fbpx
Wikipedia

Just war theory

The just war theory (Latin: bellum iustum)[1][2] is a doctrine, also referred to as a tradition, of military ethics which is studied by military leaders, theologians, ethicists and policy makers. The purpose of the doctrine is to ensure that a war is morally justifiable through a series of criteria, all of which must be met for a war to be considered just. The criteria are split into two groups: jus ad bellum ("right to go to war") and jus in bello ("right conduct in war"). The first group of criteria concerns the morality of going to war, and the second group of criteria concerns the moral conduct within war.[3] There have been calls for the inclusion of a third category of just war theory (jus post bellum) dealing with the morality of post-war settlement and reconstruction. The just war theory postulates the belief that war, while it is terrible but less so with the right conduct, is not always the worst option. Important responsibilities, undesirable outcomes, or preventable atrocities may justify war.[3]

Saint Augustine was the first clear advocate of just-war theory.

Opponents of the just war theory may either be inclined to a stricter pacifist standard (proposing that there has never been nor can there ever be a justifiable basis for war) or they may be inclined toward a more permissive nationalist standard (proposing that a war need only to serve a nation's interests to be justifiable). In many cases, philosophers state that individuals do not need to be plagued by a guilty conscience if they are required to fight. A few philosophers ennoble the virtues of the soldier while they also declare their apprehensions for war itself.[4] A few, such as Rousseau, argue for insurrection against oppressive rule.

The historical aspect, or the "just war tradition", deals with the historical body of rules or agreements that have applied in various wars across the ages. The just war tradition also considers the writings of various philosophers and lawyers through history, and examines both their philosophical visions of war's ethical limits and whether their thoughts have contributed to the body of conventions that have evolved to guide war and warfare.[5]

Origins

Ancient Egypt

A 2017 study found that the just war tradition can be traced as far back as to Ancient Egypt.[6] Egyptian ethics of war usually centered on three main ideas, these including the cosmological role of Egypt, the pharaoh as a divine office and executor of the will of the gods, and the superiority of the Egyptian state and population over all other states and peoples. Egyptian political theology held that the pharaoh had the exclusive legitimacy in justly initiating a war, usually claimed to carry out the will of the gods. Senusret I, in the Twelfth Dynasty, claimed, "I was nursed to be a conqueror...his [Atum's] son and his protector, he gave me to conquer what he conquered." Later pharaohs also considered their sonship of the god Amun-Re as granting them absolute ability to declare war on the deity's behalf. Pharaohs often visited temples prior to initiating campaigns, where the pharaoh was believed to receive their commands of war from the deities. For example, Kamose claimed that "I went north because I was strong (enough) to attack the Asiatics through the command of Amon, the just of counsels." A stele erected by Thutmose III at the Temple of Amun at Karnak "provides an unequivocal statement of the pharaoh's divine mandate to wage war on his enemies." As the period of the New Kingdom progressed and Egypt heightened its territorial ambition, so did the invocation of just war aid the justification of these efforts. The universal principle of Maat, signifying order and justice, was central to the Egyptian notion of just war and its ability to guarantee Egypt virtually no limits on what it could take, do, or use to guarantee the ambitions of the state.[6]

Confucian

Chinese philosophy produced a massive body of work on warfare, much of it during the Zhou dynasty, especially the Warring States era. War was justified only as a last resort and only by the rightful sovereign; however, questioning the decision of the emperor concerning the necessity of a military action was not permissible. The success of a military campaign was sufficient proof that the campaign had been righteous.[7]

Japan did not develop its own doctrine of just war but between the 5th and the 7th centuries drew heavily from Chinese philosophy, and especially Confucian views. As part of the Japanese campaign to take the northeastern island Honshu, Japanese military action was portrayed as an effort to "pacify" the Emishi people, who were likened to "bandits" and "wild-hearted wolf cubs" and accused of invading Japan's frontier lands.[7]

India

The Indian Hindu epic, the Mahabharata, offers the first written discussions of a "just war" (dharma-yuddha or "righteous war"). In it, one of five ruling brothers (Pandavas) asks if the suffering caused by war can ever be justified. A long discussion then ensues between the siblings, establishing criteria like proportionality (chariots cannot attack cavalry, only other chariots; no attacking people in distress), just means (no poisoned or barbed arrows), just cause (no attacking out of rage), and fair treatment of captives and the wounded.[8] The war in the Mahabharata is preceded by context that develops the "just cause" for the war including last-minute efforts to reconcile differences to avoid war. At the beginning of the war, there is the discussion of "just conduct" appropriate to the context of war.

In Sikhism, the term dharamyudh describes a war that is fought for just, righteous or religious reasons, especially in defence of one's own beliefs. Though some core tenets in the Sikh religion are understood to emphasise peace and nonviolence, especially before the 1606 execution of Guru Arjan by Mughal emperor Jahangir,[9] military force may be justified if all peaceful means to settle a conflict have been exhausted, thus resulting in a dharamyudh.[10]

Ancient Greece and Rome

The notion of just war in Europe originates and is developed first in ancient Greece and then in the Roman Empire.[11][12][13]

It was Aristotle who first introduced the concept and terminology to the Hellenic world that called war a last resort requiring conduct that would allow the restoration of peace. Aristotle argues that the cultivation of a military is necessary and good for the purpose of self-defense, not for conquering: "The proper object of practising military training is not in order that men may enslave those who do not deserve slavery, but in order that first they may themselves avoid becoming enslaved to others" (Politics, Book 7).[14]

In ancient Rome, a "just cause" for war might include the necessity of repelling an invasion, or retaliation for pillaging or a breach of treaty.[15] War was always potentially nefas ("wrong, forbidden"), and risked religious pollution and divine disfavor.[16] A "just war" (bellum iustum) thus required a ritualized declaration by the fetial priests.[17] More broadly, conventions of war and treaty-making were part of the ius gentium, the "law of nations", the customary moral obligations regarded as innate and universal to human beings.[18] The quintessential explanation of Just War theory in the ancient world is found in Cicero's De Officiis, Book 1, sections 1.11.33–1.13.41. Although, it is well known that Julius Caesar did not often follow these necessities.

Muslim teaching of Jihad

"Jihad" is an Arabic word which literally means "striving" or "struggling", especially with a praiseworthy aim.[19][20][21][22] In an Islamic context, it can refer to almost any effort to make personal and social life conform with God's guidance, such as struggle against one's evil inclinations, proselytizing, or efforts toward the moral betterment of the Muslim community (Ummah),[19][20][23][24] though it is most frequently associated with war.[22][25] In classical Islamic law (sharia), the term refers to armed struggle against unbelievers,[20][21] while modernist Islamic scholars generally equate military jihad with defensive warfare.[26][27] In Sufi circles, spiritual and moral jihad has been traditionally emphasized under the name of greater jihad.[23][28][21] The term has gained additional attention in recent decades through its use by various insurgent Islamic extremist, militant Islamist, and terrorist individuals and organizations whose ideology is, purportedly, based on the Islamic notion of jihad.[23][25][29][30]

The word jihad appears frequently in the Qur'an with and without military connotations,[31] often in the idiomatic expression "striving in the path of God (al-jihad fi sabil Allah)",[32][33] conveying a sense of self-exertion.[34] They[who?] developed an elaborate set of rules pertaining to jihad, including prohibitions on harming those who are not engaged in combat.[35][36] In the modern era, the notion of jihad has lost its jurisprudential relevance and instead given rise to an ideological and political discourse.[23][26] While modernist Islamic scholars have emphasized the defensive and non-military aspects of jihad, some Islamists have advanced aggressive interpretations that go beyond the classical theory.[26][30]

Jihad is classified into inner ("greater") jihad, which involves a struggle against one's own base impulses, and external ("lesser") jihad, which is further subdivided into jihad of the pen/tongue (debate or persuasion) and jihad of the sword.[23][37][28] Most Western writers consider external jihad to have primacy over inner jihad in the Islamic tradition, while much of contemporary Muslim opinion favors the opposite view.[37]

The sense of jihad as armed resistance was first used in the context of persecution faced by Muslims, as when Muhammad was at Mecca, when the community had two choices: emigration (hijra) or jihad.[38] In Twelver Shi'a Islam, jihad is one of the ten Practices of the Religion.[39] A person engaged in jihad is called a mujahid (plural: mujahideen). The term jihad is often rendered in English as "Holy War",[40][41][42] although this translation is controversial.[43][44] Today, the word jihad is often used without religious connotations, like the English crusade.[19][20]

Christian views

Christian theory of the Just War begins around the time of Augustine of Hippo[45] The Just War theory, with some amendments, is still used by Christians today as a guide to whether or not a war can be justified. War may be necessary and right, even though it may not be good. In the case of a country that has been invaded by an occupying force, war may be the only way to restore justice. [46]

Saint Augustine

Saint Augustine held that individuals should not resort immediately to violence, but God has given the sword to government for a good reason (based upon Romans 13:4). In Contra Faustum Manichaeum book 22 sections 69–76, Augustine argues that Christians, as part of a government, need not be ashamed of protecting peace and punishing wickedness when they are forced to do so by a government. Augustine asserted that was a personal and philosophical stance: "What is here required is not a bodily action, but an inward disposition. The sacred seat of virtue is the heart."[47]

