humans may have an obligation to assist wild animals if humans are responsible for their situation.[164] Hettinger argues for laissez-faire based on the environmental value of "Respect for an Independent Nature".[165]

Catia Faria argues that following the principle that humans should only help individuals when they are being harmed by humans, rather than by natural processes, would also mean refusing to help humans and companion animals when they suffer due to natural processes, however, this implication does not seem acceptable to most people and she asserts that there are strong reasons to help these individuals when humans have capacity to do so. Faria argues that there is an obligation to help animals in the wild suffering in similar situations and, as a result, the laissez-faire view does not hold up.[166] Similarly, Steven Nadler argues that it is morally wrong to refuse help to animals in the wild regardless of whether humans are indirectly or directly responsible for their suffering, as the same arguments used to decline aid to humans who were suffering due to natural harms such as famine, a tsunami or pneumonia would be considered immoral. He concludes that if the only thing that is morally relevant is an individual's capacity to suffer, there is no relevant moral difference between humans and other animals suffering in these situations.[118] In the same vein, Steve F. Sapontizis asserts that: "When our interests or the interests of those we care for will be hurt, we do not recognize a moral obligation to 'let nature take its course'".[167]

Wild animal sovereignty

Some writers, such as the animal rights philosophers Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka, in Zoopolis, argue that humans should not perform large interventions to help animals in the wild. They assert that these interventions would be taking away their sovereignty, by removing the ability for these animals to govern themselves.[168] Christiane Bailey asserts that certain wild animals, especially prosocial animals, have sufficient criteria to be considered as moral agents, that is to say, individuals capable of making moral judgments and who have responsibilities. She argues that aiding them would be reducing wild animals to beings incapable of making decisions for themselves.[169]

Oscar Horta emphasizes the fact that although some individuals may form sovereign groups, the vast majority of wild animals are either solitary or re-selectors, whose population size varies greatly from year to year. He contends that most of their interactions would be amensalism, commensalism, antagonism or competition. Therefore, the majority of animals in the wild would not form sovereign communities if humans use the criteria established by Donaldson and Kymlicka.[170]

Analogy with colonialism

Estiva Reus asserts that a comparison exists, from a certain perspective, between the spirit which animated the defenders of colonialism who saw it as necessary human progress for "backward peoples", and the idea which inspires writers who argue for reforming nature in the interest of wild animals: the proponents of the two positions consider that they have the right and the duty, because of their superior skills, to model the existence of beings unable to remedy by their own means the evils which overwhelm them.[171]

Thomas Lepeltier, a historian and writer on animal ethics, argues that "if colonization is to be criticized, it is because, beyond the rhetoric, it was an enterprise of spoliation and exaction exercised with great cruelty."[172] He also contends that writers who advocate for helping wild animals do not do so for their own benefit because they would have nothing to gain by helping these individuals. Lepeltier goes on to assert that the advocates for reducing wild animal suffering would be aware of their doubts about how best to help these individuals and that they would not act by considering them as rudimentary and simple to understand beings, contrary to the vision that the former colonizers had of colonized populations.[172]

Intervention in practice

Existing forms of assistance

 
Rescued baby eastern gray squirrel being fed using a syringe

Existing ways that individual animals suffering in the wild are aided include providing medical care to sick and injured animals, vaccinating animals to prevent disease, taking care of orphaned animals, rescuing animals who are trapped, or in natural disasters, taking care of the needs of animals who are starving or thirsty, sheltering animals who are suffering due to weather conditions,[145] and using contraception to regulate population sizes.[173]

History of interventions

The Bishnoi, a Hindu sect founded in the 15th century, have a tradition of feeding wild animals.[174] Some Bishnoi temples also act as rescue centres, where priests take care of injured animals; a few of these individuals are returned to the wild, while others remain, roaming freely in the temple compounds.[175] The Borana Oromo people leave out water overnight for wild animals to drink because they believe that the animals have a right to drinking water.[176]

In 2002, the Australian Government authorized the killing of 15,000, out of 100,000, kangaroos who were trapped in a fenced-in national military base and suffering in a state of illness, misery and starvation.[177] In 2016, 350 starving hippos and buffaloes at Kruger National Park were killed by park rangers; one of the motives for the action was to prevent them from suffering as they died.[178]

Rescues of multiple animals in the wild have taken place: in 1988, the US and Soviet governments collaborated in Operation Breakthrough, to free three gray whales who were trapped in pack ice off the coast of Alaska;[179] in 2018, a team of BBC filmmakers dug a ramp in the snow to allow a group of penguins to escape a ravine in Antarctica;[180] in 2019, 2,000 baby flamingos were rescued during a drought in South Africa;[181] during the 2019–20 Australian bushfire season, a number of fire-threatened wild animals were rescued;[182] in 2020, 120 pilot whales, who were beached, were rescued in Sri Lanka;[183] in 2021, 1,700 Cape cormorant chicks, who had been abandoned by their parents, were rescued in South Africa;[184] in the same year, nearly 5,000 cold-stunned sea turtles were rescued in Texas.[185]

Vaccination programs have been successfully implemented to prevent rabies and tuberculosis in wild animals.[186] Wildlife contraception has been used to reduce and stabilize populations of wild horses, white-tailed deer, American bison and African elephants.[173][187]

Future developments

Proposed interventions

It has been argued that in the future, based on research, feasibility and whether interventions could be carried out without increasing suffering overall, existing forms of assistance for wild animals could be employed on a larger scale to reduce suffering.[115][188] Technological proposals include gene drives and CRISPR to reduce the suffering of members of r-strategist species[189] and using biotechnology to eradicate suffering in wild animals.[19][190]

When it comes to reducing suffering as a result of predation, propositions include removing predators from wild areas,[191][192] refraining from reintroducing predators into areas where they have previously gone extinct,[72][193] arranging the gradual extinction of carnivorous species,[54] and "reprogramming" them to become herbivores using germline engineering.[188] With predation due to cats and dogs, it has been recommended that these companion animals should always be sterilized to prevent the existence of feral animals, that cats should be kept indoors and dogs kept on a leash, unless in designated areas.[194]

Some writers, such as Brian Tomasik have argued from a consequentialist perspective, that following the conclusion that the majority of wild animals live negative lives, that loss of habitat, rather than being opposed, should be encouraged. Tyler M. John and Jeff Sebo have criticised this position, terming it the "Logic of the Logger", based on the concept of the "Logic of the Larder".[195]

Welfare biology

Welfare biology is a proposed research field for studying the welfare of animals, with a particular focus on their relationship with natural ecosystems.[196] It was first advanced in 1995 by Yew-Kwang Ng, who defined it as "the study of living things and their environment with respect to their welfare (defined as net happiness, or enjoyment minus suffering)".[71] Such research is intended to promote concern for animal suffering in the wild and to establish effective actions that can be undertaken to help these individuals in the future.[197][198] The organizations Animal Ethics and Wild Animal Initiative promote the establishment of welfare biology as a field of research.[199]

Impact of climate change

It has been argued that climate change may have a large direct impact on a number of animals, with the largest effect on individuals who belong to specialist species that specialise in living in environments which could be most affected by climate change; this could then lead to replacement by individuals belonging to more generalist species. It has also been asserted that the indirect impact of climate change on wild animal suffering will be whether it leads to an increase or decrease of individuals being born into lives where they suffer and die shortly after coming into existence, with a large number of factors needing to be taken into consideration and requiring further study to assess this.[155]

Risks

Spreading wild animal suffering beyond Earth

Several researchers and non-profit organizations have raised concern that human civilization may cause wild animal suffering outside Earth. For example, wild habitats may be created—or allowed to happen—on extraterrestrial colonies like terraformed planets.[200][201] Another example of a potential realization of the risk is directed panspermia where the initial microbial population eventually evolves into sentient organisms.[202][203][204]

Spreading sentient wild animals beyond Earth may constitute a suffering risk, as this could potentially lead to an immense increase in the amount of wild animal suffering in existence.[205]

Cultural depictions

Wildlife documentaries

 
Lions attacking an African buffalo in Botswana; it is argued that wildlife documentaries commonly focus on encounters between individuals, such as these, who are considered to be charismatic, while the suffering of other animals is underrepresented.

Criticism of portrayals of wild animal suffering

It has been argued that much of people's knowledge about wild animals comes from wildlife documentaries, which have been described as non-representative of the reality of wild animal suffering because they underrepresent uncharismatic animals who may have the capacity to suffer, such as animals who are preyed upon, as well as small animals and invertebrates.[206] In addition, it is claimed that such documentaries focus on adult animals, while the majority of animals who likely suffer the most, die before reaching adulthood;[206] that wildlife documentaries don't generally show animals suffering from parasitism;[137]: 47  that such documentaries can leave viewers with the false impression that animals who have been attacked by predators and suffered serious injury survived and thrived afterwards;[207] and that much of the particularly violent incidents of predation are not included.[208] The broadcaster David Attenborough has stated: "People who accuse us of putting in too much violence, [should see] what we leave on the cutting-room floor."[209]

It is also contended that wildlife documentaries present nature as a spectacle to be passively consumed by viewers, as well as a sacred and unique place that needs protection. Additionally, attention is drawn to how hardships that are experienced by animals are portrayed in a way that give the impression that wild animals, through adaptive processes, are able to overcome these sources of harm. However, the development of such adaptive traits takes place over a number of generations of individuals who will likely experience much suffering and hardship in their lives, while passing down their genes.[210]

David Pearce, a transhumanist and advocate for technological solutions for reducing the suffering of wild animals, is highly critical of how wildlife documentaries, which he refers to as "animal snuff-movies", represent wild animal suffering:[211]

Nature documentaries are mostly travesties of real life. They entertain and edify us with evocative mood-music and travelogue-style voice-overs. They impose significance and narrative structure on life's messiness. Wildlife shows have their sad moments, for sure. Yet suffering never lasts very long. It is always offset by homely platitudes about the balance of Nature, the good of the herd, and a sort of poor-man's secular theodicy on behalf of Mother Nature which reassures us that it's not so bad after all. ... That's a convenient lie. ... Lions kill their targets primarily by suffocation; which will last minutes. The wolf pack may start eating their prey while the victim is still conscious, though hamstrung. Sharks and the orca basically eat their prey alive; but in sections for the larger prey, notably seals.

Pearce also argues, through analogy, how the idea of intelligent aliens creating stylised portrayals of human deaths for popular entertainment would be considered abhorrent; he asserts that, in reality, this is the role that humans play when creating wildlife documentaries.[211]

Clare Palmer asserts that even when wildlife documentaries contain vivid images of wild animal suffering, they don't motivate a moral or practical response in the way that companion animals, such as dogs or cats, suffering in similar situations would and most people instinctively adopt the position of laissez-faire: allowing suffering to take its course, without intervention.[212]

Non-intervention as a filmmaking rule

The question of whether wildlife documentary filmmakers should intervene to help animals is a topic of much debate.[213] It has been described as a "golden rule" of such filmmaking to observe animals, but not intervene.[214] The rule is occasionally broken, with BBC documentary crews rescuing some stranded baby turtles in 2016 and rescuing a group of penguins trapped in a ravine in 2018;[215] the latter decision was defended by other wildlife documentary filmmakers.[180] Filmmakers following the rule have been criticized for filming dying animals, such as an elephant dying of thirst, without helping them.[215]

In fiction

 
In "The Ugly Duckling", the winter cold causes the duckling to become frozen in an icy pond; the duckling is rescued by a farmer.

Herman Melville, in Moby-Dick, published in 1851, describes the sea as a place of "universal cannibalism", where "creatures prey upon each other, carrying on eternal war since the world began"; this is illustrated by a later scene depicting sharks consuming their own entrails.[216]

The fairy tales of Hans Christian Andersen contain depictions of the suffering of animals due to natural processes and their rescues by humans. The titular character in "Thumbelina" encounters a seemingly dead frozen swallow. Thumbelina feels sorry for the bird and her companion the mole states: "What a wretched thing it is to be born a little bird. Thank goodness none of my children can be a bird, who has nothing but his 'chirp, chirp', and must starve to death when winter comes along."[217] However, Thumbelina discovers that the swallow isn't actually dead and manages to nurse them back to health.[218] In "The Ugly Duckling", the bitter winter cold causes the duckling to become frozen in an icy pond; the duckling is rescued by a farmer who breaks the ice and takes the duckling to his home to be resuscitated.[219]

In the 1923 book Bambi, a Life in the Woods, Felix Salten portrays a world where predation and death are continuous: a sick young hare is killed by crows, a pheasant and a duck are killed by foxes, a mouse is killed by an owl and a squirrel describes how their family members were killed by predators.[220] The 1942 Disney adaptation has been criticized for inaccurately portraying a world where predation and death are no longer emphasized, creating a "fantasy of nature cleansed of the traumas and difficulties that may trouble children and that adults prefer to avoid."[221] The film version has also been criticized for unrealistically portraying nature undisturbed by humans as an idyllic place, made up of interspecies friendships, with Bambi's life undisturbed by many of the harms routinely experienced by his real-life counterparts, such as starvation, predation, bovine tuberculosis and chronic wasting disease.[206]

John Wyndham's character Zelby, in the 1957 book The Midwich Cuckoos, describes nature as "ruthless, hideous, and cruel beyond belief" and observes that the lives of insects are "sustained only by intricate processes of fantastic horror".[222]

In Watership Down, published in 1972, Richard Adams compares the hardship experienced by animals in winter to the suffering experienced by poor humans, stating: "For birds and animals, as for poor men, winter is another matter. Rabbits, like most wild animals, suffer hardship."[223] Adams also describes rabbits as being more susceptible to disease in the winter.[223]

In the philosopher Nick Bostrom's short story "Golden", the main character Albert, an uplifted golden retriever, observes that humans observe nature from an ecologically aesthetic perspective which disregards the suffering of the individuals who inhabit "healthy" ecosystems;[224] Albert also asserts that it is a taboo in the animal rights movement that the majority of the suffering experienced by animals is due to natural processes and that "[a]ny proposal for remedying this situation is bound to sound utopian, but my dream is that one day the sun will rise on Earth and all sentient creatures will greet the new day with joy."[225]

The character Lord Vetinari, in Terry Pratchett's Unseen Academicals, in a speech, tells how he once observed a salmon being consumed alive by a mother otter and her children feeding on the salmon's eggs. He sarcastically describes "[m]other and children dining upon mother and children" as one of "nature's wonders", using it as an example of how evil is "built into the very nature of the universe".[226] This depiction of evil has been described as non-traditional because it expresses horror at the idea that evil has been designed as a feature of the universe.[227]

In poetry

 
Isaac Gompertz's 1813 poem "To the Thoughtless"

Homer, in the Iliad, employs the simile of a stag who, as a victim, is wounded by a human hunter and is then devoured by jackals, who themselves are frightened away by a scavenging lion.[228] In the epigram "The Swallow and the Grasshopper", attributed to Euenus, the poet writes of a swallow feeding a grasshopper to its young, remarking: "wilt not quickly cast it loose? for it is not right nor just that singers should perish by singers' mouths."[229]

Al-Ma'arri wrote of the kindness of giving water to birds and speculated whether there was a future existence where innocent animals would experience happiness to remedy the suffering they experience in this world. In the Luzūmiyyāt, he included a poem addressed to the wolf, who: "if he were conscious of his bloodguiltiness, would rather have remained unborn."[230]

In "On Poetry: A Rhaposdy", written in 1733, Jonathan Swift argues that Hobbes proved that all creatures exist in a state of eternal war and uses predation by different animals as evidence of this: "A Whale of moderate Size will draw / A Shole of Herrings down his Maw. / A Fox with Geese his Belly crams; / A Wolf destroys a thousand Lambs."[231] Voltaire makes similar descriptions of predation in his "Poem on the Lisbon Disaster", published in 1756, arguing: "Elements, animals, humans, everything is at war".[232] Voltaire also asserts that "all animals [are] condemned to live, / All sentient things, born by the same stern law, / Suffer like me, and like me also die."[233]

In William Blake's Vala, or The Four Zoas, the character Enion laments the cruelty of nature,[234] observing how ravens cry out, but don't receive pity and how sparrows and robins starve to death in the winter. Enion also mourns how wolves and lions reproduce in a state of love, then abandon their young to the wilds and how a spider labours to create a web, awaiting a fly, but then is consumed by a bird.[235]

Erasmus Darwin in The Temple of Nature, published posthumously in 1803, observes the struggle for existence, describing how different animals feed upon each other: "The towering eagle, darting from above, / Unfeeling rends the inoffensive dove [...] Nor spares, enamour'd of his radiant form, / The hungry nightingale the glowing worm" and how parasitic animals, like botflies, reproduce, their young feeding inside the living bodies of other animals: "Fell Oestrus buries in her rapid course / Her countless brood in stag, or bull, or horse; / Whose hungry larva eats its living way, / Hatch'd by the warmth, and issues into day."[236]: 154–155  He also refers to the world as "one great Slaughter-house".[236]: 159  In a footnote, he speculates whether humans could someday create a food source for predatory animals based on sugar, asserting that, as a result, "food for animals would then become as plentiful as water, and they might live upon the earth without preying on each other, as thick as blades of grass, with no restraint to their numbers but the want of local room."[236]: 160  The poem has been used as an example of how Erasmus Darwin predicted evolutionary theory.[237]

Isaac Gompertz, the brother of Lewis Gompertz, in his 1813 poem "To the Thoughtless", criticises the assertion that human consumption of other animals is justified because it is designed that way by nature, inviting the reader to imagine themselves being predated by an animal and to consider whether they would want to have their life saved, in the same way an animal being preyed upon—such as a fly attacked by a spider—would, despite predation being part of nature-given law.[238]

In the 1818 poem "Epistle to John Hamilton Reynolds", John Keats retells to John Hamilton Reynolds how one evening he was by the ocean, when he saw: "Too far into the sea; where every maw / The greater on the less feeds evermore" and observes that there exists an "eternal fierce destruction" at the core of the world: "The Shark at savage prey — the hawk at pounce, — / The gentle Robin, like a Pard or Ounce, / Ravening a worm".[239] The poem has been cited as an example of Erasmus Darwin's writings on Keats.[240]

In 1850, Alfred Tennyson published the poem "In Memoriam A.H.H.", which contained the expression "Nature, red in tooth and claw"; this phrase has since become commonly used as a shorthand to refer to the extent of suffering in nature.[241] In his 1855 poem "Maud", Tennyson described nature as irredeemable because of the theft and predation it intrinsically contains: "For nature is one with rapine, a harm no preacher can heal; / The Mayfly is torn by the swallow, the sparrow spear'd by the shrike, / And the whole little wood where I sit is a world of plunder and prey."[242]

