fbpx
Wikipedia

Leo Strauss

Leo Strauss (/strs/ STROWSS, German: [ˈleːoː ˈʃtʁaʊs]; September 20, 1899 – October 18, 1973) was a 20th century German-American scholar of political philosophy who specialized in classical political philosophy. Born in Germany to Jewish parents, Strauss later emigrated from Germany to the United States. He spent much of his career as a professor of political science at the University of Chicago, where he taught several generations of students and published fifteen books.

Leo Strauss

Born(1899-09-20)September 20, 1899
DiedOctober 18, 1973(1973-10-18) (aged 74)
Alma mater
Notable work
SpouseMiriam Bernsohn Strauss
AwardsOrder of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Institutions
ThesisDas Erkenntnisproblem in der philosophischen Lehre Fr. H. Jacobis (On the Problem of Knowledge in the Philosophical Doctrine of F. H. Jacobi) (1921)
Doctoral advisorErnst Cassirer
Main interests
Notable ideas
List

Trained in the neo-Kantian tradition with Ernst Cassirer and immersed in the work of the phenomenologists Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger, Strauss authored books on Spinoza and Hobbes, and articles on Maimonides and Al-Farabi. In the late 1930s, his research focused on the texts of Plato and Aristotle, retracing their interpretation through medieval Islamic and Jewish philosophy, and encouraging the application of those ideas to contemporary political theory.

Biography edit

Early life and education edit

Strauss was born on September 20, 1899, in the small town of Kirchhain in Hesse-Nassau, a province of the Kingdom of Prussia (part of the German Empire), to Hugo Strauss and Jennie Strauss, née David. According to Allan Bloom's 1974 obituary in Political Theory, Strauss "was raised as an Orthodox Jew", but the family does not appear to have completely embraced Orthodox practice.[1] Strauss himself noted that he came from a "conservative, even orthodox Jewish home", but one which knew little about Judaism except strict adherence to ceremonial laws. His father and uncle operated a farm supply and livestock business that they inherited from their father, Meyer (1835–1919), a leading member of the local Jewish community.[2]

After attending the Kirchhain Volksschule and the Protestant Rektoratsschule, Leo Strauss was enrolled at the Gymnasium Philippinum (affiliated with the University of Marburg) in nearby Marburg (from which Johannes Althusius and Carl Joachim Friedrich also graduated) in 1912, graduating in 1917. He boarded with the Marburg cantor Strauss (no relation), whose residence served as a meeting place for followers of the neo-Kantian philosopher Hermann Cohen. Strauss served in the German army from World War I from July 5, 1917, to December 1918.

Strauss subsequently enrolled in the University of Hamburg, where he received his doctorate in 1921; his thesis, On the Problem of Knowledge in the Philosophical Doctrine of F. H. Jacobi (Das Erkenntnisproblem in der philosophischen Lehre Fr. H. Jacobis), was supervised by Ernst Cassirer. He also attended courses at the Universities of Freiburg and Marburg, including some taught by Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger. Strauss joined a Jewish fraternity and worked for the German Zionist movement, which introduced him to various German Jewish intellectuals, such as Norbert Elias, Leo Löwenthal, Hannah Arendt and Walter Benjamin. Benjamin was and remained an admirer of Strauss and his work throughout his life.[3][4][5]

Strauss's closest friend was Jacob Klein but he also was intellectually engaged with Gerhard Krüger—and also Karl Löwith, Julius Guttmann, Hans-Georg Gadamer, and Franz Rosenzweig (to whom Strauss dedicated his first book), as well as Gershom Scholem, Alexander Altmann, and the Arabist Paul Kraus, who married Strauss's sister Bettina (Strauss and his wife later adopted Paul and Bettina Kraus's child when both parents died in the Middle East). With several of these friends, Strauss carried on vigorous epistolary exchanges later in life, many of which are published in the Gesammelte Schriften (Collected Writings), some in translation from the German. Strauss had also been engaged in a discourse with Carl Schmitt. However, after Strauss left Germany, he broke off the discourse when Schmitt failed to respond to his letters.

Career edit

After receiving a Rockefeller Fellowship in 1932, Strauss left his position at the Higher Institute for Jewish Studies in Berlin for Paris. He returned to Germany only once, for a few short days twenty years later. In Paris, he married Marie (Miriam) Bernsohn, a widow with a young child, whom he had known previously in Germany. He adopted his wife's son, Thomas, and later his sister's child, Jenny Strauss Clay (later a professor of classics at the University of Virginia); he and Miriam had no biological children of their own. At his death, he was survived by Thomas, Jenny Strauss Clay, and three grandchildren. Strauss became a lifelong friend of Alexandre Kojève and was on friendly terms with Raymond Aron and Étienne Gilson. Because of the Nazis' rise to power, he chose not to return to his native country. Strauss found shelter, after some vicissitudes, in England, where, in 1935 he gained temporary employment at the University of Cambridge with the help of his in-law David Daube, who was affiliated with Gonville and Caius College. While in England, he became a close friend of R. H. Tawney and was on less friendly terms with Isaiah Berlin.[6]

 
The University of Chicago, the school with which Strauss is most closely associated

Unable to find permanent employment in England, Strauss moved in 1937 to the United States, under the patronage of Harold Laski, who made introductions and helped him obtain a brief lectureship. After a short stint as a research fellow in the Department of History at Columbia University, Strauss secured a position at The New School, where, between 1938 and 1948, he worked in the political science faculty and also took on adjunct jobs.[7] In 1939, he served for a short term as a visiting professor at Hamilton College. He became a U.S. citizen in 1944, and in 1949 became a professor of political science at the University of Chicago, holding the Robert Maynard Hutchins Distinguished Service Professorship until he left in 1969.

In 1953, Strauss coined the phrase reductio ad Hitlerum, a play on reductio ad absurdum, suggesting that comparing an argument to one of Hitler's, or "playing the Nazi card", is often a fallacy of irrelevance.[8]

In 1954 he met Karl Löwith and Hans-Georg Gadamer in Heidelberg and delivered a public speech on Socrates. He had received a call for a temporary lectureship in Hamburg in 1965 (which he declined for health reasons) and received and accepted an honorary doctorate from the University of Hamburg and the Bundesverdienstkreuz (German Order of Merit) via the German representative in Chicago. In 1969 Strauss moved to Claremont McKenna College (formerly Claremont Men's College) in California for a year, and then to St. John's College, Annapolis in 1970, where he was the Scott Buchanan Distinguished Scholar in Residence until his death from pneumonia in 1973.[9] He was buried in Annapolis Hebrew Cemetery, with his wife Miriam Bernsohn Strauss, who died in 1985. Psalm 114 was read in the funeral service at the request of family and friends.[10]

Thought edit

Strauss's thought can be characterized by two main themes: the critique of modernity and the recovery of classical political philosophy. He argued that modernity, which began with the Enlightenment, was a radical break from the tradition of Western civilization, and that it led to a crisis of nihilism, relativism, historicism, and scientism. He claimed that modern political and social sciences, which were based on empirical observation and rational analysis, failed to grasp the essential questions of human nature, morality, and justice, and that they reduced human beings to mere objects of manipulation and calculation. He also criticized modern liberalism, which he saw as a product of modernity, for its lack of moral and spiritual foundations, and for its tendency to undermine the authority of religion, tradition, and natural law.[11][12]

To overcome the crisis of modernity, Strauss proposed a return to the classical political philosophy of the ancient Greeks and the medieval thinkers, who he believed had a deeper and more comprehensive understanding of human nature and society. He advocated a careful and respectful reading of the classical texts, arguing that their authors wrote in an esoteric manner, which he called "the art of writing" and which he practiced in his own works. He suggested that the classical authors hid their true teachings behind a surface layer of conventional opinions, in order to avoid persecution and to educate only the few who were capable of grasping them, and that they engaged in a dialogue with each other across the ages. Strauss called this dialogue "the great conversation", and invited his readers to join it.[11][12]

Strauss's interpretation of the classical political philosophy was influenced by his own Jewish background and his encounter with Islamic and Jewish medieval philosophy, especially the works of Al-Farabi and Maimonides. He argued that these philosophers, who lived under the rule of Islam, faced similar challenges as the ancient Greeks. He also claimed that these philosophers, who were both faithful to their revealed religions and loyal to the rational pursuit of philosophy, offered a model of how to reconcile reason and revelation, philosophy and theology, Athens and Jerusalem.[11][12]

Views edit

Philosophy edit

For Strauss, politics and philosophy were necessarily intertwined. He regarded the trial and death of Socrates as the moment when political philosophy came into existence. Strauss considered one of the most important moments in the history of philosophy Socrates' argument that philosophers could not study nature without considering their own human nature,[13] which, in the words of Aristotle, is that of "a political animal."[14] However, he also held that the ends of politics and philosophy were inherently irreconcilable and irreducible to one another.[15][16]

Strauss distinguished "scholars" from "great thinkers," identifying himself as a scholar. He wrote that most self-described philosophers are in actuality scholars, cautious and methodical. Great thinkers, in contrast, boldly and creatively address big problems. Scholars deal with these problems only indirectly by reasoning about the great thinkers' differences.[17]

In Natural Right and History Strauss begins with a critique of Max Weber's epistemology, briefly engages the relativism of Martin Heidegger (who goes unnamed) and continues with a discussion of the evolution of natural rights via an analysis of the thought of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke. He concludes by critiquing Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Edmund Burke. At the heart of the book are excerpts from Plato, Aristotle, and Cicero. Much of his philosophy is a reaction to the works of Heidegger. Indeed, Strauss wrote that Heidegger's thinking must be understood and confronted before any complete formulation of modern political theory is possible, and this means that political thought has to engage with issues of ontology and the history of metaphysics.[18]

Strauss wrote that Friedrich Nietzsche was the first philosopher to properly understand historicism, an idea grounded in a general acceptance of Hegelian philosophy of history. Heidegger, in Strauss's view, sanitized and politicized Nietzsche, whereas Nietzsche believed "our own principles, including the belief in progress, will become as unconvincing and alien as all earlier principles (essences) had shown themselves to be" and "the only way out seems to be ... that one voluntarily choose life-giving delusion instead of deadly truth, that one fabricate a myth."[19] Heidegger believed that the tragic nihilism of Nietzsche was itself a "myth" guided by a defective Western conception of Being that Heidegger traced to Plato. In his published correspondence with Alexandre Kojève, Strauss wrote that Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel was correct when he postulated that an end of history implies an end to philosophy as understood by classical political philosophy.[20]

On reading edit

 
Strauss's study of philosophy and political discourses produced by the Islamic civilization — especially those of Al-Farabi (shown here) and Maimonides — was instrumental in the development of his theory of reading.

In the late 1930s, Strauss called for the first time for a reconsideration of the "distinction between exoteric (or public) and esoteric (or secret) teaching."[21] In 1952 he published Persecution and the Art of Writing, arguing that serious writers write esoterically, that is, with multiple or layered meanings, often disguised within irony or paradox, obscure references, even deliberate self-contradiction. Esoteric writing serves several purposes: protecting the philosopher from the retribution of the regime, and protecting the regime from the corrosion of philosophy; it attracts the right kind of reader and repels the wrong kind; and ferreting out the interior message is in itself an exercise of philosophic reasoning.[22][23][24]

Taking his bearings from his study of Maimonides and Al-Farabi, and pointing further back to Plato's discussion of writing as contained in the Phaedrus, Strauss proposed that the classical and medieval art of esoteric writing is the proper medium for philosophic learning: rather than displaying philosophers' thoughts superficially, classical and medieval philosophical texts guide their readers in thinking and learning independently of imparted knowledge. Thus, Strauss agrees with the Socrates of the Phaedrus, where the Greek indicates that, insofar as writing does not respond when questioned, good writing provokes questions in the reader—questions that orient the reader towards an understanding of problems the author thought about with utmost seriousness. Strauss thus, in Persecution and the Art of Writing, presents Maimonides "as a closet nonbeliever obfuscating his message for political reasons".[25]

Strauss's hermeneutical argument[26]—rearticulated throughout his subsequent writings (most notably in The City and Man [1964])—is that, before the 19th century, Western scholars commonly understood that philosophical writing is not at home in any polity, no matter how liberal. Insofar as it questions conventional wisdom at its roots, philosophy must guard itself especially against those readers who believe themselves authoritative, wise, and liberal defenders of the status quo. In questioning established opinions, or in investigating the principles of morality, philosophers of old found it necessary to convey their messages in an oblique manner. Their "art of writing" was the art of esoteric communication. This was especially apparent in medieval times when heterodox political thinkers wrote under the threat of the Inquisition or comparably obtuse tribunals.

Strauss's argument is not that the medieval writers he studies reserved one exoteric meaning for the many (hoi polloi) and an esoteric, hidden one for the few (hoi oligoi), but that, through rhetorical stratagems including self-contradiction and hyperboles, these writers succeeded in conveying their proper meaning at the tacit heart of their writings—a heart or message irreducible to "the letter" or historical dimension of texts.

Explicitly following Gotthold Ephraim Lessing's lead, Strauss indicates that medieval political philosophers, no less than their ancient counterparts, carefully adapted their wording to the dominant moral views of their time, lest their writings be condemned as heretical or unjust, not by "the many" (who did not read), but by those "few" whom the many regarded as the most righteous guardians of morality. It was precisely these righteous personalities who would be most inclined to persecute/ostracize anyone who was in the business of exposing the noble or great lie upon which the authority of the few over the many stands or falls.[27]

On politics edit

According to Strauss, modern social science is flawed because it assumes the fact–value distinction, a concept which Strauss found dubious. He traced its roots in Enlightenment philosophy to Max Weber, a thinker whom Strauss described as a "serious and noble mind". Weber wanted to separate values from science but, according to Strauss, was really a derivative thinker, deeply influenced by Nietzsche's relativism.[28] Strauss treated politics as something that could not be studied from afar. A political scientist examining politics with a value-free scientific eye, for Strauss, was self-deluded. Positivism, the heir to both Auguste Comte and Max Weber in the quest to make purportedly value-free judgments, failed to justify its own existence, which would require a value judgment.[29]

While modern-era liberalism had stressed the pursuit of individual liberty as its highest goal, Strauss felt that there should be a greater interest in the problem of human excellence and political virtue. Through his writings, Strauss constantly raised the question of how, and to what extent, freedom and excellence can coexist. Strauss refused to make do with any simplistic or one-sided resolutions of the Socratic question: What is the good for the city and man?[30]

Encounters with Carl Schmitt and Alexandre Kojève edit

Two significant political-philosophical dialogues Strauss had with living thinkers were those he held with Carl Schmitt and Alexandre Kojève. Schmitt, who would later become, for a short time, the chief jurist of Nazi Germany, was one of the first important German academics to review Strauss's early work positively. Schmitt's positive reference for, and approval of, Strauss's work on Hobbes was instrumental in winning Strauss the scholarship funding that allowed him to leave Germany.[31]

Strauss's critique and clarifications of The Concept of the Political led Schmitt to make significant emendations in its second edition. Writing to Schmitt in 1932, Strauss summarised Schmitt's political theology that "because man is by nature evil, he, therefore, needs dominion. But dominion can be established, that is, men can be unified only in a unity against—against other men. Every association of men is necessarily a separation from other men ... the political thus understood is not the constitutive principle of the state, of order, but a condition of the state."[32]

Strauss, however, directly opposed Schmitt's position. For Strauss, Schmitt and his return to Thomas Hobbes helpfully clarified the nature of our political existence and our modern self-understanding. Schmitt's position was therefore symptomatic of the modern-era liberal self-understanding. Strauss believed that such an analysis, as in Hobbes's time, served as a useful "preparatory action," revealing our contemporary orientation towards the eternal problems of politics (social existence). However, Strauss believed that Schmitt's reification of our modern self-understanding of the problem of politics into a political theology was not an adequate solution. Strauss instead advocated a return to a broader classical understanding of human nature and a tentative return to political philosophy, in the tradition of the ancient philosophers.[33]

With Kojève, Strauss had a close and lifelong philosophical friendship. They had first met as students in Berlin. The two thinkers shared boundless philosophical respect for each other. Kojève would later write that, without befriending Strauss, "I never would have known ... what philosophy is".[34] The political-philosophical dispute between Kojève and Strauss centered on the role that philosophy should and can be allowed to play in politics.