Nonetheless, he asserted, peacefulness in the face of a grave wrong that could be stopped by only violence would be a sin. Defense of one's self or others could be a necessity, especially when it is authorized by a legitimate authority:

They who have waged war in obedience to the divine command, or in conformity with His laws, have represented in their persons the public justice or the wisdom of government, and in this capacity have put to death wicked men; such persons have by no means violated the commandment, "Thou shalt not kill."[48]

While not breaking down the conditions necessary for war to be just, Augustine nonetheless originated the very phrase itself in his work The City of God:

But, say they, the wise man will wage Just Wars. As if he would not all the rather lament the necessity of just wars, if he remembers that he is a man; for if they were not just he would not wage them, and would therefore be delivered from all wars.[48]

J. Mark Mattox writes,

In terms of the traditional notion of jus ad bellum (justice of war, that is, the circumstances in which wars can be justly fought), war is a coping mechanism for righteous sovereigns who would ensure that their violent international encounters are minimal, a reflection of the Divine Will to the greatest extent possible, and always justified. In terms of the traditional notion of jus in bello (justice in war, or the moral considerations which ought to constrain the use of violence in war), war is a coping mechanism for righteous combatants who, by divine edict, have no choice but to subject themselves to their political masters and seek to ensure that they execute their war-fighting duty as justly as possible.[49]

Saint Thomas Aquinas

The just war theory by Thomas Aquinas has had a lasting impact on later generations of thinkers and was part of an emerging consensus in Medieval Europe on just war.[50] In the 13th century Aquinas reflected in detail on peace and war. Aquinas was a Dominican friar and contemplated the teachings of the Bible on peace and war in combination with ideas from Aristotle, Plato, Saint Augustine and other philosophers whose writings are part of the Western canon. Aquinas' views on war drew heavily on the Decretum Gratiani, a book the Italian monk Gratian had compiled with passages from the Bible. After its publication in the 12th century, the Decretum Gratiani had been republished with commentary from Pope Innocent IV and the Dominican friar Raymond of Penafort. Other significant influences on Aquinas just war theory were Alexander of Hales and Henry of Segusio.[51]

In Summa Theologica Aquinas asserted that it is not always a sin to wage war, and he set out criteria for a just war. According to Aquinas, three requirements must be met. Firstly, the war must be waged upon the command of a rightful sovereign. Secondly, the war needs to be waged for just cause, on account of some wrong the attacked have committed. Thirdly, warriors must have the right intent, namely to promote good and to avoid evil.[52][53] Aquinas came to the conclusion that a just war could be offensive and that injustice should not be tolerated so as to avoid war. Nevertheless, Aquinas argued that violence must only be used as a last resort. On the battlefield, violence was only justified to the extent it was necessary. Soldiers needed to avoid cruelty and a just war was limited by the conduct of just combatants. Aquinas argued that it was only in the pursuit of justice, that the good intention of a moral act could justify negative consequences, including the killing of the innocent during a war.[54]

First World War

At the beginning of the First World War, a group of theologians in Germany published a manifesto that sought to justify the actions of the German government. At the British government's request, Randall Davidson, Archbishop of Canterbury, took the lead in collaborating with a large number of other religious leaders, including some with whom he had differed in the past, to write a rebuttal of the Germans' contentions. Both German and British theologians based themselves on the just war theory, each group seeking to prove that it applied to the war waged by its own side.[55]

Contemporary Catholic doctrine

The just war doctrine of the Catholic Church found in the 1992 Catechism of the Catholic Church, in paragraph 2309, lists four strict conditions for "legitimate defense by military force:"[56][57]

  • The damage inflicted by the aggressor on the nation or community of nations must be lasting, grave and certain.
  • All other means of putting an end to it must have been shown to be impractical or ineffective.
  • there must be serious prospects of success.
  • The use of arms must not produce evils and disorders graver than the evil to be eliminated.

The Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church elaborates on the just war doctrine in paragraphs 500 to 501:[58]

If this responsibility justifies the possession of sufficient means to exercise this right to defense, States still have the obligation to do everything possible "to ensure that the conditions of peace exist, not only within their own territory but throughout the world". It is important to remember that "it is one thing to wage a war of self-defense; it is quite another to seek to impose domination on another nation. The possession of war potential does not justify the use of force for political or military objectives. Nor does the mere fact that war has unfortunately broken out mean that all is fair between the warring parties".
The Charter of the United Nations intends to preserve future generations from war with a prohibition against force to resolve disputes between States. Like most philosophy, it permits legitimate defense and measures to maintain peace. In every case, the charter requires that self-defense must respect the traditional limits of necessity and proportionality.
Therefore, engaging in a preventive war without clear proof that an attack is imminent cannot fail to raise serious moral and juridical questions. International legitimacy for the use of armed force, on the basis of rigorous assessment and with well-founded motivations, can only be given by the decision of a competent body that identifies specific situations as threats to peace and authorizes an intrusion into the sphere of autonomy usually reserved to a State.

Pope John Paul II in an address to a group of soldiers said the following:[59]

Peace, as taught by Sacred Scripture and the experience of men itself, is more than just the absence of war. And the Christian is aware that on earth a human society that is completely and always peaceful is, unfortunately, an utopia and that the ideologies which present it as easily attainable only nourish vain hopes. The cause of peace will not go forward by denying the possibility and the obligation to defend it.

Russian Orthodox Church

The War and Peace section in the Basis of the Social Concept of the Russian Orthodox Church is crucial for understanding the Russian Orthodox Church's attitude towards war. The document offers criteria of distinguishing between an aggressive war, which is unacceptable, and a justified war, attributing the highest moral and sacred value of military acts of bravery to a true believer who participates in a justified war. Additionally, the document considers the just war criteria as developed in Western Christianity to be eligible for Russian Orthodoxy; therefore, the justified war theory in Western theology is also applicable to the Russian Orthodox Church.[60]

In the same document, it is stated that wars have accompanied human history since the fall of man, and according to the gospel, they will continue to accompany it. While recognizing war as evil, the Russian Orthodox Church does not prohibit its members from participating in hostilities if there is the security of their neighbours and the restoration of trampled justice at stake. War is considered to be necessary but undesirable. It is also stated that the Russian Orthodox Church has had profound respect for soldiers who gave their lives to protect the life and security of their neighbours.[61]

Just war tradition

The just war theory, propounded by the medieval Christian philosopher Thomas Aquinas, was developed further by legal scholars in the context of international law. Cardinal Cajetan, the jurist Francisco de Vitoria, the two Jesuit priests Luis de Molina and Francisco Suárez, as well as the humanist Hugo Grotius and the lawyer Luigi Taparelli were most influential in the formation of a just war tradition. The just war tradition, which was well established by the 19th century, found its practical application in the Hague Peace Conferences (1899 and 1907) and in the founding of the League of Nations in 1920. After the United States Congress declared war on Germany in 1917, Cardinal James Gibbons issued a letter that all Catholics were to support the war[62] because "Our Lord Jesus Christ does not stand for peace at any price... If by Pacifism is meant the teaching that the use of force is never justifiable, then, however well meant, it is mistaken, and it is hurtful to the life of our country."[63]

Armed conflicts such as the Spanish Civil War, World War II and the Cold War were, as a matter of course, judged according to the norms (as established in Aquinas' just war theory) by philosophers such as Jacques Maritain, Elizabeth Anscombe and John Finnis.[50]

The first work dedicated specifically to just war was the 15th-century sermon De bellis justis of Stanisław of Skarbimierz (1360–1431), who justified war by the Kingdom of Poland against the Teutonic Knights.[64] Francisco de Vitoria criticized the conquest of America by the Spanish conquistadors on the basis of just-war theory.[65] With Alberico Gentili and Hugo Grotius, just war theory was replaced by international law theory, codified as a set of rules, which today still encompass the points commonly debated, with some modifications.[66]

Just-war theorists combine a moral abhorrence towards war with a readiness to accept that war may sometimes be necessary. The criteria of the just-war tradition act as an aid in determining whether resorting to arms is morally permissible. Just-war theories aim "to distinguish between justifiable and unjustifiable uses of organized armed forces"; they attempt "to conceive of how the use of arms might be restrained, made more humane, and ultimately directed towards the aim of establishing lasting peace and justice".[67] Although the criticism can be made that the application of just war theory is relativistic, one of the fundamental bases of the tradition is the Ethic of Reciprocity, particularly when it comes to in bello considerations of deportment during battle. If one set of combatants promise to treat their enemies with a modicum of restraint and respect, then the hope is that other sets of combatants will do similarly in reciprocation (a concept not unrelated to the considerations of game theory).

The just war tradition addresses the morality of the use of force in two parts: when it is right to resort to armed force (the concern of jus ad bellum) and what is acceptable in using such force (the concern of jus in bello).[68] In more recent years, a third category—jus post bellum—has been added by certain theorists and addresses the justice of war termination and peace agreements, as well as the prosecution of war criminals.