Edwin Arnold in The Light of Asia, a narrative poem published in 1879 about the life of Prince Gautama Buddha, describes how originally the prince saw the "peace and plenty" of nature, but upon closer inspection he observed: "Life living upon death. So the fair show / Veiled one vast, savage, grim conspiracy / Of mutual murder, from the worm to man".[243] It has been asserted that the Darwinian struggle depicted in the poem comes more from Arnold than Buddhist tradition.[244]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b c d Tomasik, Brian (2015-11-02). "The Importance of Wild-Animal Suffering". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 133–152. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-toma. ISSN 2280-9643.
  2. ^ a b c Faria, Catia; Paez, Eze (2015-05-11). "Animals in Need: the Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (1): 7–13. ISSN 2280-9643.
  3. ^ a b Wilcox, Christie (2011-12-04). "Bambi or Bessie: Are wild animals happier?". Scientific American. Retrieved 2019-10-29.
  4. ^ a b c Horta, Oscar (2014-11-25). "Egalitarianism and Animals". Between the Species. 19 (1).
  5. ^ a b c Dawkins, Richard (1995). "Chapter 4: God's Utility Function". River Out of Eden. London: Orion Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-297-81540-2.
  6. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Horta, Oscar (2010). "Debunking the Idyllic View of Natural Processes: Population Dynamics and Suffering in the Wild" (PDF). Télos. 17 (1): 73–88.
  7. ^ a b c Iglesias, Alejandro Villamor (2018). "The overwhelming prevalence of suffering in Nature". Revista de Bioética y Derecho. 2019: 181–195.
  8. ^ For discussion of wild animal suffering and its relation to the problem of evil see:
    • Darwin, Charles (September 1993). Barlow, Nora (ed.). The Autobiography of Charles Darwin: 1809-1882. W. W. Norton & Company. p. 90. ISBN 978-0393310696.
    • Lewis, C. S. (2015). The Problem of Pain. HarperOne. ISBN 9780060652968.
    • Murray, Michael (April 30, 2011). Nature Red in Tooth and Claw: Theism and the Problem of Animal Suffering. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199596324.
    • Gould, Stephen (February 1982). "Nonmoral Nature" (PDF). Natural History. 91 (2): 19–26. Retrieved 19 January 2014.
    • McMahan, Jeff (2013). "The Moral Problem of Predation" (PDF). In Chignell, Andrew; Cuneo, Terence; Halteman, Matt (eds.). Philosophy Comes to Dinner: Arguments on the Ethics of Eating. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0415806831.
  9. ^ For academic discussion of wild animal suffering and its alleviation from a secular standpoint see:
    • McMahan, Jeff (2013). "The Moral Problem of Predation" (PDF). In Chignell, Andrew; Cuneo, Terence; Halteman, Matt (eds.). Philosophy Comes to Dinner: Arguments on the Ethics of Eating. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0415806831.
    • Ng, Yew-Kwang (1995). "Towards Welfare Biology: Evolutionary Economics of Animal Consciousness and Suffering" (PDF). Biology and Philosophy. 10 (3): 255–285. doi:10.1007/BF00852469. S2CID 59407458.
    • Dorado, Daniel (2015). "Ethical Interventions in the Wild. An Annotated Bibliography". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 219–238. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-dora. Retrieved 21 April 2016.
    • Moen, Ole Martin (2016). "The Ethics of Wild Animal Suffering" (PDF). Etikk I Praksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics. 10: 1–14. doi:10.5324/eip.v10i1.1972. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Horta, Oscar (2015). "The Problem of Evil in Nature: Evolutionary Bases of the Prevalence of Disvalue". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (1): 17–32. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-001-hort. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Torres, Mikel (2015). "The Case for Intervention in Nature on Behalf of Animals: A Critical Review of the Main Arguments against Intervention". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (1): 33–49. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-001-torr. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Cunha, Luciano Carlos (2015). "If Natural Entities Have Intrinsic Value, Should We Then Abstain from Helping Animals Who Are Victims of Natural Processes?". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (1): 51–63. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-001-cunh. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Tomasik, Brian (2015). "The Importance of Wild-Animal Suffering". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 133–152. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-toma. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Pearce, David (2015). "A Welfare State For Elephants? A Case Study of Compassionate Stewardship". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 153–164. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-pear. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Paez, Eze (2015). "Refusing Help and Inflicting Harm. A Critique of the Environmentalist View". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 165–178. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-paez. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Sözmen, Beril (2015). "Relations and Moral Obligations towards Other Animals". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 179–193. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-sozm. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
    • Faria, Catia (2016). Animal Ethics Goes Wild: The Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature (Ph.D.). Universitat Pompeu Fabra.
  10. ^ a b Delon, Nicolas; Purves, Duncan (2018-04-01). "Wild Animal Suffering is Intractable". Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 31 (2): 239–260. doi:10.1007/s10806-018-9722-y. ISSN 1573-322X. S2CID 158886418.
  11. ^ Callicott, J. Baird (1980-11-01). "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair" (PDF). Environmental Ethics. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19802424. S2CID 41646945. (PDF) from the original on 2019-02-20. Retrieved 2021-03-21.
  12. ^ a b c Simmons, Aaron (2009). "Animals, Predators, The Right to Life and The Duty to Save Lives". Ethics & the Environment. 14 (1): 15–27. doi:10.2979/ete.2009.14.1.15. S2CID 89542818.
  13. ^ a b c Sözmen, Beril İdemen (2013-11-01). "Harm in the Wild: Facing Non-Human Suffering in Nature" (PDF). Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 16 (5): 1075–1088. doi:10.1007/s10677-013-9416-5. ISSN 1572-8447. S2CID 143964923.
  14. ^ a b Regan, Tom (2004). The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press. p. 357. ISBN 978-0-520-24386-6.
  15. ^ a b Kapembwa, Julius (2017). Wildlife rights and human obligations (PhD thesis). University of Reading. p. 50
  16. ^ a b c Horta, Oscar (2015-01-05). "Why the Situation of Animals in the Wild Should Concern Us". Animal Charity Evaluators. Retrieved 2019-08-17.
  17. ^ a b c Sebo, Jeff (2020-01-15). "All we owe to animals". Aeon. Retrieved 2021-03-15.
  18. ^ "Helping animals in the wild". Animal Ethics. 2013-08-28. Retrieved 2019-08-17.
  19. ^ a b Vinding, Magnus (2020). "Reducing Extreme Suffering for Non-Human Animals: Enhancement vs. Smaller Future Populations?". Between the Species. 23 (1).
  20. ^ Wiblin, Robert; Harris, Kieran (2019-08-15). "Animals in the wild often suffer a great deal. What, if anything, should we do about that?". 80,000 Hours. Retrieved 2019-10-25.
  21. ^ a b c d Ray, Georgia (2017-11-22). . Wild-Animal Suffering Research. Archived from the original on 2021-06-12. Retrieved 2021-03-24.
  22. ^ Calvete, C.; Estrada, R.; Villafuerte, R.; Osácar, J. J.; Lucientes, J. (2002). "Epidemiology of viral haemorrhagic disease and myxomatosis in a free-living population of wild rabbits". Veterinary Record. 150 (25): 776–782. doi:10.1136/vr.150.25.776. ISSN 2042-7670. PMID 12135072. S2CID 7084943.
  23. ^ Knight, Kelli; Wick, Peach van (2019), "Medical and Surgical Management of Deer and Relatives", Medical Management of Wildlife Species, John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, pp. 259–270, doi:10.1002/9781119036708.ch20, ISBN 978-1-119-03670-8, S2CID 208578632, retrieved 2021-03-24
  24. ^ Botzler, Richard G.; Brown, Richard N. (2014). Foundations of Wildlife Diseases. Berkeley, California: University of California Press. p. 378. ISBN 978-0-520-27609-3.
  25. ^ Beldomenico, Pablo M; Telfer, Sandra; Gebert, Stephanie; Lukomski, Lukasz; Bennett, Malcolm; Begon, Michael (2008-08-07). "Poor condition and infection: a vicious circle in natural populations". Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 275 (1644): 1753–1759. doi:10.1098/rspb.2008.0147. ISSN 0962-8452. PMC 2453294. PMID 18448414.
  26. ^ Brannelly, Laura A.; Webb, Rebecca; Skerratt, Lee F.; Berger, Lee (2016). "Amphibians with infectious disease increase their reproductive effort: evidence for the terminal investment hypothesis". Open Biology. 6 (6): 150251. doi:10.1098/rsob.150251. PMC 4929933. PMID 27358291.
  27. ^ "Physical injuries in wild animals". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-24.
  28. ^ Scott, Marilyn E. (1988). "The Impact of Infection and Disease on Animal Populations: Implications for Conservation Biology". Conservation Biology. 2 (1): 40–56. doi:10.1111/j.1523-1739.1988.tb00334.x. ISSN 1523-1739.
  29. ^ Goodman, Brett A.; Johnson, Pieter T. J. (2011-05-25). "Disease and the Extended Phenotype: Parasites Control Host Performance and Survival through Induced Changes in Body Plan". PLOS ONE. 6 (5): e20193. Bibcode:2011PLoSO...620193G. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0020193. ISSN 1932-6203. PMC 3102088. PMID 21633498.
  30. ^ Libersat, Frederic; Kaiser, Maayan; Emanuel, Stav (2018). "Mind Control: How Parasites Manipulate Cognitive Functions in Their Insect Hosts". Frontiers in Psychology. 9: 572. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00572. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5938628. PMID 29765342.
  31. ^ Robar, Nicholas; Burness, Gary; Murray, Dennis L. (2010). "Tropics, trophics and taxonomy: the determinants of parasite-associated host mortality". Oikos. 119 (8): 1273–1280. doi:10.1111/j.1600-0706.2009.18292.x. ISSN 1600-0706.
  32. ^ a b c "Predators, parasites and parasitoids". The Australian Museum. Retrieved 2021-03-24.
  33. ^ "Parasitoids". Cornell University College of Agriculture and Life Sciences. Retrieved 2021-03-24.
  34. ^ Fiske, W. F. (1910-02-01). "Superparasitism: an Important Factor in the Natural Control of Insects1". Journal of Economic Entomology. 3 (1): 88–97. doi:10.1093/jee/3.1.88. ISSN 0022-0493.
  35. ^ Sekar, Sandhya (2015-05-22). "Parasitoid wasps may be the most diverse animal group". BBC Earth. Retrieved 2021-03-24.
  36. ^ "Malnutrition and Starvation". Michigan Department of Natural Resources. Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  37. ^ Faria, Catia (2016). Animal Ethics Goes Wild: The Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature (PDF) (PhD thesis). Universitat Pompeu Fabra.
  38. ^ China, Victor; Holzman, Roi (2014-06-03). "Hydrodynamic starvation in first-feeding larval fishes". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 111 (22): 8083–8088. Bibcode:2014PNAS..111.8083C. doi:10.1073/pnas.1323205111. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 4050599. PMID 24843180.
  39. ^ "Malnutrition, hunger and thirst in wild animals". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-26.
  40. ^ Russo, Catherine J. M.; Ohmer, Michel E. B.; Cramp, Rebecca L.; Franklin, Craig E. (2018-05-01). "A pathogenic skin fungus and sloughing exacerbate cutaneous water loss in amphibians". Journal of Experimental Biology. 221 (9). doi:10.1242/jeb.167445. ISSN 0022-0949. PMID 29752415.
  41. ^ a b Weidman, T.; Litvaitis, J. A. (2011-07-01). "Can supplemental food increase winter survival of a threatened cottontail rabbit?". Biological Conservation. 144 (7): 2054–2058. doi:10.1016/j.biocon.2011.04.027. ISSN 0006-3207.
  42. ^ a b c d "Weather conditions and nonhuman animals". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-27.
  43. ^ Amos, Jonathan (2019-04-24). "Antarctica: Thousands of emperor penguin chicks wiped out". BBC News. Retrieved 2021-04-05.
  44. ^ Sharman, Jon (2019-08-20). "Thousands of birds killed after freak weather event leaves them with smashed skulls and internal damage". The Independent. Retrieved 2021-04-07.
  45. ^ Smith, Allen G.; Webster, Harry R. (1955). "Effects of Hail Storms on Waterfowl Populations in Alberta, Canada: 1953". The Journal of Wildlife Management. 19 (3): 368–374. doi:10.2307/3797388. ISSN 0022-541X. JSTOR 3797388.
  46. ^ Elbaum, Rachel; Eckardt, Andy (2018-08-16). "Wildlife, animals suffer in Europe's summer of extreme heat". NBC News. Retrieved 2021-04-05.
  47. ^ Sanderson, Katharine (2007-01-04). "Hot waters make it hard for fish to breathe". Nature: news070101–5. doi:10.1038/news070101-5. ISSN 0028-0836. S2CID 129050854.
  48. ^ "With Temperatures Rising, Can Animals Survive the Heat Stress?". Yale E360. Retrieved 2021-04-05.
  49. ^ "Wildlife mass mortality events associated with harsh winter weather". The Veterinary Record. 182 (22): 628–629. 2018-06-02. doi:10.1136/vr.k2413. ISSN 2042-7670. PMID 29858315. S2CID 49335517.
  50. ^ Rödel, H. G.; Bora, A.; Kaetzke, P.; Khaschei, M.; Hutzelmeyer, H.; von Holst, D. (August 2004). "Over-winter survival in subadult European rabbits: weather effects, density dependence, and the impact of individual characteristics". Oecologia. 140 (4): 566–576. Bibcode:2004Oecol.140..566R. doi:10.1007/s00442-004-1616-1. ISSN 0029-8549. PMID 15309616. S2CID 40720075.
  51. ^ a b "Animals in natural disasters". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-28.
  52. ^ Olvera, Lola (2020-03-25). "When Natural Disaster Strikes, Wildlife Pays A Heavy Price". Sentient Media. Retrieved 2021-03-28.
  53. ^ Minelli, Alessandro (2008). "Predation". In Jørgensen, Sven Erik; Fath, Brian D. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ecology. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-08-093116-6. OCLC 527382954.
  54. ^ a b McMahan, Jeff (2010-09-19). "The Meat Eaters". Opinionator. Retrieved 2021-03-12.
  55. ^ "Antagonism in nature: Interspecific conflict". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-28.
  56. ^ Harris, J. B.; Goonetilleke, A. (2004-09-01). "Animal poisons and the nervous system: what the neurologist needs to know". Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry. 75 (suppl 3): iii40–iii46. doi:10.1136/jnnp.2004.045724. ISSN 0022-3050. PMC 1765666. PMID 15316044.
  57. ^ "Antagonism in nature: Intraspecific fights". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-28.
  58. ^ Povinelli, Daniel J. (2020-11-01). "Can Comparative Psychology Crack its Toughest Nut?" (PDF). Animal Behavior and Cognition. 7 (4): 589–652. doi:10.26451/abc.07.04.09.2020.
  59. ^ Zanette, Liana Y.; Clinchy, Michael (2019-05-06). "Ecology of fear". Current Biology. 29 (9): R309–R313. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2019.02.042. ISSN 0960-9822. PMID 31063718. S2CID 145049061.
  60. ^ Robbins, Jim (2017-04-11). "The Fear Factor: How the Peril of Predators Can Transform a Landscape". Yale E360. Retrieved 2020-08-01.
  61. ^ Zanette, Liana Y.; Hobbs, Emma C.; Witterick, Lauren E.; MacDougall-Shackleton, Scott A.; Clinchy, Michael (2019-08-07). "Predator-induced fear causes PTSD-like changes in the brains and behaviour of wild animals". Scientific Reports. 9 (1): 11474. Bibcode:2019NatSR...911474Z. doi:10.1038/s41598-019-47684-6. ISSN 2045-2322. PMC 6685979. PMID 31391473.
  62. ^ Allan, Bridie J. M. (2020-01-01). "Scared to death? the killer effect of predation risk in snowshoe hares". Conservation Physiology. 7 (1): coz029. doi:10.1093/conphys/coz029. PMC 6572791. PMID 31217976.
  63. ^ Ray, Georgia (2017-06-29). . Wild-Animal Suffering Research. Archived from the original on 2021-04-13. Retrieved 2021-03-10.
  64. ^ Bar-On, Yinon M.; Phillips, Rob; Milo, Ron (2018-06-19). "Supplementary Information Appendix" (PDF). Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 115 (25): 6506–6511. Bibcode:2018PNAS..115.6506B. doi:10.1073/pnas.1711842115. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 6016768. PMID 29784790.
  65. ^ Matheny, Gaverick; Chan, Kai M. A. (December 2005). "Human Diets and Animal Welfare: the Illogic of the Larder". Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 18 (6): 579–594. doi:10.1007/s10806-005-1805-x. ISSN 1187-7863. S2CID 154198751.
  66. ^ Klein, Alice (2022-09-19). "There are 20,000,000,000,000,000 ants crawling all over Earth". New Scientist. Retrieved 2022-09-26.
  67. ^ Paez, Eze (2020-01-01). "Preserving nature for the benefit of all sentient individuals". Animal Sentience. 4 (27). doi:10.51291/2377-7478.1551. ISSN 2377-7478.
  68. ^ Darwin, Charles (September 1993). Barlow, Nora (ed.). The Autobiography of Charles Darwin: 1809-1882. W. W. Norton & Company. p. 90. ISBN 978-0393310696.
  69. ^ Dawkins, Richard (1995). River Out of Eden: A Darwinian View of Life. London: Orion Publishing Group. pp. 131–132. ISBN 978-0-297-81540-2.
  70. ^ Simpson, Keith (1979). Schultz, Martin (ed.). The Mysteries of Life & Death: An Illustrated Investigation into the Incredible World of Death. London: Salamander Books. p. 22. ISBN 978-0-86101-036-3.
  71. ^ a b c Ng, Yew-Kwang (1995). "Towards Welfare Biology: Evolutionary Economics of Animal Consciousness and Suffering" (PDF). Biology and Philosophy. 10 (3): 255–285. doi:10.1007/BF00852469. S2CID 59407458.
  72. ^ a b c Sagoff, Mark (1984). "Animal Liberation and Environmental Ethics: Bad Marriage, Quick Divorce". Osgoode Hall Law Journal. 22 (2): 297–307.
  73. ^ Groff, Zach; Ng, Yew-Kwang (2019-06-18). "Does suffering dominate enjoyment in the animal kingdom? An update to welfare biology". Biology & Philosophy. 34 (4): 40. doi:10.1007/s10539-019-9692-0. ISSN 1572-8404. S2CID 196683974.
  74. ^ Leonardo da Vinci (2004-01-01). The Notebooks of Leonardo Da Vinci — Complete. Translated by Richter, Jean Paul. folio 1219.
  75. ^ Hume, David (1779). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. London. p. 176.
  76. ^ a b c Paley, William (1879) [1802]. Paxton, James; Ware, John (eds.). Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity. Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity. New York: Sheldon & Company.
  77. ^ a b Gregory, T. Ryan (December 2009). "The Argument from Design: A Guided Tour of William Paley's Natural Theology (1802)". Evolution: Education and Outreach. 2 (4): 602–611. doi:10.1007/s12052-009-0184-6. ISSN 1936-6434.
  78. ^ Murray, Michael J. (2008). Nature Red in Tooth and Claw: Theism and the Problem of Animal Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-923727-2. OCLC 209815655.
  79. ^ Hoggard Creegan, Nicola (2013). Animal Suffering and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 44–55. ISBN 978-0-19-993185-9.
  80. ^ Evans, Edward Payson (September 1894). "Ethical Relations Between Man and Beast". Popular Science Monthly. 45: 646.
  81. ^ Schneider, John R. (2020). "Facing the Darwinian Problem of Evil". Animal Suffering and the Darwinian Problem of Evil (1 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 15–47. doi:10.1017/9781108767439.003. ISBN 978-1-108-76743-9. S2CID 238121342.
  82. ^ Darwin, Charles (1860-05-22). "To Asa Gray". Letter to Asa Gray. Retrieved 2021-03-07.
  83. ^ Darwin, Charles (1958). Barlow, Nora (ed.). The Autobiography of Charles Darwin. London: Collins. p. 90.
  84. ^ Moen, Ole Martin (2016-05-09). "The ethics of wild animal suffering". Etikk I Praksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics. 10 (1): 91–104. doi:10.5324/eip.v10i1.1972. ISSN 1890-4009.
  85. ^ Schmithausen, Lambert (1997). "The Early Buddhist Tradition and Ethics". Journal of Buddhist Ethics.
  86. ^ James, Simon P. (2006-02-01). "Buddhism and the Ethics of Species Conservation". Environmental Values. 15 (1): 85–97. doi:10.3197/096327106776678942.
  87. ^ a b Cooper, David E.; James, Simon P. (2005). Buddhism, Virtue and Environment. Farnham: Ashgate. pp. 119-120. ISBN 978-1-351-95431-0.
  88. ^ Stuart, Daniel M. (September 2019). "Becoming Animal: Karma and the Animal Realm Envisioned through an Early Yogācāra Lens". Religions. 10 (6): 363. doi:10.3390/rel10060363. ISSN 2077-1444.
  89. ^ Shantideva (2006). The Way of the Bodhisattva (Revised ed.). Shambhala. p. 165. ISBN 978-1590303887.
  90. ^ Rinpoche, Patrul (1998). The Words of My Perfect Teacher (Revised ed.). Shambhala. pp. 76–77. ISBN 978-1-57062-412-4.
  91. ^ Kemmerer, Lisa (April 2009). "Hindu Ethics and Nonhuman Animals". Swadharam Journal. 3: 32–45.
  92. ^ a b Buffon, Georges Louis Leclerc (1807). Natural History: Containing a Theory of the Earth, a General History of Man, of the Brute Creation, and of Vegetables, Minerals, &c. &c. &c. London: H. D. Symonds.
  93. ^ Herder, Johann Gottfried (1801). "The Animal Kingdom: In Relation to the History of Man". The Union Magazine, and Imperial Register. 2: 172.
  94. ^ a b c Gompertz, Lewis (1992) [1824]. Singer, Peter (ed.). Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes. Fontwell: Centaur Press.
  95. ^ Gompertz, Lewis (1852). Fragments in Defence of Animals, and Essays on Morals, Soul, and Future State. London: W. Horsell. p. 18.
  96. ^ Pedatella, Stefan (2009-03-01). "Images of Animal Predation in Giacomo Leopardi's Dialogo della Natura e di un Islandese". Italian Culture. 27 (1): 25–42. doi:10.1179/155909009X401665. ISSN 0161-4622. S2CID 159793645.
  97. ^ Leopardi, Giacomo (2013). "4511". Zibaldone: The Notebooks of Leopardi. Penguin. ISBN 978-0-14-196200-9. Indeed, precisely the order that exists in the world, and seeing that evil is in this order, that such order cannot exist without evil, makes the existence of the latter inconceivable. Animals destined for the nourishment of other species. The inborn envy and hatred of living beings toward their fellows
  98. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (2000). Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 292. ISBN 9780199242214.
  99. ^ Mill, John Stuart (1874). "Nature". Three Essays on Religion. London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer. pp. 28, 32, 65.
  100. ^ a b Salt, Henry Stephens; Leffingwell, Albert (1894). Animals' Rights: Considered in Relation to Social Progress. Columbia University Libraries. New York, London: Macmillan & Co.
  101. ^ Moore, J. Howard (1906). The Universal Kinship. Chicago: Charles H. Kerr & Co. pp. 249–250.
  102. ^ a b Moore, J. Howard (1912). Ethics and Education. London: G. Bell & Sons.
  103. ^ Skutch, Alexander F. (1952). "Which Shall We Protect? Thoughts on the Ethics of the Treatment of Free Life" (PDF). Aryan Path. 23: 382–386.
  104. ^ a b Singer, Peter (June 14, 1973). "Food for Thought". The New York Review of Books. Retrieved 23 February 2015.
  105. ^ Clark, Stephen R. L. (2008-08-29) [1979]. "The rights of Wild things". Inquiry. 22 (1–4): 171–188. doi:10.1080/00201747908601871.
  106. ^ Callicott, J. Baird (1980-11-01). "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair" (PDF). Environmental Ethics. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19802424. Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  107. ^ "30 years since the publication of Morals, reason and animals". Animal Ethics. 2017-07-25. Retrieved 2021-09-09.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  108. ^ Naess, Arne (1991). "Should We Try to Relieve Clear Cases of Suffering in Nature?" (PDF). Pan Ecology. 6: 1–5. Retrieved 20 November 2016.
