fbpx
Wikipedia

Four causes

The four causes or four explanations are, in Aristotelian thought, four fundamental types of answer to the question "why?" in analysis of change or movement in nature: the material, the formal, the efficient, and the final. Aristotle wrote that "we do not have knowledge of a thing until we have grasped its why, that is to say, its cause."[1][2] While there are cases in which classifying a "cause" is difficult, or in which "causes" might merge, Aristotle held that his four "causes" provided an analytical scheme of general applicability.[3]

Aristotle's Four Causes illustrated for a table: material (wood), formal (structure), efficient (carpentry), final (dining).

Aristotle's word aitia (Greek: αἰτία) has, in philosophical scholarly tradition, been translated as 'cause'. This peculiar, specialized, technical, usage of the word 'cause' is not that of everyday English language.[4] Rather, the translation of Aristotle's αἰτία that is nearest to current ordinary language is "explanation."[5][2][4]

In Physics II.3 and Metaphysics V.2, Aristotle holds that there are four kinds of answers to "why" questions:[2][5][6]

Matter
The material cause of a change or movement. This is the aspect of the change or movement that is determined by the material that composes the moving or changing things. For a table, this might be wood; for a statue, it might be bronze or marble.
Form
The formal cause of a change or movement. This is a change or movement caused by the arrangement, shape, or appearance of the thing changing or moving. Aristotle says, for example, that the ratio 2:1, and number in general, is the formal cause of the octave.
Efficient, or agent
The efficient or moving cause of a change or movement. This consists of things apart from the thing being changed or moved, which interact so as to be an agency of the change or movement. For example, the efficient cause of a table is a carpenter, or a person working as one, and according to Aristotle the efficient cause of a child is a parent.
Final, end, or purpose
The final cause of a change or movement. This is a change or movement for the sake of a thing to be what it is. For a seed, it might be an adult plant; for a sailboat, it might be sailing; for a ball at the top of a ramp, it might be coming to rest at the bottom.

The four "causes" are not mutually exclusive. For Aristotle, several, preferably four, answers to the question "why" have to be given to explain a phenomenon and especially the actual configuration of an object.[7] For example, if asking why a table is such and such, an explanation in terms of the four causes would sound like this: This table is solid and brown because it is made of wood (matter); it does not collapse because it has four legs of equal length (form); it is as it is because a carpenter made it, starting from a tree (agent); it has these dimensions because it is to be used by humans (end).

Aristotle distinguished between intrinsic and extrinsic causes. Matter and form are intrinsic causes because they deal directly with the object, whereas efficient and finality causes are said to be extrinsic because they are external.[8]

Thomas Aquinas demonstrated that only those four types of causes can exist and no others. He also introduced a priority order according to which "matter is made perfect by the form, form is made perfect by the agent, and agent is made perfect by the finality."[9] Hence, the finality is the cause of causes or, equivalently, the queen of causes.[10]

Definition of "cause" edit

In his philosophical writings, Aristotle used the Greek word αἴτιον (aition), a neuter singular form of an adjective. The Greek word had meant, perhaps originally in a "legal" context, what or who is "responsible," mostly but not always in a bad sense of "guilt" or "blame." Alternatively, it could mean "to the credit of" someone or something. The appropriation of this word by Aristotle and other philosophers reflects how the Greek experience of legal practice influenced the concern in Greek thought to determine what is responsible.[11]: 100, 106–107  The word developed other meanings, including its use in philosophy in a more abstract sense.[12][13][14]

About a century before Aristotle, the anonymous author of the Hippocratic text On Ancient Medicine had described the essential characteristics of a cause as it is considered in medicine:[15]

We must, therefore, consider the causes of each [medical] condition to be those things which are such that, when they are present, the condition necessarily occurs, but when they change to another combination, it ceases.

Aristotle's "four causes" edit

Aristotle used the four causes to provide different answers to the question, "because of what?" The four answers to this question illuminate different aspects of how a thing comes into being or of how an event takes place.[11]: 96–98 

Material edit

Aristotle considers the material "cause" (ὕλη, hū́lē)[16] of an object as equivalent to the nature of the raw material out of which the object is composed. (The word "nature" for Aristotle applies to both its potential in the raw material and its ultimate finished form. In a sense this form already existed in the material: see potentiality and actuality.)

Whereas modern physics looks to simple bodies, Aristotle's physics took a more general viewpoint, and treated living things as exemplary. Nevertheless, he felt that simple natural bodies such as earth, fire, air, and water also showed signs of having their own innate sources of motion, change, and rest. Fire, for example, carries things upwards, unless stopped from doing so. Things formed by human artifice, such as beds and cloaks, have no innate tendency to become beds or cloaks.[17]

In traditional Aristotelian philosophical terminology, material is not the same as substance. Matter has parallels with substance in so far as primary matter serves as the substratum for simple bodies which are not substance: sand and rock (mostly earth), rivers and seas (mostly water), atmosphere and wind (mostly air and then mostly fire below the moon). In this traditional terminology, 'substance' is a term of ontology, referring to really existing things; only individuals are said to be substances (subjects) in the primary sense. Secondary substance, in a different sense, also applies to man-made artifacts.

Formal edit

Aristotle considers the formal "cause" (εἶδος, eîdos)[16] as describing the pattern or form which when present makes matter into a particular type of thing, which we recognize as being of that particular type.

By Aristotle's own account, this is a difficult and controversial concept.[citation needed] It links with theories of forms such as those of Aristotle's teacher, Plato, but in Aristotle's own account (see his Metaphysics), he takes into account many previous writers who had expressed opinions about forms and ideas, but he shows how his own views differ from them.[18]

Efficient edit

Aristotle defines the agent or efficient "cause" (κινοῦν, kinoûn)[16] of an object as that which causes change and drives transient motion (such as a painter painting a house) (see Aristotle, Physics II 3, 194b29). In many cases, this is simply the thing that brings something about. For example, in the case of a statue, it is the person chiseling away which transforms a block of marble into a statue. According to Lloyd, of the four causes, only this one is what is meant by the modern English word "cause" in ordinary speech.[19]

Final edit

Aristotle defines the end, purpose, or final "cause" (τέλος, télos)[16] as that for the sake of which a thing is done.[20] Like the form, this is a controversial type of explanation in science; some have argued for its survival in evolutionary biology,[21] while Ernst Mayr denied that it continued to play a role.[22] It is commonly recognised[23] that Aristotle's conception of nature is teleological in the sense that Nature exhibits functionality in a more general sense than is exemplified in the purposes that humans have. Aristotle observed that a telos does not necessarily involve deliberation, intention, consciousness, or intelligence:[24]

This is most obvious in the animals other than man: they make things neither by art nor after inquiry or deliberation. That is why people wonder whether it is by intelligence or by some other faculty that these creatures work, – spiders, ants, and the like... It is absurd to suppose that purpose is not present because we do not observe the agent deliberating. Art does not deliberate. If the ship-building art were in the wood, it would produce the same results by nature. If, therefore, purpose is present in art, it is present also in nature.