In 1869 the Russian military theorist Genrikh Antonovich Leer [ru] theorised on the advantages and potential benefits of war.[69]

The Soviet leader Vladimir Lenin defined only three types of just war,[70] all of which share the central trait of being revolutionary in character. In simple terms: "To the Russian workers has fallen the honor and the good fortune of being the first to start the revolution—the great and only legitimate and just war, the war of the oppressed against the oppressors",[71] with these two opposing categories being defined in terms of class, as is typical in the left. In that manner, Lenin shunned the more common interpretation of a defensive war as a just one, often summarized as "who fired the first shot?", precisely because it failed to take into consideration the class factor. Which side initiated aggressions or had a grievance or any other commonly-considered factor of jus ad bellum mattered not at all, he claimed. if one side was being oppressed by the other, the war against the oppressor would always be, by definition, a defensive war anyway. Any war lacking that duality of oppressed and oppressor was, in contradistinction, always a reactionary, unjust war, in which the oppressed effectively fight in order to protect their own oppressors:

But picture to yourselves a slave-owner who owned 100 slaves warring against a slave-owner who owned 200 slaves for a more "just" distribution of slaves. Clearly, the application of the term "defensive" war, or war "for the defense of the fatherland" in such a case would be historically false, and in practice would be sheer deception of the common people, of philistines, of ignorant people, by the astute slaveowners. Precisely in this way are the present-day imperialist bourgeoisie deceiving the peoples by means of "national ideology" and the term "defense of the fatherland" in the present war between slave-owners for fortifying and strengthening slavery.[72]

The anarcho-capitalist scholar Murray Rothbard (1926-1995) stated that "a just war exists when a people tries to ward off the threat of coercive domination by another people, or to overthrow an already-existing domination. A war is unjust, on the other hand, when a people try to impose domination on another people or try to retain an already-existing coercive rule over them."[73]

Jonathan Riley-Smith writes:

The consensus among Christians on the use of violence has changed radically since the crusades were fought. The just war theory prevailing for most of the last two centuries—that violence is an evil that can, in certain situations, be condoned as the lesser of evils—is relatively young. Although it has inherited some elements (the criteria of legitimate authority, just cause, right intention) from the older war theory that first evolved around AD 400, it has rejected two premises that underpinned all medieval just wars, including crusades: first, that violence could be employed on behalf of Christ's intentions for mankind and could even be directly authorized by him; and second, that it was a morally neutral force that drew whatever ethical coloring it had from the intentions of the perpetrators.[74]

Criteria

The just war theory has two sets of criteria, the first establishing jus ad bellum (the right to go to war),and the second establishing jus in bello (right conduct within war).[75]

Jus ad bellum

Just cause
The reason for going to war needs to be just and cannot, therefore, be solely for recapturing things taken or punishing people who have done wrong; innocent life must be in imminent danger and intervention must be to protect life. A contemporary view of just cause was expressed in 1993 when the US Catholic Conference said: "Force may be used only to correct a grave, public evil, i.e., aggression or massive violation of the basic human rights of whole populations."
Comparative justice
While there may be rights and wrongs on all sides of a conflict, to overcome the presumption against the use of force, the injustice suffered by one party must significantly outweigh that suffered by the other. Some theorists such as Brian Orend omit this term, seeing it as fertile ground for exploitation by bellicose regimes.
Competent authority
Only duly constituted public authorities may wage war. "A just war must be initiated by a political authority within a political system that allows distinctions of justice. Dictatorships (e.g. Hitler's Regime) or deceptive military actions (e.g. the 1968 US bombing of Cambodia) are typically considered as violations of this criterion. The importance of this condition is key. Plainly, we cannot have a genuine process of judging a just war within a system that represses the process of genuine justice. A just war must be initiated by a political authority within a political system that allows distinctions of justice".[76]
Right intention
Force may be used only in a truly just cause and solely for that purpose—correcting a suffered wrong is considered a right intention, while material gain or maintaining economies is not.
Probability of success
Arms may not be used in a futile cause or in a case where disproportionate measures are required to achieve success;
Last resort
Force may be used only after all peaceful and viable alternatives have been seriously tried and exhausted or are clearly not practical. It may be clear that the other side is using negotiations as a delaying tactic and will not make meaningful concessions.
Proportionality
The anticipated benefits of waging a war must be proportionate to its expected evils or harms. This principle is also known as the principle of macro-proportionality, so as to distinguish it from the jus in bello principle of proportionality.

In modern terms, just war is waged in terms of self-defense, or in defense of another (with sufficient evidence).

Jus in bello

Once war has begun, just war theory (jus in bello) also directs how combatants are to act or should act:

Distinction
Just war conduct should be governed by the principle of distinction. The acts of war should be directed towards enemy combatants, and not towards non-combatants caught in circumstances they did not create. The prohibited acts include bombing civilian residential areas that include no legitimate military targets, committing acts of terrorism or reprisal against civilians or prisoners of war (POWs), and attacking neutral targets. Moreover, combatants are not permitted to attack enemy combatants who have surrendered or who have been captured or who are injured and not presenting an immediate lethal threat or who are parachuting from disabled aircraft and are not airborne forces or who are shipwrecked.
Proportionality
Just war conduct should be governed by the principle of proportionality. Combatants must make sure that the harm caused to civilians or civilian property is not excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage anticipated by an attack on a legitimate military objective. This principle is meant to discern the correct balance between the restriction imposed by a corrective measure and the severity of the nature of the prohibited act.
Military necessity
Just war conduct should be governed by the principle of military necessity. An attack or action must be intended to help in the defeat of the enemy; it must be an attack on a legitimate military objective, and the harm caused to civilians or civilian property must be proportional and not excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage anticipated. This principle is meant to limit excessive and unnecessary death and destruction.
Fair treatment of prisoners of war
Enemy combatants who surrendered or who are captured no longer pose a threat. It is therefore wrong to torture them or otherwise mistreat them.
No means malum in se
Combatants may not use weapons or other methods of warfare that are considered evil, such as mass rape, forcing enemy combatants to fight against their own side or using weapons whose effects cannot be controlled (e.g., nuclear/biological weapons).

Ending a war: Jus post bellum

In recent years, some theorists, such as Gary Bass, Louis Iasiello and Brian Orend, have proposed a third category within the just war theory. Jus post bellum concerns justice after a war, including peace treaties, reconstruction, environmental remediation, war crimes trials, and war reparations. Jus post bellum has been added to deal with the fact that some hostile actions may take place outside a traditional battlefield. Jus post bellum governs the justice of war termination and peace agreements, as well as the prosecution of war criminals, and publicly labelled terrorists. The idea has largely been added to help decide what to do if there are prisoners that have been taken during battle. It is, through government labelling and public opinion, that people use jus post bellum to justify the pursuit of labelled terrorist for the safety of the government's state in a modern context. The actual fault lies with the aggressor and so by being the aggressor, they forfeit their rights for honourable treatment by their actions. That theory is used to justify the actions taken by anyone fighting in a war to treat prisoners outside of war.[77] Actions after a conflict can be warranted by actions observed during war, meaning that there can be justification to meet violence with violence even after war. Orend, who was one of the theorists mentioned earlier, proposes the following principles:

Just cause for termination
A state may terminate a war if there has been a reasonable vindication of the rights that were violated in the first place, and if the aggressor is willing to negotiate the terms of surrender. These terms of surrender include a formal apology, compensations, war crimes trials and perhaps rehabilitation. Alternatively, a state may end a war if it becomes clear that any just goals of the war cannot be reached at all or cannot be reached without using excessive force.
Right intention
A state must only terminate a war under the conditions agreed upon in the above criteria. Revenge is not permitted. The victor state must also be willing to apply the same level of objectivity and investigation into any war crimes its armed forces may have committed.
Public declaration and authority
The terms of peace must be made by a legitimate authority, and the terms must be accepted by a legitimate authority.
Discrimination
The victor state is to differentiate between political and military leaders, and combatants and civilians. Punitive measures are to be limited to those directly responsible for the conflict. Truth and reconciliation may sometimes be more important than punishing war crimes.
Proportionality
Any terms of surrender must be proportional to the rights that were initially violated. Draconian measures, absolutionist crusades, and any attempt at denying the surrendered country the right to participate in the world community are not permitted.