  109. ^ Olivier, David (1993-06-01). "Pourquoi je ne suis pas écologiste" [Why I am not an environmentalist]. Les Cahiers antispécistes (in French). Retrieved 2020-04-11.
  110. ^ Tomasik, Brian (July 2009). "The Importance of Wild-Animal Suffering". Center on Long-Term Risk. Retrieved 2021-10-08.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  111. ^ "Vol 3, No 1 (2015)". ledonline.it. 2015. Retrieved 2022-06-18.
  112. ^ "Vol 3, No 2 (2015)". ledonline.it. 2015. Retrieved 2022-09-26.
  113. ^ Faria, Catia (May 2015). "Making a Difference on Behalf of Animals Living in the Wild: Interview with Jeff McMahan" (PDF). Relations. 3 (1): 81–84. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-001-fari. ISSN 2283-3196.
  114. ^ a b c McMahan, Jeff (2010-09-28). "Predators: A Response". The New York Times. Retrieved 2019-10-29.
  115. ^ a b Reese, Jacy (14 December 2015). "Wild animals endure illness, injury, and starvation. We should help". Vox. Retrieved 17 April 2016.
  116. ^ Reese, Jacy (2018). "The Expanding Moral Circle, Revisited". The End of Animal Farming: How Scientists, Entrepreneurs, and Activists Are Building an Animal-Free Food System. Beacon Press. ISBN 978-0-8070-1945-0.
  117. ^ Matthews, Dylan (2021-04-12). "The wild frontier of animal welfare". Vox. Retrieved 2022-06-18.
  118. ^ a b c d Nadler, Steven (2018-08-10). "We have an ethical obligation to relieve individual animal suffering". Aeon. Retrieved 2021-03-15.
  119. ^ "First dissertation on helping animals in the wild". Center for Animal Ethics (UPF). 2016-03-19. Retrieved 2021-02-13.
  120. ^ "Animal Ethics in the Wild". Cambridge University Press. Retrieved 2022-06-13.
  121. ^ "Kyle Johannsen, 'Wild Animal Ethics: The Moral and The Moral and Political Problem of Wild Animal Suffering'". New Books Network. 2021-01-11. Retrieved 2021-07-07.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  122. ^ "Symposium on Kyle Johannsen's Wild Animal Ethics". APPLE. 2021-01-21. Retrieved 2021-09-30.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  123. ^ Horta, Oscar (2022), "In defense of animals!", Making a Stand for Animals, pp. 135–165, doi:10.4324/9781003285922-7, ISBN 9781003285922, retrieved 2022-07-10
  124. ^ "Announcing Wild Animal Initiative". Wild Animal Initiative. 2019-01-19. Retrieved 2021-07-07.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  125. ^ "Why wild animal suffering matters". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2021-07-07.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  126. ^ Schukraft, Jason (2019-11-06). "Opinion: estimating invertebrate sentience". Rethink Priorities. Retrieved 2022-06-18.
  127. ^ Schukraft, Jason (2019-07-09). "Invertebrate welfare cause profile". Rethink Priorities. Retrieved 2022-06-18.
  128. ^ Canon, Gabrielle (2021-09-10). "How a Tahoe refuge saved owls, coyotes and raccoons from wildfire". The Guardian. Retrieved 2021-09-10.
  129. ^ Keulartz, Jozef (2016-10-01). "Should the Lion Eat Straw Like the Ox? Animal Ethics and the Predation Problem". Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 29 (5): 813–834. doi:10.1007/s10806-016-9637-4. ISSN 1573-322X.
  130. ^ Raterman, Ty (Winter 2008). "An Environmentalist's Lament on Predation" (PDF). Environmental Ethics. 30 (4): 417–434. doi:10.5840/enviroethics200830443.
  131. ^ Kapembwa, Julius (October 2018). "Predation Catch-22: Disentangling the Rights of Prey, Predators, and Rescuers". Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 31 (5): 527–542. doi:10.1007/s10806-018-9743-6. ISSN 1187-7863. S2CID 158949810.
  132. ^ a b McMahan, Jeff (2013). "The Moral Problem of Predation" (PDF). In Chignell, Andrew; Cuneo, Terence; Halteman, Matt (eds.). Philosophy Comes to Dinner: Arguments on the Ethics of Eating. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0415806831.
  133. ^ Ebert, Rainer (2012). "Innocent Threats and the Moral Problem of Carnivorous Animals". Journal of Applied Philosophy. 29 (2): 146–159. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.2012.00561.x.
  134. ^ Trindade, Gabriel Garmendia da; Woodhall, Andrew, eds. (2020). Intervention or Protest: Acting for Nonhuman Animals. Vernon Press. p. 244. ISBN 978-1-62273-975-2.
  135. ^ Everett, Jennifer (2001). "Environmental Ethics, Animal Welfarism, and the Problem of Predation: A Bambi Lover's Respect for Nature". Ethics and the Environment. 6 (1): 42–67. ISSN 1085-6633. JSTOR 40339003.
  136. ^ a b Aaltola, Elisa (February 2010). "Animal Ethics and the Argument from Absurdity". Environmental Values. 19 (1): 79–98. doi:10.3197/096327110X485392.
  137. ^ a b Ryf, Philipp (2016-09-01). Environmental Ethics: The Case of Wild Animals (Master's thesis). University of Basel.
  138. ^ Shooster, Jay (2017-07-11). . Wild-Animal Suffering Research. Archived from the original on 2020-12-04. Retrieved 2021-03-09.
  139. ^ a b Cowen, Tyler (2003). (PDF). Environmental Ethics. 25 (2): 169–182. doi:10.5840/enviroethics200325231. S2CID 16279915. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2019-10-29.
  140. ^ McShane, Katie (2018). "Why Animal Welfare Is Not Biodiversity, Ecosystem Services, or Human Welfare: Toward a More Complete Assessment of Climate Impacts" (PDF). Les ateliers de l'éthique / The Ethics Forum. 13 (1): 43–64. doi:10.7202/1055117ar. ISSN 1718-9977.
  141. ^ Hopster, Jeroen (2019-12-01). "The Speciesism Debate: Intuition, Method, and Empirical Advances". Animals. 9 (12): 1054. doi:10.3390/ani9121054. ISSN 2076-2615. PMC 6940905. PMID 31805715. There are various definitions of speciesism in circulation in the academic literature and beyond. Some authors treat speciesism as an unjustified position by definition. This is problematic, however, since the defensibility of speciesism is subject to substantive debate. A more fruitful approach is to distinguish the descriptive concept of speciesism from its normative evaluation. Here, and in what follows, I will adopt Singer's definition, according to which speciesism involves the preferential consideration of the interests of members of one's own species.
  142. ^ Mayerfeld, Jamie (1999). Suffering and Moral Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 117. ISBN 978-0-19-515495-5.
  143. ^ Bruers, Stijn (2020-10-22). "Speciesism, Arbitrariness and Moral Illusions". Philosophia. 49 (3): 957–975. doi:10.1007/s11406-020-00282-7. ISSN 0048-3893. S2CID 226346638.
  144. ^ Muraille, Eric (2018-07-23). "Debate: Could anti-speciesism and veganism form the basis for a rational society?". The Conversation. Retrieved 2021-04-02.
  145. ^ a b Horta, Oscar (2016-07-05). "Changing attitudes towards animals in the wild and speciesism". Animal Sentience. 1 (7). doi:10.51291/2377-7478.1109. ISSN 2377-7478.
  146. ^ a b Nussbaum, Martha C. (2006). Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-04157-8. OCLC 434003841.
  147. ^ Singer, Peter (2014). The Point of View of The Universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 346. ISBN 978-0199603695.
  148. ^ Horta, Oscar (2017). "Animal Suffering in the Wild". Environmental Ethics. 39 (3): 261–279. doi:10.5840/enviroethics201739320.
  149. ^ Verchot, Manon. "Meet the people who want to turn predators into herbivores". TreeHugger. Retrieved 2019-10-29.
  150. ^ Belshaw, Christoher (2001). Environmental Philosophy. McGill-Queen's Press. p. xii. ISBN 978-1-902683-21-8.
  151. ^ Paez, Eze (2015-11-02). "Refusing Help and Inflicting Harm. A Critique of the Environmentalist View". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 165–178. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-paez. ISSN 2280-9643.
  152. ^ Faria, Catia; Paez, Eze (2019-07-01). "It's Splitsville: Why Animal Ethics and Environmental Ethics Are Incompatible". American Behavioral Scientist. 63 (8): 1047–1060. doi:10.1177/0002764219830467. ISSN 0002-7642. S2CID 150854523.
  153. ^ a b c Hettinger, Ned (1994). (PDF). Environmental Ethics. 16 (1): 3–20. doi:10.5840/enviroethics199416138. S2CID 18428255. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2019-02-25.
  154. ^ Moen, Ole Martin (2016). "The Ethics of Wild Animal Suffering" (PDF). Etikk I Praksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics. 10: 1–14. doi:10.5324/eip.v10i1.1972. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
  155. ^ a b c Horta, Oscar (2018). "Concern for Wild Animal Suffering and Environmental Ethics: What Are the Limits of the Disagreement". Les Ateliers de l'Éthique. 13 (1): 85–100. doi:10.7202/1055119ar. ISSN 1718-9977.
  156. ^ Rolston III, Holmes (1988). Environmental Ethics: Duties To and Values in the Natural World. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. ISBN 9780877225010.
  157. ^ Moriarty, Paul; Mark Woods (1997). "Hunting ≠ Predation". Environmental Ethics. 19 (4): 391–404. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19971945.
  158. ^ "Yves Bonnardel: l'antispéciste qui n'aimait pas la nature" [Yves Bonnardel: the anti-speciesist who did not like nature]. Usbek & Rica (in French). 2016-08-22. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
  159. ^ Nelson, Michael P.; Vucetich, John A. (2013-02-01), "Wilderness, Value of" (PDF), in Lafollette, Hugh (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. wbiee645, doi:10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee645, ISBN 978-1-4051-8641-4, retrieved 2022-07-16
  160. ^ Duclos, Joshua (2018). Value, morality, and wilderness (Thesis). Boston University.
  161. ^ Walker, Jack (June 2022). "Born to be Wild? On "Wildness" Objections to Preventing Wild Animal Suffering" (PDF). Aporia. 32 (1).
  162. ^ Duclos, Joshua S. (2022). Wilderness, Morality, and Value. Lanham: Lexington Books. ISBN 978-1-6669-0136-8. OCLC 1330426290.
  163. ^ Fischer, Bob (2018-01-01). "Individuals in the wild". Animal Sentience. 3 (23). doi:10.51291/2377-7478.1382. ISSN 2377-7478.
  164. ^ Wilson, Scott D. (2011). "Animal Ethics in Context by Palmer, Claire". Ethics 121 (4): 824–8. doi:10.1086/660788.
  165. ^ Hettinger, Ned (2018). "Naturalness, Wild-animal Suffering, and Palmer on Laissez-faire". Les ateliers de l'éthique / The Ethics Forum. 13 (1): 65–84. doi:10.7202/1055118ar. ISSN 1718-9977.
  166. ^ Faria, Catia (2014-12-21). "Should we intervene in nature to help animals?". Practical Ethics. Retrieved 2021-03-13.
  167. ^ Sapontzis, Steve (2011-03-18). "Predation". Ethics and Animals. 5 (2). doi:10.15368/ea.1984v5n2.1. ISSN 0197-9094.
  168. ^ Ladwig, Bernd (2015). "Against Wild Animal Sovereignty: An Interest-based Critique of Zoopolis". Journal of Political Philosophy. 23 (3): 282–301. doi:10.1111/jopp.12068. ISSN 1467-9760.
  169. ^ Bailey, Christiane (2014). "Le double sens de la communauté morale: la considérabilité morale et l'agentivité morale des autres animaux" [The double meaning of moral community: moral consideration and the moral agency of other animals]. Les ateliers de l'éthique / The Ethics Forum (in French). 9 (3): 31–67. doi:10.7202/1029059ar. ISSN 1718-9977.
  170. ^ Horta, Oscar (2013). "Zoopolis, interventions and the State of Nature" (PDF). Law, Ethics and Philosophy: 113–125. ISSN 2341-1465.
  171. ^ Reus, Estiva (2018). "Le lourd fardeau de l'être humain" [The Heavy Burden of Human Being]. Éliminer les animaux pour leur bien: promenade chez les réducteurs de la souffrance dans la nature [Eliminate animals for their good: walk among the reducers of suffering in nature] (in French). Vol. 41. Les Cahiers antispécistes.
  172. ^ a b Lepeltier, Thomas (2018-11-07). "Se soucier des animaux sauvages" [Caring about wild animals]. L'Amorce (in French). Retrieved 2021-03-12.
  173. ^ a b Brennan, Ozy (2018-12-20). . Wild-Animal Suffering Research. Archived from the original on 2021-03-21. Retrieved 2019-10-25.
  174. ^ "In pictures: India's 'original conservationists'". BBC News. 2014-07-20. Retrieved 2020-10-23. In Bishnoi villages, birds and animals roam without fear and feed off human hands
  175. ^ Menon, Gangadharan (2012-07-03). "The Land of The Bishnois - Where Conservation Of Wildlife Is A Religion!". The Better India. Retrieved 2021-03-07.
  176. ^ Attfield, Robin (2018). Environmental Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 103. ISBN 978-0-19-879716-6.
  177. ^ Clarke, Matthew; Ng, Yew-Kwang (October 2006). "Population Dynamics and Animal Welfare: Issues Raised by the Culling of Kangaroos in Puckapunyal". Social Choice and Welfare. 27 (2): 407–422. doi:10.1007/s00355-006-0137-8. ISSN 0176-1714. S2CID 15023392.
  178. ^ Burke, Jason (2016-09-14). "South African national park to kill animals in response to severe drought". The Guardian. Retrieved 2021-03-07.
  179. ^ Dorfman, Andrea (1988-11-07). "Environment: Free At Last! Bon Voyage!". Time. ISSN 0040-781X. Retrieved 2021-04-06.
  180. ^ a b Mohdin, Aamna (2018-11-19). "Top film-makers back penguin intervention on Attenborough show". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2020-05-01.
  181. ^ "2,000 baby flamingos rescued after being abandoned in South African drought". The Guardian. 2019-02-07. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2019-02-09.
  182. ^ Zhou, Naaman (2019-12-24). "Heartbreaking and heartwarming: animals rescued from Australia's bushfires devastation". The Guardian. Retrieved 2021-03-21.
  183. ^ "Sri Lanka rescues 120 whales after biggest mass stranding". The Guardian. 2020-11-03. Retrieved 2021-03-16.
  184. ^ Trenchard, Tommy; d'Unienville, Aurélie Marrier (2021-02-03). "Cape cormorants: Caring for South Africa's chicks abandoned in wild". BBC News. Retrieved 2021-02-08.
  185. ^ Daly, Natasha (2021-02-19). "Nearly 5,000 sea turtles rescued from freezing waters on Texas island". National Geographic. Retrieved 2021-02-19.
  186. ^ Abbott, Rachel C. (2020-02-17). "Wildlife Vaccination - Growing in Feasibility?". Cornell Wildlife Health Lab. Retrieved 2020-05-30.
  187. ^ "Questions and answers about immunocontraception". The Humane Society of the United States. Retrieved 2019-09-09.
  188. ^ a b Pearce, David (2015). "A Welfare State For Elephants? A Case Study of Compassionate Stewardship". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 153–164. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-pear. Retrieved 8 May 2016.
  189. ^ Johannsen, Kyle (April 2017). "Animal Rights and the Problem of r-Strategists". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 20 (2): 333–345. doi:10.1007/s10677-016-9774-x. ISSN 1386-2820. S2CID 151950095.
  190. ^ Thornhill, Richard; Morris, Michael (2006-01-01). "Animal Liberationist Responses to Non-Anthropogenic Animal Suffering" (PDF). Worldviews: Global Religions, Culture, and Ecology. 10 (3): 355–379. doi:10.1163/156853506778942077. ISSN 1363-5247.
  191. ^ MacAskill, William; MacAskill, Amanda (9 September 2015). "To Truly End Animal Suffering, the Most Ethical Choice is To Kill Wild Predators (Especially Cecil the Lion)". Quartz. Retrieved 17 April 2016.
  192. ^ Grush, Loren (2015-09-10). "Killing off wild predators is a stupid idea". The Verge. Retrieved 2019-10-29.
  193. ^ Horta, Oscar (2010). "The Ethics of the Ecology of Fear against the Nonspeciesist Paradigm A Shift in the Aims of Intervention in Nature". Between the Species. 13 (10): 163–187. doi:10.15368/bts.2010v13n10.10.
  194. ^ Brennan, Ozy (2018-05-23). . Wild-Animal Suffering Research. Archived from the original on 2020-12-04. Retrieved 2021-03-28.
  195. ^ John, Tyler M.; Sebo, Jeff (2020). "Consequentialism and Nonhuman Animals" (PDF). In Portmore, Douglas W. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Douglas W. Portmore. New York, NY. ISBN 978-0-19-090535-4. OCLC 1154100861.
  196. ^ Faria, Catia; Horta, Oscar (2019). "Welfare Biology". In Fischer, Bob (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics. New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315105840-41. ISBN 978-1-315-10584-0. S2CID 241043958.
  197. ^ Brennan, Ozy (2017-11-25). . Wild-Animal Suffering Research. Archived from the original on 2021-07-11. Retrieved 2019-09-09.
  198. ^ Salazar, Maria (2019-07-31). "Why is Welfare Biology Important?". Animal Charity Evaluators. Retrieved 2019-09-09.
  199. ^ Matthews, Dylan (2021-04-12). "The wild frontier of animal welfare". Vox. Retrieved 2021-09-05.
  200. ^ Kovic, Marko (2021-02-01). "Risks of space colonization". Futures. 126: 102638. doi:10.1016/j.futures.2020.102638. ISSN 0016-3287. S2CID 230597480.
  201. ^ Eskander, P. (2018). "Crucial considerations in wild animal suffering". EA Global 2018: San Francisco. Retrieved from: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=qK-VNh1AKy0 (transcript: https://forum.effectivealtruism.org/posts/DN8WceuyKDqN3m4Jd/persis-eskander-crucial-considerations-in-wild-animal)
  202. ^ O'Brien, Gary David (2021). "Directed Panspermia, Wild Animal Suffering, and the Ethics of World-Creation". Journal of Applied Philosophy. 39: 87–102. doi:10.1111/japp.12538. ISSN 1468-5930. S2CID 237774241.
  203. ^ Tomasik, Brian (2018-05-20) [2014]. "Will Space Colonization Multiply Wild-Animal Suffering?". Essays on Reducing Suffering. Retrieved 2021-10-08.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  204. ^ Sivula, Oskari (2022). "The Cosmic Significance of Directed Panspermia: Should Humanity Spread Life to Other Solar Systems?". Utilitas. 34 (2): 178–194. doi:10.1017/S095382082100042X. ISSN 0953-8208. S2CID 246519996.
  205. ^ Vinding, Magnus (2020). Suffering-Focused Ethics: Defense and Implications (PDF). Ratio Ethica. p. 249. ISBN 979-8624910911.
  206. ^ a b c Brennan, Ozy (2019-01-01). "Complexity of wild ruminants". Animal Sentience. 4 (25). doi:10.51291/2377-7478.1492. ISSN 2377-7478.
  207. ^ Norcross, Desli. "Wildlife Documentaries: What Happens to the Limping Gazelle?". Nature Ethics. Retrieved 2019-10-09.
  208. ^ Lopatto, Elizabeth (2016-08-15). "How natural are nature documentaries?". The Verge. Retrieved 2019-10-09.
  209. ^ Rustin, Susanna (2011-10-21). "David Attenborough: 'I'm an essential evil'". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2020-04-19. People who accuse us of putting in too much violence, [should see] what we leave on the cutting-room floor.
  210. ^ Muñoz, Toni (2019-02-08). "La representación del sufrimiento de los animales silvestres en los documentales de naturaleza" [The representation of the suffering of wild animals in nature documentaries]. ElDiario.es (in Spanish). Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  211. ^ a b Pearce, David (1996). "The Post-Darwinian Transition". The Animal Rights Library. Retrieved 2021-03-21.
  212. ^ Palmer, Clare (2019-12-06), Fischer, Bob (ed.), "The Laissez-Faire View", The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics (1 ed.), Routledge, pp. 444–454, doi:10.4324/9781315105840-40, ISBN 978-1-315-10584-0, S2CID 212772160, retrieved 2021-03-21
  213. ^ Gentle, Louise (2018-11-29). "Dynasties: should nature documentary crews save the animals they film?". The Conversation. Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  214. ^ Mabbott, Alastair (2019-12-15). "Review: My Penguin Year by Lindsay McCrae". The Herald. Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  215. ^ a b Furness, Hannah (2016-12-12). "Planet Earth II filmmakers defy convention to save lost baby turtles". The Telegraph. ISSN 0307-1235. from the original on 2017-01-25. Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  216. ^ Hamilton, William (1979). "Melville and the Sea". Soundings: An Interdisciplinary Journal. 62 (4): 417–429. ISSN 0038-1861. JSTOR 41178134.
  217. ^ Andersen, Hans Christian. "Thumbelina". The Hans Christian Andersen Centre. Retrieved 2021-03-25.
  218. ^ Ruiz, Javier Herrero (2007). "At the crossroads between literature, culture, linguistics, and cognition: death metaphors in fairy tales". Revista española de lingüística aplicada (20): 59–84. ISSN 0213-2028.
  219. ^ Andersen, Hans Christian. "The Ugly Duckling". The Hans Christian Andersen Centre. Retrieved 2021-02-24.
  220. ^ Lutts, Ralph H. (1992-10-01). "The Trouble with Bambi: Walt Disney's Bambi and the American Vision of Nature" (PDF). Forest & Conservation History. 36 (4): 160–171. doi:10.2307/3983677. ISSN 1046-7009. JSTOR 3983677. S2CID 191482526.
  221. ^ Lutts, Ralph H. (October 1992). . Forest and Conservation History. 36 (4): 160–171. doi:10.2307/3983677. JSTOR 3983677. S2CID 191482526. Archived from the original on 2015-11-03.
  222. ^ Wyndham, John (2000). The Midwich Cuckoos (1st electronic ed.). New York: Rosetta Books. p. 97. ISBN 978-0-7953-0292-3. OCLC 50737644.
  223. ^ a b Adams, Richard (2009). Watership Down. New York: Simon and Schuster. p. 465. ISBN 978-1-4391-7612-2.
  224. ^ Mannino, Adriano (2012-01-22). "Natur, Befreiung und Enhancement" [Nature, Liberation and Enhancement]. tier-im-fokus.ch (in German). Retrieved 2021-02-25.
  225. ^ Bostrom, Nick (1994). "Golden". Nick Bostrom. Retrieved 2021-03-20.
  226. ^ Pratchett, Terry (2009). Unseen Academicals. Random House. pp. 311–312. ISBN 978-1-4070-4729-4.
  227. ^ Lockett, Christopher (2021). "Death, Cruelty and Magical Humanism". In Brooks, Neil; Blanchette, Sarah (eds.). Narrative Art and the Politics of Health. Anthem Press. p. 199. ISBN 978-1-78527-711-5.
  228. ^ Hawtree, Laura Joy (September 2011). Wild Animals in Roman Epic (PDF) (PhD thesis). University of Exeter. pp. 72–73
  229. ^ Mackail, John William (1906). Select Epigrams from the Greek Anthology. London; New York: Longmans, Green. p. 209.
  230. ^ Nicholson, Reynold Alleyne (1921). Studies in Islamic Poetry. Cambridge: University Press. p. 202.
  231. ^ Swift, Jonathan (1766). The Works of Dr. Jonathan Swift. Vol. 7. Edinburgh: G. Hamilton & J. Balfour, and L. Hunter. p. 40.
  232. ^ Voltaire (1883). "Poème sur le désastre de lisbonne". In Moland, Louis (ed.). Œuvres complètes de Voltaire (in French). Garnier.
  233. ^ Voltaire (1912). "Poem on the Lisbon Disaster". In MacCabe, Joseph (ed.). Toleration and Other Essays. New York; London: G. P. Putnam's Sons. pp. 258–259.
  234. ^ Blackstone, Bernard (2015). English Blake. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 83. ISBN 978-1-107-50342-7. OCLC 914164179.
  235. ^ Blake, William (1915). Pierce, Frederick Erastus (ed.). Selections from the Symbolical Poems of William Blake. New Haven: Yale University Press. pp. 10–11.
  236. ^ a b c Darwin, Erasmus (1804). The Temple of Nature. Baltimore: Bonsal & Niles.
  237. ^ Simon, Ed (2019-05-29). "How Erasmus Darwin's poetry prophesied evolutionary theory". Aeon. Retrieved 2021-03-20.
  238. ^ Gompertz, Isaac (1813). The Modern Antique; Or, The Muse in the Costume of Queen Anne. London: W. Pople. p. 307.
  239. ^ Keats, John (1905). De Selincourt, Ernest (ed.). The Poems of John Keats. New York: Dodd, Mead & Co. p. 272.
  240. ^ Hillier, Russell M. (2014-11-01). "'A Wondrous Lesson in thy Silent Face': Keats, Darwin, and the Geological Sublime". Arcadia. 49 (2): 254–284. doi:10.1515/arcadia-2014-0023. ISSN 1613-0642.
  241. ^ Weiss, Kenneth M. (2010). ""Nature, red in tooth and claw", so what?" (PDF). Evolutionary Anthropology. 19 (2): 41–45. doi:10.1002/evan.20255. ISSN 1520-6505. S2CID 32999483.
  242. ^ Tennyson, Alfred (1893). Maud: A Monodrama. London: Kelmscott Press. p. 11.
  243. ^ Arnold, Edwin (1900) [1879]. The Light of Asia. Chicago: W. B. Conkey. pp. 25–26.
  244. ^ Stenerson, Douglas C. (Winter 1991). "Some impressions of the Buddha: Dreiser and Sir Edwin Arnold's the light of Asia". Canadian Review of American Studies. 22 (3): 387–405. doi:10.3138/CRAS-022-03-05. S2CID 159914010.