Kojève, a senior civil servant in the French government, was instrumental in the creation of the European Economic Community. He argued that philosophers should have an active role in shaping political events. Strauss, on the contrary, believed that philosophers should play a role in politics only to the extent that they can ensure that philosophy, which he saw as mankind's highest activity, can be free from political intervention.[35]

Liberalism and nihilism edit

Strauss argued that liberalism in its modern form (which is oriented toward universal freedom as opposed to "ancient liberalism" which is oriented toward human excellence), contained within it an intrinsic tendency towards extreme relativism, which in turn led to two types of nihilism:[36]

The first was a "brutal" nihilism, expressed in Nazi and Bolshevik regimes. In On Tyranny, he wrote that these ideologies, both descendants of Enlightenment thought, tried to destroy all traditions, history, ethics, and moral standards and replace them by force under which nature and mankind are subjugated and conquered.[37] The second type—the "gentle" nihilism expressed in Western liberal democracies—was a kind of value-free aimlessness and a hedonistic "permissive egalitarianism," which he saw as permeating the fabric of contemporary American society.[38][39]

In the belief that 20th-century relativism, scientism, historicism, and nihilism were all implicated in the deterioration of modern society and philosophy, Strauss sought to uncover the philosophical pathways that had led to this situation. The resultant study led him to advocate a tentative return to classical political philosophy as a starting point for judging political action.[40]

Strauss's interpretation of Plato's Republic edit

According to Strauss, the Republic by Plato is not "a blueprint for regime reform" (a play on words from Karl Popper's The Open Society and Its Enemies, which attacks The Republic for being just that). Strauss quotes Cicero: "The Republic does not bring to light the best possible regime but rather the nature of political things—the nature of the city."[41]

Strauss argued that the city-in-speech was unnatural, precisely because "it is rendered possible by the abstraction from eros".[42] Though skeptical of "progress," Strauss was equally skeptical about political agendas of "return"—that is, going backward instead of forward.

In fact, he was consistently suspicious of anything claiming to be a solution to an old political or philosophical problem. He spoke of the danger in trying finally to resolve the debate between rationalism and traditionalism in politics. In particular, along with many in the pre-World War II German Right, he feared people trying to force a world state to come into being in the future, thinking that it would inevitably become a tyranny.[43] Hence he kept his distance from the two totalitarianisms that he denounced in his century, both fascists and communists.

Strauss and Karl Popper edit

Strauss actively rejected Karl Popper's views as illogical. He agreed with a letter of response to his request of Eric Voegelin to look into the issue. In the response, Voegelin wrote that studying Popper's views was a waste of precious time, and "an annoyance". Specifically about The Open Society and Its Enemies and Popper's understanding of Plato's The Republic, after giving some examples, Voegelin wrote:

Popper is philosophically so uncultured, so fully a primitive ideological brawler, that he is not able to even approximately to reproduce correctly the contents of one page of Plato. Reading is of no use to him; he is too lacking in knowledge to understand what the author says.[misquoted][44]

Strauss proceeded to show this letter to Kurt Riezler, who used his influence in order to oppose Popper's appointment at the University of Chicago.[45]

Ancients and Moderns edit

Strauss constantly stressed the importance of two dichotomies in political philosophy, namely Athens and Jerusalem (reason and revelation) and Ancient versus Modern. The "Ancients" were the Socratic philosophers and their intellectual heirs; the "Moderns" start with Niccolò Machiavelli. The contrast between Ancients and Moderns was understood to be related to the unresolvable tension between Reason and Revelation. The Socratics, reacting to the first Greek philosophers, brought philosophy back to earth, and hence back to the marketplace, making it more political.[46]

The Moderns reacted to the dominance of revelation in medieval society by promoting the possibilities of Reason. They objected to Aquinas's merger of natural right and natural theology, for it made natural right vulnerable to sideshow theological disputes.[47] Thomas Hobbes, under the influence of Francis Bacon, re-oriented political thought to what was most solid but also most low in man—his physical hopes and fears—setting a precedent for John Locke and the later economic approach to political thought, as in David Hume and Adam Smith.[48]

Strauss and Zionism edit

As a youth, Strauss belonged to the German Zionist youth group, along with his friends Gershom Scholem and Walter Benjamin. Both were admirers of Strauss and would continue to be throughout their lives.[49] When he was 17, as he said, he was "converted" to political Zionism as a follower of Ze'ev Jabotinsky. He wrote several essays about its controversies but left these activities behind by his early twenties.[50]

While Strauss maintained a sympathetic interest in Zionism, he later came to refer to Zionism as "problematic" and became disillusioned with some of its aims.

He taught at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem during the 1954–55 academic year. In his letter to a National Review editor, Strauss asked why Israel had been called a racist state by one of their writers. He argued that the author did not provide enough proof for his argument. He ended his essay with this statement: "Political Zionism is problematic for obvious reasons. But I can never forget what it achieved as a moral force in an era of complete dissolution. It helped to stem the tide of 'progressive' leveling of venerable, ancestral differences; it fulfilled a conservative function."[51]

Religious belief edit

Although Strauss accepted the utility of religious belief, there is some question about his religious views. He was openly disdainful of atheism[52][better source needed] and disapproved of contemporary dogmatic disbelief, which he considered intemperate and irrational.[53] However, like Thomas Aquinas, he felt that revelation must be subject to examination by reason.[54] At the end of The City and Man, Strauss invites us to "be open to ... the question quid sit deus ["What is God?"]" (p. 241). Edward Feser writes that "Strauss was not himself an orthodox believer, neither was he a convinced atheist. Since whether or not to accept a purported divine revelation is itself one of the 'permanent' questions, orthodoxy must always remain an option equally as defensible as unbelief."[55]

In Natural Right and History Strauss distinguishes a Socratic (Platonic, Ciceronian, Aristotelian) from a conventionalist (materialistic, Epicurean) reading of divinity, and argues that "the question of religion" (what is religion?) is inseparable from the question of the nature of civil society and civil authority. Throughout the volume he argues for the Socratic reading of civil authority and rejects the conventionalist reading (of which atheism is an essential component).[56] This is incompatible with interpretations by Shadia Drury and other scholars who argue that Strauss viewed religion purely instrumentally.[57][58]

Reception and legacy edit

Reception by contemporaries edit

Strauss's works were read and admired by thinkers as diverse as the philosophers Gershom Scholem, Walter Benjamin,[49] Hans-Georg Gadamer,[59] and Alexandre Kojève,[59] and the psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan.[59] Benjamin had become acquainted with Strauss as a student in Berlin, and expressed admiration for Strauss throughout his life.[3][4][5] Gadamer stated that he 'largely agreed' with Strauss's interpretations.[59]

The Straussian school edit

Straussianism is the name given "to denote the research methods, common concepts, theoretical presuppositions, central questions, and pedagogic style (teaching style[60]) characteristic of the large number of conservatives who have been influenced by the thought and teaching of Leo Strauss".[61] While it "is particularly influential among university professors of historical political theory ... it also sometimes serves as a common intellectual framework more generally among conservative activists, think tank professionals, and public intellectuals".[61] Harvey C. Mansfield, Steven B. Smith and Steven Berg, though never students of Strauss, are "Straussians" (as some followers of Strauss identify themselves). Mansfield has argued that there is no such thing as "Straussianism" yet there are Straussians and a school of Straussians. Mansfield describes the school as "open to the whole of philosophy" and without any definite doctrines that one has to believe in order to belong to it.[62]

Within the discipline of political theory, the method calls for its practitioners to use "a 'close reading' of the 'Great Books' of political thought; they strive to understand a thinker 'as he understood himself'; they are unconcerned with questions about the historical context of, or historical influences on, a given author"[61] and strive to be open to the idea that they may find something timelessly true in a great book. The approach "resembles in important ways the old New Criticism in literary studies."[61]

There is some controversy in the approach over what distinguishes a great book from lesser works. Great books are held to be written by authors/philosophers "of such sovereign critical self-knowledge and intellectual power that they can in no way be reduced to the general thought of their time and place,"[61] with other works "understood as epiphenomenal to the original insights of a thinker of the first rank."[61] This approach is seen as a counter "to the historicist presuppositions of the mid-twentieth century, which read the history of political thought in a progressivist way, with past philosophies forever cut off from us in a superseded past."[61] Straussianism puts forward the possibility that past thinkers may have "hold of the truth—and that more recent thinkers are therefore wrong."[61]

The Chinese Straussians edit

Almost the entirety of Strauss's writings has been translated into Chinese; and there even is a school of Straussians in China, the most prominent being Liu Xiaofeng (Renmin University) and Gan Yang. "Chinese Straussians" (who often are also fascinated by Carl Schmitt) represent a remarkable example of the hybridization of Western political theory in a non-Western context. As the editors of a recent volume write, "the reception of Schmitt and Strauss in the Chinese-speaking world (and especially in the People's Republic of China) not only says much about how Schmitt and Strauss can be read today, but also provides important clues about the deeper contradictions of Western modernity and the dilemmas of non-liberal societies in our increasingly contentious world."[63]

Criticism edit

Basis for esotericism edit

In the essay, Persecution and the Art of Writing, Strauss posits that information needs to be kept secret from the masses by "writing between the lines". However, this seems like a false premise, as most authors Strauss refers to in his work lived in times when only the social elites were literate enough to understand works of philosophy.[64]

Conservatism edit

Some critics of Strauss have accused him of being elitist, illiberal and anti-democratic. Journalists such as Seymour Hersh have opined that Strauss endorsed noble lies, "myths used by political leaders seeking to maintain a cohesive society".[65][66] In The City and Man, Strauss discusses the myths outlined in Plato's Republic that are required for all governments. These include a belief that the state's land belongs to it even though it may have been acquired illegitimately and that citizenship is rooted in something more than accidents of birth.[67]

Shadia Drury, in Leo Strauss and the American Right (1999), claimed that Strauss inculcated an elitist strain in American political leaders linked to imperialist militarism, neoconservatism and Christian fundamentalism. Drury argues that Strauss teaches that "perpetual deception of the citizens by those in power is critical because they need to be led, and they need strong rulers to tell them what's good for them". Nicholas Xenos similarly argues that Strauss was "an anti-democrat in a fundamental sense, a true reactionary". Xenos says: "Strauss was somebody who wanted to go back to a previous, pre-liberal, pre-bourgeois era of blood and guts, of imperial domination, of authoritarian rule, of pure fascism."[68]

Anti-historicism edit

Strauss has also been criticized by some conservatives. According to Claes G. Ryn, Strauss's anti-historicist thinking creates an artificial contrast between moral universality and "the conventional", "the ancestral", and "the historical". Strauss, Ryn argues, wrongly and reductively assumes that respect for tradition must undermine reason and universality. Contrary to Strauss's criticism of Edmund Burke, the historical sense may be indispensable to an adequate apprehension of universality. Strauss's abstract, ahistorical conception of natural right distorts genuine universality, Ryn contends. Strauss does not consider the possibility that real universality becomes known to human beings in a concretized, particular form. Strauss and the Straussians have paradoxically taught philosophically unsuspecting American conservatives, not least Roman Catholic intellectuals, to reject tradition in favor of ahistorical theorizing, a bias that flies in the face of the central Christian notion of the Incarnation, which represents a synthesis of the universal and the historical. According to Ryn, the propagation of a purely abstract idea of universality has contributed to the neoconservative advocacy of allegedly universal American principles, which neoconservatives see as justification for American intervention around the world—bringing the blessings of the "West" to the benighted "rest". Strauss's anti-historical thinking connects him and his followers with the French Jacobins, who also regarded tradition as incompatible with virtue and rationality.[69]

What Ryn calls the "new Jacobinism" of the "neoconservative" philosophy is, writes Paul Gottfried, also the rhetoric of Saint-Just and Leon Trotsky, which the philosophically impoverished American Right has taken over with mindless alacrity; Republican operators and think tanks apparently believe they can carry the electorate by appealing to yesterday's leftist clichés.[70][71]

Response to criticism edit

In his 2009 book, Straussophobia, Peter Minowitz provides a detailed critique of Drury, Xenos, and other critics of Strauss whom he accuses of "bigotry and buffoonery".[72]

In Reading Leo Strauss, Steven B. Smith rejects the link between Strauss and neoconservative thought, arguing that Strauss was never personally active in politics, never endorsed imperialism, and questioned the utility of political philosophy for the practice of politics. In particular, Strauss argued that Plato's myth of the philosopher king should be read as a reductio ad absurdum, and that philosophers should understand politics not in order to influence policy but to ensure philosophy's autonomy from politics.[73] In his review of Reading Leo Strauss, Robert Alter writes that Smith "persuasively sets the record straight on Strauss's political views and on what his writing is really about".[74]

Strauss's daughter, Jenny Strauss Clay, defended Strauss against the charge that he was the "mastermind behind the neoconservative ideologues who control United States foreign policy." "He was a conservative", she says, "insofar as he did not think change is necessarily change for the better." Since contemporary academia "leaned to the left", with its "unquestioned faith in progress and science combined with a queasiness regarding any kind of moral judgment", Strauss stood outside of the academic consensus. Had academia leaned to the right, he would have questioned it, too—and on certain occasions did question the tenets of the right.[75]

Mark Lilla has argued that the attribution to Strauss of neoconservative views contradicts a careful reading of Strauss' actual texts, in particular On Tyranny. Lilla summarizes Strauss as follows:

Philosophy must always be aware of the dangers of tyranny, as a threat to both political decency and the philosophical life. It must understand enough about politics to defend its own autonomy, without falling into the error of thinking that philosophy can shape the political world according to its own lights.[76]

Responding to charges that Strauss's teachings fostered the neoconservative foreign policy of the George W. Bush administration, such as "unrealistic hopes for the spread of liberal democracy through military conquest", Nathan Tarcov, director of the Leo Strauss Center at the University of Chicago, asserts that Strauss as a political philosopher was essentially non-political. After an exegesis of the very limited practical political views to be gleaned from Strauss's writings, Tarcov concludes that "Strauss can remind us of the permanent problems, but we have only ourselves to blame for our faulty solutions to the problems of today."[77]