— Aristotle, Physics, II.8

According to Aristotle, a seed has the eventual adult plant as its end (i.e., as its telos) if and only if the seed would become the adult plant under normal circumstances.[25] In Physics II.9, Aristotle hazards a few arguments that a determination of the end (i.e., final cause) of a phenomenon is more important than the others. He argues that the end is that which brings it about, so for example "if one defines the operation of sawing as being a certain kind of dividing, then this cannot come about unless the saw has teeth of a certain kind; and these cannot be unless it is of iron."[26] According to Aristotle, once a final "cause" is in place, the material, efficient and formal "causes" follow by necessity. However, he recommends that the student of nature determine the other "causes" as well,[27] and notes that not all phenomena have an end, e.g., chance events.[28]

Aristotle saw that his biological investigations provided insights into the causes of things, especially into the final cause:

We should approach the investigation of every kind of animal without being ashamed, since in each one of them there is something natural and something beautiful. The absence of chance and the serving of ends are found in the works of nature especially. And the end, for the sake of which a thing has been constructed or has come to be, belongs to what is beautiful.

— Aristotle, On the Parts of Animals 645a 21–26, Book I, Part 5.[29]

George Holmes Howison highlights "final causation" in presenting his theory of metaphysics, which he terms "personal idealism", and to which he invites not only man, but all (ideal) life:[30]

Here, in seeing that Final Cause – causation at the call of self-posited aim or end – is the only full and genuine cause, we further see that Nature, the cosmic aggregate of phenomena and the cosmic bond of their law which in the mood of vague and inaccurate abstraction we call Force, is after all only an effect... Thus teleology, or the Reign of Final Cause, the reign of ideality, is not only an element in the notion of Evolution, but is the very vital cord in the notion. The conception of evolution is founded at last and essentially in the conception of Progress: but this conception has no meaning at all except in the light of a goal; there can be no goal unless there is a Beyond for everything actual; and there is no such Beyond except through a spontaneous ideal. The presupposition of Nature, as a system undergoing evolution, is therefore the causal activity of our Pure Ideals. These are our three organic and organizing conceptions called the True, the Beautiful, and the Good.

— George Holmes Howison, The Limits of Evolution (1901)

However, Edward Feser argues, in line with the Aristotelian and Thomistic tradition, that finality has been greatly misunderstood. Indeed, without finality, efficient causality becomes inexplicable. Finality thus understood is not purpose but that end towards which a thing is ordered.[31] When a match is rubbed against the side of a matchbox, the effect is not the appearance of an elephant or the sounding of a drum, but fire.[32] The effect is not arbitrary because the match is ordered towards the end of fire[33] which is realized through efficient causes.

In their biosemiotic study, Stuart Kauffman, Robert K. Logan et al. (2007) remark:[34]

Our language is teleological. We believe that autonomous agents constitute the minimal physical system to which teleological language rightly applies.

Scholasticism edit

In the Scholasticism, the efficient causality[35] was governed by two principles:

  • omne agens agit simile sibi[36][37][38] (every agent produces something similar to itself): stated frequently in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas, the principle establishes a relationship of similarity and analogy between cause and effect;
  • nemo dat quod non habet (no one gives what he does not possess):[39][40][41] partially similar to the legal principle of the same name, in Metaphysics it establishes that the cause cannot bestow on the effect the quantity of being (and thus of unity, truth, goodness, reality and perfection) that it does not already possess within itself. Otherwise, there would be creation out of nothingness of self and other-from-self[42] In other words, the cause must possess a degree of reality greater than or equal to that of the effect. If it is greater, we speak of equivocal causation, in analogy to the three types of logical predication (univocal, equivocal, analogical); if it is equal, we speak of univocal predication.

Thomas in this regard distinguished between causa fiendi (cause of occurring, of only beginning to be) and causa essendi (cause of being and also of beginning to be)[39][43] When the being of the agent cause is in the effect in a lesser or equal degree, this is a causa fiendi.[44] Furthermore, the second principle also establishes a qualitative link: the cause can only transmit its own essence to the effect. For example, a dog cannot transmit the essence of a feline to its young, but only that of a dog.[45] The principle is equivalent to that of Causa aequat effectum (cause equals effect)[46] in both a quantitative and qualitative sense.

Modern science edit

In his Advancement of Learning (1605), Francis Bacon wrote that natural science "doth make inquiry, and take consideration of the same natures : but how? Only as to the material and efficient causes of them, and not as to the forms." Using the terminology of Aristotle, Bacon demands that, apart from the "laws of nature" themselves, the causes relevant to natural science are only efficient causes and material causes, or, to use the formulation which became famous later, natural phenomena require scientific explanation in terms of matter and motion.

In The New Organon, Bacon divides knowledge into physics and metaphysics:[47]

From the two kinds of axioms which have been spoken of arises a just division of philosophy and the sciences, taking the received terms (which come nearest to express the thing) in a sense agreeable to my own views. Thus, let the investigation of forms, which are (in the eye of reason at least, and in their essential law) eternal and immutable, constitute Metaphysics; and let the investigation of the efficient cause, and of matter, and of the latent process, and the latent configuration (all of which have reference to the common and ordinary course of nature, not to her eternal and fundamental laws) constitute Physics. And to these let there be subordinate two practical divisions: to Physics, Mechanics; to Metaphysics, what (in a purer sense of the word) I call Magic, on account of the broadness of the ways it moves in, and its greater command over nature.