References

  1. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius; Miller, Walter (1913). De officiis. With an English translation by Walter Miller. Robarts - University of Toronto. London Heinemann.
  2. ^ Fellmeth, Aaron X.; Horwitz, Maurice (2009). "Bellum iustum". Guide to Latin in International Law. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acref/9780195369380.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-536938-0. Retrieved 27 February 2022.
  3. ^ a b Guthrie, Charles; Quinlan, Michael (2007). "III: The Structure of the Tradition". Just War: The Just War Tradition: Ethics in Modern Warfare. pp. 11–15. ISBN 978-0747595571.
  4. ^ McHenry, Robert (22 March 2010). . blogs.britannica.com. Britannica Blog. Archived from the original on 31 October 2015. Retrieved 6 August 2017.
  5. ^ "Just War Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 30 October 2016.
  6. ^ a b Cox, Rory (2017). "Expanding the History of the Just War: The Ethics of War in Ancient Egypt". International Studies Quarterly. 61 (2): 371. doi:10.1093/isq/sqx009. hdl:10023/17848.
  7. ^ a b Friday, Karl F. (2004). Samurai, Warfare and the State in Early Medieval Japan. Routledge. pp. 21–22. ISBN 9781134330225.
  8. ^ Robinson, Paul F.; Robinson, Paul (2003). Just War in Comparative Perspective. ISBN 9780754635871. Retrieved 25 April 2015.
  9. ^ Syan, Hardip Singh (2013). Sikh Militancy in the Seventeenth Century: Religious Violence in Mughal and Early Modern India. London & New York: I.B.Tauris. pp. 3–4, 252. ISBN 9781780762500. Retrieved 15 September 2019.
  10. ^ Fenech, Louis E.; McLeod, W. H. (2014). Historical Dictionary of Sikhism. Plymouth & Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 99–100. ISBN 9781442236011. Retrieved 16 September 2019.
  11. ^ Gregory Raymond, The Greco-Roman Roots of the Western Just War Tradition, Routledge 2010.
  12. ^ Rory Cox, "The Ethics of War up to Thomas Aquinas" in (eds. Lazar & Frowe) The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War, Oxford 2018.
  13. ^ Cian O'Driscoll, "Rewriting the Just War Tradition: Just War in Classical Greek Political Thought and Practice," International Studies Quarterly (2015).
  14. ^ Aristotle. "Politics, Book 7". Perseus Digital Library.
  15. ^ Livy 9.1.10; Cicero, Divinatio in Caecilium 63; De provinciis consularibus 4; Ad Atticum VII 14, 3; IX 19, 1; Pro rege Deiotauro 13; De officiis I 36; Philippicae XI 37; XIII 35; De re publica II 31; III 35; Isidore of Seville, Origines XVIII 1, 2; Modestinus, Libro I regolarum = Digesta I 3, 40; E. Badian, Roman Imperialism in the Late Republic (Ithaca 1968, 2nd ed.), p.11.
  16. ^ William Warde Fowler, The Roman Festivals of the Period of the Republic (London 1925), pp. 33ff.; M. Kaser, Das altroemische Ius (Goettingen 1949), pp. 22ff; P. Catalano, Linee del sistema sovrannazionale romano (Torino 1965), pp. 14ff.; W. V. Harris, War and imperialism in Republican Rome, 327-70 B.C. (Oxford 1979), pp. 161 ff.
  17. ^ Livy 1.32; 31.8.3; 36.3.9
  18. ^ Cicero, De officiis 3.17.69; Marcia L. Colish, The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages (Brill, 1980), p. 150.
  19. ^ a b c John L. Esposito, ed. (2014). "Jihad". The Oxford Dictionary of Islam. Oxford: Oxford University Press. from the original on 3 September 2014. Retrieved 29 August 2014.
  20. ^ a b c d Peters, Rudolph; Cook, David (2014). "Jihād". The Oxford Encyclopedia of Islam and Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acref:oiso/9780199739356.001.0001. ISBN 9780199739356. from the original on 23 January 2017. Retrieved 24 January 2017.
  21. ^ a b c Tyan, E. (1965). "D̲j̲ihād". In Bosworth, C. E.; van Donzel, E. J.; Heinrichs, W. P.; Lewis, B.; Pellat, Ch.; Schacht, J. (eds.). Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Vol. 2. Leiden: Brill Publishers. doi:10.1163/1573-3912_islam_COM_0189. ISBN 978-90-04-16121-4.
  22. ^ a b Roy Jackson (2014). What is Islamic philosophy?. Routledge. p. 173. ISBN 978-1317814047. jihad Literally 'struggle' which has many meanings, though most frequently associated with war.
  23. ^ a b c d e DeLong-Bas, Natana J. (22 February 2018) [10 May 2017]. "Jihad". Oxford Bibliographies – Islamic Studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195390155-0045. from the original on 29 June 2016. Retrieved 25 October 2021.
  24. ^ Gerhard Böwering, Patricia Crone, ed. (2013). "Jihad". The Princeton Encyclopedia of Islamic Political Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Literally meaning "struggle", jihad may be associated with almost any activity by which Muslims attempt to bring personal and social life into a pattern of conformity with the guidance of God.
  25. ^ a b Badara, Mohamed; Nagata, Masaki (November 2017). "Modern Extremist Groups and the Division of the World: A Critique from an Islamic Perspective". Arab Law Quarterly. Leiden: Brill Publishers. 31 (4): 305–335. doi:10.1163/15730255-12314024. ISSN 1573-0255.
  26. ^ a b c Wael B. Hallaq (2009). Sharī'a: Theory, Practice, Transformations. Cambridge University Press (Kindle edition). pp. 334–38.
  27. ^ Peters, Rudolph (2015). Islam and Colonialism: The Doctrine of Jihad in Modern History. De Gruyter Mouton. p. 124. doi:10.1515/9783110824858. ISBN 9783110824858. from the original on 25 October 2016. Retrieved 24 January 2017 – via De Gruyter.
  28. ^ a b Rudolph Peters (2005). "Jihad". In Lindsay Jones (ed.). Encyclopedia of Religion. Vol. 7 (2nd ed.). MacMillan Reference. p. 4917.
  29. ^ Cook, David (2015) [2005]. "Radical Islam and Contemporary Jihad Theory". Understanding Jihad (2nd ed.). Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 93–127. ISBN 9780520287327. JSTOR 10.1525/j.ctv1xxt55.10. LCCN 2015010201.
  30. ^ a b Jalal, Ayesha (2009). "Islam Subverted? Jihad as Terrorism". Partisans of Allah: Jihad in South Asia. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. pp. 239–240. doi:10.4159/9780674039070-007. ISBN 9780674039070. S2CID 152941120.
  31. ^ Al-Dawoody 2011, p. 56: Seventeen derivatives of jihād occur altogether forty-one times in eleven Meccan texts and thirty Medinan ones, with the following five meanings: striving because of religious belief (21), war (12), non-Muslim parents exerting pressure, that is, jihād, to make their children abandon Islam (2), solemn oaths (5), and physical strength (1).
  32. ^ Morgan, Diane (2010). Essential Islam: A Comprehensive Guide to Belief and Practice. ABC-CLIO. p. 87. ISBN 978-0313360251. Retrieved 5 January 2011.
  33. ^ Josef W. Meri, ed. (2005). "Medieval Islamic Civilization". Medieval Islamic Civilization: An Encyclopedia. Routledge. ISBN 978-0415966900., Jihad, p. 419.
  34. ^ Esposito 1988, p. 54.
  35. ^ Bernard Lewis (27 September 2001). "Jihad vs. Crusade". Opinionjournal.com. from the original on 16 August 2016. Retrieved 4 August 2016.
  36. ^ Blankinship, Khalid Yahya (2011). "Parity of Muslim and Western Concepts of Just War". The Muslim World. 101 (3): 416. doi:10.1111/j.1478-1913.2011.01384.x. ISSN 1478-1913. In classical Muslim doctrine on war, likewise, genuine non-combatants are not to be harmed. These include women, minors, servants and slaves who do not take part in the fighting, the blind, monks, hermits, the aged, those physically unable to fight, the insane, the delirious, farmers who do not fight, traders, merchants, and contractors. The main criterion distinguishing combatants from non-combatants is that the latter do not fight and do not contribute to the war effort.
  37. ^ a b Bonner 2006, p. 13.
  38. ^ Esposito 1988, p. 30.
  39. ^ "Part 2: Islamic Practices". al-Islam.org. from the original on 7 September 2014. Retrieved 27 August 2014.
  40. ^ Lloyd Steffen, Lloyd (2007). Holy War, Just War: Exploring the Moral Meaning of Religious Violence. Rowman& Littlefield. p. 221. ISBN 978-1461637394.
  41. ^ cf., e.g., "Libya's Gaddafi urges 'holy war' against Switzerland". BBC News. 26 February 2010. from the original on 4 March 2010. Retrieved 27 March 2010.
  42. ^ Rudolph F. Peters, Jihad in Medieval and Modern Islam (Brill, 1977), p. 3
  43. ^ Crone, Patricia (2005). Medieval Islamic Political Thought. Edinburgh University Press. p. 363. ISBN 0-7486-2194-6. OCLC 61176687.
  44. ^ Khaled Abou El Fadl stresses that the Islamic theological tradition did not have a notion of "Holy war" (in Arabic al-harb al-muqaddasa), which is not an expression used by the Quranic text or Muslim theologians. He further states that in Islamic theology, war is never holy; it is either justified or not. He then writes that the Quran does not use the word jihad to refer to warfare or fighting; such acts are referred to as qital. Source: Abou El Fadl, Khaled (23 January 2007). The Great Theft: Wrestling Islam from the Extremists. HarperOne. p. 222. ISBN 978-0061189036.
  45. ^ Christians and War: Augustine of Hippo and the "Just War theory" 28 November 2006 at the Wayback Machine
  46. ^ "What is a just war?". BBC. Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  47. ^ Robert L. Holmes. "A Time For War?". ChristianityToday.com. Retrieved 25 April 2015.
  48. ^ a b . Archived from the original on 25 July 2013. Retrieved 25 April 2015.
  49. ^ Augustine: Political and Social Philosophy, §3-c "War and Peace – The Just War"
  50. ^ a b Gregory M. Reichberg (2017). Thomas Aquinas on War and Peace. Cambridge University Press. p. viii. ISBN 9781107019904.
  51. ^ Gregory M. Reichberg (2017). Thomas Aquinas on War and Peace. Cambridge University Press. p. vii. ISBN 9781107019904.
  52. ^ Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologica. Christian Classics Ethereal Library. pp. pt. II, sec. 2, q. 40, a. 1.
  53. ^ Seth Lazar; Helen Frowe, eds. (2018). The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War. Oxford University Press. p. 114. ISBN 9780199943418.
  54. ^ Seth Lazar; Helen Frowe, eds. (2018). The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War. Oxford University Press. p. 115. ISBN 9780199943418.
  55. ^ Mews, Stuart. "Davidson, Randall Thomas, Baron Davidson of Lambeth (1848–1930), Archbishop of Canterbury", Oxford Dictionary of National Biography, Oxford University Press, 2011.
  56. ^ Catechism of the Catholic Church (2 ed.). Liberia Editrice Vaticana. 2000. ISBN 1574551108. Retrieved 25 April 2015.
  57. ^ "Just-War Theory, Catholic Morality, And The Response To International Terrorism". Retrieved 11 May 2020.
  58. ^ "Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church". Retrieved 25 April 2015.
  59. ^ Saunders, William. "The Church's Just War Theory". Catholic Education Resource Center. Retrieved 10 May 2020.
  60. ^ Knorre, Boris; Zygmont, Aleksei (2019). "'Militant Piety in 21st-Century Orthodox Christianity: Return to Classical Traditions or Formation of a New Theology of War?". Religions. 11: 2. doi:10.3390/rel11010002.   Text was copied from this source, which is available under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
  61. ^ "Social Concepts, Chapter VIII". Retrieved 10 May 2020.
  62. ^ John Dear (23 February 2010). "Ben Salmon and the Army of Peace". National Catholic Reporter.
  63. ^ C. T. Bridgeman (1962). A History of the Parish of Trinity Church in the City of New York: The rectorship of Dr. William Thomas Manning 1908 to 1921. p. 256.
  64. ^ David, Saul (1 October 2009). "Ethics of War". The Encyclopedia of War from Ancient Egypt to Iraq. Dorling Kindersley Limited. p. 345. ISBN 978-1-4053-4778-5.
  65. ^ Victor M. Salas Jr. (2012). "Francisco de Vitoria on the Ius Gentium and the American Indios" (PDF). Ave Maria Law Review.
  66. ^ Gutman R, Rieff D. Crimes of War: What the Public Should Know. New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Company; 1999
  67. ^ "JustWarTheory.com". JustWarTheory.com. Retrieved 16 March 2010.
  68. ^ . Eppc.org. 1 September 1998. Archived from the original on 9 May 2009. Retrieved 16 March 2010.
  69. ^ Leer, Genrikh Antonovich (1869). Opyt kritiko-istoricheskogo issledovaniya zakonov isskusstva vedeniya voyny Опыт критико-исторического исследования законов искусства ведения войны [Critico-historical research into the laws of the art of the conduct of war] (in Russian). Nikolayevskaya inzhenernaya akademiya. Saint Petersburg. p. 1ff. ISBN 9785458055901. Retrieved 3 September 2022.
  70. ^ Wollenberg, Erich. "Just Wars in the Light of Marxism". Marxists Internet Archive.
  71. ^ Lenin, Vladimir. "The Revolution in Russia and the Tasks of the Workers of All Countries". Marxists Internet Archive.
  72. ^ Lenin, Vladimir. "Socialism and War, ch. 1". Marxists Internet Archive.
  73. ^ Murray N. Rothbard. "Just War". lewrockwell.com. Retrieved 26 June 2019.
  74. ^ Smith, Jonathan R. . Catholic Education Resource Center. Archived from the original on 23 July 2001.
  75. ^ Childress, James F. (1978). "Just-War Theories: The Bases, Interrelations, Priorities, and Functions of Their Criteria" (PDF). Theological Studies. 39 (3): 427–445. doi:10.1177/004056397803900302. S2CID 159493143.
  76. ^ . Archived from the original on 7 September 2013. Retrieved 25 April 2015.
  77. ^ Brooks, Thom (October 2012). Studies in Moral philosophy: Just War Theory. Brill. p. 187. ISBN 978-9004228504.