Bibliography edit

Books and articles
  • Gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Heinrich Meier. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler, 1996. Four vols. published to date: Vol. 1, Die Religionskritik Spinozas und zugehörige Schriften (rev. ed. 2001); vol. 2, Philosophie und Gesetz, Frühe Schriften (1997); Vol. 3, Hobbes' politische Wissenschaft und zugehörige Schrifte – Briefe (2001); Vol. 4, Politische Philosophie. Studien zum theologisch-politischen Problem (2010). The full series will also include Vol. 5, Über Tyrannis (2013) and Vol. 6, Gedanken über Machiavelli. Deutsche Erstübersetzung (2014).
  • Leo Strauss: The Early Writings (1921–1932). (Trans. from parts of Gesammelte Schriften). Trans. Michael Zank. Albany: SUNY Press, 2002.
  • Die Religionskritik Spinozas als Grundlage seiner Bibelwissenschaft: Untersuchungen zu Spinozas Theologisch-politischem Traktat. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1930.
    • Spinoza's Critique of Religion. (English trans. by Elsa M. Sinclair of Die Religionskritik Spinozas, 1930.) With a new English preface and a trans. of Strauss's 1932 German essay on Carl Schmitt. New York: Schocken, 1965. Reissued without that essay, Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1997.
  • "Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitt, Der Begriff des Politischen". Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 67, no. 6 (August–September 1932): 732–49.
    • "Comments on Carl Schmitt's Begriff des Politischen". (English trans. by Elsa M. Sinclair of "Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitt", 1932.) 331–51 in Spinoza's Critique of Religion, 1965. Reprinted in Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, ed. and trans. George Schwab. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers U Press, 1976.
    • "Notes on Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political". (English trans. by J. Harvey Lomax of "Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitt", 1932.) In Heinrich Meier, Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: The Hidden Dialogue, trans. J. Harvey Lomax. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1995. Reprinted in Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, ed. and trans. George Schwab. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1996, 2007.
  • Philosophie und Gesetz: Beiträge zum Verständnis Maimunis und seiner Vorläufer. Berlin: Schocken, 1935.
    • Philosophy and Law: Essays Toward the Understanding of Maimonides and His Predecessors. (English trans. by Fred Baumann of Philosophie und Gesetz, 1935.) Philadelphia: Jewish Publication Society, 1987.
    • Philosophy and Law: Contributions to the Understanding of Maimonides and His Predecessors. (English trans. with introd. by Eve Adler of Philosophie und Gesetz, 1935.) Albany: SUNY Press, 1995.
  • The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: Its Basis and Its Genesis. (English trans. by Elsa M. Sinclair from German manuscript.) Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936. Reissued with new preface, Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1952.
    • Hobbes' politische Wissenschaft in ihrer Genesis. (1935 German original of The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, 1936.) Neuwied am Rhein: Hermann Luchterhand, 1965.
  • "The Spirit of Sparta or the Taste of Xenophon". Social Research 6, no. 4 (Winter 1939): 502–36.
  • "On German Nihilism" (1999, originally a 1941 lecture), Interpretation 26, no. 3 edited by David Janssens and Daniel Tanguay.
  • "Farabi's Plato" American Academy for Jewish Research, Louis Ginzberg Jubilee Volume, 1945. 45 pp.
  • "On a New Interpretation of Plato's Political Philosophy". Social Research 13, no. 3 (Fall 1946): 326–67.
  • "On the Intention of Rousseau". Social Research 14, no. 4 (Winter 1947): 455–87.
  • On Tyranny: An Interpretation of Xenophon's Hiero. Foreword by Alvin Johnson. New York: Political Science Classics, 1948. Reissued Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1950.
    • De la tyrannie. (French trans. of On Tyranny, 1948, with "Restatement on Xenophon's Hiero" and Alexandre Kojève's "Tyranny and Wisdom".) Paris: Librairie Gallimard, 1954.
    • On Tyranny. (English edition of De la tyrannie, 1954.) Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1963.
    • On Tyranny. (Revised and expanded edition of On Tyranny, 1963.) Includes Strauss–Kojève correspondence. Ed. Victor Gourevitch and Michael S. Roth. New York: The Free Press, 1991.
  • "On Collingwood’s Philosophy of History". Review of Metaphysics 5, no. 4 (June 1952): 559–86.
  • Persecution and the Art of Writing. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1952. Reissued Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1988.
  • Natural Right and History. (Based on the 1949 Walgreen lectures.) Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1953. Reprinted with new preface, 1971. ISBN 978-0-226-77694-1.
  • "Existentialism" (1956), a public lecture on Martin Heidegger's thought, published in Interpretation, Spring 1995, Vol.22 No. 3: 303–18.
  • Seminar on Plato's Republic, (1957 Lecture), (1961 Lecture). University of Chicago.
  • Thoughts on Machiavelli. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1958. Reissued Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1978.
  • What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Studies. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1959. Reissued Chicago: U of Chicago Press, 1988.
  • On Plato's Symposium [1959]. Ed. Seth Benardete. (Edited transcript of 1959 lectures.) Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2001.
  • "'Relativism'". 135–57 in Helmut Schoeck and James W. Wiggins, eds., Relativism and the Study of Man. Princeton: D. Van Nostrand, 1961. Partial reprint, 13–26 in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, 1989.
  • History of Political Philosophy. Co-editor with Joseph Cropsey. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1963 (1st ed.), 1972 (2nd ed.), 1987 (3rd ed.).
  • "The Crisis of Our Time", 41–54, and "The Crisis of Political Philosophy", 91–103, in Howard Spaeth, ed., The Predicament of Modern Politics. Detroit: U of Detroit P, 1964.
    • "Political Philosophy and the Crisis of Our Time". (Adaptation of the two essays in Howard Spaeth, ed., The Predicament of Modern Politics, 1964.) 217–42 in George J. Graham, Jr., and George W. Carey, eds., The Post-Behavioral Era: Perspectives on Political Science. New York: David McKay, 1972.
  • The City and Man. (Based on the 1962 Page-Barbour lectures.) Chicago: Rand McNally, 1964.
  • Socrates and Aristophanes. New York: Basic Books, 1966. Reissued Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1980.
  • Liberalism Ancient and Modern. New York: Basic Books, 1968. Reissued with foreword by Allan Bloom, 1989. Reissued Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1995.
  • Xenophon's Socratic Discourse: An Interpretation of the Oeconomicus. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1970.
  • Note on the Plan of Nietzsche's "Beyond Good & Evil". St. John's College, 1971.
  • Xenophon's Socrates. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1972.
  • The Argument and the Action of Plato's Laws. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1975.
  • Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss. Ed. Hilail Gilden. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975.
    • An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. (Expanded version of Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, 1975.) Ed. Hilail Gilden. Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1989.
  • Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy. Introd. by Thomas L. Pangle. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1983.
  • The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism: An Introduction to the Thought of Leo Strauss – Essays and Lectures by Leo Strauss. Ed. Thomas L. Pangle. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1989.
  • Faith and Political Philosophy: the Correspondence Between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin, 1934–1964. Ed. Peter Emberley and Barry Cooper. Introd. by Thomas L. Pangle. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State UP, 1993.
  • Hobbes's Critique of Religion and Related Writings. Ed. and trans. Gabriel Bartlett and Svetozar Minkov. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2011. (Trans. of materials first published in the Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 3, including an unfinished manuscript by Leo Strauss of a book on Hobbes, written in 1933–1934, and some shorter related writings.)
  • Leo Strauss on Moses Mendelssohn. Edited and translated by Martin D. Yaffe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012. (Annotated translation of ten introductions written by Strauss to a multi-volume critical edition of Mendelssohn's work.)
  • "Exoteric Teaching" (Critical Edition by Hannes Kerber). In Reorientation: Leo Strauss in the 1930s. Edited by Martin D. Yaffe and Richard S. Ruderman. New York: Palgrave, 2014, pp. 275–86.
  • "Lecture Notes for 'Persecution and the Art of Writing'" (Critical Edition by Hannes Kerber). In Reorientation: Leo Strauss in the 1930s. Edited by Martin D. Yaffe and Richard S. Ruderman. New York: Palgrave, 2014, pp. 293–304.
  • Leo Strauss on Nietzsche’s “Thus Spoke Zarathustra”. Edited by Richard L. Velkley. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2017.
  • Leo Strauss on Political Philosophy: Responding to the Challenge of Positivism and Historicism. Edited by Catherine H. Zuckert. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018.
  • Leo Strauss on Hegel. Edited by Paul Franco. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2019.
Writings about Maimonides and Jewish philosophy
  • Spinoza's Critique of Religion (see above, 1930).
  • Philosophy and Law (see above, 1935).
  • "Quelques remarques sur la science politique de Maïmonide et de Farabi". Revue des études juives 100 (1936): 1–37.
  • "Der Ort der Vorsehungslehre nach der Ansicht Maimunis". Monatschrift für Geschichte und Wissenschaft des Judentums 81 (1936): 448–56.
  • "The Literary Character of The Guide for the Perplexed" [1941]. 38–94 in Persecution and the Art of Writing. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1952.
  • [1944] "How to Study Medieval Philosophy" [. Interpretation 23, no. 3 (Spring 1996): 319–338. Previously published, less annotations and fifth paragraph, as "How to Begin to Study Medieval Philosophy" in Pangle (ed.), The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, 1989 (see above).
  • [1952]. Modern Judaism 1, no. 1 (May 1981): 17–45. Reprinted Chap. 1 (I–II) in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, 1997 (see below).
  • [1952]. Independent Journal of Philosophy 3 (1979), 111–18. Reprinted Chap. 1 (III) in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, 1997 (see below).
  • "Maimonides' Statement on Political Science". Proceedings of the American Academy for Jewish Research 22 (1953): 115–30.
  • [1957]. L'Homme 21, n° 1 (janvier–mars 1981): 5–20. Reprinted Chap. 8 in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, 1997 (see below).
  • "How to Begin to Study The Guide of the Perplexed". In The Guide of the Perplexed, Volume One. Trans. Shlomo Pines. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1963.
  • [1965] "On the Plan of the Guide of the Perplexed" . Harry Austryn Wolfson Jubilee. Volume (Jerusalem: American Academy for Jewish Research), pp. 775–91.
  • "Notes on Maimonides' Book of Knowledge". 269–83 in Studies in Mysticism and Religion Presented to G. G. Scholem. Jerusalem: Magnes Press, 1967.
  • Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity: Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought. Ed. Kenneth Hart Green. Albany: SUNY P, 1997.
  • Leo Strauss on Maimonides: The Complete Writings. Edited by Kenneth Hart Green. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Joachim Lüders and Ariane Wehner, Mittelhessen – eine Heimat für Juden? Das Schicksal der Familie Strauss aus Kirchhain (Central Hesse – a Homeland for Jews? The Fate of the Strauss Family from Kirchhain) 1989.
  2. ^ In "A Giving of Accounts", published in The College 22 (1) and later reprinted in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity.
  3. ^ a b Jewish philosophy and the crisis of modernity (SUNY 1997), Leo Strauss as a Modern Jewish thinker, Kenneth Hart Green, Leo Strauss, page 55
  4. ^ a b Scholem, Gershom. 1981. Walter Benjamin: The Story of a Friendship. Trans. Harry Zohn, p. 201
  5. ^ a b The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin and Gershom Scholem, 1932–40, New York 1989, pp. 155–58
  6. ^ Leo Strauss And the Politics of Exile: The Making of a Political Philosopher p. 87
  7. ^ Eugene Sheppard (2014). Leo Strauss and the Politics of Exile: The Making of a Political Philosopher. Brandeis UP. pp. 102–03. ISBN 9781611687699.
  8. ^ Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1965 [1953], p. 42.
  9. ^ Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity: Essays and Lectures in Modernity preface p. 6.
  10. ^ "Leo Strauss". from the original on 2021-01-17. Retrieved 2020-12-02.
  11. ^ a b c Leora Batnitzky, Leo Strauss, the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 9 April 2021.
  12. ^ a b c Shadia Drury (1998). Strauss, Leo (1899–1973). In The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor and Francis. Retrieved 30 Dec. 2023. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-S092-1
  13. ^ Laurence Lampert, The Enduring Importance of Leo Strauss, University of Chicago Press, 2013, p. 126.
  14. ^ "From these things it is evident, that the city belongs among the things that exist by nature, and that man is by nature a political animal" (Aristotle, The Politics, 1253a1–3).
  15. ^ Steven B. Smith, Reading Leo Strauss: Politics, Philosophy, Judaism, University of Chicago Press, 2007, p. 13.
  16. ^ Pangle, Thomas L., Leo Strauss: An Introduction to His Thought and Intellectual Legacy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 2006, p. 51: "Classical political philosophy is not concerned to rule, but it is concerned to understand, political society—and to share its understanding, in a constructive fashion, with the various political societies and their citizens and rulers." Cf. also his "Fundamental Tension" (ibid., p.54f)
  17. ^ Leo Strauss, "An Introduction to Heideggerian Existentialism," 27–46 in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, ed. Thomas L. Pangle (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1989) 29–30.
  18. ^ Velkley, Richard L. (2015). Heidegger, Strauss, and the premises of philosophy : on original forgetting (Paperback 2015 ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 9780226214948.
  19. ^ Leo Strauss, "Relativism", 13–26 in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, ed. Thomas L. Pangle (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 25.
  20. ^ Drury, S. B. (1987). "Leo Strauss's Classic Natural Right Teaching". Political Theory. 15 (3): 299–315. doi:10.1177/0090591787015003001. JSTOR 191204. S2CID 143546488.
  21. ^ "Exoteric Teaching" (Critical Edition by Hannes Kerber). In Reorientation: Leo Strauss in the 1930s. Edited by Martin D. Yaffe and Richard S. Ruderman. New York: Palgrave, 2014, p. 275.
  22. ^ Smith, Steven (2007). Reading Leo Strauss. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226763897. from the original on 2020-11-09. Retrieved 2006-09-20. excerpt entitled "Why Strauss, Why Now?"
  23. ^ Mansfield, Harvey (1975). "Strauss's Machiavelli". Political Theory. JSTOR 190834. ... a book containing much that is appreciably esoteric to any reader stated in a manner either so elusive or so challenging as to cause him to give up trying to understand it.
  24. ^ Damon Linker (October 31, 2014). "What if Leo Strauss was Right?". The Week. from the original on 2014-11-03. Retrieved 2014-11-04.
  25. ^ Michael Paley and Jacob J. Staub in Jewish Philosophy: Medieval and Modern, printed in The Schocken Guide to Jewish Books (1992) p. 215.
  26. ^ Winfried Schröder (ed.), Reading between the lines – Leo Strauss and the history of early modern philosophy, Walter de Gruyter, 2015, p. 39, "According to Robert Hunt, '[t]he Straussian hermeneutic ... sees the course of intellectual history as an ongoing conversation about important philosophical questions'."
  27. ^ Jew and Philosopher: The Return to Maimonides in the Jewish Thought of Leo Strauss p. 25
  28. ^ Allan Bloom, "Leo Strauss", 235–55 in Giants and Dwarfs: Essays 1960–1990 (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990) 238–39.
  29. ^ Faith and Political Philosophy: The Correspondence Between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin, 1934–1964, p. 193
  30. ^ Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker, p. 3
  31. ^ Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: the hidden dialogue, Heinrich Meier, University of Chicago Press 1995, 123
  32. ^ Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: the hidden dialogue, Heinrich Meier, University of Chicago Press 1995, 125
  33. ^ Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: the hidden dialogue, Heinrich Meier, University of Chicago Press 1995
  34. ^ Lilla, Mark (2001), "Alexandre Kojève", The Reckless Mind. Intellectuals in Politics, New York: New York Review Books, p. 131, ISBN 978-0-940322-76-9.
  35. ^ Strauss, Leo, Gourevitch, Victor; Roth, Michael S. (eds.), On Tyranny
  36. ^ Thomas L. Pangle, "Epilogue", 907–38 in History of Political Philosophy, ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, 3rd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987) 907–8.
  37. ^ Leo Strauss, On Tyranny (New York: Free Press, 1991) 22–23, 178.
  38. ^ Leo Strauss, "The Crisis of Our Time", 41–54 in Howard Spaeth, ed., The Predicament of Modern Politics (Detroit: University of Detroit Press, 1964) 47–48.
  39. ^ Leo Strauss, "What Is Political Philosophy?" 9–55 in Leo Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Studies (Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1959) 18–19.
  40. ^ Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1964) 10–11.
  41. ^ Leo Strauss, "Plato", 33–89 in History of Political Philosophy, ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, 3rd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987) 68.
  42. ^ Leo Strauss, "Plato", 33–89 in History of Political Philosophy, ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, 3rd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987) 60.
  43. ^ On Tyranny, p. 143
  44. ^ Voegelin, Eric; Strauss, Leo (20 August 2004). "Letter 30: April 18, 1950". In Emberley, Peter; Cooper, Barry (eds.). Faith and Political Philosophy: The Correspondence between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin, 1934-1964. University of Missouri. p. 68. ISBN 978-0826215512.
  45. ^ Anonymous (2011-07-15). . Philosophy of Science. Archived from the original on 2013-07-28. Retrieved 4 February 2019.
  46. ^ Leo Strauss, the Straussians, and the American Regime by Kenneth Deutch (1999), p. 104
  47. ^ Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953) p. 164
  48. ^ Adam Smith in His Time and Ours: Designing the Decent Society By Jerry Z. Müller
  49. ^ a b Jewish philosophy and the crisis of modernity (SUNY 1997), Leo Strauss as a Modern Jewish thinker, Kenneth Hart Green, Leo Strauss, p. 55
  50. ^ Green, K. H. (editor), Strauss, Leo, Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity : Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought, 1997, State University of New York Press, p. 3
  51. ^ Green, K. H. (editor), Strauss, L., Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity : Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought, 1997, State University of New York Press, pp. 413–14
  52. ^ see his writings on Max Weber
  53. ^ Strauss felt that one should either be "the philosopher open to the challenge of theology or the theologian open to the challenge of philosophy." see Deutsch, Kenneth L. and Walter Nicgorski Leo Strauss: Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker pp. 11–12, 1994 Rowman & Littlefield
  54. ^ but where Aquinas saw an amicable interplay between reason and revelation, Strauss saw two impregnable fortresses. per Schall S.J., James V. A Latitude for Statesmanship: Strauss on St. Thomas in Leo Strauss: Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker, ed. Kenneth L. Deutsch and Walter Nicgorski, pp. 212–15, 1994 Rowman & Littlefield. For an early treatment of Aquinas' understanding of the relation between philosophy and sacred, revealed law, see Strauss's early Philosophy and Law (Philosophie und Gesetz), where Christian medieval theology testifies to a less than amicable opposition between pagan (though not necessarily Platonic or political) philosophy and Biblical morality.
  55. ^ Feser, Edward, "Leo Strauss 101" (a review of Steven B. Smith's Reading Leo Strauss: Politics, Philosophy, Judaism), National Review Online, May 22, 2006. November 15, 2006, at the Wayback Machine
  56. ^ See Natural Right and History, especially p. 119A and Chapter III: "The Origin of the Idea of Natural Right"
  57. ^ Shadia B. Drury, Leo Strauss and the American Right (Palgrave Macmillan; 1999)
  58. ^ Peter Minowitz, Straussophobia: Defending Leo Strauss and Straussians against Shadia Drury and Other Accusers (Lexington Books; 2009)
  59. ^ a b c d Approaches to Political Thought, edited by William L. Richter, (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 16 Mar 2009), p. 56
  60. ^ "Definition of PEDAGOGIC". from the original on 2020-10-22. Retrieved 2020-12-26.
  61. ^ a b c d e f g h Mark C. Henrie (May 5, 2011). . First Principles – ISI Web Journal. Archived from the original on December 21, 2018. Retrieved November 24, 2014.
  62. ^ "Transcript of Harvey Mansfield (IV)". conversationswithbillkristol.org. from the original on 15 March 2018. Retrieved 14 March 2018.
  63. ^ Marchal, Kai (2017). Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss in the Chinese-speaking World: Reorienting the Political. Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books. p. 7. ISBN 978-1498536264..
  64. ^ Bekesi, Aron B (2019-12-31). "Esoteric philosophy: Leo Strauss and sociolinguistics". Science & Philosophy. 7 (2). doi:10.23756/sp.v7i2.481.
  65. ^ Seymour M. Hersh, "Selective Intelligence" 2014-07-17 at the Wayback Machine, The New Yorker, May 12, 2003. Retrieved June 1, 2007.
  66. ^ Brian Doherty, "Origin of the Specious: Why Do Neoconservatives Doubt Darwin?" 2016-07-31 at the Wayback Machine, Reason Online, July 1997. Retrieved February 16, 2007.
  67. ^ The City and Man, p. 104
  68. ^ Nicholas Xenos, "Leo Strauss and the Rhetoric of the War on Terror," 2021-01-26 at the Wayback Machine Logosjournal.com
  69. ^ Claes G. Ryn, "Leo Strauss and History: The Philosopher as Conspirator", Humanitas, Vol. XVIII, Nos. 1 & 2 (2005).
  70. ^ Paul Gottfried, "Strauss and the Straussians" 2015-06-18 at the Wayback Machine, LewRockwell.com, April 17, 2006. Retrieved February 16, 2007.
  71. ^ Cf. Paul Gottfried, "Paul Gottfried: Archives" 2015-06-18 at the Wayback Machine, Lewrockwell.com. Retrieved February 16, 2007.
  72. ^ Peter Minowitz, Straussophobia: Defending Leo Strauss and Straussians against Shadia Drury and Other Accusers (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2009). Also see "Straussophobia: Six Questions for Peter Minowitz," Harper's Magazine, 9/29/09 [1] 2012-10-19 at the Wayback Machine
  73. ^ Steven B. Smith, excerpt from "Why Strauss, Why Now?" 2020-11-09 at the Wayback Machine, 1–15 in Reading Leo Strauss: Politics, Philosophy, Judaism (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2006), online posting, press.uchicago.edu. Retrieved June 1, 2007.
  74. ^ Robert Alter, "Neocon or Not?" 2017-08-26 at the Wayback Machine, The New York Times Book Review, June 25, 2006, accessed February 16, 2007, citing Yale scholar Steven B. Smith, Reading Leo Strauss: Politics, Philosophy, Judaism (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2006).
  75. ^ Jenny Strauss Clay (June 7, 2003). "The Real Leo Strauss". The New York Times. from the original on April 2, 2015. Retrieved March 30, 2015.
  76. ^ Mark Lilla, The Reckless Mind (New York: NY Review of Books, 2001) 133.
  77. ^ Nathan Tarcov, "Will the Real Leo Strauss Please Stand Up" in The American Interest September–October 1986, at . Archived from the original on 2010-11-30. Retrieved 2009-06-28.