Further reading

  • Matthews, Dylan (2021-04-12). "The wild frontier of animal welfare". Vox. Retrieved 2021-05-15.
  • Introduction to Wild Animal Suffering: A Guide to the Key Issues (PDF). Animal Ethics. 2020.
  • "Helping animals in the wild bibliography". Animal Ethics. 2018-08-05. Retrieved 2021-02-18.
  • "The situation of animals in the wild bibliography". Animal Ethics. 2018-08-02. Retrieved 2021-02-18.
  • "Publications about wild animal suffering". Animal Ethics. 2018-04-30. Retrieved 2021-02-18.
  • Dorado, Daniel (2015-11-02). "Ethical Interventions in the Wild. An Annotated Bibliography". Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism. 3 (2): 219–238. doi:10.7358/rela-2015-002-dora. ISSN 2280-9643.
  • Stafforini, Pablo (2013-06-06). "Wild animal welfare: a bibliography". Pablo's miscellany. Retrieved 2021-02-18.

External links

  • Wild Animal Initiative
  • Wild Animal Suffering - Animal Ethics
  • Wild animal suffering video course - Animal Ethics
  • Timeline of wild-animal suffering
  • WildAnimalSuffering.org

wild, animal, suffering, suffering, experienced, nonhuman, animals, living, outside, direct, human, control, harms, such, disease, injury, parasitism, starvation, malnutrition, dehydration, weather, conditions, natural, disasters, killings, other, animals, wel. Wild animal suffering is the suffering experienced by nonhuman animals living outside of direct human control due to harms such as disease injury parasitism starvation and malnutrition dehydration weather conditions natural disasters and killings by other animals 1 2 as well as psychological stress 3 Some estimates indicate that these individual animals make up the vast majority of animals in existence 4 An extensive amount of natural suffering has been described as an unavoidable consequence of Darwinian evolution 5 and the pervasiveness of reproductive strategies which favor producing large numbers of offspring with a low amount of parental care and of which only a small number survive to adulthood the rest dying in painful ways has led some to argue that suffering dominates happiness in nature 1 6 7 Juvenile red tailed hawk eating a California vole The topic has historically been discussed in the context of the philosophy of religion as an instance of the problem of evil 8 More recently starting in the 19th century a number of writers have considered the subject from a secular standpoint as a general moral issue that humans might be able to take actions toward preventing 9 There is considerable disagreement around taking such actions as many believe that human interventions in nature for this reason should not take place because of practicality 10 valuing ecological preservation over the well being and interests of individual animals 11 considering any obligation to reduce wild animal suffering implied by animal rights to be absurd 12 or viewing nature as an idyllic place where happiness is widespread 6 Some have argued that such interventions would be an example of human hubris or playing God and use examples of how human interventions for other reasons have unintentionally caused harm 13 Others including animal rights writers have defended variants of a laissez faire position which argues that humans should not harm wild animals but that humans should not intervene to reduce natural harms that they experience 14 15 Advocates of such interventions argue that animal rights and welfare positions imply an obligation to help animals suffering in the wild due to natural processes Some have asserted that refusing to help animals in situations where humans would consider it wrong not to help humans is an example of speciesism 2 Others argue that humans intervene in nature constantly sometimes in very substantial ways for their own interests and to further environmentalist goals 16 Human responsibility for enhancing existing natural harms has also been cited as a reason for intervention 17 Some advocates argue that humans already successfully help animals in the wild such as vaccinating and healing injured and sick animals rescuing animals in fires and other natural disasters feeding hungry animals providing thirsty animals with water and caring for orphaned animals 18 They also assert that although wide scale interventions may not be possible with our current level of understanding they could become feasible in the future with improved knowledge and technologies 19 20 For these reasons they claim it is important to raise awareness about the issue of wild animal suffering spread the idea that humans should help animals suffering in these situations and encourage research into effective measures which can be taken in the future to reduce the suffering of these individuals without causing greater harms 6 16 Contents 1 Extent of suffering in nature 1 1 Sources of harm 1 1 1 Disease 1 1 2 Injury 1 1 3 Parasitism 1 1 4 Starvation and malnutrition 1 1 5 Dehydration 1 1 6 Weather conditions 1 1 7 Natural disasters 1 1 8 Killing by other animals 1 1 9 Psychological stress 1 2 Number of affected individuals 1 3 Natural selection 1 4 Reproductive strategies and population dynamics 2 History of concern for wild animals 2 1 Religious views 2 1 1 Problem of evil 2 1 2 Eastern perspectives 2 1 2 1 Buddhism 2 1 2 2 Hinduism 2 2 18th century 2 3 19th century 2 4 20th century 2 5 21st century 2 5 1 Publications 2 5 2 Organizations 3 Philosophical status 3 1 Predation as a moral problem 3 2 Arguments for intervention 3 2 1 Animal rights and welfare perspectives 3 2 2 Non intervention as a form of speciesism 3 2 3 Humans already intervene to further human interests 3 2 4 Human responsibility for enhancing natural harms 3 3 Arguments against intervention 3 3 1 Practicality of intervening in nature 3 3 2 Potential conflict between animal rights and environmentalism 3 3 3 Intrinsic value of ecological processes wilderness and wildness 3 3 4 Nature as idyllic 3 3 5 Intervention as hubris 3 3 6 Laissez faire 3 3 7 Wild animal sovereignty 3 3 8 Analogy with colonialism 4 Intervention in practice 4 1 Existing forms of assistance 4 2 History of interventions 5 Future developments 5 1 Proposed interventions 5 2 Welfare biology 5 3 Impact of climate change 5 4 Risks 5 4 1 Spreading wild animal suffering beyond Earth 6 Cultural depictions 6 1 Wildlife documentaries 6 1 1 Criticism of portrayals of wild animal suffering 6 1 2 Non intervention as a filmmaking rule 6 2 In fiction 6 3 In poetry 7 See also 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External linksExtent of suffering in nature EditSources of harm Edit Disease Edit Dead limosa harlequin frog showing symptoms of chytridiomycosis Animals in the wild may suffer from diseases which circulate similarly to human colds and flus as well as epizootics which are analogous to human epidemics epizootics are relatively understudied in the scientific literature 21 Some well studied examples include chronic wasting disease in elk and deer white nose syndrome in bats devil facial tumour disease in Tasmanian devils and Newcastle disease in birds 21 Examples of other diseases include myxomatosis and viral haemorrhagic disease in rabbits 22 ringworm and cutaneous fibroma in deer 23 and chytridiomycosis in amphibians 24 Diseases combined with parasitism may induce listlessness shivering ulcers pneumonia starvation violent behavior or other gruesome symptoms over the course of days or weeks leading up to death 1 Poor health may dispose wild animals to increased risk of infection which in turn reduces the health of the animal further increasing the risk of infection 25 The terminal investment hypothesis holds that infection can lead some animals to focus their limited remaining resources on increasing the number of offspring they produce 26 Injury Edit Wild animals can experience injury from a variety of causes such as predation intraspecific competition accidents which can cause fractures crushing injuries eye injuries and wing tears self amputation molting a common source of injury for arthropods extreme weather conditions such as storms extreme heat or cold weather and natural disasters Such injuries may be extremely painful which can lead to behaviors which further negatively affect the well being of the injured animal Injuries can also make animals susceptible to diseases and other injuries as well as parasitic infections Additionally the affected animal may find it harder to eat and drink and struggle to escape from predators and attacks from other members of their species 27 Parasitism Edit Tongue eating lice are parasites who destroy and replace the tongues of fish Many wild animals particularly larger ones have been found to be infected with at least one parasite Parasites can negatively affect the well being of their hosts by redirecting their host s resources to themselves destroying their host s tissue and increasing their host s susceptibility to predation 21 As a result parasites may reduce the movement reproduction and survival of their hosts 28 Parasites can alter the phenotype of their hosts limb malformations in amphibians caused by Ribeiroia ondatrae is one example 29 Some parasites have the capacity to manipulate the cognitive function of their hosts such as worms which make crickets kill themselves by directing them to drown themselves in water for the purpose of reproduction in an aquatic environment as well as caterpillars using dopamine containing secretions that manipulate ants to act as bodyguards for protecting the caterpillar from parasites 30 It is rare that parasites directly cause the death of their host rather they may increase the chances of their host s death by other means 21 one meta study found that mortality was 2 65 times higher in animals affected by parasites than those that weren t 31 Unlike parasites parasitoids which include species of worms wasps beetles and flies kill their hosts who are generally other invertebrates 32 Parasitoids specialize in attacking one particular species Different methods are used by parasitoids to infect their hosts laying their eggs on plants which are frequently visited by their host laying their eggs on or close to the host s eggs or young and stinging adult hosts so that they are paralyzed then laying their eggs near or on them 32 The larvae of parasitoids grow by feeding on the internal organs and bodily fluids of their hosts 33 which eventually leads to the death of their host when their organs have ceased to function or they have lost all of their bodily fluids 32 Superparasitism is a phenomenon where multiple different parasitoid species simultaneously infect the same host 34 Parasitoid wasps have been described as having the largest number of species of any other animal species 35 Starvation and malnutrition Edit Starvation and malnutrition particularly affect young old sick and weak animals and can be caused by injury disease poor teeth and environmental conditions with winter being particularly associated with an increased risk 36 It is argued that because food availability limits the size of wild animal populations that this means that a huge number of individuals die as a result of starvation such deaths are described as prolonged and marked by extreme distress as the animal s bodily functions shut down 37 67 Within days of hatching fish larvae may experience hydrodynamic starvation whereby the motion of fluids in their environment limits their ability to feed this can lead to mortality of greater than 99 38 Dehydration Edit Dehydration is associated with high mortality in wild animals Drought can cause many animals in larger populations to die of thirst Thirst can also expose animals to an increased risk of being preyed upon they may remain hidden in safe spaces to avoid this However their need for water may eventually force them to leave these spaces being in a weakened state this makes them easier targets for predatory animals Animals who remain hidden cannot move due to dehydration and may end up dying of thirst When dehydration is combined with starvation the process of dehydration can be accelerated 39 Diseases such as chytridiomycosis can also increase the risk of dehydration 40 Weather conditions Edit Mountain cottontail in the snow approximately 60 of these rabbits die during the winter 41 Weather has a strong influence on the health and survival of wild animals Weather phenomena such as heavy snow flooding and droughts can directly harm animals 42 and indirectly harm them by increasing the risks of other forms of suffering such as starvation and disease 42 Extreme weather can cause the deaths of animals by destroying their habitats and directly killing animals 43 hailstorms are known to kill thousands of birds 44 45 Certain weather conditions may maintain large numbers of individuals over many generations such conditions while conducive to survival may still cause suffering for animals Humidity or lack thereof can be beneficial or harmful depending on an individual animals needs 42 Deaths of large numbers of animals particularly cold blooded ones such as amphibians reptiles fishes and invertebrates can take place as a result of temperature fluctuations with young animals being particularly susceptible Temperature may not be a problem for parts of the year but can be a problem in especially hot summers or cold winters 42 Extreme heat and lack of rainfall are also associated with suffering and increased mortality by increasing susceptibility to disease and causing vegetation that insects and other animals rely upon to dry out this drying out can also make animals who rely on plants as hiding places more susceptible to predation Amphibians who rely on moisture to breathe and stay cool may die when water sources dry up 46 Hot temperatures can cause fish to die by making it hard for them to breathe 47 Climate change and associated warming and drying is making certain habitats intolerable for some animals through heat stress and reducing available water sources 48 Mass mortality is particularly linked with winter weather due to low temperatures lack of food and bodies of water where animals live such as frogs freezing over 49 a study on cottontail rabbits indicates that only 32 of them survive the winter 41 Fluctuating environmental conditions in the winter months is also associated with increased mortality 50 Natural disasters Edit Fires volcanic eruptions earthquakes tsunamis hurricanes storms floods and other natural disasters are sources of extensive short and long term harm for wild animals causing death injury illness and malnutrition as well as poisoning by contaminating food and water sources 51 Such disasters can also alter the physical environment of individual animals in ways which are harmful to them 52 fires and large volcanic eruptions can affect the weather and marine animals may die due to disasters affecting water temperature and salinity 51 Killing by other animals Edit Cannibalism in sand lizards Predation has been described as the act of one animal capturing and killing another animal to consume part or all of their body 53 Jeff McMahan a moral philosopher asserts that Wherever there is animal life predators are stalking chasing capturing killing and devouring their prey Agonized suffering and violent death are ubiquitous and continuous 54 Preyed upon animals die in a variety of different ways with the time taking for them to die which can be lengthy depending on the method that the predatory animal uses to kill them some animals are swallowed and digested while still being alive 55 Other preyed upon animals are paralysed with venom before being eaten venom can also be used to start digesting the animal 56 Animals may be killed by members of their own species due to territorial disputes competition for mates and social status as well as cannibalism infanticide and siblicide 57 Psychological stress Edit It has been argued that animals in the wild do not appear to be happier than domestic animals based on findings that these individuals have greater levels of cortisol and elevated stress responses relative to domestic animals additionally unlike domestic animals wild animals do not have their needs provided for them by human caretakers 3 Sources of stress for these individuals include illness and infection predation avoidance nutritional stress and social interactions these stressors can begin before birth and continue as the individual develops 58 A framework known as the ecology of fear conceptualises the psychological impact that the fear of predatory animals can have on the individuals that they predate such as altering their behavior and reducing their survival chances 59 60 Fear inducing interactions with predators may cause lasting effects on behavior and PTSD like changes in the brains of animals in the wild 61 These interactions can also cause a spike in stress hormones such as cortisol which can increase the risk of both the individual s death and their offspring 62 Number of affected individuals Edit Marine arthropods such as this Northern krill are the largest estimated group of individual wild animals The number of individual animals in the wild is relatively unexplored in the scientific literature and estimates vary considerably 63 An analysis undertaken in 2018 estimates not including wild mammals that there are 1015 fish 1011 wild birds 1018 terrestrial arthropods and 1020 marine arthropods 1018 annelids 1018 molluscs and 1016 cnidarians for a total of 1021 wild animals 64 It has been estimated that there are 2 25 times more wild mammals than wild birds in Britain but the authors of this estimate assert that this calculation would likely be a severe underestimate when applied to the number of individual wild mammals in other continents 65 A 2022 study estimated that there are 20 quadrillion individual ants across the world 66 Based on some of these estimates it has been argued that the number of individual wild animals in existence is considerably higher by an order of magnitude than the number of animals humans kill for food each year 4 with individuals in the wild making up over 99 of all sentient beings in existence 67 Natural selection Edit In his autobiography the naturalist and biologist Charles Darwin acknowledged that the existence of extensive suffering in nature was fully compatible with the workings of natural selection yet maintained that pleasure was the main driver of fitness increasing behavior in organisms 68 Evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins challenged Darwin s claim in his book River Out of Eden wherein he argued that wild animal suffering must be extensive due to the interplay of the following evolutionary mechanisms 5 Selfish genes genes are wholly indifferent to the well being of individual organisms as long as DNA is passed on The struggle for existence competition over limited resources results in the majority of organisms dying before passing on their genes Malthusian checks even bountiful periods within a given ecosystem eventually lead to overpopulation and subsequent population crashes From this Dawkins concludes that the natural world must necessarily contain enormous amounts of animal suffering as an inevitable consequence of Darwinian evolution 5 To illustrate this he writes 69 The total amount of suffering per year in the natural world is beyond all decent contemplation During the minute that it takes me to compose this sentence thousands of animals are being eaten alive many others are running for their lives whimpering with fear others are slowly being devoured from within by rasping parasites thousands of all kinds are dying of starvation thirst and disease It must be so If there ever is a time of plenty this very fact will automatically lead to an increase in the population until the natural state of starvation and misery is restored Reproductive strategies and population dynamics Edit A litter of rats with their mother The reproduction of rats follows an r selection strategy with many offspring short gestation less parental care and a short time until sexual maturity Some writers have argued that the prevalence of r selected animals in the wild who produce large numbers of offspring with a low amount of parental care and of which only a small number in a stable population will survive to adulthood indicates that the average life of these individuals is likely to be very short and end in a painful death 6 7 The pathologist Keith Simpson described this as follows 70 In the wild plagues of excess population are a rarity The seas are not crowded with sunfish the ponds are not brimming with toads elephants do not stand shoulder to shoulder over the land With few exceptions animal populations are remarkably stable On average of each pair s offspring only sufficient survive to replace the parents when they die Surplus young die and birth rates are balanced by death rates In the case of spawners and egg layers some young are killed before hatching Almost half of all blackbird eggs are taken by jays but even so each pair usually manages to fledge about four young By the end of summer however an average of under two are still alive Since one parent will probably die or be killed during the winter only one of the young will survive to breed the following summer The high mortality rate among young animals is an inevitable consequence of high fecundity Of the millions of fry produced by a pair of sunfish only one or two escape starvation disease or predators Half the young of house mice living on the Welsh island of Skokholm are lost before weaning Even in large mammals the lives of the young can be pathetically brief and the killing wholesale During the calving season many young wildebeeste still wet feeble and bewildered are seized and torn apart by jackals hyenas and lions within minutes of emerging from their mothers bellies Three out of every four die violently within six months According to this view the lives of the majority of animals in the wild likely contain more suffering than happiness since a painful death would outweigh any short lived moments of happiness experienced in their short lives 6 71 72 Welfare economist Yew Kwang Ng has argued that evolutionary dynamics can lead to welfare outcomes that are worse than necessary for a given population equilibrium 71 A 2019 follow up challenged the conclusions of Ng s original paper 73 History of concern for wild animals EditSee also Struggle for existence Historical development Religious views Edit Problem of evil Edit See also Problem of evil Problem of evil and animal suffering and Evolutionary theodicy Charles Darwin referred to the Ichneumonidae feeding inside the living bodies of caterpillars as an example of the problem of evil The idea that suffering is common in nature has been observed by several writers historically who engaged with the problem of evil In his notebooks written between 1487 and 1505 Italian polymath Leonardo da Vinci described the suffering experienced by animals in the wild due to predation and reproduction questioning Why did nature not ordain that one animal should not live by the death of another 74 In his 1779 posthumous work Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion the philosopher David Hume described the antagonism inflicted by animals upon each other and the psychological impact experienced by the victims observing The stronger prey upon the weaker and keep them in perpetual terror and anxiety 75 In Natural Theology published in 1802 Christian philosopher William Paley argued that animals in the wild die as a result of violence decay disease starvation and malnutrition and that they exist in a state of suffering and misery their suffering unaided by their fellow animals He compared this to humans who even when they can t relieve the suffering of their fellow humans at least provide them with necessities Paley also engaged with the reader of his book asking whether based on these observations you would alter the present system of pursuit and prey 76 261 262 Additionally he argued that the subject of animals devouring one another forms the chief if not the only instance in the works of the Deity in which the character of utility can be called in question 76 265 However he defended predation as being a part of God s design by asserting that it was a solution to the problem of superfecundity 77 animals producing more offspring than can possibly survive 76 264 Paley also contended that venom is a merciful way for poisonous animals to kill the animals that they predate 77 The problem of evil has also been extended to include the suffering of animals in the context of evolution 78 79 In Phytologia or the Philosophy of Agriculture and Gardening published in 1800 Erasmus Darwin a physician and the grandfather of Charles Darwin aimed to vindicate the goodness of God allowing the consumption of lower animals by higher ones by asserting that