Further reading

  • Benson, Richard. , The Tidings (2006). Showing the Catholic view in three points, including John Paul II's position concerning war.
  • Blattberg, Charles. Taking War Seriously. A critique of just war theory.
  • Brough, Michael W., John W. Lango, Harry van der Linden, eds., Rethinking the Just War Tradition (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2007). Discusses the contemporary relevance of just war theory. Offers an annotated bibliography of current writings on just war theory.
  • Brunsletter, D., & D. O'Driscoll, Just war thinkers from Cicero to the 21st century (Routledge, 2017).
  • Butler, Paul (2002–2003). "By Any Means Necessary: Using Violence and Subversion to Change Unjust Law". UCLA Law Review. 50: 721 – via HeinOnline.
  • Churchman, David. "Just War Theory Across Time and Culture" in Oliver Richmond, and Gëzim Visoka, eds. The Palgrave Encyclopedia of Peace and Conflict Studies (2022) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77954-2_59
  • Churchman, David. Why we fight: the origins, nature, and management of human conflict (University Press of America, 2013) online.
  • Crawford, Neta. "Just War Theory and the US Countertenor War", Perspectives on Politics 1(1), 2003. online
  • Elshtain, Jean Bethke, ed. Just war theory (NYU Press, 1992) online.
  • Evans, Mark (editor) Just War Theory: A Reappraisal (Edinburgh University Press, 2005)
  • Fotion, Nicholas. War and Ethics (London, New York: Continuum, 2007). ISBN 0-8264-9260-6. A defence of an updated form of just war theory.
  • Heindel, Max. The Rosicrucian Philosophy in Questions and Answers – Volume II (The Philosophy of War, World War I reference, ed. 1918), ISBN 0-911274-90-1 (Describing a philosophy of war and just war concepts from the point of view of his Rosicrucian Fellowship)
  • Gutbrod, Hans. Assembling the Moral Puzzle – Just War Tradition and Karabakh ("Global Policy Journal", February 2021); illustrates how the just war theory can offer a comprehensive assessment of the 2020 conflict around Nagorno-Karabakh.
  • Gutbrod, Hans. Russia's Recent Invasion of Ukraine and Just War Theory ("Global Policy Journal", March 2022); applies the concept to Russia's February 2022 invasion of Ukraine.
  • Kelsay, John; Lo, PC; and Morkevicius, Valerie, "Comparative Ethics of War: Islamic, Chinese and Hindu Perspectives," McCain Conference, Stockdale Center, United States Naval Academy, 2011.
  • Khawaja, Irfan. Review of Larry May, War Crimes and Just War, in Democratiya 10, (), an extended critique of just war theory.
  • Lazar, Seth (Spring 2020). "War". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • MacDonald, David Roberts. Padre E. C. Crosse and 'the Devonshire Epitaph': The Astonishing Story of One Man at the Battle of the Somme (with Antecedents to Today's 'Just War' Dialogue), 2007 Cloverdale Books, South Bend. ISBN 978-1-929569-45-8
  • McMahan, Jeff. "Just Cause for War," Ethics and International Affairs, 2005.
  • Nájera, Luna. "Myth and Prophecy in Juan Ginés de Sepúlveda's Crusading "Exhortación" 11 March 2011 at the Wayback Machine, in Bulletin for Spanish and Portuguese Historical Studies, 35:1 (2011). Discusses Sepúlveda's theories of war in relation to the war against the Ottoman Turks.
  • Nardin, Terry, ed. The ethics of war and peace: Religious and secular perspectives (Princeton University Press, 1998) online
  • O'Donovan, Oliver. The Just War Revisited (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
  • Ramsey, Paul. The Just War (New York: Scribners, 1969).
  • Steinhoff, Uwe. On the Ethics of War and Terrorism (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2007). Covers the basics and some of the most controversial current debates.
  • v. Starck, Christian (Ed.). Kann es heute noch gerechte Kriege geben? (Göttingen: Wallstein-Verlag, 2008). ISBN 9783835302617
  • Walzer, Michael. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations, 4th ed. (New York: Basic Books, 1977). ISBN 0-465-03707-0
  • Walzer, Michael. Arguing about War, (Yale University Press, 2004). ISBN 978-0-300-10978-8