Further reading edit

  • "A Giving of Accounts". In Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity – Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought. Ed. Kenneth H. Green. Albany: SUNY Press, 1997.
  • Altman, William H. F., The German Stranger: Leo Strauss and National Socialism. Lexington Books, 2011
  • Andreacchio, Marco. "Philosophy and Religion in Leo Strauss : Critical Review of Menon's Interpretation". Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy 46, no. 2 (Spring 2020): 383–98.
  • Behnegar, Nasser, Leo Strauss, Max Weber, And The Scientific Study Of Politics. University of Chicago Press, 2005.
  • Benardete, Seth. Encounters and Reflections: Conversations with Seth Benardete. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2002.
  • Bloom, Allan. "Leo Strauss". 235–55 in Giants and Dwarfs: Essays 1960–1990. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990.
  • Bluhm, Harald. Die Ordnung der Ordnung : das politische Philosophieren von Leo Strauss. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 2002.
  • Brague, Rémi. "Leo Strauss and Maimonides". 93–114 in Leo Strauss's Thought. Ed. Alan Udoff. Boulder: Lynne Reiner, 1991.
  • Brittain, Christopher Craig. "Leo Strauss and Resourceful Odysseus: Rhetorical Violence and the Holy Middle". Canadian Review of American Studies 38, no. 1 (2008): 147–63.
  • Bruell, Christopher. "A Return to Classical Political Philosophy and the Understanding of the American Founding". Review of Politics 53, no. 1 (Winter 1991): 173–86.
  • Chivilò, Giampiero and Menon, Marco (eds). Tirannide e filosofia: Con un saggio di Leo Strauss ed un inedito di Gaston Fessard sj. Venezia: Edizioni Ca' Foscari, 2015. ISBN 978-88-6969-032-7.
  • Colen, Jose. Facts and values. London: Plusprint, 2012.
  • Deutsch, Kenneth L. and John A. Murley, eds. Leo Strauss, the Straussians, and the American Regime. New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999. ISBN 978-0-8476-8692-6.
  • Drury, Shadia B. Leo Strauss and the American Right. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1999.
  • ———. The Political Ideas of Leo Strauss. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1988.
  • Gottfried, Paul. Leo Strauss and the Conservative Movement in America: A Critical Appraisal (Cambridge University Press; 2011)
  • Gourevitch, Victor. "Philosophy and Politics I–II". Review of Metaphysics 22, nos. 1–2 (September–December 1968): 58–84, 281–328.
  • Green, Kenneth. Jew and Philosopher – The Return to Maimonides in the Jewish Thought of Leo Strauss. Albany: SUNY Press, 1993.
  • Havers, Grant N. Leo Strauss and Anglo-American Democracy: A Conservative Critique. DeKalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, 2013.
  • Holmes, Stephen. The Anatomy of Antiliberalism. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1996. ISBN 978-0-674-03185-2.
  • Howse, Robert. Leo Strauss, Man of Peace, Cambridge University Press, 2014]
  • Ivry, Alfred L. "Leo Strauss on Maimonides". 75–91 in Leo Strauss's Thought. Ed. Alan Udoff. Boulder: Lynne Reiner, 1991.
  • Janssens, David. Between Athens and Jerusalem. Philosophy, Prophecy, and Politics in Leo Strauss's Early Thought. Albany: SUNY Press, 2008.
  • Kartheininger, Markus. "Heterogenität. Politische Philosophie im Frühwerk von Leo Strauss". München: Fink, 2006. ISBN 978-3-7705-4378-6.
  • Kartheininger, Markus. "Aristokratisierung des Geistes". In: Kartheininger, Markus/ Hutter, Axel (ed.). "Bildung als Mittel und Selbstzweck". Freiburg: Alber, 2009, pp. 157–208. ISBN 978-3-495-48393-0.
  • Kerber, Hannes. "Strauss and Schleiermacher. An Introduction to 'Exoteric Teaching". In Reorientation: Leo Strauss in the 1930s. Ed. Yaffe/Ruderman. New York: Palgrave, 2014, pp. 203–14.
  • Kerber, Hannes. "Leo Strauss on Exoteric Writing". Interpretation. 46, no. 1 (2019): 3–25.
  • Kinzel, Till. Platonische Kulturkritik in Amerika. Studien zu Allan Blooms The Closing of the American Mind. Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 2002.
  • Kochin, Michael S. "Morality, Nature, and Esotericism in Leo Strauss's Persecution and the Art of Writing". Review of Politics 64, no. 2 (Spring 2002): 261–83.
  • Lampert, Laurence. Leo Strauss and Nietzsche. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1996.
  • Lutz, Mark J. “Living the Theologico-Political Problem: Leo Strauss on the Common Ground of Philosophy and Theology.” The European Legacy. 2018. Vol. 23. No. 8. pp. 1–25.
  • Macpherson, C. B. "Hobbes's Bourgeois Man". In Democratic Theory: Essays in Retrieval. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972.
  • Major, Rafael (ed.). Leo Strauss's Defense of the Philosophic Life: Reading "What is Political Philosophy?". University of Chicago Press, 2013. ISBN 978-0-226-92420-5 (cloth)
  • Marchal, Kai, Shaw, Carl K.Y. Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss in the Chinese-speaking World: Reorienting the Political. Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books, 2017.
  • McAllister, Ted V. Revolt Against Modernity: Leo Strauss, Eric Voegelin & the Search for Postliberal Order. Lawrence, KS: UP of Kansas. 1996.
  • McWilliams, Wilson Carey. "Leo Strauss and the Dignity of American Political Thought". Review of Politics 60, no. 2 (Spring 1998): 231–46.
  • Meier, Heinrich. Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: The Hidden Dialogue, Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1995.
  • ———. "Editor's Introduction[s]". Gesammelte Schriften. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler, 1996. 3 vols.
  • ———. Leo Strauss and the Theologico-Political Problem. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2006.
  • ———. How Strauss Became Strauss". 363–82 in Enlightening Revolutions: Essays in Honor of Ralph Lerner. Ed. Svetozar Minkov. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2006.
  • Melzer, Arthur. "Esotericism and the Critique of Historicism". American Political Science Review 100 (2006): 279–95.
  • Minowitz, Peter. "Machiavellianism Come of Age? Leo Strauss on Modernity and Economics". The Political Science Reviewer 22 (1993): 157–97.
  • ———. Straussophobia: Defending Leo Strauss and Straussians against Shadia Drury and Other Accusers. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2009.
  • Momigliano, Arnaldo. "Hermeneutics and Classical Political Thought in Leo Strauss", 178–89 in Essays on Ancient and Modern Judaism. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1994.
  • Moyn, Samuel. "From experience to law: Leo Strauss and the Weimar crisis of the philosophy of religion." History of European Ideas 33, (2007): 174–94.
  • Neumann, Harry. Liberalism. Durham, NC: Carolina Academic P, 1991.
  • Norton, Anne. Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire. New Haven & London: Yale UP, 2004.
  • Pangle, Thomas L. "The Epistolary Dialogue Between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin". Review of Politics 53, no. 1 (Winter 1991): 100–25.
  • ———. "Leo Strauss's Perspective on Modern Politics". Perspectives on Political Science 33, no. 4 (Fall 2004): 197–203.
  • ———. Leo Strauss: An Introduction to His Thought and Intellectual Legacy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 2006.
  • Pelluchon, Corine. Leo Strauss and the Crisis of Rationalism: Another Reason, Another Enlightenment, Robert Howse (tr.), SUNY Press, 2014.
  • Piccinini, Irene Abigail. Una guida fedele. L'influenza di Hermann Cohen sul pensiero di Leo Strauss. Torino: Trauben, 2007. ISBN 978-88-89909-31-7.
  • Rosen, Stanley. "Hermeneutics as Politics". 87–140 in Hermeneutics as Politics, New York: Oxford UP, 1987.
  • Sheppard, Eugene R. Leo Strauss and the Politics of Exile: The Making of a Political Philosopher. Waltham, MA: Brandeis UP, 2006. ISBN 978-1-58465-600-5.
  • Shorris, Earl. "Ignoble Liars: Leo Strauss, George Bush, and the Philosophy of Mass Deception". Harper's Magazine 308, issue 1849 (June 2004): 65–71.
  • Smith, Steven B. Reading Leo Strauss: Politics, Philosophy, Judaism. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2006. ISBN 978-0-226-76402-3. (Introd: "Why Strauss, Why Now?", online posting, press.uchicago.edu.)
  • Smith, Steven B. (editor). The Cambridge Companion to Leo Strauss. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2009. ISBN 978-0-521-70399-4.
  • Steiner, Stephan: Weimar in Amerika. Leo Strauss' Politische Philosophie, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck 2013.
  • Strong, Tracy B. "Leo Strauss and the Demos," The European Legacy (October, 2012)
  • Tanguay, Daniel. Leo Strauss: une biographie intellectuelle. Paris, 2005. ISBN 978-2-253-13067-3.
  • Tarcov, Nathan. "On a Certain Critique of 'Straussianism' ". Review of Politics 53, no. 1 (Winter 1991): 3–18.
  • ———. "Philosophy and History: Tradition and Interpretation in the Work of Leo Strauss". Polity 16, no. 1 (Autumn 1983): 5–29.
  • ——— and Thomas L. Pangle, "Epilogue: Leo Strauss and the History of Political Philosophy". 907–38 in History of Political Philosophy. Ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey. 3rd ed. 1963; Chicago and London, U of Chicago P, 1987.
  • Tepper, Aryeh. "Progressive Minds, Conservative Politics: Leo Strauss' Later Writings on Maimonides." SUNY: 2013.
  • Thompson, Bradley C. (with Yaron Brook). Neoconservatism. An Obituary for an Idea. Boulder/London: Paradigm Publishers, 2010. pp. 55–131. ISBN 978-1-59451-831-7.
  • Velkley, Richard. Heidegger, Strauss, and the Premises of Philosophy: On Original Forgetting. University of Chicago Press, 2011.
  • West, Thomas G. "Jaffa Versus Mansfield: Does America Have a Constitutional or a "Declaration of Independence" Soul?" Perspectives on Political Science 31, no. 4 (Fall 2002): 35–46.
  • Xenos, Nicholas. Cloaked in virtue: Unveiling Leo Strauss and the Rhetoric of American Foreign Policy. New York, Routledge Press, 2008.
  • Zuckert, Catherine H. Postmodern Platos. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1996.
  • Zuckert, Catherine H., and Michael Zuckert. The Truth about Leo Strauss. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2006.