more pleasurable sensation exists in the world as the organic matter is taken from a state of less irritability and less sensibility and converted into a greater he claimed that this process secures the greatest happiness for sentient beings Writing in response in 1894 Edward Payson Evans a linguist and early advocate for animal rights argued that evolution which regards the antagonism between animals purely as events within the context of a universal struggle for existence has disregarded this kind of theodicy and ended teleological attempts to infer from the nature and operations of creation the moral character of the Creator 80 In an 1856 letter to Joseph Dalton Hooker Charles Darwin remarked sarcastically on the cruelty and wastefulness of nature describing it as something that a Devil s chaplain could write about 81 Writing in 1860 to Asa Gray Darwin asserted that he could not reconcile an omnibenevolent and omnipotent God with the intentional existence of the Ichneumonidae a parasitoid wasp family the larvae of which feed internally on the living bodies of caterpillars 82 In his autobiography published in 1887 Darwin described a feeling of revolt at the idea that God s benevolence is limited stating for what advantage can there be in the sufferings of millions of the lower animals throughout almost endless time 83 Eastern perspectives Edit Philosopher Ole Martin Moen argues that unlike Western Judeo Christian views Jainism Buddhism and Hinduism all hold that the natural world is filled with suffering that suffering is bad for all who endure it and that our ultimate aim should be to bring suffering to an end 84 Buddhism Edit In Buddhist doctrine rebirth as an animal is regarded as evil because of the different forms of suffering that animals experience due to humans and natural processes 85 Buddhists may also regard the suffering experienced by animals in nature as evidence for the truth of dukkha 86 87 The Buddhist scripture Aṅguttara Nikaya describes the lives of wild animals as so cruel so harsh so painful 87 The Indian Buddhist sutra Saddharmasmṛtyupasthanasutra written in the first half of the first millennium categorises the different forms of suffering experienced by the animals living in the water on the earth and in the sky and draws attention to certain animals who can be liberated from their suffering through consciousness There are those animals who though fearful of predation of threats beatings cold heat and bad weather if capable disregard their trembling and just for a moment arouse a mind of faith towards the Buddha the Dharma and the Saṅgha 88 Around 700 AD the Indian Buddhist monk and scholar Shantideva wrote in his Bodhisattvacaryavatara And may the stooping animals be freed From fear of being preyed upon each other s food 89 Patrul Rinpoche a 19th century Tibetan Buddhist teacher described animals in the ocean as experiencing immense suffering as a result of predation as well as parasites burrowing inside them and eating them alive He also described animals on land as existing in a state of continuous fear and of killing and being killed 90 Hinduism Edit Hindu literature has been described as holding the lives and welfare of wild animals as equal with that of humans 91 18th century Edit In Histoire Naturelle published in 1753 the naturalist Buffon described wild animals as suffering much want in the winter focusing specifically on the plight of stags who are exhausted by the rutting season which in turn leads to the breeding of parasites under their skin further adding to their misery 92 53 Later in the book he described predation as necessary to prevent the superabundance of animals who produce vast numbers of offspring who if not killed would have their fecundity diminished due to a lack of food and would die as a result of disease and starvation Buffon concluded that violent deaths seem to be equally as necessary as natural ones they are both modes of destruction and renovation the one serves to preserve nature in a perpetual spring and the other maintains the order of her productions and limits the number of each species 92 116 117 Herder a philosopher and theologian in Ideen zur Philosphie der Geschichte der Menschheit published between 1784 and 1791 argued that animals exist in a state of constant striving needing to provide for their own subsistence and to defend their lives He contended that nature ensured peace in creation by creating an equilibrium of animals with different instincts and belonging to different species who live opposed to each other 93 19th century Edit Lewis Gompertz argued that both humans and animals in their natural state suffer similarly and that both should be assisted In 1824 Lewis Gompertz an early vegan and animal rights activist published Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes in which he advocated for an egalitarian view towards animals and aiding animals suffering in the wild 4 Gompertz asserted that humans and animals in their natural state both suffer similarly 94 47 B oth of them being miserably subject to almost every evil destitute of the means of palliating them living in the continual apprehension of immediate starvation of destruction by their enemies which swarm around them of receiving dreadful injuries from the revengeful and malicious feelings of their associates uncontrolled by laws or by education and acting as their strength alone dictates without proper shelter from the inclemencies of the weather without proper attention and medical or surgical aid in sickness destitute frequently of fire of candle light and in man also of clothing without amusements or occupations excepting a few the chief of which are immediately necessary for their existence and subject to all the ill consequences arising from the want of them Gompertz also argued that as much as animals suffer in the wild that they suffer much more at the hands of humans because in their natural state they have the capacity to also experience periods of much enjoyment 94 52 Additionally he contended that if he was to encounter a situation where an animal was eating another that he would intervene to help the animal being attacked even if this might probably be wrong 94 93 94 In his 1852 book Fragments in Defence of Animals and Essays on Morals Soul and Future State Gompertz compared the suffering of animals in the wild to the suffering inflicted by humans stating Much as animals suffer in a natural state much more do they seem to suffer when under the dominion of the generality of men What suffering in the former can be supposed to equal the constant torture of a hackney coach horse 95 Philosopher and poet Giacomo Leopardi in his 1824 Dialogue between Nature and an Icelander from Operette morali used images of animal predation which he rejected as having value to represent nature s cycles of creation and destruction 96 Writing in his notebooks Zibaldone di pensieri published posthumously in 1898 Leopardi asserted that predation is a leading example of the evil design of nature 97 In 1851 the philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer commented on the vast amount of suffering in nature drawing attention to the asymmetry between the pleasure experienced by a carnivorous animal and the suffering of the animal that they are consuming stating Whoever wants summarily to test the assertion that the pleasure in the world outweighs the pain or at any rate that the two balance each other should compare the feelings of an animal that is devouring another with those of that other 98 In the 1874 posthumous essay Nature utilitarian philosopher John Stuart Mill wrote about suffering in nature and the imperative of struggling against it 99 In sober truth nearly all the things which men are hanged or imprisoned for doing to one another are nature s every day performances The phrases which ascribe perfection to the course of nature can only be considered as the exaggerations of poetic or devotional feeling not intended to stand the test of a sober examination No one either religious or irreligious believes that the hurtful agencies of nature considered as a whole promote good purposes in any other way than by inciting human rational creatures to rise up and struggle against them Whatsoever in nature gives indication of beneficent design proves this beneficence to be armed only with limited power and the duty of man is to cooperate with the beneficent powers not by imitating but by perpetually striving to amend the course of nature and bringing that part of it over which we can exercise control more nearly into conformity with a high standard of justice and goodness In his 1892 book Animals Rights Considered in Relation to Social Progress the writer and early activist for animal rights Henry Stephens Salt focused an entire chapter on the plight of wild animals The Case of Wild Animals Salt wrote that the rights of animals should not be dependent on the rights of being property and that sympathy and protection should be extended to non owned animals too 100 He also argued that humans are justified in killing wild animals in self defense but that neither unnecessary killing nor torturing harmless beings is justified 100 20th century Edit J Howard Moore speculated whether a sufficiently sympathetic human if only given the chance could significantly improve the situation of animals suffering in the wild In the 1906 book The Universal Kinship the zoologist and utilitarian philosopher J Howard Moore argued that the egoism of sentient beings a product of natural selection which leads them to exploit their sentient fellows was the most mournful and immense fact in the phenomena of conscious life and speculated whether an ordinary human who was sufficiently sympathetic to the welfare of the world could significantly improve this situation if only given the opportunity 101 In Ethics and Education published in 1912 Moore critiqued the human conception of animals in the wild Many of these non human beings are so remote from human beings in language appearance interests and ways of life as to be nothing but wild animals These wild things have of course no rights whatever in the eyes of men 102 71 Later in the book he described them as independent beings who suffer and enjoy in the same way humans do and have their own ends and justifications of life 102 157 In his 1952 article Which Shall We Protect Thoughts on the Ethics of the Treatment of Free Life Alexander Skutch a naturalist and writer explored five ethical principles that humans could follow when considering their relationship with animals in the wild including the principle of only considering human interests the laissez faire or hands off principle the do no harm ahimsa principle the principle of favoring the higher animals which are most similar to ourselves the principle of harmonious association whereby humans and animals in the wild could live symbiotically with each providing benefits to the other and individuals who disrupt this harmony such as predators are removed Skutch endorsed a combination of the laissez faire ahimsa and harmonious association approaches as the way to create the ultimate harmony between humans and animals in the wild 103 Moral philosopher Peter Singer in 1973 responded to a question on whether humans have a moral obligation to prevent predation arguing that intervening in this way may cause more suffering in the long term but asserting that he would support actions if the long term outcome was positive 104 In 1979 the animal rights philosopher Stephen R L Clark published The Rights of Wild Things in which he argued that humans should protect animals in the wild from particularly large dangers but that humans do not have an obligation to regulate all of their relationships 105 The following year J Baird Callicott an environmental ethicist published Animal Liberation A Triangular Affair in which he compared the ethical underpinnings of the animal liberation movement asserting that it is based on Benthamite principles and Aldo Leopold s land ethic which he used as a model for environmental ethics Callicott concluded that intractable differences exist between the two ethical positions when it comes to the issue of wild animal suffering 106 In his 1987 book Morals Reason and Animals animal rights philosopher Steve F Sapontzis argued that from an antispeciesist perspective humans should aid animals suffering in the wild as long as a greater harm is not inflicted overall 107 In 1991 the environmental philosopher Arne Naess critiqued what he termed the cult of nature of contemporary and historical attitudes of indifference towards suffering in nature He argued that humans should confront the reality of the wilderness including disturbing natural processes when feasible to relieve suffering 108 In his 1993 article Pourquoi je ne suis pas ecologiste Why I am not an environmentalist published in the antispeciesist journal Cahiers antispecistes the animal rights philosopher David Olivier argued that he is opposed to environmentalists because they consider predation to be good because of the preservation of species and natural balance while Olivier gives consideration to the suffering of the individual animal being predated He also asserted that if the environmentalists were themselves at risk of being predated they wouldn t follow the order of nature Olivier concluded I don t want to turn the universe into a planned man made world Synthetic food for foxes contraception for hares I only half like that I have a problem that I do not know how to solve and I am unlikely to find a solution even theoretical as long as I am almost alone looking for one 109 21st century Edit Publications Edit Brian Tomasik argues that animal advocates should promote concern for wild animal suffering and highlights the risk of human descendants astronomically multiplying such suffering In 2009 essayist Brian Tomasik published the essay The Importance of Wild Animal Suffering In the essay Tomasik makes the case that the number of individual wild animals in existence is significantly larger than the number of non human animals used by humans and that as a result animal advocates should focus on promoting concern for the suffering experienced by animals in their natural environments He also makes the point that as much as there is a vast amount of suffering existing in the present that human descendants could increase the amount of wild animal suffering in existence astronomically if these descendants chose to multiply wild animal suffering rather than preventing it 110 In 2015 a version of the essay was published in the journal Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 1 in the special two volume issue Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature which collected contributions from a number of authors on the topic of wild animal suffering 111 112 Jeff McMahan s 2010 essay The Meat Eaters was published by The New York Times in which he argued in favor of taking steps to reduce animal suffering in the wild particularly by reducing predation 113 In the same year McMahan published Predators A Response a reply to the criticism he received for his original article 114 Vox has published multiple articles on the topic of wild animal suffering In 2015 it published sociologist Jacy Reese Anthis s article Wild animals endure illness injury and starvation We should help 115 in his 2018 book The End of Animal Farming Anthis discusses expanding the circle of human moral concern to include invertebrates and animals suffering in the wild 116 In 2021 Vox published the journalist Dylan Matthews s article The wild frontier of animal welfare which analyzed the views of various philosophers and scientists on the topic 117 The digital magazine Aeon has published essays by philosophers which discuss wild animal suffering We have an ethical obligation to relieve individual animal suffering 2018 118 and All we owe to animals 2020 17 Philosopher Catia Faria in 2016 successfully defended her Ph D thesis Animal Ethics Goes Wild The Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature the first thesis of its kind to argue that humans have an obligation to help animals in the wild 119 In 2022 she is expected to publish a book on the topic Animal Ethics in the Wild Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature 120 In 2020 philosopher Kyle Johannsen published Wild Animal Ethics The Moral and Political Problem of Wild Animal Suffering The book argues that wild animal suffering is a pressing moral issue and that humans have a collective moral duty to intervene in nature to reduce suffering 121 In the same year a symposium was held at Queen s University on Johannsen s book 122 Animal rights activist and philosopher Oscar Horta published Making a Stand for Animals in 2022 which includes a chapter titled In defense of animals which argues that giving moral consideration to animals implies aiding them when they suffer due to natural processes 123 Organizations Edit In response to arguments for the moral and political importance of wild animal suffering a number of organizations have been created to research and address the issue Two of these Utility Farm and Wild Animal Suffering Research merged in 2019 to form Wild Animal Initiative 124 The nonprofit organization Animal Ethics also researches wild animal suffering and advocates on behalf of wild animals among other populations 125 Rethink Priorities is a research organization which among other topics has conducted research on wild animal suffering particularly around invertebrate sentience and invertebrate welfare 126 127 The Wildlife Disaster Network was founded in 2020 with the intention of helping wild animals suffering in natural disasters Jamie Payton who works for the network challenges the view that wild animals in disasters situations manage best when left alone stating Without human interference these animals will suffer and succumb due not only to their injuries but also to the loss of food water and habitat It is our obligation to provide the missing link for the wildlife that share our home 128 Philosophical status EditPredation as a moral problem Edit Main article Predation problem Predation has been considered a moral problem by some philosophers who argue that humans have an obligation to prevent it 12 129 while others argue that intervention is not ethically required 130 131 Others have argued that humans shouldn t do anything about it right now because there s a chance we ll unwittingly cause serious harm but that with better information and technology it may be possible to take meaningful action in the future 132 An obligation to prevent predation has been considered untenable or absurd by some writers who have used the position as a reductio ad absurdum to reject the concept of animal rights altogether 133 134 Others have argued that attempting to reduce it would be environmentally harmful 135 Arguments for intervention Edit Animal rights and welfare perspectives Edit Oscar Horta argues that animals in the wild experience vast amounts of suffering due to natural processes and that taking a nonspeciesist perspective there is a moral obligation to reduce the suffering of these individuals Some theorists have reflected on whether the harms animals suffer in the wild should be accepted or if something should be done to mitigate them 6 The moral basis for interventions aimed at reducing wild animal suffering can be rights or welfare based Advocates of such interventions argue that non intervention is inconsistent with either of these approaches From a rights based perspective if animals have a moral right to life or bodily integrity intervention may be required to prevent such rights from being violated by other animals 136 Animal rights philosopher Tom Regan was critical of this view he argued that because animals aren t moral agents in the sense of being morally responsible for their actions they can t violate each other s rights Based on this he concluded that humans don t need to concern themselves with preventing suffering of this kind unless such interactions were strongly influenced by humans 137 14 15 Oscar Horta argues that it is a mistaken perception that the animal rights position implies a respect for natural processes because of the assumption that animals in the wild live easy and happy lives when in reality they live short and painful lives full of suffering 6 It has also been argued that a non speciesist legal system would mean animals in the wild would be entitled to positive rights similar to what humans are entitled to by their species membership which would give them the legal right to food shelter healthcare and protection 138 From a welfare based perspective a requirement to intervene may arise insofar as it is possible to prevent some of the suffering experienced by wild animals without causing even more suffering 139 Katie McShane argues that biodiversity is not a good proxy for wild animal welfare A region with high biodiversity is full of lots of different kinds of individuals They might be suffering their lives might be barely worth living But if they are alive they count positively toward biodiversity 140 Non intervention as a form of speciesism Edit Some writers have argued that humans refusing to aid animals suffering in the wild when they would help humans suffering in a similar situation is an example of speciesism 2 the differential treatment or moral consideration of individuals based on their species membership 141 Jamie Mayerfeld contends that a duty to relive suffering which is blind to species membership implies an obligation to relieve the suffering of animals due to natural processes 142 Stijn Bruers argues that even long term animal rights activists sometimes hold speciesist views when it comes to this specific topic which he calls a moral blind spot 143 His view is echoed by Eze Paez who asserts that advocates who disregard the interests of animals purely because they live in the wild are responsible for the same form of discrimination used by those who justify the exploitation of animals by humans 144 Oscar Horta argues that spreading awareness of speciesism will in turn increase concern for the plight of animals in the wild 145 Humans already intervene to further human interests Edit Oscar Horta asserts that humans are constantly intervening in nature in significant ways to further human interests such as furthering environmentalist ideals He criticizes how interventions are considered to be realistic safe or acceptable when their aims favor humans but not when they focus on helping wild animals He argues that humans should shift the aim of these interventions to consider the interests of sentient beings not just humans 16 Human responsibility for enhancing natural harms Edit Philosopher Martha Nussbaum asserts that humans continually affect the habitats of animals determining opportunities for nutrition free movement and other aspects of flourishing and contends that the pervasive human involvement in natural processes means that humans have a moral responsibility to help individuals affected by our actions She also argues that humans may have the capacity to help animals suffering due to entirely natural processes such as diseases and natural disasters and asserts that way may have duties to provide care in these cases 146 374 Jeff Sebo a philosopher argues that animals in the wild suffer as a result of natural processes as well as human caused harms He asserts that climate change is making existing harms more severe and creating new harms for these individuals From this he concludes that there are two reasons to help individual animals in the wild they are suffering and dying and we are either partly or wholly responsible 17 Similarly philosopher Steven Nadler argues that climate change means that the scope of actions that are proscribed and especially prescribed by a consideration of animal suffering should be broadened 118 However Nadler goes further asserting that humans have a moral obligation to help individual animals suffering in the wild regardless of human responsibility 118 Arguments against intervention Edit Practicality of intervening in nature Edit Peter Singer argues that in theory intervention would be justified if one could be reasonably assured that this would greatly reduce wild animal suffering in the long term he cautions against such interventions in practice A common objection to intervening in nature is that it would be impractical either because of the amount of work involved or because the complexity of ecosystems would make it difficult to know whether or not an intervention would be net beneficial on balance 114 Aaron Simmons argues that humans should not intervene to save animals in nature because doing so would result in unintended consequences such as damaging ecosystems interfering