Biology edit

Explanations in terms of final causes remain common in evolutionary biology.[21][48] Francisco J. Ayala has claimed that teleology is indispensable to biology since the concept of adaptation is inherently teleological.[48] In an appreciation of Charles Darwin published in Nature in 1874, Asa Gray noted "Darwin's great service to Natural Science" lies in bringing back teleology "so that, instead of Morphology versus Teleology, we shall have Morphology wedded to Teleology." Darwin quickly responded, "What you say about Teleology pleases me especially and I do not think anyone else has ever noticed the point."[21] Francis Darwin and T. H. Huxley reiterate this sentiment. The latter wrote that "the most remarkable service to the philosophy of Biology rendered by Mr. Darwin is the reconciliation of Teleology and Morphology, and the explanation of the facts of both, which his view offers."[21] James G. Lennox states that Darwin uses the term 'Final Cause' consistently in his Species Notebook, On the Origin of Species, and after.[21]

Contrary to Ayala's position, Ernst Mayr states that "adaptedness... is a posteriori result rather than an a priori goal-seeking."[49] Various commentators view the teleological phrases used in modern evolutionary biology as a type of shorthand. For example, S. H. P. Madrell writes that "the proper but cumbersome way of describing change by evolutionary adaptation [may be] substituted by shorter overtly teleological statements" for the sake of saving space, but that this "should not be taken to imply that evolution proceeds by anything other than from mutations arising by chance, with those that impart an advantage being retained by natural selection."[50] However, Lennox states that in evolution as conceived by Darwin, it is true both that evolution is the result of mutations arising by chance and that evolution is teleological in nature.[21]

Statements that a species does something "in order to" achieve survival are teleological. The validity or invalidity of such statements depends on the species and the intention of the writer as to the meaning of the phrase "in order to." Sometimes it is possible or useful to rewrite such sentences so as to avoid teleology.[51] Some biology courses have incorporated exercises requiring students to rephrase such sentences so that they do not read teleologically. Nevertheless, biologists still frequently write in a way which can be read as implying teleology even if that is not the intention.

Animal behaviour (Tinbergen's four questions) edit

Tinbergen's four questions, named after the ethologist Nikolaas Tinbergen and based on Aristotle's four causes, are complementary categories of explanations for animal behaviour. They are also commonly referred to as levels of analysis.

The four questions are on:[52][53]

  1. function, what an adaptation does that is selected for in evolution;
  2. phylogeny, the evolutionary history of an organism, revealing its relationships to other species;
  3. mechanism, namely the proximate cause of a behaviour, such as the role of testosterone in aggression; and
  4. ontogeny, the development of an organism from egg to embryo to adult.

Technology (Heidegger's four causes) edit

In The Question Concerning Technology, echoing Aristotle, Martin Heidegger describes the four causes as follows:[54]

  1. causa materialis: the material or matter
  2. causa formalis: the form or shape the material or matter enters
  3. causa finalis: the end
  4. causa efficiens: the effect that brings about the finished result.

Heidegger explains that "[w]hoever builds a house or a ship or forges a sacrificial chalice reveals what is to be brought forth, according to the terms of the four modes of occasioning."[55]