Strauss family edit

  • Lüders, Joachim and Ariane Wehner. Mittelhessen – eine Heimat für Juden? Das Schicksal der Familie Strauss aus Kirchhain. Marburg: Gymnasium Philippinum, 1989. (In German; English translation: Central Hesse – a Homeland for Jews? The Fate of the Strauss Family from Kirchhain.)

External links edit

strauss, strowss, german, ˈleːoː, ˈʃtʁaʊs, september, 1899, october, 1973, 20th, century, german, american, scholar, political, philosophy, specialized, classical, political, philosophy, born, germany, jewish, parents, strauss, later, emigrated, from, germany,. Leo Strauss s t r aʊ s STROWSS German ˈleːoː ˈʃtʁaʊs September 20 1899 October 18 1973 was a 20th century German American scholar of political philosophy who specialized in classical political philosophy Born in Germany to Jewish parents Strauss later emigrated from Germany to the United States He spent much of his career as a professor of political science at the University of Chicago where he taught several generations of students and published fifteen books Leo StraussBVOBorn 1899 09 20 September 20 1899Kirchhain Kingdom of Prussia German EmpireDiedOctober 18 1973 1973 10 18 aged 74 Annapolis Maryland U S Alma materUniversity of MarburgUniversity of HamburgUniversity of FreiburgColumbia UniversityNotable workPersecution and the Art of WritingThoughts on MachiavelliHistory of Political PhilosophySpouseMiriam Bernsohn StraussAwardsOrder of Merit of the Federal Republic of GermanyEra20th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolContinental philosophyNeo Kantianism early Modern Platonism later Straussian hermeneuticsClassical republicanismModern republicanismInstitutionsHigher Institute for Jewish StudiesColumbia UniversityUniversity of CambridgeThe New SchoolHamilton CollegeUniversity of ChicagoClaremont McKenna CollegeSt John s CollegeThesisDas Erkenntnisproblem in der philosophischen Lehre Fr H Jacobis On the Problem of Knowledge in the Philosophical Doctrine of F H Jacobi 1921 Doctoral advisorErnst CassirerMain interestsMetaphysicsEpistemologyHistory of philosophy especially Greek Islamic Jewish and continental philosophy Philosophy of religionPolitical philosophyNotable ideasList Noetic heterogeneityThe ends of politics and philosophy as irreducible to one anotherThe unresolvable tension between reason and revelationCriticism of positivism moral relativism historicism and nihilismThe distinction between esoteric and exoteric writingReopening the quarrel of the ancients and the modernsReductio ad HitlerumTrained in the neo Kantian tradition with Ernst Cassirer and immersed in the work of the phenomenologists Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger Strauss authored books on Spinoza and Hobbes and articles on Maimonides and Al Farabi In the late 1930s his research focused on the texts of Plato and Aristotle retracing their interpretation through medieval Islamic and Jewish philosophy and encouraging the application of those ideas to contemporary political theory Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Early life and education 1 2 Career 2 Thought 3 Views 3 1 Philosophy 3 2 On reading 3 3 On politics 3 4 Encounters with Carl Schmitt and Alexandre Kojeve 3 5 Liberalism and nihilism 3 6 Strauss s interpretation of Plato s Republic 3 7 Strauss and Karl Popper 3 8 Ancients and Moderns 3 9 Strauss and Zionism 3 10 Religious belief 4 Reception and legacy 4 1 Reception by contemporaries 4 2 The Straussian school 4 3 The Chinese Straussians 5 Criticism 5 1 Basis for esotericism 5 2 Conservatism 5 3 Anti historicism 5 4 Response to criticism 6 Bibliography 7 See also 8 Notes 9 Further reading 9 1 Strauss family 10 External linksBiography editEarly life and education edit Strauss was born on September 20 1899 in the small town of Kirchhain in Hesse Nassau a province of the Kingdom of Prussia part of the German Empire to Hugo Strauss and Jennie Strauss nee David According to Allan Bloom s 1974 obituary in Political Theory Strauss was raised as an Orthodox Jew but the family does not appear to have completely embraced Orthodox practice 1 Strauss himself noted that he came from a conservative even orthodox Jewish home but one which knew little about Judaism except strict adherence to ceremonial laws His father and uncle operated a farm supply and livestock business that they inherited from their father Meyer 1835 1919 a leading member of the local Jewish community 2 After attending the Kirchhain Volksschule and the Protestant Rektoratsschule Leo Strauss was enrolled at the Gymnasium Philippinum affiliated with the University of Marburg in nearby Marburg from which Johannes Althusius and Carl Joachim Friedrich also graduated in 1912 graduating in 1917 He boarded with the Marburg cantor Strauss no relation whose residence served as a meeting place for followers of the neo Kantian philosopher Hermann Cohen Strauss served in the German army from World War I from July 5 1917 to December 1918 Strauss subsequently enrolled in the University of Hamburg where he received his doctorate in 1921 his thesis On the Problem of Knowledge in the Philosophical Doctrine of F H Jacobi Das Erkenntnisproblem in der philosophischen Lehre Fr H Jacobis was supervised by Ernst Cassirer He also attended courses at the Universities of Freiburg and Marburg including some taught by Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger Strauss joined a Jewish fraternity and worked for the German Zionist movement which introduced him to various German Jewish intellectuals such as Norbert Elias Leo Lowenthal Hannah Arendt and Walter Benjamin Benjamin was and remained an admirer of Strauss and his work throughout his life 3 4 5 Strauss s closest friend was Jacob Klein but he also was intellectually engaged with Gerhard Kruger and also Karl Lowith Julius Guttmann Hans Georg Gadamer and Franz Rosenzweig to whom Strauss dedicated his first book as well as Gershom Scholem Alexander Altmann and the Arabist Paul Kraus who married Strauss s sister Bettina Strauss and his wife later adopted Paul and Bettina Kraus s child when both parents died in the Middle East With several of these friends Strauss carried on vigorous epistolary exchanges later in life many of which are published in the Gesammelte Schriften Collected Writings some in translation from the German Strauss had also been engaged in a discourse with Carl Schmitt However after Strauss left Germany he broke off the discourse when Schmitt failed to respond to his letters Career edit After receiving a Rockefeller Fellowship in 1932 Strauss left his position at the Higher Institute for Jewish Studies in Berlin for Paris He returned to Germany only once for a few short days twenty years later In Paris he married Marie Miriam Bernsohn a widow with a young child whom he had known previously in Germany He adopted his wife s son Thomas and later his sister s child Jenny Strauss Clay later a professor of classics at the University of Virginia he and Miriam had no biological children of their own At his death he was survived by Thomas Jenny Strauss Clay and three grandchildren Strauss became a lifelong friend of Alexandre Kojeve and was on friendly terms with Raymond Aron and Etienne Gilson Because of the Nazis rise to power he chose not to return to his native country Strauss found shelter after some vicissitudes in England where in 1935 he gained temporary employment at the University of Cambridge with the help of his in law David Daube who was affiliated with Gonville and Caius College While in England he became a close friend of R H Tawney and was on less friendly terms with Isaiah Berlin 6 nbsp The University of Chicago the school with which Strauss is most closely associatedUnable to find permanent employment in England Strauss moved in 1937 to the United States under the patronage of Harold Laski who made introductions and helped him obtain a brief lectureship After a short stint as a research fellow in the Department of History at Columbia University Strauss secured a position at The New School where between 1938 and 1948 he worked in the political science faculty and also took on adjunct jobs 7 In 1939 he served for a short term as a visiting professor at Hamilton College He became a U S citizen in 1944 and in 1949 became a professor of political science at the University of Chicago holding the Robert Maynard Hutchins Distinguished Service Professorship until he left in 1969 In 1953 Strauss coined the phrase reductio ad Hitlerum a play on reductio ad absurdum suggesting that comparing an argument to one of Hitler s or playing the Nazi card is often a fallacy of irrelevance 8 In 1954 he met Karl Lowith and Hans Georg Gadamer in Heidelberg and delivered a public speech on Socrates He had received a call for a temporary lectureship in Hamburg in 1965 which he declined for health reasons and received and accepted an honorary doctorate from the University of Hamburg and the Bundesverdienstkreuz German Order of Merit via the German representative in Chicago In 1969 Strauss moved to Claremont McKenna College formerly Claremont Men s College in California for a year and then to St John s College Annapolis in 1970 where he was the Scott Buchanan Distinguished Scholar in Residence until his death from pneumonia in 1973 9 He was buried in Annapolis Hebrew Cemetery with his wife Miriam Bernsohn Strauss who died in 1985 Psalm 114 was read in the funeral service at the request of family and friends 10 Thought editStrauss s thought can be characterized by two main themes the critique of modernity and the recovery of classical political philosophy He argued that modernity which began with the Enlightenment was a radical break from the tradition of Western civilization and that it led to a crisis of nihilism relativism historicism and scientism He claimed that modern political and social sciences which were based on empirical observation and rational analysis failed to grasp the essential questions of human nature morality and justice and that they reduced human beings to mere objects of manipulation and calculation He also criticized modern liberalism which he saw as a product of modernity for its lack of moral and spiritual foundations and for its tendency to undermine the authority of religion tradition and natural law 11 12 To overcome the crisis of modernity Strauss proposed a return to the classical political philosophy of the ancient Greeks and the medieval thinkers who he believed had a deeper and more comprehensive understanding of human nature and society He advocated a careful and respectful reading of the classical texts arguing that their authors wrote in an esoteric manner which he called the art of writing and which he practiced in his own works He suggested that the classical authors hid their true teachings behind a surface layer of conventional opinions in order to avoid persecution and to educate only the few who were capable of grasping them and that they engaged in a dialogue with each other across the ages Strauss called this dialogue the great conversation and invited his readers to join it 11 12 Strauss s interpretation of the classical political philosophy was influenced by his own Jewish background and his encounter with Islamic and Jewish medieval philosophy especially the works of Al Farabi and Maimonides He argued that these philosophers who lived under the rule of Islam faced similar challenges as the ancient Greeks He also claimed that these philosophers who were both faithful to their revealed religions and loyal to the rational pursuit of philosophy offered a model of how to reconcile reason and revelation philosophy and theology Athens and Jerusalem 11 12 Views editPhilosophy edit For Strauss politics and philosophy were necessarily intertwined He regarded the trial and death of Socrates as the moment when political philosophy came into existence Strauss considered one of the most important moments in the history of philosophy Socrates argument that philosophers could not study nature without considering their own human nature 13 which in the words of Aristotle is that of a political animal 14 However he also held that the ends of politics and philosophy were inherently irreconcilable and irreducible to one another 15 16 Strauss distinguished scholars from great thinkers identifying himself as a scholar He wrote that most self described philosophers are in actuality scholars cautious and methodical Great thinkers in contrast boldly and creatively address big problems Scholars deal with these problems only indirectly by reasoning about the great thinkers differences 17 In Natural Right and History Strauss begins with a critique of Max Weber s epistemology briefly engages the relativism of Martin Heidegger who goes unnamed and continues with a discussion of the evolution of natural rights via an analysis of the thought of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke He concludes by critiquing Jean Jacques Rousseau and Edmund Burke At the heart of the book are excerpts from Plato Aristotle and Cicero Much of his philosophy is a reaction to the works of Heidegger Indeed Strauss wrote that Heidegger s thinking must be understood and confronted before any complete formulation of modern political theory is possible and this means that political thought has to engage with issues of ontology and the history of metaphysics 18 Strauss wrote that Friedrich Nietzsche was the first philosopher to properly understand historicism an idea grounded in a general acceptance of Hegelian philosophy of history Heidegger in Strauss s view sanitized and politicized Nietzsche whereas Nietzsche believed our own principles including the belief in progress will become as unconvincing and alien as all earlier principles essences had shown themselves to be and the only way out seems to be that one voluntarily choose life giving delusion instead of deadly truth that one fabricate a myth 19 Heidegger believed that the tragic nihilism of Nietzsche was itself a myth guided by a defective Western conception of Being that Heidegger traced to Plato In his published correspondence with Alexandre Kojeve Strauss wrote that Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel was correct when he postulated that an end of history implies an end to philosophy as understood by classical political philosophy 20 On reading edit nbsp Strauss s study of philosophy and political discourses produced by the Islamic civilization especially those of Al Farabi shown here and Maimonides was instrumental in the development of his theory of reading In the late 1930s Strauss called for the first time for a reconsideration of the distinction between exoteric or public and esoteric or secret teaching 21 In 1952 he published Persecution and the Art of Writing arguing that serious writers write esoterically that is with multiple or layered meanings often disguised within irony or paradox obscure references even deliberate self contradiction Esoteric writing serves several purposes protecting the philosopher from the retribution of the regime and protecting the regime from the corrosion of philosophy it attracts the right kind of reader and repels the wrong kind and ferreting out the interior message is in itself an exercise of philosophic reasoning 22 23 24 Taking his bearings from his study of Maimonides and Al Farabi and pointing further back to Plato s discussion of writing as contained in the Phaedrus Strauss proposed that the classical and medieval art of esoteric writing is the proper medium for philosophic learning rather than displaying philosophers thoughts superficially classical and medieval philosophical texts guide their readers in thinking and learning independently of imparted knowledge Thus Strauss agrees with the Socrates of the Phaedrus where the Greek indicates that insofar as writing does not respond when questioned good writing provokes questions in the reader questions that orient the reader towards an understanding of problems the author thought about with utmost seriousness Strauss thus in Persecution and the Art of Writing presents Maimonides as a closet nonbeliever obfuscating his message for political reasons 25 Strauss s hermeneutical argument 26 rearticulated throughout his subsequent writings most notably in The City and Man 1964 is that before the 19th century Western scholars commonly understood that philosophical writing is not at home in any polity no matter how liberal Insofar as it questions conventional wisdom at its roots philosophy must guard itself especially against those readers who believe themselves authoritative wise and liberal defenders of the status quo In questioning established opinions or in investigating the principles of morality philosophers of old found it necessary to convey their messages in an oblique manner Their art of writing was the art of esoteric communication This was especially apparent in medieval times when heterodox political thinkers wrote under the threat of the Inquisition or comparably obtuse tribunals Strauss s argument is not that the medieval writers he studies reserved one exoteric meaning for the many hoi polloi and an esoteric hidden one for the few hoi oligoi but that through rhetorical stratagems including self contradiction and hyperboles these writers succeeded in conveying their proper meaning at the tacit heart of their writings a heart or message irreducible to the letter or