with human projects or resulting in more animal deaths overall 12 Nicolas Delon and Duncan Purves argue that the nature of ecosystems leaves us with no reason to predict that interventions would reduce rather than exacerbate suffering 10 Peter Singer has argued that intervention in nature would be justified if one could be reasonably confident that this would greatly reduce wild animal suffering and death in the long run In practice however Singer cautions against interfering with ecosystems because he fears that doing so would cause more harm than good 104 147 Other authors dispute Singer s empirical claim about the likely consequences of intervening in the natural world and argue that some types of intervention can be expected to produce good consequences overall Economist Tyler Cowen cites examples of animal species whose extinction is not generally regarded as having been on balance bad for the world Cowen also notes that insofar as humans are already intervening in nature the relevant practical question is not whether there should be intervention but what particular forms of intervention should be favored 139 Oscar Horta similarly writes that there are already many cases in which humans intervene in nature for other reasons such as for human interest in nature and environmental preservation as something valuable in their own rights 6 Horta has also proposed that courses of action aiming at helping wild animals should be carried out and adequately monitored first in urban suburban industrial or agricultural areas 148 Likewise Jeff McMahan argues that since humans are already causing massive precipitate changes in the natural world humans should favor those changes that would promote the survival of herbivorous rather than carnivorous species 114 Peter Vallentyne a philosopher suggests that while humans should not eliminate predators in nature they can intervene to help prey in more limited ways In the same way that humans help humans in need when the cost to us is small humans might help some wild animals at least in limited circumstances 149 Potential conflict between animal rights and environmentalism Edit See also Relationship between animal ethics and environmental ethics It has been argued that the environmentalist goal of preserving certain abstract entities such as species and ecosystems and a policy of non interference in regard to natural processes is incompatible with animal rights views which place the welfare and interests of individual animals at the center of concern 150 151 152 Examples include environmentalists supporting hunting for species population control while animal rights advocates oppose it 72 animal rights advocates arguing for the extinction or reengineering of carnivores or r strategist species while deep ecologists defend their right to be and flourish as they are 132 153 animal rights advocates defending the reduction of wildlife habitats or arguing against their expansion out of concern that most animal suffering takes place within them while environmentalists want to safeguard and expand them 154 155 Oscar Horta argues that there are instances where environmentalists and animal rights advocates may both support approaches that would consequently reduce wild animal suffering 155 Intrinsic value of ecological processes wilderness and wildness Edit Some writers such as the environmental ethicist Holmes Rolston III argue that natural animal suffering is valuable because it serves an ecological purpose and that only animal suffering due to non natural processes is morally bad and as a result humans do not have a duty to intervene in cases of suffering caused by natural processes 156 page needed Rolston celebrates carnivores in nature because of the significant ecological role they play 153 Others argue that the reason that humans have a duty to protect other humans from predation but not wild animals is that humans are part of the cultural world rather than the natural world and so different rules apply to them in these situations 153 157 Some writers assert that animals who are preyed upon are fulfilling their natural function and thus flourishing when they are preyed upon or otherwise die since this allows natural selection to work 136 Yves Bonnardel an animal rights philosopher has criticized this view as well as the concept of nature which he describes as an ideological tool that places humans in a superior position above other animals who exist only to perform certain ecosystem functions such as a rabbit being food for a wolf Bonnardel compares this with the religious idea that a slaves exist for their masters or that woman exists for the sake of man He argues that animals as individuals all have an interest in living 158 Wilderness advocates argue that wilderness is intrinsically valuable the biologist E O Wilson wrote that wilderness has virtue unto itself and needs no extraneous justification 159 Joshua Duclos describes the moral argument against preserving wilderness because of the suffering experienced by wild animals who live in them as the objection from welfare 160 Jack Walker argues that the intrinsic value of wildness cannot be used to oppose large scale interventions to reduce wild animal suffering 161 Joshua Duclos that wilderness is given intrinsic value of from a narrow anthropocentric perspective with a religio spiritual dimension 162 Nature as idyllic Edit The idyllic view of nature is described as the widely held view that happiness in nature is widespread 6 7 Oscar Horta argues that even though many people are aware of the harms that animals in the wild experience such as predation starvation and disease as well as recognizing that these animals may suffer as a result of these harms they don t conclude from this that wild animals have bad enough lives to imply that nature is not a happy place Horta also contends that a romantic conception of nature has significant implications for attitudes people have towards animals in the wild as holders of the view may oppose interventions to reduce suffering 6 Bob Fischer argues that many wild animals may have net negative lives experiencing more pain than pleasure even in the absence of human activity However Fischer argues that if many animals have net negative lives then what is good for the animal as an individual may not be good for its species other species the climate or the preservation of biodiversity for example some animals may have to have their populations massively reduced and controlled and some species such as parasites or predators eliminated entirely 163 Intervention as hubris Edit Some writers have argued that interventions to reduce wild animal suffering would be an example of arrogance hubris or playing God as such interventions could potentially have disastrous unforeseen consequences They are also sceptical of the competence of humans when it comes to making correct moral judgements as well as human fallibility Additionally they contend that the moral stance of humans and moral agency can lead to the imposition of anthropocentric or paternalistic values on others To support these claims they use the history of human negative impacts on nature including species extinctions wilderness and resource depletion as well as climate change From this they conclude that the best way that humans can help animals in the wild is through the preservation of larger wilderness areas and by reducing the human sphere of influence on nature 13 Critics of this position such as Beril Sozmen argue that human negative impacts are not inevitable and that until recently interventions were not undertaken with the goal of improving the well being of individual animals in the wild Furthermore she contends that such examples of anthropogenic harms are not the consequence of misguided human intervention gone awry but are actually the result of human agriculture and industry which do not consider or do not care about their impact on nature and animals in the wild Sozmen also asserts that the holders of this position may view that nature as exists in a delicate state of balance and have an overly romantic view of the lives of animals in the wild and that she contends actually contain vast amounts of suffering 13 Martha Nussbaum argues that because humans are constantly intervening in nature the central question should be what form should these interventions take rather than whether interventions should take place arguing that intelligently respectful paternalism is vastly superior to neglect 146 377 Laissez faire Edit See also Clare Palmer Animal ethics A laissez faire view which holds that humans should not harm animals in the wild but do not have an obligation to aid these individuals when in need has been defended by Tom Regan Elisa Aaltola Clare Palmer and Ned Hettinger Regan argued that the suffering animals inflict on each other should not be a concern of ethically motivated wildlife management and that these wildlife managers should instead focus on letting animals in the wild exist as they are with no human predation and to carve out their own destiny 14 Aaltola similarly argues that predators should be left to flourish despite the suffering that they cause to the animals that they predate 15 Palmer endorses a variant of this position which claims that humans may have an obligation to assist wild animals if humans are responsible for their situation 164 Hettinger argues for laissez faire based on the environmental value of Respect for an Independent Nature 165 Catia Faria argues that following the principle that humans should only help individuals when they are being harmed by humans rather than by natural processes would also mean refusing to help humans and companion animals when they suffer due to natural processes however this implication does not seem acceptable to most people and she asserts that there are strong reasons to help these individuals when humans have capacity to do so Faria argues that there is an obligation to help animals in the wild suffering in similar situations and as a result the laissez faire view does not hold up 166 Similarly Steven Nadler argues that it is morally wrong to refuse help to animals in the wild regardless of whether humans are indirectly or directly responsible for their suffering as the same arguments used to decline aid to humans who were suffering due to natural harms such as famine a tsunami or pneumonia would be considered immoral He concludes that if the only thing that is morally relevant is an individual s capacity to suffer there is no relevant moral difference between humans and other animals suffering in these situations 118 In the same vein Steve F Sapontizis asserts that When our interests or the interests of those we care for will be hurt we do not recognize a moral obligation to let nature take its course 167 Wild animal sovereignty Edit Some writers such as the animal rights philosophers Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka in Zoopolis argue that humans should not perform large interventions to help animals in the wild They assert that these interventions would be taking away their sovereignty by removing the ability for these animals to govern themselves 168 Christiane Bailey asserts that certain wild animals especially prosocial animals have sufficient criteria to be considered as moral agents that is to say individuals capable of making moral judgments and who have responsibilities She argues that aiding them would be reducing wild animals to beings incapable of making decisions for themselves 169 Oscar Horta emphasizes the fact that although some individuals may form sovereign groups the vast majority of wild animals are either solitary or re selectors whose population size varies greatly from year to year He contends that most of their interactions would be amensalism commensalism antagonism or competition Therefore the majority of animals in the wild would not form sovereign communities if humans use the criteria established by Donaldson and Kymlicka 170 Analogy with colonialism Edit Estiva Reus asserts that a comparison exists from a certain perspective between the spirit which animated the defenders of colonialism who saw it as necessary human progress for backward peoples and the idea which inspires writers who argue for reforming nature in the interest of wild animals the proponents of the two positions consider that they have the right and the duty because of their superior skills to model the existence of beings unable to remedy by their own means the evils which overwhelm them 171 Thomas Lepeltier a historian and writer on animal ethics argues that if colonization is to be criticized it is because beyond the rhetoric it was an enterprise of spoliation and exaction exercised with great cruelty 172 He also contends that writers who advocate for helping wild animals do not do so for their own benefit because they would have nothing to gain by helping these individuals Lepeltier goes on to assert that the advocates for reducing wild animal suffering would be aware of their doubts about how best to help these individuals and that they would not act by considering them as rudimentary and simple to understand beings contrary to the vision that the former colonizers had of colonized populations 172 Intervention in practice EditExisting forms of assistance Edit See also Wildlife rehabilitation Rescued baby eastern gray squirrel being fed using a syringe Existing ways that individual animals suffering in the wild are aided include providing medical care to sick and injured animals vaccinating animals to prevent disease taking care of orphaned animals rescuing animals who are trapped or in natural disasters taking care of the needs of animals who are starving or thirsty sheltering animals who are suffering due to weather conditions 145 and using contraception to regulate population sizes 173 History of interventions Edit Oral rabies vaccine in bait The Bishnoi a Hindu sect founded in the 15th century have a tradition of feeding wild animals 174 Some Bishnoi temples also act as rescue centres where priests take care of injured animals a few of these individuals are returned to the wild while others remain roaming freely in the temple compounds 175 The Borana Oromo people leave out water overnight for wild animals to drink because they believe that the animals have a right to drinking water 176 In 2002 the Australian Government authorized the killing of 15 000 out of 100 000 kangaroos who were trapped in a fenced in national military base and suffering in a state of illness misery and starvation 177 In 2016 350 starving hippos and buffaloes at Kruger National Park were killed by park rangers one of the motives for the action was to prevent them from suffering as they died 178 Rescues of multiple animals in the wild have taken place in 1988 the US and Soviet governments collaborated in Operation Breakthrough to free three gray whales who were trapped in pack ice off the coast of Alaska 179 in 2018 a team of BBC filmmakers dug a ramp in the snow to allow a group of penguins to escape a ravine in Antarctica 180 in 2019 2 000 baby flamingos were rescued during a drought in South Africa 181 during the 2019 20 Australian bushfire season a number of fire threatened wild animals were rescued 182 in 2020 120 pilot whales who were beached were rescued in Sri Lanka 183 in 2021 1 700 Cape cormorant chicks who had been abandoned by their parents were rescued in South Africa 184 in the same year nearly 5 000 cold stunned sea turtles were rescued in Texas 185 Vaccination programs have been successfully implemented to prevent rabies and tuberculosis in wild animals 186 Wildlife contraception has been used to reduce and stabilize populations of wild horses white tailed deer American bison and African elephants 173 187 Future developments EditProposed interventions Edit It has been argued that in the future based on research feasibility and whether interventions could be carried out without increasing suffering overall existing forms of assistance for wild animals could be employed on a larger scale to reduce suffering 115 188 Technological proposals include gene drives and CRISPR to reduce the suffering of members of r strategist species 189 and using biotechnology to eradicate suffering in wild animals 19 190 When it comes to reducing suffering as a result of predation propositions include removing predators from wild areas 191 192 refraining from reintroducing predators into areas where they have previously gone extinct 72 193 arranging the gradual extinction of carnivorous species 54 and reprogramming them to become herbivores using germline engineering 188 With predation due to cats and dogs it has been recommended that these companion animals should always be sterilized to prevent the existence of feral animals that cats should be kept indoors and dogs kept on a leash unless in designated areas 194 Some writers such as Brian Tomasik have argued from a consequentialist perspective that following the conclusion that the majority of wild animals live negative lives that loss of habitat rather than being opposed should be encouraged Tyler M John and Jeff Sebo have criticised this position terming it the Logic of the Logger based on the concept of the Logic of the Larder 195 Welfare biology Edit Main article Welfare biology Welfare biology is a proposed research field for studying the welfare of animals with a particular focus on their relationship with natural ecosystems 196 It was first advanced in 1995 by Yew Kwang Ng who defined it as the study of living things and their environment with respect to their welfare defined as net happiness or enjoyment minus suffering 71 Such research is intended to promote concern for animal suffering in the wild and to establish effective actions that can be undertaken to help these individuals in the future 197 198 The organizations Animal Ethics and Wild Animal Initiative promote the establishment of welfare biology as a field of research 199 Impact of climate change Edit It has been argued that climate change may have a large direct impact on a number of animals with the largest effect on individuals who belong to specialist species that specialise in living in environments which could be most affected by climate change this could then lead to replacement by individuals belonging to more generalist species It has also been asserted that the indirect impact of climate change on wild animal suffering will be whether it leads to an increase or decrease of individuals being born into lives where they suffer and die shortly after coming into existence with a large number of factors needing to be taken into consideration and requiring further study to assess this 155 Risks Edit Spreading wild animal suffering beyond Earth Edit Several researchers and non profit organizations have raised concern that human civilization may cause wild animal suffering outside Earth For example wild habitats may be created or allowed to happen on extraterrestrial colonies like terraformed planets 200 201 Another example of a potential realization of the risk is directed panspermia where the initial microbial population eventually evolves into sentient organisms 202 203 204 Spreading sentient wild animals beyond Earth may constitute a suffering risk as this could potentially lead to an immense increase in the amount of wild animal suffering in existence 205 Cultural depictions EditWildlife documentaries Edit Lions attacking an African buffalo in Botswana it is argued that wildlife documentaries commonly focus on encounters between individuals such as these who are considered to be charismatic while the suffering of other animals is underrepresented Criticism of portrayals of wild animal suffering Edit It has been argued that much of people s knowledge about wild animals comes from wildlife documentaries which have been described as non representative of the reality of wild animal suffering because they underrepresent uncharismatic animals who may have the capacity to suffer such as animals who are preyed upon as well as small animals and invertebrates 206 In addition it is claimed that such documentaries focus on adult animals while the majority of animals who likely suffer the most die before reaching adulthood 206 that wildlife documentaries don t generally show animals suffering from parasitism 137 47 that such documentaries can leave viewers with the false impression that animals who have been attacked by predators and suffered serious injury survived and thrived afterwards 207 and that much of the particularly violent incidents of predation are not included 208 The broadcaster David Attenborough has stated People who accuse us of putting in too much violence should see what we leave on the cutting room floor 209 It is also contended that wildlife documentaries present nature as a spectacle to be passively consumed by viewers as well as a sacred and unique place that needs protection Additionally attention is drawn to how hardships that are experienced by animals are portrayed in a way that give the impression that wild animals through adaptive processes are able to overcome these sources of harm However the development of such adaptive traits takes place over a number of generations of individuals who will likely experience much suffering and hardship in their lives while passing down their genes 210 David Pearce a transhumanist and advocate for technological solutions for reducing the suffering of wild animals is highly critical of how wildlife documentaries which he refers to as animal snuff movies represent wild animal suffering 211 Nature documentaries are mostly travesties of real life They entertain and edify us with evocative mood music and travelogue style voice overs They impose significance and narrative structure on life s messiness Wildlife shows have their sad moments for sure Yet suffering never lasts very long It is always offset by homely platitudes about the balance of Nature the good of the herd and a sort of poor man s secular theodicy on behalf of Mother Nature which reassures us that it s not so bad after all That s a convenient lie Lions kill their targets primarily by suffocation which will last minutes The wolf pack may start eating their prey while the victim is still conscious though hamstrung Sharks and the orca basically eat their prey alive but in sections for the larger prey notably seals Pearce also argues through analogy how the idea of intelligent aliens creating stylised portrayals of human deaths for popular entertainment would be considered abhorrent he asserts that in reality this is the role that humans play when creating wildlife documentaries 211 Clare Palmer asserts that even when wildlife documentaries contain vivid images of wild animal suffering they don t motivate a moral or practical response in the way that companion animals such as dogs or cats suffering in similar situations would and most people instinctively adopt the position of laissez faire allowing suffering to take its course without intervention 212 Non intervention as a filmmaking rule Edit The question of whether wildlife documentary filmmakers should intervene to help animals is a topic of much debate 213 It has been described as a golden rule of such filmmaking to observe animals but not intervene 214 The rule is occasionally broken with BBC documentary crews rescuing some stranded baby turtles in 2016 and rescuing a group of penguins trapped in a ravine in 2018 215 the latter decision was defended by other wildlife documentary filmmakers 180 Filmmakers following the rule have been criticized for filming dying animals such as an elephant dying of thirst without helping them 215 In fiction Edit In The Ugly Duckling the winter cold causes the duckling to become frozen in an icy pond the duckling is rescued by a farmer Herman Melville in Moby Dick published in 1851 describes the sea as a place of universal cannibalism where creatures prey upon each other carrying on eternal war since the world began this is illustrated by a later scene depicting sharks consuming their own entrails 216 The fairy tales of Hans Christian Andersen contain depictions of the suffering of animals due to natural processes and their rescues by humans The titular character in Thumbelina encounters a seemingly dead frozen swallow Thumbelina feels sorry for the bird and her companion the mole states What a wretched thing it is to be born a little bird Thank goodness none of my children can be a bird who has nothing but his chirp chirp and must starve to death when winter comes along 217 However Thumbelina discovers that the swallow isn t actually dead and manages to nurse them back to health 218 In The Ugly Duckling the bitter winter cold causes the duckling to become frozen in an icy pond the duckling is rescued by a farmer who breaks the ice and takes the duckling