External links

  • "Just war theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Just War Theory 7 September 2013 at the Wayback Machine Oregon State University
  • Text of Cicero's Just War Theory in De Officiis
  • Catholic Teaching Concerning Just War at Catholicism.org
  • Jeff McMahon, Rethinking the 'Just War,' Part 1, New York Times
  • American Solidarity Party – New 3rd Party which applies Just War Theory in foreign policy
  • "Just War" In Our Time, BBC Radio 4 discussion with John Keane and Niall Ferguson (3 June 1999)

just, theory, just, redirects, here, 1996, science, fiction, novel, just, novel, just, theory, latin, bellum, iustum, doctrine, also, referred, tradition, military, ethics, which, studied, military, leaders, theologians, ethicists, policy, makers, purpose, doc. Just war redirects here For the 1996 science fiction novel see Just War novel The just war theory Latin bellum iustum 1 2 is a doctrine also referred to as a tradition of military ethics which is studied by military leaders theologians ethicists and policy makers The purpose of the doctrine is to ensure that a war is morally justifiable through a series of criteria all of which must be met for a war to be considered just The criteria are split into two groups jus ad bellum right to go to war and jus in bello right conduct in war The first group of criteria concerns the morality of going to war and the second group of criteria concerns the moral conduct within war 3 There have been calls for the inclusion of a third category of just war theory jus post bellum dealing with the morality of post war settlement and reconstruction The just war theory postulates the belief that war while it is terrible but less so with the right conduct is not always the worst option Important responsibilities undesirable outcomes or preventable atrocities may justify war 3 Saint Augustine was the first clear advocate of just war theory Opponents of the just war theory may either be inclined to a stricter pacifist standard proposing that there has never been nor can there ever be a justifiable basis for war or they may be inclined toward a more permissive nationalist standard proposing that a war need only to serve a nation s interests to be justifiable In many cases philosophers state that individuals do not need to be plagued by a guilty conscience if they are required to fight A few philosophers ennoble the virtues of the soldier while they also declare their apprehensions for war itself 4 A few such as Rousseau argue for insurrection against oppressive rule The historical aspect or the just war tradition deals with the historical body of rules or agreements that have applied in various wars across the ages The just war tradition also considers the writings of various philosophers and lawyers through history and examines both their philosophical visions of war s ethical limits and whether their thoughts have contributed to the body of conventions that have evolved to guide war and warfare 5 Contents 1 Origins 1 1 Ancient Egypt 1 2 Confucian 1 3 India 1 4 Ancient Greece and Rome 1 5 Muslim teaching of Jihad 1 6 Christian views 1 6 1 Saint Augustine 1 6 2 Saint Thomas Aquinas 1 6 3 First World War 1 6 4 Contemporary Catholic doctrine 1 6 5 Russian Orthodox Church 1 7 Just war tradition 2 Criteria 2 1 Jus ad bellum 2 2 Jus in bello 2 3 Ending a war Jus post bellum 3 References 4 Further reading 5 External linksOrigins EditAncient Egypt Edit A 2017 study found that the just war tradition can be traced as far back as to Ancient Egypt 6 Egyptian ethics of war usually centered on three main ideas these including the cosmological role of Egypt the pharaoh as a divine office and executor of the will of the gods and the superiority of the Egyptian state and population over all other states and peoples Egyptian political theology held that the pharaoh had the exclusive legitimacy in justly initiating a war usually claimed to carry out the will of the gods Senusret I in the Twelfth Dynasty claimed I was nursed to be a conqueror his Atum s son and his protector he gave me to conquer what he conquered Later pharaohs also considered their sonship of the god Amun Re as granting them absolute ability to declare war on the deity s behalf Pharaohs often visited temples prior to initiating campaigns where the pharaoh was believed to receive their commands of war from the deities For example Kamose claimed that I went north because I was strong enough to attack the Asiatics through the command of Amon the just of counsels A stele erected by Thutmose III at the Temple of Amun at Karnak provides an unequivocal statement of the pharaoh s divine mandate to wage war on his enemies As the period of the New Kingdom progressed and Egypt heightened its territorial ambition so did the invocation of just war aid the justification of these efforts The universal principle of Maat signifying order and justice was central to the Egyptian notion of just war and its ability to guarantee Egypt virtually no limits on what it could take do or use to guarantee the ambitions of the state 6 Confucian Edit Chinese philosophy produced a massive body of work on warfare much of it during the Zhou dynasty especially the Warring States era War was justified only as a last resort and only by the rightful sovereign however questioning the decision of the emperor concerning the necessity of a military action was not permissible The success of a military campaign was sufficient proof that the campaign had been righteous 7 Japan did not develop its own doctrine of just war but between the 5th and the 7th centuries drew heavily from Chinese philosophy and especially Confucian views As part of the Japanese campaign to take the northeastern island Honshu Japanese military action was portrayed as an effort to pacify the Emishi people who were likened to bandits and wild hearted wolf cubs and accused of invading Japan s frontier lands 7 India Edit The Indian Hindu epic the Mahabharata offers the first written discussions of a just war dharma yuddha or righteous war In it one of five ruling brothers Pandavas asks if the suffering caused by war can ever be justified A long discussion then ensues between the siblings establishing criteria like proportionality chariots cannot attack cavalry only other chariots no attacking people in distress just means no poisoned or barbed arrows just cause no attacking out of rage and fair treatment of captives and the wounded 8 The war in the Mahabharata is preceded by context that develops the just cause for the war including last minute efforts to reconcile differences to avoid war At the beginning of the war there is the discussion of just conduct appropriate to the context of war In Sikhism the term dharamyudh describes a war that is fought for just righteous or religious reasons especially in defence of one s own beliefs Though some core tenets in the Sikh religion are understood to emphasise peace and nonviolence especially before the 1606 execution of Guru Arjan by Mughal emperor Jahangir 9 military force may be justified if all peaceful means to settle a conflict have been exhausted thus resulting in a dharamyudh 10 Ancient Greece and Rome Edit The notion of just war in Europe originates and is developed first in ancient Greece and then in the Roman Empire 11 12 13 It was Aristotle who first introduced the concept and terminology to the Hellenic world that called war a last resort requiring conduct that would allow the restoration of peace Aristotle argues that the cultivation of a military is necessary and good for the purpose of self defense not for conquering The proper object of practising military training is not in order that men may enslave those who do not deserve slavery but in order that first they may themselves avoid becoming enslaved to others Politics Book 7 14 In ancient Rome a just cause for war might include the necessity of repelling an invasion or retaliation for pillaging or a breach of treaty 15 War was always potentially nefas wrong forbidden and risked religious pollution and divine disfavor 16 A just war bellum iustum thus required a ritualized declaration by the fetial priests 17 More broadly conventions of war and treaty making were part of the ius gentium the law of nations the customary moral obligations regarded as innate and universal to human beings 18 The quintessential explanation of Just War theory in the ancient world is found in Cicero s De Officiis Book 1 sections 1 11 33 1 13 41 Although it is well known that Julius Caesar did not often follow these necessities Muslim teaching of Jihad Edit Main article Jihad Jihad is an Arabic word which literally means striving or struggling especially with a praiseworthy aim 19 20 21 22 In an Islamic context it can refer to almost any effort to make personal and social life conform with God s guidance such as struggle against one s evil inclinations proselytizing or efforts toward the moral betterment of the Muslim community Ummah 19 20 23 24 though it is most frequently associated with war 22 25 In classical Islamic law sharia the term refers to armed struggle against unbelievers 20 21 while modernist Islamic scholars generally equate military jihad with defensive warfare 26 27 In Sufi circles spiritual and moral jihad has been traditionally emphasized under the name of greater jihad 23 28 21 The term has gained additional attention in recent decades through its use by various insurgent Islamic extremist militant Islamist and terrorist individuals and organizations whose ideology is purportedly based on the Islamic notion of jihad 23 25 29 30 The word jihad appears frequently in the Qur an with and without military connotations 31 often in the idiomatic expression striving in the path of God al jihad fi sabil Allah 32 33 conveying a sense of self exertion 34 They who developed an elaborate set of rules pertaining to jihad including prohibitions on harming those who are not engaged in combat 35 36 In the modern era the notion of jihad has lost its jurisprudential relevance and instead given rise to an ideological and political discourse 23 26 While modernist Islamic scholars have emphasized the defensive and non military aspects of jihad some Islamists have advanced aggressive interpretations that go beyond the classical theory 26 30 Jihad is classified into inner greater jihad which involves a struggle against one s own base impulses and external lesser jihad which is further subdivided into jihad of the pen tongue debate or persuasion and jihad of the sword 23 37 28 Most Western writers consider external jihad to have primacy over inner jihad in the Islamic tradition while much of contemporary Muslim opinion favors the opposite view 37 The sense of jihad as armed resistance was first used in the context of persecution faced by Muslims as when Muhammad was at Mecca when the community had two choices emigration hijra or jihad 38 In Twelver Shi a Islam jihad is one of the ten Practices of the Religion 39 A person engaged in jihad is called a mujahid plural mujahideen The term jihad is often rendered in English as Holy War 40 41 42 although this translation is controversial 43 44 Today the word jihad is often used without religious connotations like the English crusade 19 20 Christian views Edit Christian theory of the Just War begins around the time of Augustine of Hippo 45 The Just War theory with some amendments is still used by Christians today as a guide to whether or not a war can be justified War may be necessary and right even though it may not be good In the case of a country that has been invaded by an occupying force war may be the only way to restore justice 46 Saint Augustine Edit Saint Augustine held that individuals should not resort immediately to violence but God has given the sword to government for a good reason based upon Romans 13 4 In Contra Faustum Manichaeum book 22 sections 69 76 Augustine argues that Christians as part of a government need not be ashamed of protecting peace and punishing wickedness when they are forced to do so by a government Augustine asserted that was a personal and philosophical stance What is here required is not a bodily action but an inward disposition The sacred seat of virtue is the heart 