historical dimension of texts Explicitly following Gotthold Ephraim Lessing s lead Strauss indicates that medieval political philosophers no less than their ancient counterparts carefully adapted their wording to the dominant moral views of their time lest their writings be condemned as heretical or unjust not by the many who did not read but by those few whom the many regarded as the most righteous guardians of morality It was precisely these righteous personalities who would be most inclined to persecute ostracize anyone who was in the business of exposing the noble or great lie upon which the authority of the few over the many stands or falls 27 On politics edit According to Strauss modern social science is flawed because it assumes the fact value distinction a concept which Strauss found dubious He traced its roots in Enlightenment philosophy to Max Weber a thinker whom Strauss described as a serious and noble mind Weber wanted to separate values from science but according to Strauss was really a derivative thinker deeply influenced by Nietzsche s relativism 28 Strauss treated politics as something that could not be studied from afar A political scientist examining politics with a value free scientific eye for Strauss was self deluded Positivism the heir to both Auguste Comte and Max Weber in the quest to make purportedly value free judgments failed to justify its own existence which would require a value judgment 29 While modern era liberalism had stressed the pursuit of individual liberty as its highest goal Strauss felt that there should be a greater interest in the problem of human excellence and political virtue Through his writings Strauss constantly raised the question of how and to what extent freedom and excellence can coexist Strauss refused to make do with any simplistic or one sided resolutions of the Socratic question What is the good for the city and man 30 Encounters with Carl Schmitt and Alexandre Kojeve edit Two significant political philosophical dialogues Strauss had with living thinkers were those he held with Carl Schmitt and Alexandre Kojeve Schmitt who would later become for a short time the chief jurist of Nazi Germany was one of the first important German academics to review Strauss s early work positively Schmitt s positive reference for and approval of Strauss s work on Hobbes was instrumental in winning Strauss the scholarship funding that allowed him to leave Germany 31 Strauss s critique and clarifications of The Concept of the Political led Schmitt to make significant emendations in its second edition Writing to Schmitt in 1932 Strauss summarised Schmitt s political theology that because man is by nature evil he therefore needs dominion But dominion can be established that is men can be unified only in a unity against against other men Every association of men is necessarily a separation from other men the political thus understood is not the constitutive principle of the state of order but a condition of the state 32 Strauss however directly opposed Schmitt s position For Strauss Schmitt and his return to Thomas Hobbes helpfully clarified the nature of our political existence and our modern self understanding Schmitt s position was therefore symptomatic of the modern era liberal self understanding Strauss believed that such an analysis as in Hobbes s time served as a useful preparatory action revealing our contemporary orientation towards the eternal problems of politics social existence However Strauss believed that Schmitt s reification of our modern self understanding of the problem of politics into a political theology was not an adequate solution Strauss instead advocated a return to a broader classical understanding of human nature and a tentative return to political philosophy in the tradition of the ancient philosophers 33 With Kojeve Strauss had a close and lifelong philosophical friendship They had first met as students in Berlin The two thinkers shared boundless philosophical respect for each other Kojeve would later write that without befriending Strauss I never would have known what philosophy is 34 The political philosophical dispute between Kojeve and Strauss centered on the role that philosophy should and can be allowed to play in politics Kojeve a senior civil servant in the French government was instrumental in the creation of the European Economic Community He argued that philosophers should have an active role in shaping political events Strauss on the contrary believed that philosophers should play a role in politics only to the extent that they can ensure that philosophy which he saw as mankind s highest activity can be free from political intervention 35 Liberalism and nihilism edit Strauss argued that liberalism in its modern form which is oriented toward universal freedom as opposed to ancient liberalism which is oriented toward human excellence contained within it an intrinsic tendency towards extreme relativism which in turn led to two types of nihilism 36 The first was a brutal nihilism expressed in Nazi and Bolshevik regimes In On Tyranny he wrote that these ideologies both descendants of Enlightenment thought tried to destroy all traditions history ethics and moral standards and replace them by force under which nature and mankind are subjugated and conquered 37 The second type the gentle nihilism expressed in Western liberal democracies was a kind of value free aimlessness and a hedonistic permissive egalitarianism which he saw as permeating the fabric of contemporary American society 38 39 In the belief that 20th century relativism scientism historicism and nihilism were all implicated in the deterioration of modern society and philosophy Strauss sought to uncover the philosophical pathways that had led to this situation The resultant study led him to advocate a tentative return to classical political philosophy as a starting point for judging political action 40 Strauss s interpretation of Plato s Republic edit According to Strauss the Republic by Plato is not a blueprint for regime reform a play on words from Karl Popper s The Open Society and Its Enemies which attacks The Republic for being just that Strauss quotes Cicero The Republic does not bring to light the best possible regime but rather the nature of political things the nature of the city 41 Strauss argued that the city in speech was unnatural precisely because it is rendered possible by the abstraction from eros 42 Though skeptical of progress Strauss was equally skeptical about political agendas of return that is going backward instead of forward In fact he was consistently suspicious of anything claiming to be a solution to an old political or philosophical problem He spoke of the danger in trying finally to resolve the debate between rationalism and traditionalism in politics In particular along with many in the pre World War II German Right he feared people trying to force a world state to come into being in the future thinking that it would inevitably become a tyranny 43 Hence he kept his distance from the two totalitarianisms that he denounced in his century both fascists and communists Strauss and Karl Popper edit Strauss actively rejected Karl Popper s views as illogical He agreed with a letter of response to his request of Eric Voegelin to look into the issue In the response Voegelin wrote that studying Popper s views was a waste of precious time and an annoyance Specifically about The Open Society and Its Enemies and Popper s understanding of Plato s The Republic after giving some examples Voegelin wrote Popper is philosophically so uncultured so fully a primitive ideological brawler that he is not able to even approximately to reproduce correctly the contents of one page of Plato Reading is of no use to him he is too lacking in knowledge to understand what the author says misquoted 44 Strauss proceeded to show this letter to Kurt Riezler who used his influence in order to oppose Popper s appointment at the University of Chicago 45 Ancients and Moderns edit Strauss constantly stressed the importance of two dichotomies in political philosophy namely Athens and Jerusalem reason and revelation and Ancient versus Modern The Ancients were the Socratic philosophers and their intellectual heirs the Moderns start with Niccolo Machiavelli The contrast between Ancients and Moderns was understood to be related to the unresolvable tension between Reason and Revelation The Socratics reacting to the first Greek philosophers brought philosophy back to earth and hence back to the marketplace making it more political 46 The Moderns reacted to the dominance of revelation in medieval society by promoting the possibilities of Reason They objected to Aquinas s merger of natural right and natural theology for it made natural right vulnerable to sideshow theological disputes 47 Thomas Hobbes under the influence of Francis Bacon re oriented political thought to what was most solid but also most low in man his physical hopes and fears setting a precedent for John Locke and the later economic approach to political thought as in David Hume and Adam Smith 48 Strauss and Zionism edit As a youth Strauss belonged to the German Zionist youth group along with his friends Gershom Scholem and Walter Benjamin Both were admirers of Strauss and would continue to be throughout their lives 49 When he was 17 as he said he was converted to political Zionism as a follower of Ze ev Jabotinsky He wrote several essays about its controversies but left these activities behind by his early twenties 50 While Strauss maintained a sympathetic interest in Zionism he later came to refer to Zionism as problematic and became disillusioned with some of its aims He taught at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem during the 1954 55 academic year In his letter to a National Review editor Strauss asked why Israel had been called a racist state by one of their writers He argued that the author did not provide enough proof for his argument He ended his essay with this statement Political Zionism is problematic for obvious reasons But I can never forget what it achieved as a moral force in an era of complete dissolution It helped to stem the tide of progressive leveling of venerable ancestral differences it fulfilled a conservative function 51 Religious belief edit Although Strauss accepted the utility of religious belief there is some question about his religious views He was openly disdainful of atheism 52 better source needed and disapproved of contemporary dogmatic disbelief which he considered intemperate and irrational 53 However like Thomas Aquinas he felt that revelation must be subject to examination by reason 54 At the end of The City and Man Strauss invites us to be open to the question quid sit deus What is God p 241 Edward Feser writes that Strauss was not himself an orthodox believer neither was he a convinced atheist Since whether or not to accept a purported divine revelation is itself one of the permanent questions orthodoxy must always remain an option equally as defensible as unbelief 55 In Natural Right and History Strauss distinguishes a Socratic Platonic Ciceronian Aristotelian from a conventionalist materialistic Epicurean reading of divinity and argues that the question of religion what is religion is inseparable from the question of the nature of civil society and civil authority Throughout the volume he argues for the Socratic reading of civil authority and rejects the conventionalist reading of which atheism is an essential component 56 This is incompatible with interpretations by Shadia Drury and other scholars who argue that Strauss viewed religion purely instrumentally 57 58 Reception and legacy editReception by contemporaries edit Strauss s works were read and admired by thinkers as diverse as the philosophers Gershom Scholem Walter Benjamin 49 Hans Georg Gadamer 59 and Alexandre Kojeve 59 and the psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan 59 Benjamin had become acquainted with Strauss as a student in Berlin and expressed admiration for Strauss throughout his life 3 4 5 Gadamer stated that he largely agreed with Strauss s interpretations 59 The Straussian school edit Straussianism is the name given to denote the research methods common concepts theoretical presuppositions central questions and pedagogic style teaching style 60 characteristic of the large number of conservatives who have been influenced by the thought and teaching of Leo Strauss 61 While it is particularly influential among university professors of historical political theory it also sometimes serves as a common intellectual framework more generally among conservative activists think tank professionals and public intellectuals 61 Harvey C Mansfield Steven B Smith and Steven Berg though never students of Strauss are Straussians as some followers of Strauss identify themselves Mansfield has argued that there is no such thing as Straussianism yet there are Straussians and a school of Straussians Mansfield describes the school as open to the whole of philosophy and without any definite doctrines that one has to believe in order to belong to it 62 Within the discipline of political theory the method calls for its practitioners to use a close reading of the Great Books of political thought they strive to understand a thinker as he understood himself they are unconcerned with questions about the historical context of or historical influences on a given author 61 and strive to be open to the idea that they may find something timelessly true in a great book The approach resembles in important ways the old New Criticism in literary studies 61 There is some controversy in the approach over what distinguishes a great book from lesser works Great books are held to be written by authors philosophers of such sovereign critical self knowledge and intellectual power that they can in no way be reduced to the general thought of their time and place 61 with other works understood as epiphenomenal to the original insights of a thinker of the first rank 61 This approach is seen as a counter to the historicist presuppositions of the mid twentieth century which read the history of political thought in a progressivist way with past philosophies forever cut off from us in a superseded past 61 Straussianism puts forward the possibility that past thinkers may have hold of the truth and that more recent thinkers are therefore wrong 61 The Chinese Straussians edit Almost the entirety of Strauss s writings has been translated into Chinese and there even is a school of Straussians in China the most prominent being Liu Xiaofeng Renmin University and Gan Yang Chinese Straussians who often are also fascinated by Carl Schmitt represent a remarkable example of the hybridization of Western political theory in a non Western context As the editors of a recent volume write the reception of Schmitt and Strauss in the Chinese speaking world and especially in the People s Republic of China not only says much about how Schmitt and Strauss can be read today but also provides important clues about the deeper contradictions of Western modernity and the dilemmas of non liberal societies in our increasingly contentious world 63 Criticism editBasis for esotericism edit In the essay Persecution and the Art of Writing Strauss posits that information needs to be kept secret from the masses by writing between the lines However this seems like a false premise as most authors Strauss refers to in his work lived in times when only the social elites were literate enough to understand works of philosophy 64 Conservatism edit Some critics of Strauss have accused him of being elitist illiberal and anti democratic Journalists such as Seymour Hersh have opined that Strauss endorsed noble lies myths used by political leaders seeking to maintain a cohesive society 65 66 In The City and Man Strauss discusses the myths outlined in Plato s Republic that are required for all governments These include a belief that the state s land belongs to it even though it may have been acquired illegitimately and that citizenship is rooted in something more than accidents of birth 67 Shadia Drury in Leo Strauss and the American Right 1999 claimed that Strauss inculcated an elitist strain in American political leaders linked to imperialist militarism neoconservatism and Christian fundamentalism Drury argues that Strauss teaches that perpetual deception of the citizens by those in power is critical because they need to be led and they need strong rulers to tell them what s good for them Nicholas Xenos similarly argues that Strauss was an anti democrat in a fundamental sense a true reactionary Xenos says Strauss was somebody who wanted to go back to a previous pre liberal pre bourgeois era of blood and guts of imperial domination of authoritarian rule of pure fascism 68 Anti historicism edit Strauss has also been criticized by some conservatives According to Claes G Ryn Strauss s anti historicist thinking creates an artificial contrast between moral universality and the conventional the ancestral and the historical Strauss Ryn argues wrongly and reductively assumes that respect for tradition must undermine reason and universality Contrary to Strauss s criticism of Edmund Burke the historical sense may be indispensable to an adequate apprehension of universality Strauss s abstract ahistorical conception of natural right distorts genuine