to his home to be resuscitated 219 In the 1923 book Bambi a Life in the Woods Felix Salten portrays a world where predation and death are continuous a sick young hare is killed by crows a pheasant and a duck are killed by foxes a mouse is killed by an owl and a squirrel describes how their family members were killed by predators 220 The 1942 Disney adaptation has been criticized for inaccurately portraying a world where predation and death are no longer emphasized creating a fantasy of nature cleansed of the traumas and difficulties that may trouble children and that adults prefer to avoid 221 The film version has also been criticized for unrealistically portraying nature undisturbed by humans as an idyllic place made up of interspecies friendships with Bambi s life undisturbed by many of the harms routinely experienced by his real life counterparts such as starvation predation bovine tuberculosis and chronic wasting disease 206 John Wyndham s character Zelby in the 1957 book The Midwich Cuckoos describes nature as ruthless hideous and cruel beyond belief and observes that the lives of insects are sustained only by intricate processes of fantastic horror 222 In Watership Down published in 1972 Richard Adams compares the hardship experienced by animals in winter to the suffering experienced by poor humans stating For birds and animals as for poor men winter is another matter Rabbits like most wild animals suffer hardship 223 Adams also describes rabbits as being more susceptible to disease in the winter 223 In the philosopher Nick Bostrom s short story Golden the main character Albert an uplifted golden retriever observes that humans observe nature from an ecologically aesthetic perspective which disregards the suffering of the individuals who inhabit healthy ecosystems 224 Albert also asserts that it is a taboo in the animal rights movement that the majority of the suffering experienced by animals is due to natural processes and that a ny proposal for remedying this situation is bound to sound utopian but my dream is that one day the sun will rise on Earth and all sentient creatures will greet the new day with joy 225 The character Lord Vetinari in Terry Pratchett s Unseen Academicals in a speech tells how he once observed a salmon being consumed alive by a mother otter and her children feeding on the salmon s eggs He sarcastically describes m other and children dining upon mother and children as one of nature s wonders using it as an example of how evil is built into the very nature of the universe 226 This depiction of evil has been described as non traditional because it expresses horror at the idea that evil has been designed as a feature of the universe 227 In poetry Edit Isaac Gompertz s 1813 poem To the Thoughtless Homer in the Iliad employs the simile of a stag who as a victim is wounded by a human hunter and is then devoured by jackals who themselves are frightened away by a scavenging lion 228 In the epigram The Swallow and the Grasshopper attributed to Euenus the poet writes of a swallow feeding a grasshopper to its young remarking wilt not quickly cast it loose for it is not right nor just that singers should perish by singers mouths 229 Al Ma arri wrote of the kindness of giving water to birds and speculated whether there was a future existence where innocent animals would experience happiness to remedy the suffering they experience in this world In the Luzumiyyat he included a poem addressed to the wolf who if he were conscious of his bloodguiltiness would rather have remained unborn 230 In On Poetry A Rhaposdy written in 1733 Jonathan Swift argues that Hobbes proved that all creatures exist in a state of eternal war and uses predation by different animals as evidence of this A Whale of moderate Size will draw A Shole of Herrings down his Maw A Fox with Geese his Belly crams A Wolf destroys a thousand Lambs 231 Voltaire makes similar descriptions of predation in his Poem on the Lisbon Disaster published in 1756 arguing Elements animals humans everything is at war 232 Voltaire also asserts that all animals are condemned to live All sentient things born by the same stern law Suffer like me and like me also die 233 In William Blake s Vala or The Four Zoas the character Enion laments the cruelty of nature 234 observing how ravens cry out but don t receive pity and how sparrows and robins starve to death in the winter Enion also mourns how wolves and lions reproduce in a state of love then abandon their young to the wilds and how a spider labours to create a web awaiting a fly but then is consumed by a bird 235 Erasmus Darwin in The Temple of Nature published posthumously in 1803 observes the struggle for existence describing how different animals feed upon each other The towering eagle darting from above Unfeeling rends the inoffensive dove Nor spares enamour d of his radiant form The hungry nightingale the glowing worm and how parasitic animals like botflies reproduce their young feeding inside the living bodies of other animals Fell Oestrus buries in her rapid course Her countless brood in stag or bull or horse Whose hungry larva eats its living way Hatch d by the warmth and issues into day 236 154 155 He also refers to the world as one great Slaughter house 236 159 In a footnote he speculates whether humans could someday create a food source for predatory animals based on sugar asserting that as a result food for animals would then become as plentiful as water and they might live upon the earth without preying on each other as thick as blades of grass with no restraint to their numbers but the want of local room 236 160 The poem has been used as an example of how Erasmus Darwin predicted evolutionary theory 237 Isaac Gompertz the brother of Lewis Gompertz in his 1813 poem To the Thoughtless criticises the assertion that human consumption of other animals is justified because it is designed that way by nature inviting the reader to imagine themselves being predated by an animal and to consider whether they would want to have their life saved in the same way an animal being preyed upon such as a fly attacked by a spider would despite predation being part of nature given law 238 In the 1818 poem Epistle to John Hamilton Reynolds John Keats retells to John Hamilton Reynolds how one evening he was by the ocean when he saw Too far into the sea where every maw The greater on the less feeds evermore and observes that there exists an eternal fierce destruction at the core of the world The Shark at savage prey the hawk at pounce The gentle Robin like a Pard or Ounce Ravening a worm 239 The poem has been cited as an example of Erasmus Darwin s writings on Keats 240 In 1850 Alfred Tennyson published the poem In Memoriam A H H which contained the expression Nature red in tooth and claw this phrase has since become commonly used as a shorthand to refer to the extent of suffering in nature 241 In his 1855 poem Maud Tennyson described nature as irredeemable because of the theft and predation it intrinsically contains For nature is one with rapine a harm no preacher can heal The Mayfly is torn by the swallow the sparrow spear d by the shrike And the whole little wood where I sit is a world of plunder and prey 242 Edwin Arnold in The Light of Asia a narrative poem published in 1879 about the life of Prince Gautama Buddha describes how originally the prince saw the peace and plenty of nature but upon closer inspection he observed Life living upon death So the fair show Veiled one vast savage grim conspiracy Of mutual murder from the worm to man 243 It has been asserted that the Darwinian struggle depicted in the poem comes more from Arnold than Buddhist tradition 244 See also EditAnimal consciousness Antinatalism Emotion in animals God s utility function Natural evil Pain in animals Pain in amphibians Pain in cephalopods Pain in crustaceans Pain in invertebrates Pain in fish The Problem of Pain Speciesism Suffering focused ethicsReferences Edit a b c d Tomasik Brian 2015 11 02 The Importance of Wild Animal Suffering Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 133 152 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 toma ISSN 2280 9643 a b c Faria Catia Paez Eze 2015 05 11 Animals in Need the Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 1 7 13 ISSN 2280 9643 a b Wilcox Christie 2011 12 04 Bambi or Bessie Are wild animals happier Scientific American Retrieved 2019 10 29 a b c Horta Oscar 2014 11 25 Egalitarianism and Animals Between the Species 19 1 a b c Dawkins Richard 1995 Chapter 4 God s Utility Function River Out of Eden London Orion Publishing Group ISBN 978 0 297 81540 2 a b c d e f g h i j Horta Oscar 2010 Debunking the Idyllic View of Natural Processes Population Dynamics and Suffering in the Wild PDF Telos 17 1 73 88 a b c Iglesias Alejandro Villamor 2018 The overwhelming prevalence of suffering in Nature Revista de Bioetica y Derecho 2019 181 195 For discussion of wild animal suffering and its relation to the problem of evil see Darwin Charles September 1993 Barlow Nora ed The Autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809 1882 W W Norton amp Company p 90 ISBN 978 0393310696 Lewis C S 2015 The Problem of Pain HarperOne ISBN 9780060652968 Murray Michael April 30 2011 Nature Red in Tooth and Claw Theism and the Problem of Animal Suffering Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0199596324 Gould Stephen February 1982 Nonmoral Nature PDF Natural History 91 2 19 26 Retrieved 19 January 2014 McMahan Jeff 2013 The Moral Problem of Predation PDF In Chignell Andrew Cuneo Terence Halteman Matt eds Philosophy Comes to Dinner Arguments on the Ethics of Eating London Routledge ISBN 978 0415806831 For academic discussion of wild animal suffering and its alleviation from a secular standpoint see McMahan Jeff 2013 The Moral Problem of Predation PDF In Chignell Andrew Cuneo Terence Halteman Matt eds Philosophy Comes to Dinner Arguments on the Ethics of Eating London Routledge ISBN 978 0415806831 Ng Yew Kwang 1995 Towards Welfare Biology Evolutionary Economics of Animal Consciousness and Suffering PDF Biology and Philosophy 10 3 255 285 doi 10 1007 BF00852469 S2CID 59407458 Dorado Daniel 2015 Ethical Interventions in the Wild An Annotated Bibliography Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 219 238 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 dora Retrieved 21 April 2016 Moen Ole Martin 2016 The Ethics of Wild Animal Suffering PDF Etikk I Praksis Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics 10 1 14 doi 10 5324 eip v10i1 1972 Retrieved 8 May 2016 Horta Oscar 2015 The Problem of Evil in Nature Evolutionary Bases of the Prevalence of Disvalue Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 1 17 32 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 001 hort Retrieved 8 May 2016 Torres Mikel 2015 The Case for Intervention in Nature on Behalf of Animals A Critical Review of the Main Arguments against Intervention Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 1 33 49 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 001 torr Retrieved 8 May 2016 Cunha Luciano Carlos 2015 If Natural Entities Have Intrinsic Value Should We Then Abstain from Helping Animals Who Are Victims of Natural Processes Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 1 51 63 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 001 cunh Retrieved 8 May 2016 Tomasik Brian 2015 The Importance of Wild Animal Suffering Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 133 152 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 toma Retrieved 8 May 2016 Pearce David 2015 A Welfare State For Elephants A Case Study of Compassionate Stewardship Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 153 164 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 pear Retrieved 8 May 2016 Paez Eze 2015 Refusing Help and Inflicting Harm A Critique of the Environmentalist View Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 165 178 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 paez Retrieved 8 May 2016 Sozmen Beril 2015 Relations and Moral Obligations towards Other Animals Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 179 193 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 sozm Retrieved 8 May 2016 Faria Catia 2016 Animal Ethics Goes Wild The Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature Ph D Universitat Pompeu Fabra a b Delon Nicolas Purves Duncan 2018 04 01 Wild Animal Suffering is Intractable Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31 2 239 260 doi 10 1007 s10806 018 9722 y ISSN 1573 322X S2CID 158886418 Callicott J Baird 1980 11 01 Animal Liberation A Triangular Affair PDF Environmental Ethics doi 10 5840 enviroethics19802424 S2CID 41646945 Archived PDF from the original on 2019 02 20 Retrieved 2021 03 21 a b c Simmons Aaron 2009 Animals Predators The Right to Life and The Duty to Save Lives Ethics amp the Environment 14 1 15 27 doi 10 2979 ete 2009 14 1 15 S2CID 89542818 a b c Sozmen Beril Idemen 2013 11 01 Harm in the Wild Facing Non Human Suffering in Nature PDF Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 5 1075 1088 doi 10 1007 s10677 013 9416 5 ISSN 1572 8447 S2CID 143964923 a b Regan Tom 2004 The Case for Animal Rights Berkeley University of California Press p 357 ISBN 978 0 520 24386 6 a b Kapembwa Julius 2017 Wildlife rights and human obligations PhD thesis University of Reading p 50 a b c Horta Oscar 2015 01 05 Why the Situation of Animals in the Wild Should Concern Us Animal Charity Evaluators Retrieved 2019 08 17 a b c Sebo Jeff 2020 01 15 All we owe to animals Aeon Retrieved 2021 03 15 Helping animals in the wild Animal Ethics 2013 08 28 Retrieved 2019 08 17 a b Vinding Magnus 2020 Reducing Extreme Suffering for Non Human Animals Enhancement vs Smaller Future Populations Between the Species 23 1 Wiblin Robert Harris Kieran 2019 08 15 Animals in the wild often suffer a great deal What if anything should we do about that 80 000 Hours Retrieved 2019 10 25 a b c d Ray Georgia 2017 11 22 Parasite Load and Disease in Wild Animals Wild Animal Suffering Research Archived from the original on 2021 06 12 Retrieved 2021 03 24 Calvete C Estrada R Villafuerte R Osacar J J Lucientes J 2002 Epidemiology of viral haemorrhagic disease and myxomatosis in a free living population of wild rabbits Veterinary Record 150 25 776 782 doi 10 1136 vr 150 25 776 ISSN 2042 7670 PMID 12135072 S2CID 7084943 Knight Kelli Wick Peach van 2019 Medical and Surgical Management of Deer and Relatives Medical Management of Wildlife Species John Wiley amp Sons Ltd pp 259 270 doi 10 1002 9781119036708 ch20 ISBN 978 1 119 03670 8 S2CID 208578632 retrieved 2021 03 24 Botzler Richard G Brown Richard N 2014 Foundations of Wildlife Diseases Berkeley California University of California Press p 378 ISBN 978 0 520 27609 3 Beldomenico Pablo M Telfer Sandra Gebert Stephanie Lukomski Lukasz Bennett Malcolm Begon Michael 2008 08 07 Poor condition and infection a vicious circle in natural populations Proceedings of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences 275 1644 1753 1759 doi 10 1098 rspb 2008 0147 ISSN 0962 8452 PMC 2453294 PMID 18448414 Brannelly Laura A Webb Rebecca Skerratt Lee F Berger Lee 2016 Amphibians with infectious disease increase their reproductive effort evidence for the terminal investment hypothesis Open Biology 6 6 150251 doi 10 1098 rsob 150251 PMC 4929933 PMID 27358291 Physical injuries in wild animals Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 24 Scott Marilyn E 1988 The Impact of Infection and Disease on Animal Populations Implications for Conservation Biology Conservation Biology 2 1 40 56 doi 10 1111 j 1523 1739 1988 tb00334 x ISSN 1523 1739 Goodman Brett A Johnson Pieter T J 2011 05 25 Disease and the Extended Phenotype Parasites Control Host Performance and Survival through Induced Changes in Body Plan PLOS ONE 6 5 e20193 Bibcode 2011PLoSO 620193G doi 10 1371 journal pone 0020193 ISSN 1932 6203 PMC 3102088 PMID 21633498 Libersat Frederic Kaiser Maayan Emanuel Stav 2018 Mind Control How Parasites Manipulate Cognitive Functions in Their Insect Hosts Frontiers in Psychology 9 572 doi 10 3389 fpsyg 2018 00572 ISSN 1664 1078 PMC 5938628 PMID 29765342 Robar Nicholas Burness Gary Murray Dennis L 2010 Tropics trophics and taxonomy the determinants of parasite associated host mortality Oikos 119 8 1273 1280 doi 10 1111 j 1600 0706 2009 18292 x ISSN 1600 0706 a b c Predators parasites and parasitoids The Australian Museum Retrieved 2021 03 24 Parasitoids Cornell University College of Agriculture and Life Sciences Retrieved 2021 03 24 Fiske W F 1910 02 01 Superparasitism an Important Factor in the Natural Control of Insects1 Journal of Economic Entomology 3 1 88 97 doi 10 1093 jee 3 1 88 ISSN 0022 0493 Sekar Sandhya 2015 05 22 Parasitoid wasps may be the most diverse animal group BBC Earth Retrieved 2021 03 24 Malnutrition and Starvation Michigan Department of Natural Resources Retrieved 2021 03 25 Faria Catia 2016 Animal Ethics Goes Wild The Problem of Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in Nature PDF PhD thesis Universitat Pompeu Fabra China Victor Holzman Roi 2014 06 03 Hydrodynamic starvation in first feeding larval fishes Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111 22 8083 8088 Bibcode 2014PNAS 111 8083C doi 10 1073 pnas 1323205111 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 4050599 PMID 24843180 Malnutrition hunger and thirst in wild animals Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 26 Russo Catherine J M Ohmer Michel E B Cramp Rebecca L Franklin Craig E 2018 05 01 A pathogenic skin fungus and sloughing exacerbate cutaneous water loss in amphibians Journal of Experimental Biology 221 9 doi 10 1242 jeb 167445 ISSN 0022 0949 PMID 29752415 a b Weidman T Litvaitis J A 2011 07 01 Can supplemental food increase winter survival of a threatened cottontail rabbit Biological Conservation 144 7 2054 2058 doi 10 1016 j biocon 2011 04 027 ISSN 0006 3207 a b c d Weather conditions and nonhuman animals Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 27 Amos Jonathan 2019 04 24 Antarctica Thousands of emperor penguin chicks wiped out BBC News Retrieved 2021 04 05 Sharman Jon 2019 08 20 Thousands of birds killed after freak weather event leaves them with smashed skulls and internal damage The Independent Retrieved 2021 04 07 Smith Allen G Webster Harry R 1955 Effects of Hail Storms on Waterfowl Populations in Alberta Canada 1953 The Journal of Wildlife Management 19 3 368 374 doi 10 2307 3797388 ISSN 0022 541X JSTOR 3797388 Elbaum Rachel Eckardt Andy 2018 08 16 Wildlife animals suffer in Europe s summer of extreme heat NBC News Retrieved 2021 04 05 Sanderson Katharine 2007 01 04 Hot waters make it hard for fish to breathe Nature news070101 5 doi 10 1038 news070101 5 ISSN 0028 0836 S2CID 129050854 With Temperatures Rising Can Animals Survive the Heat Stress Yale E360 Retrieved 2021 04 05 Wildlife mass mortality events associated with harsh winter weather The Veterinary Record 182 22 628 629 2018 06 02 doi 10 1136 vr k2413 ISSN 2042 7670 PMID 29858315 S2CID 49335517 Rodel H G Bora A Kaetzke P Khaschei M Hutzelmeyer H von Holst D August 2004 Over winter survival in subadult European rabbits weather effects density dependence and the impact of individual characteristics Oecologia 140 4 566 576 Bibcode 2004Oecol 140 566R doi 10 1007 s00442 004 1616 1 ISSN 0029 8549 PMID 15309616 S2CID 40720075 a b Animals in natural disasters Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 28 Olvera Lola 2020 03 25 When Natural Disaster Strikes Wildlife Pays A Heavy Price Sentient Media Retrieved 2021 03 28 Minelli Alessandro 2008 Predation In Jorgensen Sven Erik Fath Brian D eds Encyclopedia of Ecology Amsterdam Netherlands Elsevier ISBN 978 0 08 093116 6 OCLC 527382954 a b McMahan Jeff 2010 09 19 The Meat Eaters Opinionator Retrieved 2021 03 12 Antagonism in nature Interspecific conflict Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 28 Harris J B Goonetilleke A 2004 09 01 Animal poisons and the nervous system what the neurologist needs to know Journal of Neurology Neurosurgery amp Psychiatry 75 suppl 3 iii40 iii46 doi 10 1136 jnnp 2004 045724 ISSN 0022 3050 PMC 1765666 PMID 15316044 Antagonism in nature Intraspecific fights Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 28 Povinelli Daniel J 2020 11 01 Can Comparative Psychology Crack its Toughest Nut PDF Animal Behavior and Cognition 7 4 589 652 doi 10 26451 abc 07 04 09 2020 Zanette Liana Y Clinchy Michael 2019 05 06 Ecology of fear Current Biology 29 9 R309 R313 doi 10 1016 j cub 2019 02 042 ISSN 0960 9822 PMID 31063718 S2CID 145049061 Robbins Jim 2017 04 11 The Fear Factor How the Peril of Predators Can Transform a Landscape Yale E360 Retrieved 2020 08 01 Zanette Liana Y Hobbs Emma C Witterick Lauren E MacDougall Shackleton Scott A Clinchy Michael 2019 08 07 Predator induced fear causes PTSD like changes in the brains and behaviour of wild animals Scientific Reports 9 1 11474 Bibcode 2019NatSR 911474Z doi 10 1038 s41598 019 47684 6 ISSN 2045 2322 PMC 6685979 PMID 31391473 Allan Bridie J M 2020 01 01 Scared to death the killer effect of predation risk in snowshoe hares Conservation Physiology 7 1 coz029 doi 10 1093 conphys coz029 PMC 6572791 PMID 31217976 Ray Georgia 2017 06 29 How Many Wild Animals Are There Wild Animal Suffering Research Archived from the original on 2021 04 13 Retrieved 2021 03 10 Bar On Yinon M Phillips Rob Milo Ron 2018 06 19 Supplementary Information Appendix PDF Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 115 25 6506 6511 Bibcode 2018PNAS 115 6506B doi 10 1073 pnas 1711842115 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 6016768 PMID 29784790 Matheny Gaverick Chan Kai M A December 2005 Human Diets and Animal Welfare the Illogic of the Larder Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 18 6 579 594 doi 10 1007 s10806 005 1805 x ISSN 1187 7863 S2CID 154198751 Klein Alice 2022 09 19 There are 20 000 000 000 000 000 ants crawling all over Earth New Scientist Retrieved 2022 09 26 Paez Eze 2020 01 01 Preserving nature for the benefit of all sentient individuals Animal Sentience 4 27 doi 10 51291 2377 7478 1551 ISSN 2377 7478 Darwin Charles September 1993 Barlow Nora ed The Autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809 1882 W W Norton amp Company p 90 ISBN 978 0393310696 Dawkins Richard 1995 River Out of Eden A Darwinian View of Life London Orion Publishing Group pp 131 132 ISBN 978 0 297 81540 2 Simpson Keith 1979 Schultz Martin ed The Mysteries of Life amp Death An Illustrated Investigation into the Incredible World of Death London Salamander Books p 22 ISBN 978 0 86101 036 3 a b c Ng Yew Kwang 1995 Towards Welfare Biology Evolutionary Economics of Animal Consciousness and Suffering PDF Biology and Philosophy 10 3 255 285 doi 10 1007 BF00852469 S2CID 59407458 a b c Sagoff Mark 1984 Animal Liberation and Environmental Ethics Bad Marriage Quick Divorce Osgoode Hall Law Journal 22 2 297 307 Groff Zach Ng Yew Kwang 2019 06 18 Does suffering dominate enjoyment in the animal kingdom An update to welfare biology Biology amp Philosophy 34 4 40 doi 10 1007 s10539 019 9692 0 ISSN 1572 8404 S2CID 196683974 Leonardo da Vinci 2004 01 01 The Notebooks of Leonardo Da Vinci Complete Translated by Richter Jean Paul folio 1219 Hume David 1779 Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion London p 176 a b c Paley William 1879 1802 Paxton James Ware John eds Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity New York Sheldon amp Company a b Gregory T Ryan December 2009 The Argument from Design A Guided Tour of William Paley s Natural Theology 1802 Evolution Education and Outreach 2 4 602 611 doi 10 1007 s12052 009 0184 6 ISSN 1936 6434 Murray Michael J 2008 Nature Red in Tooth and Claw Theism and the Problem of Animal Suffering Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 923727 2 OCLC 209815655 Hoggard Creegan Nicola 2013 Animal Suffering and the Problem of Evil Oxford Oxford University Press pp 44 55 ISBN 978 0 19 993185 9 Evans Edward Payson September 1894 Ethical Relations Between Man and Beast Popular Science Monthly 45 646 Schneider John R 2020 Facing the Darwinian Problem of Evil Animal Suffering and the Darwinian Problem of Evil 1 ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 15 47 doi 10 1017 9781108767439 003 ISBN 978 1 108 76743 9 S2CID 238121342 Darwin Charles 1860 05 22 To Asa Gray Letter to Asa Gray Retrieved 2021 03 07 Darwin Charles 1958 Barlow Nora ed The Autobiography of Charles Darwin London Collins p 90 Moen Ole Martin 2016 05 09 The ethics of wild animal suffering Etikk I Praksis Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics 10 1 91 104 doi 10 5324 eip v10i1 1972 ISSN 1890 4009 Schmithausen Lambert 1997 The Early Buddhist Tradition and Ethics Journal of Buddhist Ethics James Simon P 2006 02 01 Buddhism and the Ethics