The educationist David Waddington comments that although the efficient cause, which he identifies as "the craftsman," might be thought the most significant of the four, in his view each of Heidegger's four causes is "equally co-responsible" for producing a craft item, in Heidegger's terms "bringing forth" the thing into existence. Waddington cites Lovitt's description of this bringing forth as "a unified process."[56][57]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Aristotle, Physics 194 b17–20; see also Posterior Analytics 71 b9–11; 94 a20.
  2. ^ a b c Falcon, Andrea (2019) [First published 2006]. "Aristotle on Causality: 2. The Four Causes". In Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2023-06-19. ... for a full range of cases, an explanation which fails to invoke all four causes is no explanation at all.
  3. ^ Lindberg, David. 1992. The Beginnings of Western Science. p. 53.
  4. ^ a b Leroi 2015, pp. 91–92.
  5. ^ a b "Aristotle famously distinguishes four 'causes' (or causal factors in explanation), the matter, the form, the end, and the agent." Hankinson, R. J. 1998. Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 159. ISBN 978-0198237457. doi:10.1093/0199246564.001.0001.
  6. ^ Aristotle. Metaphysics V, (Aristotle in 23 Volumes, vols. 17–18), translated by H. Tredennick (1933/1989). London, William Heinemann Ltd. 1989 – via Perseus Project. § 1013a. Aristotle discusses the four "causes" in his Physics, Book B, ch. 3.
  7. ^ According to Reece (2018): "Aristotle thinks that human action is a species of animal self-movement, and animal self-movement is a species of natural change. Natural changes, although they are not substances and do not have causes in precisely the same way that substances do, are to be explained in terms of the four causes, or as many of them as a given natural change has: The material cause is that out of which something comes to be, or what undergoes change from one state to another; the formal cause, what differentiates something from other things, and serves as a paradigm for its coming to be that thing; the efficient cause, the starting-point of change; the final cause, that for the sake of which something comes about."
  8. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysica I. 983 a26 ss. As quoted in Battista Mondin (2022), Ontologia e Metafisica, 3rd ed., ESD, p. 157, ISBN 978-8855450539.
  9. ^ Thomas Aquinas, In IV Sententiarum, d. 3, q. 1, a. 1. sol. 1. As quoted in Battista Mondin (2022), Ontologia e metafisica, ESD, 2022, p. 158
  10. ^ Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I, q. 5, a. 2, ad. 1
  11. ^ a b Lloyd, G. E. R. 1996. "Causes and correlations." In Adversaries and authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521556953.
  12. ^ Aristotle. Ἀναλυτικὰ ὕστερα [Posterior Analytics] (in Greek). Hochschule Augsburg. Retrieved 2023-03-07. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  13. ^ Aristotle (1924). Ross, W. D. (ed.). Aristotle's Metaphysics (in Greek). Oxford: Clarendon Press – via perseus.tufts.edu.
  14. ^ Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert (1940). "αἰτιο-λογία". A Greek–English Lexicon. revised and augmented throughout by Sir Henry Stuart Jones with the assistance of Roderick McKenzie. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Retrieved 19 June 2023 – via perseus.tufts.edu.
  15. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R. 1979. Magic, Reason and Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521296412. p. 54.
  16. ^ a b c d Preus, Anthony (2015). Material cause (2nd ed.). Rowman and Littlefield. ISBN 978-0810854871. {{cite encyclopedia}}: |work= ignored (help)
  17. ^ Physics 192b
  18. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R. 1968. "The critic of Plato." pp. 43–47 in Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521094569.
  19. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996), "Causes and correlations", Adversaries and authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 96, ISBN 0521556953, It is clear that of these four, only the efficient cause looks like a cause in any ordinary English sense.
  20. ^ Aristotle, Physics, II.3. 194 b 32
  21. ^ a b c d e f Lennox, James G. (1993), "Darwin was a teleologist", Biology and Philosophy, 8 (4): 409–421, doi:10.1007/BF00857687, S2CID 170767015
  22. ^ "The development or behavior of an individual is purposive, natural selection is definitely not…. Darwin 'has swept out such finalistic teleology by the front door.'" Mayr, Ernst. 1961. "Cause and Effect in Biology." Science 134(3489):1501–1506. doi:10.1126/science.134.3489.1501. PMID 14471768.
  23. ^ Rand, Ayn (2000), The Art of Fiction, The Penguin Group, p. 20, ISBN 0452281547
  24. ^ Barnes, Jonathan, ed. The Complete Works of Aristotle, vol. I. The Revised Oxford Translation.
  25. ^ Aristotle gives this example in Parts of Animals I.1.
  26. ^ Aristotle, Physics II.9. 200b4–7.
  27. ^ Aristotle, Physics II.9.
  28. ^ Physics II.5 where chance is opposed to nature, which he has already said acts for ends.
  29. ^ Lloyd, G. E. R. (1970). Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle, New York: W. W. Norton, p. 105. ISBN 978-0393005837
  30. ^ Howison, George Holmes. 1901. The Limits of Evolution. p. 39.
  31. ^ cf. Feser, Edward (2009). Aquinas: A Beginner's Guide. Beginner's Guides (Reprint ed.). Oxford: Oneworld Publications (published 2011). ISBN 978-1780740065. Retrieved 2018-03-12. [...] three principles are central to Aquinas's general metaphysics [...] the principle of finality is in a sense the most fundamental of them, given that the final cause is 'the cause of causes': for, again in Aquinas's' view an efficient cause can bring an effect in to being only if it is 'directed towards' that effect; and it is ultimately in that sense that the effect is 'contained in' the efficient cause.
  32. ^ cf. Feser, Edward (2009). Aquinas: A Beginner's Guide. Beginner's Guides (Reprint ed.). Oxford: Oneworld Publications (published 2011). ISBN 978-1780740065. Retrieved 2018-03-12. A match, for example, reliably generates flame and heat when struck, and never (say) frost and cold, or the smell of lilacs, or thunder.
  33. ^ Compare:The match is 'directed towards' the production of fire and heat [...]
  34. ^ a b Kauffman, Stuart; Logan, Robert K.; Este, Robert; Goebel, Randy; Hobill, David; Shmulevich, Ilya (2007-11-19). "Propagating organization: an enquiry" (PDF). Biology & Philosophy. 23 (1): 27–45. doi:10.1007/s10539-007-9066-x. ISSN 0169-3867. S2CID 10929570.
  35. ^ John Patrick Noonan (2020). General Metaphysics. Wipf and Stock Publishers. p. 228. ISBN 978-1725272644.
  36. ^ Mondin, P. Battista (1960). "Il Principio « Omne Agens Agit Simile Sibi » e l'Analogia dei Nomi Divini Nel Pensiero di S. Tommaso d'Aquino". Divus Thomas. 63: 336–348. JSTOR 45077278.
  37. ^ Philipp W. Rosemann (1996). Omne Agens Agit Sibi Simile : A "repetition" of Scholastic Metaphysics. Philosophical Studies of Louvain. Leuven University Press. ISBN 978-9061867777. (review
  38. ^ B. Mondin, Ontologia e metafisica, ESD, 2022, p. 128
  39. ^ a b B. Mondin, Ontologia e metafisica, ESD, 2022, p. 160
  40. ^ s:en:Page:Philosophical Review Volume 3.djvu/169
  41. ^ "Scholastic terms and axioms".
  42. ^ Note that this pattern also holds true in the creation described in the Book of Genesis. In fact, God the Creator possesses all Being, is the Being Himself and therefore his degree of reality (unity, truth, goodness and perfection) is greater than that of any other creature
  43. ^ The builder (causa fiendi) and the materials of a house (causa essendi) are examples. The house continues to exist even when the builder has ceased his work, which is why the latter is the necessary and sufficient cause of its beginning to be; but without the order and quality of the building materials, the house collapses, which is why these are necessary not only for its beginning to be, but also for its permanence in being (causa essendi).
  44. ^ For example, parents who procreate a human or animal being with a degree of being equal to their own, i.e. a creature with the same rights and duties and ontological status (and a soul if it is a human creature). They are causa fiendi of the creature's mere beginning of life, which, in fact, once it has given birth and after a certain period of training for life, is capable of living even without its parents
  45. ^ "The Metaphysics of the School / by Thomas Harper, S.J."
  46. ^ William James (1979). Some Problems of Philosophy. Donald F. Koch American Philosophy Collection. Curators: Frederick Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers, Ignas K. Skrupskelis. Oxford University Press. p. 97. ISBN 978-0674820357.
  47. ^ Bacon, Francis. 1620. The New Organon II, Aphorism 9.
  48. ^ a b Ayala, Francisco. 1998. "Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology." Nature's Purposes: Analyses of Function and Design in Biology. MIT Press.
  49. ^ Mayr, Ernst W. 1992. "The idea of teleology." Journal of the History of Ideas 53:117–135.
  50. ^ Madrell, S. H. P. 1998. "Why are there no insects in the open sea?" The Journal of Experimental Biology 201:2461–2464.
  51. ^ Reiss, John O. (2009). Not by Design: Retiring Darwin's Watchmaker. University of California Press.
  52. ^ MacDougall-Shackleton, Scott A. (2011-07-27). "The levels of analysis revisited". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 366 (1574): 2076–2085. doi:10.1098/rstb.2010.0363. PMC 3130367. PMID 21690126.
  53. ^ Hladký, Vojtěch, and Jan Havlíček. 2013. "Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes." Human Ethology Bulletin 28(4):3–11.
  54. ^ Heidegger 1977, pp. 289–290.
  55. ^ Heidegger 1977, p. 295.
  56. ^ Waddington, David (2005). "A Field Guide to Heidegger Understanding | The Question Concerning Technology". Educational Philosophy and Theory. 37 (4): 568. doi:10.1111/j.1469-5812.2005.00141.x. S2CID 143892202.
  57. ^ Lovitt, W. (1973). "A Gespräch with Heidegger on Technology, Man and World". Man and World. 6 (1): 44–62. doi:10.1007/BF01252782. S2CID 145770576.