universality Ryn contends Strauss does not consider the possibility that real universality becomes known to human beings in a concretized particular form Strauss and the Straussians have paradoxically taught philosophically unsuspecting American conservatives not least Roman Catholic intellectuals to reject tradition in favor of ahistorical theorizing a bias that flies in the face of the central Christian notion of the Incarnation which represents a synthesis of the universal and the historical According to Ryn the propagation of a purely abstract idea of universality has contributed to the neoconservative advocacy of allegedly universal American principles which neoconservatives see as justification for American intervention around the world bringing the blessings of the West to the benighted rest Strauss s anti historical thinking connects him and his followers with the French Jacobins who also regarded tradition as incompatible with virtue and rationality 69 What Ryn calls the new Jacobinism of the neoconservative philosophy is writes Paul Gottfried also the rhetoric of Saint Just and Leon Trotsky which the philosophically impoverished American Right has taken over with mindless alacrity Republican operators and think tanks apparently believe they can carry the electorate by appealing to yesterday s leftist cliches 70 71 Response to criticism edit In his 2009 book Straussophobia Peter Minowitz provides a detailed critique of Drury Xenos and other critics of Strauss whom he accuses of bigotry and buffoonery 72 In Reading Leo Strauss Steven B Smith rejects the link between Strauss and neoconservative thought arguing that Strauss was never personally active in politics never endorsed imperialism and questioned the utility of political philosophy for the practice of politics In particular Strauss argued that Plato s myth of the philosopher king should be read as a reductio ad absurdum and that philosophers should understand politics not in order to influence policy but to ensure philosophy s autonomy from politics 73 In his review of Reading Leo Strauss Robert Alter writes that Smith persuasively sets the record straight on Strauss s political views and on what his writing is really about 74 Strauss s daughter Jenny Strauss Clay defended Strauss against the charge that he was the mastermind behind the neoconservative ideologues who control United States foreign policy He was a conservative she says insofar as he did not think change is necessarily change for the better Since contemporary academia leaned to the left with its unquestioned faith in progress and science combined with a queasiness regarding any kind of moral judgment Strauss stood outside of the academic consensus Had academia leaned to the right he would have questioned it too and on certain occasions did question the tenets of the right 75 Mark Lilla has argued that the attribution to Strauss of neoconservative views contradicts a careful reading of Strauss actual texts in particular On Tyranny Lilla summarizes Strauss as follows Philosophy must always be aware of the dangers of tyranny as a threat to both political decency and the philosophical life It must understand enough about politics to defend its own autonomy without falling into the error of thinking that philosophy can shape the political world according to its own lights 76 Responding to charges that Strauss s teachings fostered the neoconservative foreign policy of the George W Bush administration such as unrealistic hopes for the spread of liberal democracy through military conquest Nathan Tarcov director of the Leo Strauss Center at the University of Chicago asserts that Strauss as a political philosopher was essentially non political After an exegesis of the very limited practical political views to be gleaned from Strauss s writings Tarcov concludes that Strauss can remind us of the permanent problems but we have only ourselves to blame for our faulty solutions to the problems of today 77 Bibliography editBooks and articlesGesammelte Schriften Ed Heinrich Meier Stuttgart J B Metzler 1996 Four vols published to date Vol 1 Die Religionskritik Spinozas und zugehorige Schriften rev ed 2001 vol 2 Philosophie und Gesetz Fruhe Schriften 1997 Vol 3 Hobbes politische Wissenschaft und zugehorige Schrifte Briefe 2001 Vol 4 Politische Philosophie Studien zum theologisch politischen Problem 2010 The full series will also include Vol 5 Uber Tyrannis 2013 and Vol 6 Gedanken uber Machiavelli Deutsche Erstubersetzung 2014 Leo Strauss The Early Writings 1921 1932 Trans from parts of Gesammelte Schriften Trans Michael Zank Albany SUNY Press 2002 Die Religionskritik Spinozas als Grundlage seiner Bibelwissenschaft Untersuchungen zu Spinozas Theologisch politischem Traktat Berlin Akademie Verlag 1930 Spinoza s Critique of Religion English trans by Elsa M Sinclair of Die Religionskritik Spinozas 1930 With a new English preface and a trans of Strauss s 1932 German essay on Carl Schmitt New York Schocken 1965 Reissued without that essay Chicago U of Chicago P 1997 Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitt Der Begriff des Politischen Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 67 no 6 August September 1932 732 49 Comments on Carl Schmitt s Begriff des Politischen English trans by Elsa M Sinclair of Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitt 1932 331 51 in Spinoza s Critique of Religion 1965 Reprinted in Carl Schmitt The Concept of the Political ed and trans George Schwab New Brunswick NJ Rutgers U Press 1976 Notes on Carl Schmitt The Concept of the Political English trans by J Harvey Lomax of Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitt 1932 In Heinrich Meier Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss The Hidden Dialogue trans J Harvey Lomax Chicago U of Chicago P 1995 Reprinted in Carl Schmitt The Concept of the Political ed and trans George Schwab Chicago U of Chicago P 1996 2007 Philosophie und Gesetz Beitrage zum Verstandnis Maimunis und seiner Vorlaufer Berlin Schocken 1935 Philosophy and Law Essays Toward the Understanding of Maimonides and His Predecessors English trans by Fred Baumann of Philosophie und Gesetz 1935 Philadelphia Jewish Publication Society 1987 Philosophy and Law Contributions to the Understanding of Maimonides and His Predecessors English trans with introd by Eve Adler of Philosophie und Gesetz 1935 Albany SUNY Press 1995 The Political Philosophy of Hobbes Its Basis and Its Genesis English trans by Elsa M Sinclair from German manuscript Oxford Clarendon Press 1936 Reissued with new preface Chicago U of Chicago P 1952 Hobbes politische Wissenschaft in ihrer Genesis 1935 German original of The Political Philosophy of Hobbes 1936 Neuwied am Rhein Hermann Luchterhand 1965 The Spirit of Sparta or the Taste of Xenophon Social Research 6 no 4 Winter 1939 502 36 On German Nihilism 1999 originally a 1941 lecture Interpretation 26 no 3 edited by David Janssens and Daniel Tanguay Farabi s Plato American Academy for Jewish Research Louis Ginzberg Jubilee Volume 1945 45 pp On a New Interpretation of Plato s Political Philosophy Social Research 13 no 3 Fall 1946 326 67 On the Intention of Rousseau Social Research 14 no 4 Winter 1947 455 87 On Tyranny An Interpretation of Xenophon s Hiero Foreword by Alvin Johnson New York Political Science Classics 1948 Reissued Glencoe Ill The Free Press 1950 De la tyrannie French trans of On Tyranny 1948 with Restatement on Xenophon s Hiero and Alexandre Kojeve s Tyranny and Wisdom Paris Librairie Gallimard 1954 On Tyranny English edition of De la tyrannie 1954 Ithaca Cornell UP 1963 On Tyranny Revised and expanded edition of On Tyranny 1963 Includes Strauss Kojeve correspondence Ed Victor Gourevitch and Michael S Roth New York The Free Press 1991 On Collingwood s Philosophy of History Review of Metaphysics 5 no 4 June 1952 559 86 Persecution and the Art of Writing Glencoe Ill The Free Press 1952 Reissued Chicago U of Chicago P 1988 Natural Right and History Based on the 1949 Walgreen lectures Chicago U of Chicago P 1953 Reprinted with new preface 1971 ISBN 978 0 226 77694 1 Existentialism 1956 a public lecture on Martin Heidegger s thought published in Interpretation Spring 1995 Vol 22 No 3 303 18 Seminar on Plato s Republic 1957 Lecture 1961 Lecture University of Chicago Thoughts on Machiavelli Glencoe Ill The Free Press 1958 Reissued Chicago U of Chicago P 1978 What Is Political Philosophy and Other Studies Glencoe Ill The Free Press 1959 Reissued Chicago U of Chicago Press 1988 On Plato s Symposium 1959 Ed Seth Benardete Edited transcript of 1959 lectures Chicago U of Chicago P 2001 Relativism 135 57 in Helmut Schoeck and James W Wiggins eds Relativism and the Study of Man Princeton D Van Nostrand 1961 Partial reprint 13 26 in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism 1989 History of Political Philosophy Co editor with Joseph Cropsey Chicago U of Chicago P 1963 1st ed 1972 2nd ed 1987 3rd ed The Crisis of Our Time 41 54 and The Crisis of Political Philosophy 91 103 in Howard Spaeth ed The Predicament of Modern Politics Detroit U of Detroit P 1964 Political Philosophy and the Crisis of Our Time Adaptation of the two essays in Howard Spaeth ed The Predicament of Modern Politics 1964 217 42 in George J Graham Jr and George W Carey eds The Post Behavioral Era Perspectives on Political Science New York David McKay 1972 The City and Man Based on the 1962 Page Barbour lectures Chicago Rand McNally 1964 Socrates and Aristophanes New York Basic Books 1966 Reissued Chicago U of Chicago P 1980 Liberalism Ancient and Modern New York Basic Books 1968 Reissued with foreword by Allan Bloom 1989 Reissued Chicago U of Chicago P 1995 Xenophon s Socratic Discourse An Interpretation of the Oeconomicus Ithaca Cornell UP 1970 Note on the Plan of Nietzsche s Beyond Good amp Evil St John s College 1971 Xenophon s Socrates Ithaca Cornell UP 1972 The Argument and the Action of Plato s Laws Chicago U of Chicago P 1975 Political Philosophy Six Essays by Leo Strauss Ed Hilail Gilden Indianapolis Bobbs Merrill 1975 An Introduction to Political Philosophy Ten Essays by Leo Strauss Expanded version of Political Philosophy Six Essays by Leo Strauss 1975 Ed Hilail Gilden Detroit Wayne State UP 1989 Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy Introd by Thomas L Pangle Chicago U of Chicago P 1983 The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism An Introduction to the Thought of Leo Strauss Essays and Lectures by Leo Strauss Ed Thomas L Pangle Chicago U of Chicago P 1989 Faith and Political Philosophy the Correspondence Between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin 1934 1964 Ed Peter Emberley and Barry Cooper Introd by Thomas L Pangle University Park PA The Pennsylvania State UP 1993 Hobbes s Critique of Religion and Related Writings Ed and trans Gabriel Bartlett and Svetozar Minkov Chicago U of Chicago P 2011 Trans of materials first published in the Gesammelte Schriften Vol 3 including an unfinished manuscript by Leo Strauss of a book on Hobbes written in 1933 1934 and some shorter related writings Leo Strauss on Moses Mendelssohn Edited and translated by Martin D Yaffe Chicago University of Chicago Press 2012 Annotated translation of ten introductions written by Strauss to a multi volume critical edition of Mendelssohn s work Exoteric Teaching Critical Edition by Hannes Kerber In Reorientation Leo Strauss in the 1930s Edited by Martin D Yaffe and Richard S Ruderman New York Palgrave 2014 pp 275 86 Lecture Notes for Persecution and the Art of Writing Critical Edition by Hannes Kerber In Reorientation Leo Strauss in the 1930s Edited by Martin D Yaffe and Richard S Ruderman New York Palgrave 2014 pp 293 304 Leo Strauss on Nietzsche s Thus Spoke Zarathustra Edited by Richard L Velkley Chicago University of Chicago Press 2017 Leo Strauss on Political Philosophy Responding to the Challenge of Positivism and Historicism Edited by Catherine H Zuckert Chicago University of Chicago Press 2018 Leo Strauss on Hegel Edited by Paul Franco Chicago University of Chicago Press 2019 Writings about Maimonides and Jewish philosophySpinoza s Critique of Religion see above 1930 Philosophy and Law see above 1935 Quelques remarques sur la science politique de Maimonide et de Farabi Revue des etudes juives 100 1936 1 37 Der Ort der Vorsehungslehre nach der Ansicht Maimunis Monatschrift fur Geschichte und Wissenschaft des Judentums 81 1936 448 56 The Literary Character of The Guide for the Perplexed 1941 38 94 in Persecution and the Art of Writing Chicago U of Chicago P 1952 1944 How to Study Medieval Philosophy Interpretation 23 no 3 Spring 1996 319 338 Previously published less annotations and fifth paragraph as How to Begin to Study Medieval Philosophy in Pangle ed The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism 1989 see above 1952 Modern Judaism 1 no 1 May 1981 17 45 Reprinted Chap 1 I II in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity 1997 see below 1952 Independent Journal of Philosophy 3 1979 111 18 Reprinted Chap 1 III in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity 1997 see below Maimonides Statement on Political Science Proceedings of the American Academy for Jewish Research 22 1953 115 30 1957 L Homme 21 n 1 janvier mars 1981 5 20 Reprinted Chap 8 in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity 1997 see below How to Begin to Study The Guide of the Perplexed In The Guide of the Perplexed Volume One Trans Shlomo Pines Chicago U of Chicago P 1963 1965 On the Plan of the Guide of the Perplexed Harry Austryn Wolfson Jubilee Volume Jerusalem American Academy for Jewish Research pp 775 91 Notes on Maimonides Book of Knowledge 269 83 in Studies in Mysticism and Religion Presented to G G Scholem Jerusalem Magnes Press 1967 Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought Ed Kenneth Hart Green Albany SUNY P 1997 Leo Strauss on Maimonides The Complete Writings Edited by Kenneth Hart Green Chicago University of Chicago Press 2013 See also edit nbsp conservatism portalAmerican philosophy List of American philosophers Neoconservatism often referred as inspired by the work of Strauss Lev Shestov Allan Bloom Seth Benardete Jacob KleinNotes edit Joachim Luders and Ariane Wehner Mittelhessen eine Heimat fur Juden Das Schicksal der Familie Strauss aus Kirchhain Central Hesse a Homeland for Jews The Fate of the Strauss Family from Kirchhain 1989 In A Giving of Accounts published in The College 22 1 and later reprinted in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity a b Jewish philosophy and the crisis of modernity SUNY 1997 Leo Strauss as a Modern Jewish thinker Kenneth Hart Green Leo Strauss page 55 a b Scholem Gershom 1981 Walter Benjamin The Story of a Friendship Trans Harry Zohn p 201 a b The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin and Gershom Scholem 1932 40 New York 1989 pp 155 58 Leo Strauss And the Politics of Exile The Making of a Political Philosopher p 87 Eugene Sheppard 2014 Leo Strauss and the Politics of Exile The Making of a Political Philosopher Brandeis UP pp 102 03 ISBN 9781611687699 Leo Strauss Natural Right and History Chicago University of Chicago Press 1965 1953 p 42 Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity Essays and Lectures in Modernity preface p 6 Leo Strauss Archived from the original on 2021 01 17 Retrieved 2020 12 02 a b c Leora Batnitzky Leo Strauss the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 9 April 2021 a b c Shadia Drury 1998 Strauss Leo 1899 1973 In The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Taylor and Francis Retrieved 30 Dec 2023 doi 10 4324 9780415249126 S092 1 Laurence Lampert The Enduring Importance of Leo Strauss University of Chicago Press 2013 p 126 From these things it is evident that the city belongs among the things that exist by nature and that man is by nature a political animal Aristotle The Politics 1253a1 3 Steven B Smith Reading Leo Strauss Politics Philosophy Judaism University of Chicago Press 2007 p 13 Pangle Thomas L Leo Strauss An Introduction to His Thought and Intellectual Legacy Baltimore Johns Hopkins UP 2006 p 51 Classical political philosophy is not concerned to rule but it is concerned to understand political society and to share its understanding in a constructive fashion with the various political societies and their citizens and rulers Cf also his Fundamental Tension ibid p 54f Leo Strauss An Introduction to Heideggerian Existentialism 27 46 in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism ed Thomas L Pangle Chicago U of Chicago P 1989 29 30 Velkley Richard L 2015 Heidegger Strauss and the premises of philosophy on original forgetting Paperback 2015 ed Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 9780226214948 Leo Strauss Relativism 13 26 in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism ed Thomas L Pangle Chicago University of Chicago Press 25 Drury S B 1987 Leo Strauss s Classic Natural Right Teaching Political Theory 15 3 299 315 doi 10 1177 0090591787015003001 JSTOR 191204 S2CID 143546488 Exoteric Teaching Critical Edition by Hannes Kerber In Reorientation Leo Strauss in the 1930s Edited by Martin D Yaffe and Richard S Ruderman New York Palgrave 2014 p 275 Smith Steven 2007 Reading Leo Strauss University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0226763897 Archived from the original on 2020 11 09 Retrieved 2006 09 20 excerpt