of Species Conservation Environmental Values 15 1 85 97 doi 10 3197 096327106776678942 a b Cooper David E James Simon P 2005 Buddhism Virtue and Environment Farnham Ashgate pp 119 120 ISBN 978 1 351 95431 0 Stuart Daniel M September 2019 Becoming Animal Karma and the Animal Realm Envisioned through an Early Yogacara Lens Religions 10 6 363 doi 10 3390 rel10060363 ISSN 2077 1444 Shantideva 2006 The Way of the Bodhisattva Revised ed Shambhala p 165 ISBN 978 1590303887 Rinpoche Patrul 1998 The Words of My Perfect Teacher Revised ed Shambhala pp 76 77 ISBN 978 1 57062 412 4 Kemmerer Lisa April 2009 Hindu Ethics and Nonhuman Animals Swadharam Journal 3 32 45 a b Buffon Georges Louis Leclerc 1807 Natural History Containing a Theory of the Earth a General History of Man of the Brute Creation and of Vegetables Minerals amp c amp c amp c London H D Symonds Herder Johann Gottfried 1801 The Animal Kingdom In Relation to the History of Man The Union Magazine and Imperial Register 2 172 a b c Gompertz Lewis 1992 1824 Singer Peter ed Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes Fontwell Centaur Press Gompertz Lewis 1852 Fragments in Defence of Animals and Essays on Morals Soul and Future State London W Horsell p 18 Pedatella Stefan 2009 03 01 Images of Animal Predation in Giacomo Leopardi s Dialogo della Natura e di un Islandese Italian Culture 27 1 25 42 doi 10 1179 155909009X401665 ISSN 0161 4622 S2CID 159793645 Leopardi Giacomo 2013 4511 Zibaldone The Notebooks of Leopardi Penguin ISBN 978 0 14 196200 9 Indeed precisely the order that exists in the world and seeing that evil is in this order that such order cannot exist without evil makes the existence of the latter inconceivable Animals destined for the nourishment of other species The inborn envy and hatred of living beings toward their fellows Schopenhauer Arthur 2000 Parerga and Paralipomena Short Philosophical Essays Oxford Clarendon Press p 292 ISBN 9780199242214 Mill John Stuart 1874 Nature Three Essays on Religion London Longmans Green Reader and Dyer pp 28 32 65 a b Salt Henry Stephens Leffingwell Albert 1894 Animals Rights Considered in Relation to Social Progress Columbia University Libraries New York London Macmillan amp Co Moore J Howard 1906 The Universal Kinship Chicago Charles H Kerr amp Co pp 249 250 a b Moore J Howard 1912 Ethics and Education London G Bell amp Sons Skutch Alexander F 1952 Which Shall We Protect Thoughts on the Ethics of the Treatment of Free Life PDF Aryan Path 23 382 386 a b Singer Peter June 14 1973 Food for Thought The New York Review of Books Retrieved 23 February 2015 Clark Stephen R L 2008 08 29 1979 The rights of Wild things Inquiry 22 1 4 171 188 doi 10 1080 00201747908601871 Callicott J Baird 1980 11 01 Animal Liberation A Triangular Affair PDF Environmental Ethics doi 10 5840 enviroethics19802424 Retrieved 2021 03 25 30 years since the publication of Morals reason and animals Animal Ethics 2017 07 25 Retrieved 2021 09 09 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Naess Arne 1991 Should We Try to Relieve Clear Cases of Suffering in Nature PDF Pan Ecology 6 1 5 Retrieved 20 November 2016 Olivier David 1993 06 01 Pourquoi je ne suis pas ecologiste Why I am not an environmentalist Les Cahiers antispecistes in French Retrieved 2020 04 11 Tomasik Brian July 2009 The Importance of Wild Animal Suffering Center on Long Term Risk Retrieved 2021 10 08 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Vol 3 No 1 2015 ledonline it 2015 Retrieved 2022 06 18 Vol 3 No 2 2015 ledonline it 2015 Retrieved 2022 09 26 Faria Catia May 2015 Making a Difference on Behalf of Animals Living in the Wild Interview with Jeff McMahan PDF Relations 3 1 81 84 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 001 fari ISSN 2283 3196 a b c McMahan Jeff 2010 09 28 Predators A Response The New York Times Retrieved 2019 10 29 a b Reese Jacy 14 December 2015 Wild animals endure illness injury and starvation We should help Vox Retrieved 17 April 2016 Reese Jacy 2018 The Expanding Moral Circle Revisited The End of Animal Farming How Scientists Entrepreneurs and Activists Are Building an Animal Free Food System Beacon Press ISBN 978 0 8070 1945 0 Matthews Dylan 2021 04 12 The wild frontier of animal welfare Vox Retrieved 2022 06 18 a b c d Nadler Steven 2018 08 10 We have an ethical obligation to relieve individual animal suffering Aeon Retrieved 2021 03 15 First dissertation on helping animals in the wild Center for Animal Ethics UPF 2016 03 19 Retrieved 2021 02 13 Animal Ethics in the Wild Cambridge University Press Retrieved 2022 06 13 Kyle Johannsen Wild Animal Ethics The Moral and The Moral and Political Problem of Wild Animal Suffering New Books Network 2021 01 11 Retrieved 2021 07 07 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Symposium on Kyle Johannsen s Wild Animal Ethics APPLE 2021 01 21 Retrieved 2021 09 30 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Horta Oscar 2022 In defense of animals Making a Stand for Animals pp 135 165 doi 10 4324 9781003285922 7 ISBN 9781003285922 retrieved 2022 07 10 Announcing Wild Animal Initiative Wild Animal Initiative 2019 01 19 Retrieved 2021 07 07 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Why wild animal suffering matters Animal Ethics Retrieved 2021 07 07 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Schukraft Jason 2019 11 06 Opinion estimating invertebrate sentience Rethink Priorities Retrieved 2022 06 18 Schukraft Jason 2019 07 09 Invertebrate welfare cause profile Rethink Priorities Retrieved 2022 06 18 Canon Gabrielle 2021 09 10 How a Tahoe refuge saved owls coyotes and raccoons from wildfire The Guardian Retrieved 2021 09 10 Keulartz Jozef 2016 10 01 Should the Lion Eat Straw Like the Ox Animal Ethics and the Predation Problem Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 29 5 813 834 doi 10 1007 s10806 016 9637 4 ISSN 1573 322X Raterman Ty Winter 2008 An Environmentalist s Lament on Predation PDF Environmental Ethics 30 4 417 434 doi 10 5840 enviroethics200830443 Kapembwa Julius October 2018 Predation Catch 22 Disentangling the Rights of Prey Predators and Rescuers Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31 5 527 542 doi 10 1007 s10806 018 9743 6 ISSN 1187 7863 S2CID 158949810 a b McMahan Jeff 2013 The Moral Problem of Predation PDF In Chignell Andrew Cuneo Terence Halteman Matt eds Philosophy Comes to Dinner Arguments on the Ethics of Eating London Routledge ISBN 978 0415806831 Ebert Rainer 2012 Innocent Threats and the Moral Problem of Carnivorous Animals Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 2 146 159 doi 10 1111 j 1468 5930 2012 00561 x Trindade Gabriel Garmendia da Woodhall Andrew eds 2020 Intervention or Protest Acting for Nonhuman Animals Vernon Press p 244 ISBN 978 1 62273 975 2 Everett Jennifer 2001 Environmental Ethics Animal Welfarism and the Problem of Predation A Bambi Lover s Respect for Nature Ethics and the Environment 6 1 42 67 ISSN 1085 6633 JSTOR 40339003 a b Aaltola Elisa February 2010 Animal Ethics and the Argument from Absurdity Environmental Values 19 1 79 98 doi 10 3197 096327110X485392 a b Ryf Philipp 2016 09 01 Environmental Ethics The Case of Wild Animals Master s thesis University of Basel Shooster Jay 2017 07 11 Legal Personhood and the Positive Rights of Wild Animals Wild Animal Suffering Research Archived from the original on 2020 12 04 Retrieved 2021 03 09 a b Cowen Tyler 2003 Policing Nature PDF Environmental Ethics 25 2 169 182 doi 10 5840 enviroethics200325231 S2CID 16279915 Archived from the original PDF on 2019 10 29 McShane Katie 2018 Why Animal Welfare Is Not Biodiversity Ecosystem Services or Human Welfare Toward a More Complete Assessment of Climate Impacts PDF Les ateliers de l ethique The Ethics Forum 13 1 43 64 doi 10 7202 1055117ar ISSN 1718 9977 Hopster Jeroen 2019 12 01 The Speciesism Debate Intuition Method and Empirical Advances Animals 9 12 1054 doi 10 3390 ani9121054 ISSN 2076 2615 PMC 6940905 PMID 31805715 There are various definitions of speciesism in circulation in the academic literature and beyond Some authors treat speciesism as an unjustified position by definition This is problematic however since the defensibility of speciesism is subject to substantive debate A more fruitful approach is to distinguish the descriptive concept of speciesism from its normative evaluation Here and in what follows I will adopt Singer s definition according to which speciesism involves the preferential consideration of the interests of members of one s own species Mayerfeld Jamie 1999 Suffering and Moral Responsibility New York Oxford University Press p 117 ISBN 978 0 19 515495 5 Bruers Stijn 2020 10 22 Speciesism Arbitrariness and Moral Illusions Philosophia 49 3 957 975 doi 10 1007 s11406 020 00282 7 ISSN 0048 3893 S2CID 226346638 Muraille Eric 2018 07 23 Debate Could anti speciesism and veganism form the basis for a rational society The Conversation Retrieved 2021 04 02 a b Horta Oscar 2016 07 05 Changing attitudes towards animals in the wild and speciesism Animal Sentience 1 7 doi 10 51291 2377 7478 1109 ISSN 2377 7478 a b Nussbaum Martha C 2006 Frontiers of Justice Disability Nationality Species Membership Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 04157 8 OCLC 434003841 Singer Peter 2014 The Point of View of The Universe Oxford Oxford University Press p 346 ISBN 978 0199603695 Horta Oscar 2017 Animal Suffering in the Wild Environmental Ethics 39 3 261 279 doi 10 5840 enviroethics201739320 Verchot Manon Meet the people who want to turn predators into herbivores TreeHugger Retrieved 2019 10 29 Belshaw Christoher 2001 Environmental Philosophy McGill Queen s Press p xii ISBN 978 1 902683 21 8 Paez Eze 2015 11 02 Refusing Help and Inflicting Harm A Critique of the Environmentalist View Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 165 178 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 paez ISSN 2280 9643 Faria Catia Paez Eze 2019 07 01 It s Splitsville Why Animal Ethics and Environmental Ethics Are Incompatible American Behavioral Scientist 63 8 1047 1060 doi 10 1177 0002764219830467 ISSN 0002 7642 S2CID 150854523 a b c Hettinger Ned 1994 Valuing Predation in Rolston s Environmental Ethics PDF Environmental Ethics 16 1 3 20 doi 10 5840 enviroethics199416138 S2CID 18428255 Archived from the original PDF on 2019 02 25 Moen Ole Martin 2016 The Ethics of Wild Animal Suffering PDF Etikk I Praksis Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics 10 1 14 doi 10 5324 eip v10i1 1972 Retrieved 8 May 2016 a b c Horta Oscar 2018 Concern for Wild Animal Suffering and Environmental Ethics What Are the Limits of the Disagreement Les Ateliers de l Ethique 13 1 85 100 doi 10 7202 1055119ar ISSN 1718 9977 Rolston III Holmes 1988 Environmental Ethics Duties To and Values in the Natural World Philadelphia Temple University Press ISBN 9780877225010 Moriarty Paul Mark Woods 1997 Hunting Predation Environmental Ethics 19 4 391 404 doi 10 5840 enviroethics19971945 Yves Bonnardel l antispeciste qui n aimait pas la nature Yves Bonnardel the anti speciesist who did not like nature Usbek amp Rica in French 2016 08 22 Retrieved 2020 07 26 Nelson Michael P Vucetich John A 2013 02 01 Wilderness Value of PDF in Lafollette Hugh ed International Encyclopedia of Ethics Oxford UK Blackwell Publishing Ltd pp wbiee645 doi 10 1002 9781444367072 wbiee645 ISBN 978 1 4051 8641 4 retrieved 2022 07 16 Duclos Joshua 2018 Value morality and wilderness Thesis Boston University Walker Jack June 2022 Born to be Wild On Wildness Objections to Preventing Wild Animal Suffering PDF Aporia 32 1 Duclos Joshua S 2022 Wilderness Morality and Value Lanham Lexington Books ISBN 978 1 6669 0136 8 OCLC 1330426290 Fischer Bob 2018 01 01 Individuals in the wild Animal Sentience 3 23 doi 10 51291 2377 7478 1382 ISSN 2377 7478 Wilson Scott D 2011 Animal Ethics in Context by Palmer Claire Ethics 121 4 824 8 doi 10 1086 660788 Hettinger Ned 2018 Naturalness Wild animal Suffering and Palmer on Laissez faire Les ateliers de l ethique The Ethics Forum 13 1 65 84 doi 10 7202 1055118ar ISSN 1718 9977 Faria Catia 2014 12 21 Should we intervene in nature to help animals Practical Ethics Retrieved 2021 03 13 Sapontzis Steve 2011 03 18 Predation Ethics and Animals 5 2 doi 10 15368 ea 1984v5n2 1 ISSN 0197 9094 Ladwig Bernd 2015 Against Wild Animal Sovereignty An Interest based Critique of Zoopolis Journal of Political Philosophy 23 3 282 301 doi 10 1111 jopp 12068 ISSN 1467 9760 Bailey Christiane 2014 Le double sens de la communaute morale la considerabilite morale et l agentivite morale des autres animaux The double meaning of moral community moral consideration and the moral agency of other animals Les ateliers de l ethique The Ethics Forum in French 9 3 31 67 doi 10 7202 1029059ar ISSN 1718 9977 Horta Oscar 2013 Zoopolis interventions and the State of Nature PDF Law Ethics and Philosophy 113 125 ISSN 2341 1465 Reus Estiva 2018 Le lourd fardeau de l etre humain The Heavy Burden of Human Being Eliminer les animaux pour leur bien promenade chez les reducteurs de la souffrance dans la nature Eliminate animals for their good walk among the reducers of suffering in nature in French Vol 41 Les Cahiers antispecistes a b Lepeltier Thomas 2018 11 07 Se soucier des animaux sauvages Caring about wild animals L Amorce in French Retrieved 2021 03 12 a b Brennan Ozy 2018 12 20 Wildlife Contraception Wild Animal Suffering Research Archived from the original on 2021 03 21 Retrieved 2019 10 25 In pictures India s original conservationists BBC News 2014 07 20 Retrieved 2020 10 23 In Bishnoi villages birds and animals roam without fear and feed off human hands Menon Gangadharan 2012 07 03 The Land of The Bishnois Where Conservation Of Wildlife Is A Religion The Better India Retrieved 2021 03 07 Attfield Robin 2018 Environmental Ethics A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press p 103 ISBN 978 0 19 879716 6 Clarke Matthew Ng Yew Kwang October 2006 Population Dynamics and Animal Welfare Issues Raised by the Culling of Kangaroos in Puckapunyal Social Choice and Welfare 27 2 407 422 doi 10 1007 s00355 006 0137 8 ISSN 0176 1714 S2CID 15023392 Burke Jason 2016 09 14 South African national park to kill animals in response to severe drought The Guardian Retrieved 2021 03 07 Dorfman Andrea 1988 11 07 Environment Free At Last Bon Voyage Time ISSN 0040 781X Retrieved 2021 04 06 a b Mohdin Aamna 2018 11 19 Top film makers back penguin intervention on Attenborough show The Guardian ISSN 0261 3077 Retrieved 2020 05 01 2 000 baby flamingos rescued after being abandoned in South African drought The Guardian 2019 02 07 ISSN 0261 3077 Retrieved 2019 02 09 Zhou Naaman 2019 12 24 Heartbreaking and heartwarming animals rescued from Australia s bushfires devastation The Guardian Retrieved 2021 03 21 Sri Lanka rescues 120 whales after biggest mass stranding The Guardian 2020 11 03 Retrieved 2021 03 16 Trenchard Tommy d Unienville Aurelie Marrier 2021 02 03 Cape cormorants Caring for South Africa s chicks abandoned in wild BBC News Retrieved 2021 02 08 Daly Natasha 2021 02 19 Nearly 5 000 sea turtles rescued from freezing waters on Texas island National Geographic Retrieved 2021 02 19 Abbott Rachel C 2020 02 17 Wildlife Vaccination Growing in Feasibility Cornell Wildlife Health Lab Retrieved 2020 05 30 Questions and answers about immunocontraception The Humane Society of the United States Retrieved 2019 09 09 a b Pearce David 2015 A Welfare State For Elephants A Case Study of Compassionate Stewardship Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 153 164 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 pear Retrieved 8 May 2016 Johannsen Kyle April 2017 Animal Rights and the Problem of r Strategists Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 2 333 345 doi 10 1007 s10677 016 9774 x ISSN 1386 2820 S2CID 151950095 Thornhill Richard Morris Michael 2006 01 01 Animal Liberationist Responses to Non Anthropogenic Animal Suffering PDF Worldviews Global Religions Culture and Ecology 10 3 355 379 doi 10 1163 156853506778942077 ISSN 1363 5247 MacAskill William MacAskill Amanda 9 September 2015 To Truly End Animal Suffering the Most Ethical Choice is To Kill Wild Predators Especially Cecil the Lion Quartz Retrieved 17 April 2016 Grush Loren 2015 09 10 Killing off wild predators is a stupid idea The Verge Retrieved 2019 10 29 Horta Oscar 2010 The Ethics of the Ecology of Fear against the Nonspeciesist Paradigm A Shift in the Aims of Intervention in Nature Between the Species 13 10 163 187 doi 10 15368 bts 2010v13n10 10 Brennan Ozy 2018 05 23 How Pet Owners Can Help Wild Animals And The Environment Wild Animal Suffering Research Archived from the original on 2020 12 04 Retrieved 2021 03 28 John Tyler M Sebo Jeff 2020 Consequentialism and Nonhuman Animals PDF In Portmore Douglas W ed The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism Douglas W Portmore New York NY ISBN 978 0 19 090535 4 OCLC 1154100861 Faria Catia Horta Oscar 2019 Welfare Biology In Fischer Bob ed The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics New York Routledge doi 10 4324 9781315105840 41 ISBN 978 1 315 10584 0 S2CID 241043958 Brennan Ozy 2017 11 25 Creating Welfare Biology A Research Proposal Wild Animal Suffering Research Archived from the original on 2021 07 11 Retrieved 2019 09 09 Salazar Maria 2019 07 31 Why is Welfare Biology Important Animal Charity Evaluators Retrieved 2019 09 09 Matthews Dylan 2021 04 12 The wild frontier of animal welfare Vox Retrieved 2021 09 05 Kovic Marko 2021 02 01 Risks of space colonization Futures 126 102638 doi 10 1016 j futures 2020 102638 ISSN 0016 3287 S2CID 230597480 Eskander P 2018 Crucial considerations in wild animal suffering EA Global 2018 San Francisco Retrieved from https www youtube com watch v qK VNh1AKy0 transcript https forum effectivealtruism org posts DN8WceuyKDqN3m4Jd persis eskander crucial considerations in wild animal O Brien Gary David 2021 Directed Panspermia Wild Animal Suffering and the Ethics of World Creation Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 87 102 doi 10 1111 japp 12538 ISSN 1468 5930 S2CID 237774241 Tomasik Brian 2018 05 20 2014 Will Space Colonization Multiply Wild Animal Suffering Essays on Reducing Suffering Retrieved 2021 10 08 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Sivula Oskari 2022 The Cosmic Significance of Directed Panspermia Should Humanity Spread Life to Other Solar Systems Utilitas 34 2 178 194 doi 10 1017 S095382082100042X ISSN 0953 8208 S2CID 246519996 Vinding Magnus 2020 Suffering Focused Ethics Defense and Implications PDF Ratio Ethica p 249 ISBN 979 8624910911 a b c Brennan Ozy 2019 01 01 Complexity of wild ruminants Animal Sentience 4 25 doi 10 51291 2377 7478 1492 ISSN 2377 7478 Norcross Desli Wildlife Documentaries What Happens to the Limping Gazelle Nature Ethics Retrieved 2019 10 09 Lopatto Elizabeth 2016 08 15 How natural are nature documentaries The Verge Retrieved 2019 10 09 Rustin Susanna 2011 10 21 David Attenborough I m an essential evil The Guardian ISSN 0261 3077 Retrieved 2020 04 19 People who accuse us of putting in too much violence should see what we leave on the cutting room floor Munoz Toni 2019 02 08 La representacion del sufrimiento de los animales silvestres en los documentales de naturaleza The representation of the suffering of wild animals in nature documentaries ElDiario es in Spanish Retrieved 2021 03 25 a b Pearce David 1996 The Post Darwinian Transition The Animal Rights Library Retrieved 2021 03 21 Palmer Clare 2019 12 06 Fischer Bob ed The Laissez Faire View The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics 1 ed Routledge pp 444 454 doi 10 4324 9781315105840 40 ISBN 978 1 315 10584 0 S2CID 212772160 retrieved 2021 03 21 Gentle Louise 2018 11 29 Dynasties should nature documentary crews save the animals they film The Conversation Retrieved 2021 03 25 Mabbott Alastair 2019 12 15 Review My Penguin Year by Lindsay McCrae The Herald Retrieved 2021 03 25 a b Furness Hannah 2016 12 12 Planet Earth II filmmakers defy convention to save lost baby turtles The Telegraph ISSN 0307 1235 Archived from the original on 2017 01 25 Retrieved 2021 03 25 Hamilton William 1979 Melville and the Sea Soundings An Interdisciplinary Journal 62 4 417 429 ISSN 0038 1861 JSTOR 41178134 Andersen Hans Christian Thumbelina The Hans Christian Andersen Centre Retrieved 2021 03 25 Ruiz Javier Herrero 2007 At the crossroads between literature culture linguistics and cognition death metaphors in fairy tales Revista espanola de linguistica aplicada 20 59 84 ISSN 0213 2028 Andersen Hans Christian The Ugly Duckling The Hans Christian Andersen Centre Retrieved 2021 02 24 Lutts Ralph H 1992 10 01 The Trouble with Bambi Walt Disney s Bambi and the American Vision of Nature PDF Forest amp Conservation History 36 4 160 171 doi 10 2307 3983677 ISSN 1046 7009 JSTOR 3983677 S2CID 191482526 Lutts Ralph H October 1992 The Trouble with Bambi Walt Disney s Bambi and the American Vision of Nature Forest and Conservation History 36 4 160 171 doi 10 2307 3983677 JSTOR 3983677 S2CID 191482526 Archived from the original on 2015 11 03 Wyndham John 2000 The Midwich Cuckoos 1st electronic ed New York Rosetta Books p 97 ISBN 978 0 7953 0292 3 OCLC 50737644 a b Adams Richard 2009 Watership Down New York Simon and Schuster p 465 ISBN 978 1 4391 7612 2 Mannino Adriano 2012 01 22 Natur Befreiung und Enhancement Nature Liberation and Enhancement tier im fokus ch in German Retrieved 2021 02 25 Bostrom Nick 1994 Golden Nick Bostrom Retrieved 2021 03 20 Pratchett Terry 2009 Unseen Academicals Random House pp 311 312 ISBN 978 1 4070 4729 4 Lockett Christopher 2021 Death Cruelty and Magical Humanism In Brooks Neil Blanchette Sarah eds Narrative Art and the Politics of Health Anthem Press p 199 ISBN 978 1 78527 711 5 Hawtree Laura Joy September 2011 Wild Animals in Roman Epic PDF PhD thesis University of Exeter pp 72 73 Mackail John William 1906 Select Epigrams from the Greek Anthology London New York Longmans Green p 209 Nicholson Reynold Alleyne 1921 Studies in Islamic Poetry Cambridge University Press p 202 Swift Jonathan 1766 The Works of Dr Jonathan Swift Vol 7 Edinburgh G Hamilton amp J Balfour and L Hunter p 40 Voltaire 1883 Poeme sur le desastre de lisbonne In Moland Louis ed Œuvres completes de Voltaire in French Garnier Voltaire 1912 Poem on the Lisbon Disaster In MacCabe Joseph ed Toleration and Other Essays New York London G P Putnam s Sons pp 258 259 Blackstone Bernard 2015 English Blake Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 83 ISBN 978 1 107 50342 7 OCLC 914164179 Blake William 1915 Pierce Frederick Erastus ed Selections from the Symbolical Poems of William Blake New Haven Yale University Press pp 10 11 a b c Darwin Erasmus 1804 The Temple of Nature Baltimore Bonsal amp Niles Simon Ed 2019 05 29 How Erasmus Darwin s poetry prophesied evolutionary theory Aeon Retrieved 2021 03 20 Gompertz Isaac 1813 The Modern Antique Or The Muse in the Costume of Queen Anne London W Pople p 307 Keats John 1905 De Selincourt Ernest ed The Poems of John Keats New York Dodd Mead amp Co p 272 Hillier Russell M 2014 11 01 A Wondrous Lesson in thy Silent Face Keats Darwin and the Geological Sublime Arcadia 49 2 254 284 doi 10 1515 arcadia 2014 0023 ISSN 1613 0642 Weiss Kenneth M 2010 Nature red in tooth and claw so what PDF Evolutionary Anthropology 19 2 41 45 doi 10 1002 evan 20255 ISSN 1520 6505 S2CID 32999483 Tennyson Alfred 1893 Maud A Monodrama London Kelmscott Press p 11 Arnold Edwin 1900 1879 The Light of Asia Chicago W B Conkey pp 25 26 Stenerson Douglas C Winter 1991 Some impressions of the Buddha Dreiser and Sir Edwin Arnold s the light of Asia Canadian Review of American Studies 22 3 387 405 doi 10 3138 CRAS 022 03 05 S2CID 159914010 Further reading EditMatthews Dylan 2021 04 12 The wild frontier of animal welfare Vox Retrieved 2021 05 15 Introduction to Wild Animal Suffering A Guide to the Key Issues PDF Animal Ethics 2020 Helping animals in the wild bibliography Animal Ethics 2018 08 05 Retrieved 2021 02 18 The situation of animals in the wild bibliography Animal Ethics 2018 08 02 Retrieved 2021 02 18 Publications about wild animal suffering Animal Ethics 2018 04 30 Retrieved 2021 02 18 Dorado Daniel 2015 11 02 Ethical Interventions in the Wild An Annotated Bibliography Relations Beyond Anthropocentrism 3 2 219 238 doi 10 7358 rela 2015 002 dora ISSN 2280 9643 Stafforini Pablo 2013 06 06 Wild animal welfare a bibliography Pablo s miscellany Retrieved 2021 02 18 External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Wild animal suffering Wild Animal Initiative Wild Animal Suffering Animal Ethics Wild animal suffering video course Animal Ethics Timeline of wild animal suffering WildAnimalSuffering org Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Wild animal suffering amp oldid 1135161454, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.