47 Nonetheless he asserted peacefulness in the face of a grave wrong that could be stopped by only violence would be a sin Defense of one s self or others could be a necessity especially when it is authorized by a legitimate authority They who have waged war in obedience to the divine command or in conformity with His laws have represented in their persons the public justice or the wisdom of government and in this capacity have put to death wicked men such persons have by no means violated the commandment Thou shalt not kill 48 While not breaking down the conditions necessary for war to be just Augustine nonetheless originated the very phrase itself in his work The City of God But say they the wise man will wage Just Wars As if he would not all the rather lament the necessity of just wars if he remembers that he is a man for if they were not just he would not wage them and would therefore be delivered from all wars 48 J Mark Mattox writes In terms of the traditional notion of jus ad bellum justice of war that is the circumstances in which wars can be justly fought war is a coping mechanism for righteous sovereigns who would ensure that their violent international encounters are minimal a reflection of the Divine Will to the greatest extent possible and always justified In terms of the traditional notion of jus in bello justice in war or the moral considerations which ought to constrain the use of violence in war war is a coping mechanism for righteous combatants who by divine edict have no choice but to subject themselves to their political masters and seek to ensure that they execute their war fighting duty as justly as possible 49 Saint Thomas Aquinas Edit The just war theory by Thomas Aquinas has had a lasting impact on later generations of thinkers and was part of an emerging consensus in Medieval Europe on just war 50 In the 13th century Aquinas reflected in detail on peace and war Aquinas was a Dominican friar and contemplated the teachings of the Bible on peace and war in combination with ideas from Aristotle Plato Saint Augustine and other philosophers whose writings are part of the Western canon Aquinas views on war drew heavily on the Decretum Gratiani a book the Italian monk Gratian had compiled with passages from the Bible After its publication in the 12th century the Decretum Gratiani had been republished with commentary from Pope Innocent IV and the Dominican friar Raymond of Penafort Other significant influences on Aquinas just war theory were Alexander of Hales and Henry of Segusio 51 In Summa Theologica Aquinas asserted that it is not always a sin to wage war and he set out criteria for a just war According to Aquinas three requirements must be met Firstly the war must be waged upon the command of a rightful sovereign Secondly the war needs to be waged for just cause on account of some wrong the attacked have committed Thirdly warriors must have the right intent namely to promote good and to avoid evil 52 53 Aquinas came to the conclusion that a just war could be offensive and that injustice should not be tolerated so as to avoid war Nevertheless Aquinas argued that violence must only be used as a last resort On the battlefield violence was only justified to the extent it was necessary Soldiers needed to avoid cruelty and a just war was limited by the conduct of just combatants Aquinas argued that it was only in the pursuit of justice that the good intention of a moral act could justify negative consequences including the killing of the innocent during a war 54 First World War Edit At the beginning of the First World War a group of theologians in Germany published a manifesto that sought to justify the actions of the German government At the British government s request Randall Davidson Archbishop of Canterbury took the lead in collaborating with a large number of other religious leaders including some with whom he had differed in the past to write a rebuttal of the Germans contentions Both German and British theologians based themselves on the just war theory each group seeking to prove that it applied to the war waged by its own side 55 Contemporary Catholic doctrine Edit The just war doctrine of the Catholic Church found in the 1992 Catechism of the Catholic Church in paragraph 2309 lists four strict conditions for legitimate defense by military force 56 57 The damage inflicted by the aggressor on the nation or community of nations must be lasting grave and certain All other means of putting an end to it must have been shown to be impractical or ineffective there must be serious prospects of success The use of arms must not produce evils and disorders graver than the evil to be eliminated The Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church elaborates on the just war doctrine in paragraphs 500 to 501 58 If this responsibility justifies the possession of sufficient means to exercise this right to defense States still have the obligation to do everything possible to ensure that the conditions of peace exist not only within their own territory but throughout the world It is important to remember that it is one thing to wage a war of self defense it is quite another to seek to impose domination on another nation The possession of war potential does not justify the use of force for political or military objectives Nor does the mere fact that war has unfortunately broken out mean that all is fair between the warring parties The Charter of the United Nations intends to preserve future generations from war with a prohibition against force to resolve disputes between States Like most philosophy it permits legitimate defense and measures to maintain peace In every case the charter requires that self defense must respect the traditional limits of necessity and proportionality Therefore engaging in a preventive war without clear proof that an attack is imminent cannot fail to raise serious moral and juridical questions International legitimacy for the use of armed force on the basis of rigorous assessment and with well founded motivations can only be given by the decision of a competent body that identifies specific situations as threats to peace and authorizes an intrusion into the sphere of autonomy usually reserved to a State Pope John Paul II in an address to a group of soldiers said the following 59 Peace as taught by Sacred Scripture and the experience of men itself is more than just the absence of war And the Christian is aware that on earth a human society that is completely and always peaceful is unfortunately an utopia and that the ideologies which present it as easily attainable only nourish vain hopes The cause of peace will not go forward by denying the possibility and the obligation to defend it Russian Orthodox Church Edit The War and Peace section in the Basis of the Social Concept of the Russian Orthodox Church is crucial for understanding the Russian Orthodox Church s attitude towards war The document offers criteria of distinguishing between an aggressive war which is unacceptable and a justified war attributing the highest moral and sacred value of military acts of bravery to a true believer who participates in a justified war Additionally the document considers the just war criteria as developed in Western Christianity to be eligible for Russian Orthodoxy therefore the justified war theory in Western theology is also applicable to the Russian Orthodox Church 60 In the same document it is stated that wars have accompanied human history since the fall of man and according to the gospel they will continue to accompany it While recognizing war as evil the Russian Orthodox Church does not prohibit its members from participating in hostilities if there is the security of their neighbours and the restoration of trampled justice at stake War is considered to be necessary but undesirable It is also stated that the Russian Orthodox Church has had profound respect for soldiers who gave their lives to protect the life and security of their neighbours 61 Just war tradition Edit The just war theory propounded by the medieval Christian philosopher Thomas Aquinas was developed further by legal scholars in the context of international law Cardinal Cajetan the jurist Francisco de Vitoria the two Jesuit priests Luis de Molina and Francisco Suarez as well as the humanist Hugo Grotius and the lawyer Luigi Taparelli were most influential in the formation of a just war tradition The just war tradition which was well established by the 19th century found its practical application in the Hague Peace Conferences 1899 and 1907 and in the founding of the League of Nations in 1920 After the United States Congress declared war on Germany in 1917 Cardinal James Gibbons issued a letter that all Catholics were to support the war 62 because Our Lord Jesus Christ does not stand for peace at any price If by Pacifism is meant the teaching that the use of force is never justifiable then however well meant it is mistaken and it is hurtful to the life of our country 63 Armed conflicts such as the Spanish Civil War World War II and the Cold War were as a matter of course judged according to the norms as established in Aquinas just war theory by philosophers such as Jacques Maritain Elizabeth Anscombe and John Finnis 50 The first work dedicated specifically to just war was the 15th century sermon De bellis justis of Stanislaw of Skarbimierz 1360 1431 who justified war by the Kingdom of Poland against the Teutonic Knights 64 Francisco de Vitoria criticized the conquest of America by the Spanish conquistadors on the basis of just war theory 65 With Alberico Gentili and Hugo Grotius just war theory was replaced by international law theory codified as a set of rules which today still encompass the points commonly debated with some modifications 66 Just war theorists combine a moral abhorrence towards war with a readiness to accept that war may sometimes be necessary The criteria of the just war tradition act as an aid in determining whether resorting to arms is morally permissible Just war theories aim to distinguish between justifiable and unjustifiable uses of organized armed forces they attempt to conceive of how the use of arms might be restrained made more humane and ultimately directed towards the aim of establishing lasting peace and justice 67 Although the criticism can be made that the application of just war theory is relativistic one of the fundamental bases of the tradition is the Ethic of Reciprocity particularly when it comes to in bello considerations of deportment during battle If one set of combatants promise to treat their enemies with a modicum of restraint and respect then the hope is that other sets of combatants will do similarly in reciprocation a concept not unrelated to the considerations of game theory The just war tradition addresses the morality of the use of force in two parts when it is right to resort to armed force the concern of jus ad bellum and what is acceptable in using such force the concern of jus in bello 68 In more recent years a third category jus post bellum has been added by certain theorists and addresses the justice of war termination and peace agreements as well as the prosecution of war criminals In 1869 the Russian military theorist Genrikh Antonovich Leer ru theorised on the advantages and potential benefits of war 69 The Soviet leader Vladimir Lenin defined only three types of just war 70 all of which share the central trait of being revolutionary in character In simple terms To the Russian workers has fallen the honor and the good fortune of being the first to start the revolution the great and only legitimate and just war the war of the oppressed against the oppressors 71 with these two opposing categories being defined in terms of class as is typical in the left In that manner Lenin shunned the more common interpretation of a defensive war as a just one often summarized as who fired the first shot precisely because it failed to take into consideration the class factor Which side initiated aggressions or had a grievance or any other commonly considered factor of jus ad bellum mattered not at all he claimed if one side was being oppressed by the other the war against the oppressor would always be by definition a