entitled Why Strauss Why Now Mansfield Harvey 1975 Strauss s Machiavelli Political Theory JSTOR 190834 a book containing much that is appreciably esoteric to any reader stated in a manner either so elusive or so challenging as to cause him to give up trying to understand it Damon Linker October 31 2014 What if Leo Strauss was Right The Week Archived from the original on 2014 11 03 Retrieved 2014 11 04 Michael Paley and Jacob J Staub in Jewish Philosophy Medieval and Modern printed in The Schocken Guide to Jewish Books 1992 p 215 Winfried Schroder ed Reading between the lines Leo Strauss and the history of early modern philosophy Walter de Gruyter 2015 p 39 According to Robert Hunt t he Straussian hermeneutic sees the course of intellectual history as an ongoing conversation about important philosophical questions Jew and Philosopher The Return to Maimonides in the Jewish Thought of Leo Strauss p 25 Allan Bloom Leo Strauss 235 55 in Giants and Dwarfs Essays 1960 1990 New York Simon and Schuster 1990 238 39 Faith and Political Philosophy The Correspondence Between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin 1934 1964 p 193 Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker p 3 Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss the hidden dialogue Heinrich Meier University of Chicago Press 1995 123 Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss the hidden dialogue Heinrich Meier University of Chicago Press 1995 125 Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss the hidden dialogue Heinrich Meier University of Chicago Press 1995 Lilla Mark 2001 Alexandre Kojeve The Reckless Mind Intellectuals in Politics New York New York Review Books p 131 ISBN 978 0 940322 76 9 Strauss Leo Gourevitch Victor Roth Michael S eds On Tyranny Thomas L Pangle Epilogue 907 38 in History of Political Philosophy ed Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey 3rd ed Chicago University of Chicago Press 1987 907 8 Leo Strauss On Tyranny New York Free Press 1991 22 23 178 Leo Strauss The Crisis of Our Time 41 54 in Howard Spaeth ed The Predicament of Modern Politics Detroit University of Detroit Press 1964 47 48 Leo Strauss What Is Political Philosophy 9 55 in Leo Strauss What Is Political Philosophy and Other Studies Glencoe IL The Free Press 1959 18 19 Leo Strauss The City and Man Chicago Rand McNally 1964 10 11 Leo Strauss Plato 33 89 in History of Political Philosophy ed Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey 3rd ed Chicago University of Chicago Press 1987 68 Leo Strauss Plato 33 89 in History of Political Philosophy ed Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey 3rd ed Chicago University of Chicago Press 1987 60 On Tyranny p 143 Voegelin Eric Strauss Leo 20 August 2004 Letter 30 April 18 1950 In Emberley Peter Cooper Barry eds Faith and Political Philosophy The Correspondence between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin 1934 1964 University of Missouri p 68 ISBN 978 0826215512 Anonymous 2011 07 15 Strauss and Voegelin on Popper Philosophy of Science Archived from the original on 2013 07 28 Retrieved 4 February 2019 Leo Strauss the Straussians and the American Regime by Kenneth Deutch 1999 p 104 Strauss Leo Natural Right and History Chicago University of Chicago Press 1953 p 164 Adam Smith in His Time and Ours Designing the Decent Society By Jerry Z Muller a b Jewish philosophy and the crisis of modernity SUNY 1997 Leo Strauss as a Modern Jewish thinker Kenneth Hart Green Leo Strauss p 55 Green K H editor Strauss Leo Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought 1997 State University of New York Press p 3 Green K H editor Strauss L Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought 1997 State University of New York Press pp 413 14 see his writings on Max Weber Strauss felt that one should either be the philosopher open to the challenge of theology or the theologian open to the challenge of philosophy see Deutsch Kenneth L and Walter Nicgorski Leo Strauss Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker pp 11 12 1994 Rowman amp Littlefield but where Aquinas saw an amicable interplay between reason and revelation Strauss saw two impregnable fortresses per Schall S J James V A Latitude for Statesmanship Strauss on St Thomas in Leo Strauss Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker ed Kenneth L Deutsch and Walter Nicgorski pp 212 15 1994 Rowman amp Littlefield For an early treatment of Aquinas understanding of the relation between philosophy and sacred revealed law see Strauss s early Philosophy and Law Philosophie und Gesetz where Christian medieval theology testifies to a less than amicable opposition between pagan though not necessarily Platonic or political philosophy and Biblical morality Feser Edward Leo Strauss 101 a review of Steven B Smith s Reading Leo Strauss Politics Philosophy Judaism National Review Online May 22 2006 Archived November 15 2006 at the Wayback Machine See Natural Right and History especially p 119A and Chapter III The Origin of the Idea of Natural Right Shadia B Drury Leo Strauss and the American Right Palgrave Macmillan 1999 Peter Minowitz Straussophobia Defending Leo Strauss and Straussians against Shadia Drury and Other Accusers Lexington Books 2009 a b c d Approaches to Political Thought edited by William L Richter Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers 16 Mar 2009 p 56 Definition of PEDAGOGIC Archived from the original on 2020 10 22 Retrieved 2020 12 26 a b c d e f g h Mark C Henrie May 5 2011 Straussianism First Principles ISI Web Journal Archived from the original on December 21 2018 Retrieved November 24 2014 Transcript of Harvey Mansfield IV conversationswithbillkristol org Archived from the original on 15 March 2018 Retrieved 14 March 2018 Marchal Kai 2017 Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss in the Chinese speaking World Reorienting the Political Lanham Maryland Lexington Books p 7 ISBN 978 1498536264 Bekesi Aron B 2019 12 31 Esoteric philosophy Leo Strauss and sociolinguistics Science amp Philosophy 7 2 doi 10 23756 sp v7i2 481 Seymour M Hersh Selective Intelligence Archived 2014 07 17 at the Wayback Machine The New Yorker May 12 2003 Retrieved June 1 2007 Brian Doherty Origin of the Specious Why Do Neoconservatives Doubt Darwin Archived 2016 07 31 at the Wayback Machine Reason Online July 1997 Retrieved February 16 2007 The City and Man p 104 Nicholas Xenos Leo Strauss and the Rhetoric of the War on Terror Archived 2021 01 26 at the Wayback Machine Logosjournal com Claes G Ryn Leo Strauss and History The Philosopher as Conspirator Humanitas Vol XVIII Nos 1 amp 2 2005 Paul Gottfried Strauss and the Straussians Archived 2015 06 18 at the Wayback Machine LewRockwell com April 17 2006 Retrieved February 16 2007 Cf Paul Gottfried Paul Gottfried Archives Archived 2015 06 18 at the Wayback Machine Lewrockwell com Retrieved February 16 2007 Peter Minowitz Straussophobia Defending Leo Strauss and Straussians against Shadia Drury and Other Accusers Lanham MD Lexington Books 2009 Also see Straussophobia Six Questions for Peter Minowitz Harper s Magazine 9 29 09 1 Archived 2012 10 19 at the Wayback Machine Steven B Smith excerpt from Why Strauss Why Now Archived 2020 11 09 at the Wayback Machine 1 15 in Reading Leo Strauss Politics Philosophy Judaism Chicago U of Chicago P 2006 online posting press uchicago edu Retrieved June 1 2007 Robert Alter Neocon or Not Archived 2017 08 26 at the Wayback Machine The New York Times Book Review June 25 2006 accessed February 16 2007 citing Yale scholar Steven B Smith Reading Leo Strauss Politics Philosophy Judaism Chicago U of Chicago P 2006 Jenny Strauss Clay June 7 2003 The Real Leo Strauss The New York Times Archived from the original on April 2 2015 Retrieved March 30 2015 Mark Lilla The Reckless Mind New York NY Review of Books 2001 133 Nathan Tarcov Will the Real Leo Strauss Please Stand Up in The American Interest September October 1986 at Will the Real Leo Strauss Please Stand Up Nathan Tarcov the American Interest Magazine Archived from the original on 2010 11 30 Retrieved 2009 06 28 Further reading edit A Giving of Accounts In Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought Ed Kenneth H Green Albany SUNY Press 1997 Altman William H F The German Stranger Leo Strauss and National Socialism Lexington Books 2011 Andreacchio Marco Philosophy and Religion in Leo Strauss Critical Review of Menon s Interpretation Interpretation A Journal of Political Philosophy 46 no 2 Spring 2020 383 98 Behnegar Nasser Leo Strauss Max Weber And The Scientific Study Of Politics University of Chicago Press 2005 Benardete Seth Encounters and Reflections Conversations with Seth Benardete Chicago U of Chicago P 2002 Bloom Allan Leo Strauss 235 55 in Giants and Dwarfs Essays 1960 1990 New York Simon and Schuster 1990 Bluhm Harald Die Ordnung der Ordnung das politische Philosophieren von Leo Strauss Berlin Akademie Verlag 2002 Brague Remi Leo Strauss and Maimonides 93 114 in Leo Strauss s Thought Ed Alan Udoff Boulder Lynne Reiner 1991 Brittain Christopher Craig Leo Strauss and Resourceful Odysseus Rhetorical Violence and the Holy Middle Canadian Review of American Studies 38 no 1 2008 147 63 Bruell Christopher A Return to Classical Political Philosophy and the Understanding of the American Founding Review of Politics 53 no 1 Winter 1991 173 86 Chivilo Giampiero and Menon Marco eds Tirannide e filosofia Con un saggio di Leo Strauss ed un inedito di Gaston Fessard sj Venezia Edizioni Ca Foscari 2015 ISBN 978 88 6969 032 7 Colen Jose Facts and values London Plusprint 2012 Deutsch Kenneth L and John A Murley eds Leo Strauss the Straussians and the American Regime New York Rowman amp Littlefield 1999 ISBN 978 0 8476 8692 6 Drury Shadia B Leo Strauss and the American Right London Palgrave Macmillan 1999 The Political Ideas of Leo Strauss New York St Martin s Press 1988 Gottfried Paul Leo Strauss and the Conservative Movement in America A Critical Appraisal Cambridge University Press 2011 Gourevitch Victor Philosophy and Politics I II Review of Metaphysics 22 nos 1 2 September December 1968 58 84 281 328 Green Kenneth Jew and Philosopher The Return to Maimonides in the Jewish Thought of Leo Strauss Albany SUNY Press 1993 Havers Grant N Leo Strauss and Anglo American Democracy A Conservative Critique DeKalb IL Northern Illinois University Press 2013 Holmes Stephen The Anatomy of Antiliberalism Cambridge Harvard UP 1996 ISBN 978 0 674 03185 2 Howse Robert Leo Strauss Man of Peace Cambridge University Press 2014 Ivry Alfred L Leo Strauss on Maimonides 75 91 in Leo Strauss s Thought Ed Alan Udoff Boulder Lynne Reiner 1991 Janssens David Between Athens and Jerusalem Philosophy Prophecy and Politics in Leo Strauss s Early Thought Albany SUNY Press 2008 Kartheininger Markus Heterogenitat Politische Philosophie im Fruhwerk von Leo Strauss Munchen Fink 2006 ISBN 978 3 7705 4378 6 Kartheininger Markus Aristokratisierung des Geistes In Kartheininger Markus Hutter Axel ed Bildung als Mittel und Selbstzweck Freiburg Alber 2009 pp 157 208 ISBN 978 3 495 48393 0 Kerber Hannes Strauss and Schleiermacher An Introduction to Exoteric Teaching In Reorientation Leo Strauss in the 1930s Ed Yaffe Ruderman New York Palgrave 2014 pp 203 14 Kerber Hannes Leo Strauss on Exoteric Writing Interpretation 46 no 1 2019 3 25 Kinzel Till Platonische Kulturkritik in Amerika Studien zu Allan Blooms The Closing of the American Mind Berlin Duncker und Humblot 2002 Kochin Michael S Morality Nature and Esotericism in Leo Strauss s Persecution and the Art of Writing Review of Politics 64 no 2 Spring 2002 261 83 Lampert Laurence Leo Strauss and Nietzsche Chicago U of Chicago P 1996 Lutz Mark J Living the Theologico Political Problem Leo Strauss on the Common Ground of Philosophy and Theology The European Legacy 2018 Vol 23 No 8 pp 1 25 Macpherson C B Hobbes s Bourgeois Man In Democratic Theory Essays in Retrieval Oxford Oxford University Press 1972 Major Rafael ed Leo Strauss s Defense of the Philosophic Life Reading What is Political Philosophy University of Chicago Press 2013 ISBN 978 0 226 92420 5 cloth Marchal Kai Shaw Carl K Y Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss in the Chinese speaking World Reorienting the Political Lanham Maryland Lexington Books 2017 McAllister Ted V Revolt Against Modernity Leo Strauss Eric Voegelin amp the Search for Postliberal Order Lawrence KS UP of Kansas 1996 McWilliams Wilson Carey Leo Strauss and the Dignity of American Political Thought Review of Politics 60 no 2 Spring 1998 231 46 Meier Heinrich Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss The Hidden Dialogue Chicago U of Chicago P 1995 Editor s Introduction s Gesammelte Schriften Stuttgart J B Metzler 1996 3 vols Leo Strauss and the Theologico Political Problem Cambridge Cambridge UP 2006 How Strauss Became Strauss 363 82 in Enlightening Revolutions Essays in Honor of Ralph Lerner Ed Svetozar Minkov Lanham MD Lexington Books 2006 Melzer Arthur Esotericism and the Critique of Historicism American Political Science Review 100 2006 279 95 Minowitz Peter Machiavellianism Come of Age Leo Strauss on Modernity and Economics The Political Science Reviewer 22 1993 157 97 Straussophobia Defending Leo Strauss and Straussians against Shadia Drury and Other Accusers Lanham MD Lexington Books 2009 Momigliano Arnaldo Hermeneutics and Classical Political Thought in Leo Strauss 178 89 in Essays on Ancient and Modern Judaism Chicago U of Chicago P 1994 Moyn Samuel From experience to law Leo Strauss and the Weimar crisis of the philosophy of religion History of European Ideas 33 2007 174 94 Neumann Harry Liberalism Durham NC Carolina Academic P 1991 Norton Anne Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire New Haven amp London Yale UP 2004 Pangle Thomas L The Epistolary Dialogue Between Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin Review of Politics 53 no 1 Winter 1991 100 25 Leo Strauss s Perspective on Modern Politics Perspectives on Political Science 33 no 4 Fall 2004 197 203 Leo Strauss An Introduction to His Thought and Intellectual Legacy Baltimore Johns Hopkins UP 2006 Pelluchon Corine Leo Strauss and the Crisis of Rationalism Another Reason Another Enlightenment Robert Howse tr SUNY Press 2014 Piccinini Irene Abigail Una guida fedele L influenza di Hermann Cohen sul pensiero di Leo Strauss Torino Trauben 2007 ISBN 978 88 89909 31 7 Rosen Stanley Hermeneutics as Politics 87 140 in Hermeneutics as Politics New York Oxford UP 1987 Sheppard Eugene R Leo Strauss and the Politics of Exile The Making of a Political Philosopher Waltham MA Brandeis UP 2006 ISBN 978 1 58465 600 5 Shorris Earl Ignoble Liars Leo Strauss George Bush and the Philosophy of Mass Deception Harper s Magazine 308 issue 1849 June 2004 65 71 Smith Steven B Reading Leo Strauss Politics Philosophy Judaism Chicago U of Chicago P 2006 ISBN 978 0 226 76402 3 Introd Why Strauss Why Now online posting press uchicago edu Smith Steven B editor The Cambridge Companion to Leo Strauss Cambridge Cambridge UP 2009 ISBN 978 0 521 70399 4 Steiner Stephan Weimar in Amerika Leo Strauss Politische Philosophie Tubingen Mohr Siebeck 2013 Strong Tracy B Leo Strauss and the Demos The European Legacy October 2012 Tanguay Daniel Leo Strauss une biographie intellectuelle Paris 2005 ISBN 978 2 253 13067 3 Tarcov Nathan On a Certain Critique of Straussianism Review of Politics 53 no 1 Winter 1991 3 18 Philosophy and History Tradition and Interpretation in the Work of Leo Strauss Polity 16 no 1 Autumn 1983 5 29 and Thomas L Pangle Epilogue Leo Strauss and the History of Political Philosophy 907 38 in History of Political Philosophy Ed Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey 3rd ed 1963 Chicago and London U of Chicago P 1987 Tepper Aryeh Progressive Minds Conservative Politics Leo Strauss Later Writings on Maimonides SUNY 2013 Thompson Bradley C with Yaron Brook Neoconservatism An Obituary for an Idea Boulder London Paradigm Publishers 2010 pp 55 131 ISBN 978 1 59451 831 7 Velkley Richard Heidegger Strauss and the Premises of Philosophy On Original Forgetting University of Chicago Press 2011 West Thomas G Jaffa Versus Mansfield Does America Have a Constitutional or a Declaration of Independence Soul Perspectives on Political Science 31 no 4 Fall 2002 35 46 Xenos Nicholas Cloaked in virtue Unveiling Leo Strauss and the Rhetoric of American Foreign Policy New York Routledge Press 2008 Zuckert Catherine H Postmodern Platos Chicago U of Chicago P 1996 Zuckert Catherine H and Michael Zuckert The Truth about Leo Strauss Chicago U of Chicago P 2006 Strauss family edit Luders Joachim and Ariane Wehner Mittelhessen eine Heimat fur Juden Das Schicksal der Familie Strauss aus Kirchhain Marburg Gymnasium Philippinum 1989 In German English translation Central Hesse a Homeland for Jews The Fate of the Strauss Family from Kirchhain External links editLeo Strauss at Wikipedia s sister projects nbsp Media from Commons nbsp Quotations from Wikiquote nbsp Textbooks from Wikibooks The Leo Strauss Center The Leo Strauss Foundation Guide to the Leo Strauss Papers circa 1930 1997 at the University of Chicago Special Collections Research Center Works by or about Leo Strauss at Internet Archive Leora Batnitzky Leo Strauss In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Leo Strauss amp oldid 1206217986, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.