References edit

  • Cohen, Marc S. "The Four Causes" (Lecture Notes) Accessed March 14, 2006.
  • Falcon, Andrea. Aristotle on Causality (link to section labeled "Four Causes"). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2008.
  • Heidegger, Martin (1977) [1949]. Krell, D. F. (ed.). Die Frage nach der Technik [The Question Concerning Technology]. Harper & Row. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  • Hennig, Boris. "The Four Causes." Journal of Philosophy 106(3), 2009, 137–160.
  • Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1408836224.
  • Moravcsik, J.M. "Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle's philosophy." Dialogue, 14 : pp 622–638, 1975.
  • Reece, Bryan C. (2019). "Aristotle's Four Causes of Action". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 97 (2): 213–227. doi:10.1080/00048402.2018.1482932. S2CID 172010122.
  • English translation of Study on Phideas, by Pía Figueroa written with theme of Final Cause as per Aristotle.

External links edit

  • The Consequences of Ideas: Understanding the Concepts that Shaped Our World, By R. C. Sproul
  • Aristotle on definition. By Marguerite Deslauriers, p. 81
  • Philosophy in the ancient world: an introduction. By James A. Arieti. p. 201.
  • Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics. By Joseph Owens and Etienne Gilson.
  • Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle's philosophy
  • A Compass for the Imagination, by Harold C. Morris. Philosophy thesis elaborates on Aristotle's Theory of the Four Causes. Washington State University, 1981.

four, causes, also, potentiality, actualitythis, article, uses, word, cause, traditional, scholarly, philosophical, sense, confused, with, word, main, usage, current, ordinary, language, four, causes, four, explanations, aristotelian, thought, four, fundamenta. See also Potentiality and actualityThis article uses the word cause in its traditional scholarly philosophical sense not to be confused with the word s main usage in current ordinary language The four causes or four explanations are in Aristotelian thought four fundamental types of answer to the question why in analysis of change or movement in nature the material the formal the efficient and the final Aristotle wrote that we do not have knowledge of a thing until we have grasped its why that is to say its cause 1 2 While there are cases in which classifying a cause is difficult or in which causes might merge Aristotle held that his four causes provided an analytical scheme of general applicability 3 Aristotle s Four Causes illustrated for a table material wood formal structure efficient carpentry final dining Aristotle s word aitia Greek aἰtia has in philosophical scholarly tradition been translated as cause This peculiar specialized technical usage of the word cause is not that of everyday English language 4 Rather the translation of Aristotle s aἰtia that is nearest to current ordinary language is explanation 5 2 4 In Physics II 3 and Metaphysics V 2 Aristotle holds that there are four kinds of answers to why questions 2 5 6 Matter The material cause of a change or movement This is the aspect of the change or movement that is determined by the material that composes the moving or changing things For a table this might be wood for a statue it might be bronze or marble Form The formal cause of a change or movement This is a change or movement caused by the arrangement shape or appearance of the thing changing or moving Aristotle says for example that the ratio 2 1 and number in general is the formal cause of the octave Efficient or agent The efficient or moving cause of a change or movement This consists of things apart from the thing being changed or moved which interact so as to be an agency of the change or movement For example the efficient cause of a table is a carpenter or a person working as one and according to Aristotle the efficient cause of a child is a parent Final end or purpose The final cause of a change or movement This is a change or movement for the sake of a thing to be what it is For a seed it might be an adult plant for a sailboat it might be sailing for a ball at the top of a ramp it might be coming to rest at the bottom The four causes are not mutually exclusive For Aristotle several preferably four answers to the question why have to be given to explain a phenomenon and especially the actual configuration of an object 7 For example if asking why a table is such and such an explanation in terms of the four causes would sound like this This table is solid and brown because it is made of wood matter it does not collapse because it has four legs of equal length form it is as it is because a carpenter made it starting from a tree agent it has these dimensions because it is to be used by humans end Aristotle distinguished between intrinsic and extrinsic causes Matter and form are intrinsic causes because they deal directly with the object whereas efficient and finality causes are said to be extrinsic because they are external 8 Thomas Aquinas demonstrated that only those four types of causes can exist and no others He also introduced a priority order according to which matter is made perfect by the form form is made perfect by the agent and agent is made perfect by the finality 9 Hence the finality is the cause of causes or equivalently the queen of causes 10 Contents 1 Definition of cause 2 Aristotle s four causes 2 1 Material 2 2 Formal 2 3 Efficient 2 4 Final 3 Scholasticism 4 Modern science 4 1 Biology 4 2 Animal behaviour Tinbergen s four questions 5 Technology Heidegger s four causes 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 External linksDefinition of cause editMain article Aristotelianism In his philosophical writings Aristotle used the Greek word aἴtion aition a neuter singular form of an adjective The Greek word had meant perhaps originally in a legal context what or who is responsible mostly but not always in a bad sense of guilt or blame Alternatively it could mean to the credit of someone or something The appropriation of this word by Aristotle and other philosophers reflects how the Greek experience of legal practice influenced the concern in Greek thought to determine what is responsible 11 100 106 107 The word developed other meanings including its use in philosophy in a more abstract sense 12 13 14 About a century before Aristotle the anonymous author of the Hippocratic text On Ancient Medicine had described the essential characteristics of a cause as it is considered in medicine 15 We must therefore consider the causes of each medical condition to be those things which are such that when they are present the condition necessarily occurs but when they change to another combination it ceases Aristotle s four causes editAristotle used the four causes to provide different answers to the question because of what The four answers to this question illuminate different aspects of how a thing comes into being or of how an event takes place 11 96 98 Material edit Aristotle considers the material cause ὕlh hu le 16 of an object as equivalent to the nature of the raw material out of which the object is composed The word nature for Aristotle applies to both its potential in the raw material and its ultimate finished form In a sense this form already existed in the material see potentiality and actuality Whereas modern physics looks to simple bodies Aristotle s physics took a more general viewpoint and treated living things as exemplary Nevertheless he felt that simple natural bodies such as earth fire air and water also showed signs of having their own innate sources of motion change and rest Fire for example carries things upwards unless stopped from doing so Things formed by human artifice such as beds and cloaks have no innate tendency to become beds or cloaks 17 In traditional Aristotelian philosophical terminology material is not the same as substance Matter has parallels with substance in so far as primary matter serves as the substratum for simple bodies which are not substance sand and rock mostly earth rivers and seas mostly water atmosphere and wind mostly air and then mostly fire below the moon In this traditional terminology substance is a term of ontology referring to really existing things only individuals are said to be substances subjects in the primary sense Secondary substance in a different sense also applies to man made artifacts Formal edit Further information Platonic realism Aristotle considers the formal cause eἶdos eidos 16 as describing the pattern or form which when present makes matter into a particular type of thing which we recognize as being of that particular type By Aristotle s own account this is a difficult and controversial concept citation needed It links with theories of forms such as those of Aristotle s teacher Plato but in Aristotle s own account see his Metaphysics he takes into account many previous writers who had expressed opinions about forms and ideas but he shows how his own views differ from them 18 Efficient edit Aristotle defines the agent or efficient cause kinoῦn kinoun 16 of an object as that which causes change and drives transient motion such as a painter painting a house see Aristotle Physics II 3 194b29 In many cases this is simply the thing that brings something about For example in the case of a statue it is the person chiseling away which transforms a block of marble into a statue According to Lloyd of the four causes only this one is what is meant by the modern English word cause in ordinary speech 19 Final edit Main articles Teleology and Teleology in biology Aristotle defines the end purpose or final cause telos telos 16 as that for the sake of which a thing is done 20 Like the form this is a controversial type of explanation in science some have argued for its survival in evolutionary biology 21 while Ernst Mayr denied that it continued to play a role 22 It is commonly recognised 23 that Aristotle s conception of nature is teleological in the sense that Nature exhibits functionality in a more general sense than is exemplified in the purposes that humans have Aristotle observed that a telos does not necessarily involve deliberation intention consciousness or intelligence 24 This is most obvious in the animals other than man they make things neither by art nor after inquiry or deliberation That is why people wonder whether it is by intelligence or by some other faculty that these creatures work spiders ants and the like It is absurd to suppose that purpose is not present because we do not observe the agent deliberating Art does not deliberate If the ship building art were in the wood it would produce the same results by nature If therefore purpose is present in art it is present also in nature Aristotle Physics II 8 According to Aristotle a seed has the eventual adult plant as its end i e as its telos if and only if the seed would become the adult plant under normal circumstances 25 In Physics II 9 Aristotle hazards a few arguments that a determination of the end i e final cause of a phenomenon is more important than the others He argues that the end is that which brings it about so for example if one defines the operation of sawing as being a certain kind of dividing then this cannot come about unless the saw has teeth of a certain kind and these cannot be unless it is of iron 26 According to Aristotle once a final cause is in place the material efficient and formal causes follow by necessity However he recommends that the student of nature determine the other causes as well 27 and notes that not all phenomena have an end e g chance events 28 Aristotle saw that his biological investigations provided insights into the causes of things especially into the final cause We should approach the investigation of every kind of animal without being ashamed since in each one of them there is something natural and something beautiful The absence of chance and the serving of ends are found in the works of nature especially And the end for the sake of which a thing has been constructed or has come to be belongs to what is beautiful Aristotle On the Parts of Animals 645a 21 26 Book I Part 5 29 George Holmes Howison highlights final causation in presenting his theory of metaphysics which he terms personal idealism and to which he invites not only man but all ideal life 30 Here in seeing that Final Cause causation at the call of self posited aim or end is the only full and genuine cause we further see that Nature the cosmic aggregate of phenomena and the cosmic bond of their law which in the mood of vague and inaccurate abstraction we call Force is after all only an effect Thus teleology or the Reign of Final Cause the reign of ideality is not only an element in the notion of Evolution but is the very vital cord in the notion The conception of evolution is founded at last and essentially in the conception of Progress but this conception has no meaning at all except in the light of a goal there can be no goal unless there is a Beyond for everything actual and there is no such Beyond except through a spontaneous ideal The presupposition of Nature as a system undergoing evolution is therefore the causal activity of our Pure Ideals These are our three organic and organizing conceptions called the True the Beautiful and the Good George Holmes Howison The Limits of Evolution 1901 However Edward Feser argues in line with the Aristotelian and Thomistic tradition that finality has been greatly misunderstood Indeed without finality efficient causality becomes inexplicable Finality thus understood is not purpose but that end towards which a thing is ordered 31 When a match is rubbed against the side of a matchbox the effect is not the appearance of an elephant or the sounding of a drum but fire 32 The effect is not arbitrary because the match is ordered towards the end of fire 33 which is realized through efficient causes In their biosemiotic study Stuart Kauffman Robert K Logan et al 2007 remark 34 Our language is teleological We believe that autonomous agents constitute the minimal physical system to which teleological language rightly applies Biology and Philosophy 34 Scholasticism editIn the Scholasticism the efficient causality 35 was governed by two principles omne agens agit simile sibi 36 37 38 every agent produces something similar to itself stated frequently in the writings of St Thomas Aquinas the principle establishes a relationship of similarity and analogy between cause and effect nemo dat quod non habet no one gives what he does not possess 39 40 41 partially similar to the legal principle of the same name in Metaphysics it establishes that the cause cannot bestow on the effect the quantity of being and thus of unity truth goodness reality and perfection that it does not already possess within itself Otherwise there would be creation out of nothingness of self and other from self 42 In other words the cause must possess a degree of reality greater than or equal to that of the effect If it is greater we speak of equivocal causation in analogy to the three types of logical predication univocal equivocal analogical if it is equal we speak of univocal predication Thomas in this regard distinguished between causa fiendi cause of occurring of only beginning to be and causa essendi cause of being and also of beginning to be 39 43 When the being of the agent cause is in the effect in a lesser or equal degree this is a causa fiendi 44 Furthermore the second principle also establishes a qualitative link the cause can only transmit its own essence to the effect For example a dog cannot transmit the essence of a feline to its young but only that of a dog 45 The principle is equivalent to that of Causa aequat effectum cause equals effect 46 in both a quantitative and qualitative sense Modern science editSee also Teleology Teleology and science In his Advancement of Learning 1605 Francis Bacon wrote that natural science doth make inquiry and take consideration of the same natures but how Only as to the material and efficient causes of them and not as to the forms Using the terminology of Aristotle Bacon demands that apart from the laws of nature themselves the causes relevant to natural science are only efficient causes and material causes or to use the formulation which became famous later natural phenomena require scientific explanation in terms of matter and motion In The New Organon Bacon divides knowledge into physics and metaphysics 47 From the two kinds of axioms which have been spoken of arises a just division of philosophy and the sciences taking the received terms which come nearest to express the thing in a sense agreeable to my own views Thus let the investigation of forms which are in the eye of reason at least and in their essential law eternal and immutable constitute Metaphysics and let the investigation of the efficient cause and of matter and of the latent process and the latent configuration all of which have reference to the common and ordinary course of nature not to her eternal and fundamental laws constitute Physics And to these let there be subordinate two practical divisions to Physics Mechanics to Metaphysics what in a purer sense of the word I call Magic on account of the broadness of the ways it moves in and its greater command over nature Biology edit Explanations in terms of final causes remain common in evolutionary biology 21 48 Francisco J Ayala has claimed that teleology is indispensable to biology since the concept of adaptation is inherently teleological 48 In an appreciation of Charles Darwin published in Nature in 1874 Asa Gray noted Darwin s great service to Natural Science lies in bringing back teleology so that instead of Morphology versus Teleology we shall have Morphology wedded to Teleology Darwin quickly responded What you say about Teleology pleases me especially and I do not think anyone else has ever noticed the point 21 Francis Darwin and T H Huxley reiterate this sentiment The latter wrote that the most remarkable service to the philosophy of Biology rendered by Mr Darwin is the reconciliation of Teleology and Morphology and the explanation of the facts of both which his view offers 21 James G Lennox states that Darwin uses the term Final Cause consistently in his Species Notebook On the Origin of Species and after 21 Contrary to Ayala s position Ernst Mayr states that adaptedness is a posteriori result rather than an a priori goal seeking 49 Various commentators view the teleological phrases used in modern evolutionary biology as a type of shorthand For example S H P Madrell writes that the proper but cumbersome way of describing change by evolutionary adaptation may be substituted by shorter overtly teleological statements for the sake of saving space but that this should not be taken to imply that evolution proceeds by anything other than from mutations arising by chance with those that impart an advantage being retained by natural selection 50 However Lennox states that in evolution as conceived by Darwin it is true both that evolution is the result of mutations arising by chance and that evolution is teleological in nature 21 Statements that a species does something in order to achieve survival are teleological The validity or invalidity of such statements depends on the species and the intention of the writer as to the meaning of the phrase in order to Sometimes it is possible or useful to rewrite such sentences so as to avoid teleology 51 Some biology courses have incorporated exercises requiring students to rephrase such sentences so that they do not read teleologically Nevertheless biologists still frequently write in a way which can be read as implying teleology even if that is not the intention Animal behaviour Tinbergen s four questions edit Main article Tinbergen s four questions Tinbergen s four questions named after the ethologist Nikolaas Tinbergen and based on Aristotle s four causes are complementary categories of explanations for animal behaviour They are also commonly referred to as levels of analysis The four questions are on 52 53 function what an adaptation does that is selected for in evolution phylogeny the evolutionary history of an organism revealing its relationships to other species mechanism namely the proximate cause of a behaviour such as the role of testosterone in aggression and ontogeny the development of an organism from egg to embryo to adult Technology Heidegger s four causes editIn The Question Concerning Technology echoing Aristotle Martin Heidegger describes the four causes as follows 54 causa materialis the material or matter causa formalis the form or shape the material or matter enters causa finalis the end causa efficiens the effect that brings about the finished result Heidegger explains that w hoever builds a house or a ship or forges a sacrificial chalice reveals what is to be brought forth according to the terms of the four modes of occasioning 55 The educationist David Waddington comments that although the efficient cause which he identifies as the craftsman might be thought the most significant of the four in his view each of Heidegger s four causes is equally co responsible for producing a craft item in Heidegger s terms bringing forth the thing into existence Waddington cites Lovitt s description of this bringing forth as a unified process 56 57 See also editAnthropic principle Biosemiotics Tinbergen s four questions Convergent evolution Five whys Four discourses by Jacques Lacan Proximate and ultimate causation Socrates Teleology The purpose of a system is what it doesNotes edit Aristotle Physics 194 b17 20 see also Posterior Analytics 71 b9 11 94 a20 a b c Falcon Andrea 2019 First published 2006 Aristotle on Causality 2 The Four Causes In Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2023 06 19 for a full range of cases an explanation which fails to invoke all four causes is no explanation at all Lindberg David 1992 The Beginnings of Western Science p 53 a b Leroi 2015 pp 91 92 a b Aristotle famously distinguishes four causes or causal factors in explanation the matter the form the end and the agent Hankinson R J 1998 Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought Oxford Oxford University Press p 159 ISBN 978 0198237457 doi 10 1093 0199246564 001 0001 Aristotle Metaphysics V Aristotle in 23 Volumes vols 17 18 translated by H Tredennick 1933 1989 London William Heinemann Ltd 1989 via Perseus Project 1013a Aristotle discusses the four causes in his Physics Book B ch 3 According to Reece 2018 Aristotle thinks that human action is a species of animal self movement and animal self movement is a species of natural change Natural changes although they are not substances and do not have causes in precisely the same way that substances do are to be explained in terms of the four causes or as many of them as a given natural change has The material cause is that out of which something comes to be or what undergoes change from one state to another the formal cause what differentiates something from other things and serves as a paradigm for its coming to be that thing the efficient cause the starting point of change the final cause that for the sake of which something comes about Aristotle Metaphysica I 983 a26 ss As quoted in Battista Mondin 2022 Ontologia e Metafisica 3rd ed ESD p 157 ISBN 978 8855450539 Thomas Aquinas In IV Sententiarum d 3 q 1 a 1 sol 1 As quoted in Battista Mondin 2022 Ontologia e metafisica ESD 2022 p 158 Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae I q 5 a 2 ad 1 a b Lloyd G E R 1996 Causes and correlations In Adversaries and authorities Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0521556953 Aristotle Ἀnalytikὰ ὕstera Posterior Analytics in Greek Hochschule Augsburg Retrieved 2023 03 07 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a website ignored help Aristotle 1924 Ross W D ed Aristotle s Metaphysics in Greek Oxford Clarendon Press via perseus tufts edu Liddell Henry George Scott Robert 1940 aἰtio logia A Greek English Lexicon revised and augmented throughout by Sir Henry Stuart Jones with the assistance of Roderick McKenzie Oxford Clarendon Press Retrieved 19 June 2023 via perseus tufts edu Lloyd G E R 1979 Magic Reason and Experience Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0521296412 p 54 a b c d Preus Anthony 2015 Material cause 2nd ed Rowman and Littlefield ISBN 978 0810854871 a href Template Cite encyclopedia html title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a work ignored help Physics 192b Lloyd G E R 1968 The critic of Plato pp 43 47 in Aristotle The Growth and Structure of His Thought Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0521094569 Lloyd G E R 1996 Causes and correlations Adversaries and authorities Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 96 ISBN 0521556953 It is clear that of these four only the efficient cause looks like a cause in any ordinary English sense Aristotle Physics II 3 194 b 32 a b c d e f Lennox James G 1993 Darwin was a teleologist Biology and Philosophy 8 4 409 421 doi 10 1007 BF00857687 S2CID 170767015 The development or behavior of an individual is purposive natural selection is definitely not Darwin has swept out such finalistic teleology by the front door Mayr Ernst 1961 Cause and Effect in Biology Science 134 3489 1501 1506 doi 10 1126 science 134 3489 1501 PMID 14471768 Rand Ayn 2000 The Art of Fiction The Penguin Group p 20 ISBN 0452281547 Barnes Jonathan ed The Complete Works of Aristotle vol I The Revised Oxford Translation Aristotle gives this example in Parts of Animals I 1 Aristotle Physics II 9 200b4 7 Aristotle Physics II 9 Physics II 5 where chance is opposed to nature which he has already said acts for ends Lloyd G E R 1970 Early Greek Science Thales to Aristotle New York W W Norton p 105 ISBN 978 0393005837 Howison George Holmes 1901 The Limits of Evolution p 39 cf Feser Edward 2009 Aquinas A Beginner s Guide Beginner s Guides Reprint ed Oxford Oneworld Publications published 2011 ISBN 978 1780740065 Retrieved 2018 03 12 three principles are central to Aquinas s general metaphysics the principle of finality is in a sense the most fundamental of them given that the final cause is the cause of causes for again in Aquinas s view an efficient cause can bring an effect in to being only if it is directed towards that effect and it is ultimately in that sense that the effect is contained in the efficient cause cf Feser Edward 2009 Aquinas A Beginner s Guide Beginner s Guides Reprint ed Oxford Oneworld Publications published 2011 ISBN 978 1780740065 Retrieved 2018 03 12 A match for example reliably generates flame and heat when struck and never say frost and cold or the smell of lilacs or thunder Compare The match is directed towards the production of fire and heat a b Kauffman Stuart Logan Robert K Este Robert Goebel Randy Hobill David Shmulevich Ilya 2007 11 19 Propagating organization an enquiry PDF Biology amp Philosophy 23 1 27 45 doi 10 1007 s10539 007 9066 x ISSN 0169 3867 S2CID 10929570 John Patrick Noonan 2020 General Metaphysics Wipf and Stock Publishers p 228 ISBN 978 1725272644 Mondin P Battista 1960 Il Principio Omne Agens Agit Simile Sibi e l Analogia dei Nomi Divini Nel Pensiero di S Tommaso d Aquino Divus Thomas 63 336 348 JSTOR 45077278 Philipp W Rosemann 1996 Omne Agens Agit Sibi Simile A repetition of Scholastic Metaphysics Philosophical Studies of Louvain Leuven University Press ISBN 978 9061867777 review B Mondin Ontologia e metafisica ESD 2022 p 128 a b B Mondin Ontologia e metafisica ESD 2022 p 160 s en Page Philosophical Review Volume 3 djvu 169 Scholastic terms and axioms Note that this pattern also holds true in the creation described in the Book of Genesis In fact God the Creator possesses all Being is the Being Himself and therefore his degree of reality unity truth goodness and perfection is greater than that of any other creature The builder causa fiendi and the materials of a house causa essendi are examples The house continues to exist even when the builder has ceased his work which is why the latter is the necessary and sufficient cause of its beginning to be but without the order and quality of the building materials the house collapses which is why these are necessary not only for its beginning to be but also for its permanence in being causa essendi For example parents who procreate a human or animal being with a degree of being equal to their own i e a creature with the same rights and duties and ontological status and a soul if it is a human creature They are causa fiendi of the creature s mere beginning of life which in fact once it has given birth and after a certain period of training for life is capable of living even without its parents The Metaphysics of the School by Thomas Harper S J William James 1979 Some Problems of Philosophy Donald F Koch American Philosophy Collection Curators Frederick Burkhardt Fredson Bowers Ignas K Skrupskelis Oxford University Press p 97 ISBN 978 0674820357 Bacon Francis 1620 The New Organon II Aphorism 9 a b Ayala Francisco 1998 Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology Nature s Purposes Analyses of Function and Design in Biology MIT Press Mayr Ernst W 1992 The idea of teleology Journal of the History of Ideas 53 117 135 Madrell S H P 1998 Why are there no insects in the open sea The Journal of Experimental Biology 201 2461 2464 Reiss John O 2009 Not by Design Retiring Darwin s Watchmaker University of California Press MacDougall Shackleton Scott A 2011 07 27 The levels of analysis revisited Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences 366 1574 2076 2085 doi 10 1098 rstb 2010 0363 PMC 3130367 PMID 21690126 Hladky Vojtech and Jan Havlicek 2013 Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian Comparison of Tinbergen s Four Whys and Aristotle s Four Causes Human Ethology Bulletin 28 4 3 11 Heidegger 1977 pp 289 290 Heidegger 1977 p 295 Waddington David 2005 A Field Guide to Heidegger Understanding The Question Concerning Technology Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 4 568 doi 10 1111 j 1469 5812 2005 00141 x S2CID 143892202 Lovitt W 1973 A Gesprach with Heidegger on Technology Man and World Man and World 6 1 44 62 doi 10 1007 BF01252782 S2CID 145770576 References editCohen Marc S The Four Causes Lecture Notes Accessed March 14 2006 Falcon Andrea Aristotle on Causality link to section labeled Four Causes Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2008 Heidegger Martin 1977 1949 Krell D F ed Die Frage nach der Technik The Question Concerning Technology Harper amp Row a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Hennig Boris The Four Causes Journal of Philosophy 106 3 2009 137 160 Leroi Armand Marie 2015 The Lagoon How Aristotle Invented Science Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1408836224 Moravcsik J M Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle s philosophy Dialogue 14 pp 622 638 1975 Reece Bryan C 2019 Aristotle s Four Causes of Action Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 2 213 227 doi 10 1080 00048402 2018 1482932 S2CID 172010122 English translation of Study on Phideas by Pia Figueroa written with theme of Final Cause as per Aristotle External links editThe Consequences of Ideas Understanding the Concepts that Shaped Our World By R C Sproul Aristotle on definition By Marguerite Deslauriers p 81 Philosophy in the ancient world an introduction By James A Arieti p 201 Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics By Joseph Owens and Etienne Gilson Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle s philosophy A Compass for the Imagination by Harold C Morris Philosophy thesis elaborates on Aristotle s Theory of the Four Causes Washington State University 1981 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Four causes amp oldid 1199992770 Final cause, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.