defensive war anyway Any war lacking that duality of oppressed and oppressor was in contradistinction always a reactionary unjust war in which the oppressed effectively fight in order to protect their own oppressors But picture to yourselves a slave owner who owned 100 slaves warring against a slave owner who owned 200 slaves for a more just distribution of slaves Clearly the application of the term defensive war or war for the defense of the fatherland in such a case would be historically false and in practice would be sheer deception of the common people of philistines of ignorant people by the astute slaveowners Precisely in this way are the present day imperialist bourgeoisie deceiving the peoples by means of national ideology and the term defense of the fatherland in the present war between slave owners for fortifying and strengthening slavery 72 The anarcho capitalist scholar Murray Rothbard 1926 1995 stated that a just war exists when a people tries to ward off the threat of coercive domination by another people or to overthrow an already existing domination A war is unjust on the other hand when a people try to impose domination on another people or try to retain an already existing coercive rule over them 73 Jonathan Riley Smith writes The consensus among Christians on the use of violence has changed radically since the crusades were fought The just war theory prevailing for most of the last two centuries that violence is an evil that can in certain situations be condoned as the lesser of evils is relatively young Although it has inherited some elements the criteria of legitimate authority just cause right intention from the older war theory that first evolved around AD 400 it has rejected two premises that underpinned all medieval just wars including crusades first that violence could be employed on behalf of Christ s intentions for mankind and could even be directly authorized by him and second that it was a morally neutral force that drew whatever ethical coloring it had from the intentions of the perpetrators 74 Criteria EditThe just war theory has two sets of criteria the first establishing jus ad bellum the right to go to war and the second establishing jus in bello right conduct within war 75 Jus ad bellum Edit Main article Jus ad bellum Just cause The reason for going to war needs to be just and cannot therefore be solely for recapturing things taken or punishing people who have done wrong innocent life must be in imminent danger and intervention must be to protect life A contemporary view of just cause was expressed in 1993 when the US Catholic Conference said Force may be used only to correct a grave public evil i e aggression or massive violation of the basic human rights of whole populations Comparative justice While there may be rights and wrongs on all sides of a conflict to overcome the presumption against the use of force the injustice suffered by one party must significantly outweigh that suffered by the other Some theorists such as Brian Orend omit this term seeing it as fertile ground for exploitation by bellicose regimes Competent authority Only duly constituted public authorities may wage war A just war must be initiated by a political authority within a political system that allows distinctions of justice Dictatorships e g Hitler s Regime or deceptive military actions e g the 1968 US bombing of Cambodia are typically considered as violations of this criterion The importance of this condition is key Plainly we cannot have a genuine process of judging a just war within a system that represses the process of genuine justice A just war must be initiated by a political authority within a political system that allows distinctions of justice 76 Right intention Force may be used only in a truly just cause and solely for that purpose correcting a suffered wrong is considered a right intention while material gain or maintaining economies is not Probability of success Arms may not be used in a futile cause or in a case where disproportionate measures are required to achieve success Last resort Force may be used only after all peaceful and viable alternatives have been seriously tried and exhausted or are clearly not practical It may be clear that the other side is using negotiations as a delaying tactic and will not make meaningful concessions Proportionality The anticipated benefits of waging a war must be proportionate to its expected evils or harms This principle is also known as the principle of macro proportionality so as to distinguish it from the jus in bello principle of proportionality In modern terms just war is waged in terms of self defense or in defense of another with sufficient evidence Jus in bello Edit Once war has begun just war theory jus in bello also directs how combatants are to act or should act Distinction Just war conduct should be governed by the principle of distinction The acts of war should be directed towards enemy combatants and not towards non combatants caught in circumstances they did not create The prohibited acts include bombing civilian residential areas that include no legitimate military targets committing acts of terrorism or reprisal against civilians or prisoners of war POWs and attacking neutral targets Moreover combatants are not permitted to attack enemy combatants who have surrendered or who have been captured or who are injured and not presenting an immediate lethal threat or who are parachuting from disabled aircraft and are not airborne forces or who are shipwrecked Proportionality Just war conduct should be governed by the principle of proportionality Combatants must make sure that the harm caused to civilians or civilian property is not excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage anticipated by an attack on a legitimate military objective This principle is meant to discern the correct balance between the restriction imposed by a corrective measure and the severity of the nature of the prohibited act Military necessity Just war conduct should be governed by the principle of military necessity An attack or action must be intended to help in the defeat of the enemy it must be an attack on a legitimate military objective and the harm caused to civilians or civilian property must be proportional and not excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage anticipated This principle is meant to limit excessive and unnecessary death and destruction Fair treatment of prisoners of war Enemy combatants who surrendered or who are captured no longer pose a threat It is therefore wrong to torture them or otherwise mistreat them No means malum in se Combatants may not use weapons or other methods of warfare that are considered evil such as mass rape forcing enemy combatants to fight against their own side or using weapons whose effects cannot be controlled e g nuclear biological weapons Ending a war Jus post bellum Edit In recent years some theorists such as Gary Bass Louis Iasiello and Brian Orend have proposed a third category within the just war theory Jus post bellum concerns justice after a war including peace treaties reconstruction environmental remediation war crimes trials and war reparations Jus post bellum has been added to deal with the fact that some hostile actions may take place outside a traditional battlefield Jus post bellum governs the justice of war termination and peace agreements as well as the prosecution of war criminals and publicly labelled terrorists The idea has largely been added to help decide what to do if there are prisoners that have been taken during battle It is through government labelling and public opinion that people use jus post bellum to justify the pursuit of labelled terrorist for the safety of the government s state in a modern context The actual fault lies with the aggressor and so by being the aggressor they forfeit their rights for honourable treatment by their actions That theory is used to justify the actions taken by anyone fighting in a war to treat prisoners outside of war 77 Actions after a conflict can be warranted by actions observed during war meaning that there can be justification to meet violence with violence even after war Orend who was one of the theorists mentioned earlier proposes the following principles Just cause for termination A state may terminate a war if there has been a reasonable vindication of the rights that were violated in the first place and if the aggressor is willing to negotiate the terms of surrender These terms of surrender include a formal apology compensations war crimes trials and perhaps rehabilitation Alternatively a state may end a war if it becomes clear that any just goals of the war cannot be reached at all or cannot be reached without using excessive force Right intention A state must only terminate a war under the conditions agreed upon in the above criteria Revenge is not permitted The victor state must also be willing to apply the same level of objectivity and investigation into any war crimes its armed forces may have committed Public declaration and authority The terms of peace must be made by a legitimate authority and the terms must be accepted by a legitimate authority Discrimination The victor state is to differentiate between political and military leaders and combatants and civilians Punitive measures are to be limited to those directly responsible for the conflict Truth and reconciliation may sometimes be more important than punishing war crimes Proportionality Any terms of surrender must be proportional to the rights that were initially violated Draconian measures absolutionist crusades and any attempt at denying the surrendered country the right to participate in the world community are not permitted References Edit Cicero Marcus Tullius Miller Walter 1913 De officiis With an English translation by Walter Miller Robarts University of Toronto London Heinemann Fellmeth Aaron X Horwitz Maurice 2009 Bellum iustum Guide to Latin in International Law Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acref 9780195369380 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 536938 0 Retrieved 27 February 2022 a b Guthrie Charles Quinlan Michael 2007 III The Structure of the Tradition Just War The Just War Tradition Ethics in Modern Warfare pp 11 15 ISBN 978 0747595571 McHenry Robert 22 March 2010 William James on Peace and War blogs britannica com Britannica Blog Archived from the original on 31 October 2015 Retrieved 6 August 2017 Just War Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 30 October 2016 a b Cox Rory 2017 Expanding the History of the Just War The Ethics of War in Ancient Egypt International Studies Quarterly 61 2 371 doi 10 1093 isq sqx009 hdl 10023 17848 a b Friday Karl F 2004 Samurai Warfare and the State in Early Medieval Japan Routledge pp 21 22 ISBN 9781134330225 Robinson Paul F Robinson Paul 2003 Just War in Comparative Perspective ISBN 9780754635871 Retrieved 25 April 2015 Syan Hardip Singh 2013 Sikh Militancy in the Seventeenth Century Religious Violence in Mughal and Early Modern India London amp New York I B Tauris pp 3 4 252 ISBN 9781780762500 Retrieved 15 September 2019 Fenech Louis E McLeod W H 2014 Historical Dictionary of Sikhism Plymouth amp Lanham Maryland Rowman amp Littlefield pp 99 100 ISBN 9781442236011 Retrieved 16 September 2019 Gregory Raymond The Greco Roman Roots of the Western Just War Tradition Routledge 2010 Rory Cox The Ethics of War up to Thomas Aquinas in eds Lazar amp Frowe The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War Oxford 2018 Cian O Driscoll Rewriting the Just War Tradition Just War in Classical Greek Political Thought and Practice International Studies Quarterly 2015 Aristotle Politics Book 7 Perseus Digital Library Livy 9 1 10 Cicero Divinatio in Caecilium 63 De provinciis consularibus 4 Ad Atticum VII 14 3 IX 19 1 Pro rege Deiotauro 13 De officiis I 36 Philippicae XI 37 XIII 35 De re publica II 31 III 35 Isidore of Seville Origines XVIII 1 2 Modestinus Libro I regolarum Digesta I 3 40 E Badian Roman Imperialism in the Late Republic Ithaca 1968 2nd ed p 11 William Warde Fowler The Roman Festivals of the Period of the Republic London 1925 pp 33ff M Kaser Das altroemische Ius Goettingen 1949 pp 22ff P Catalano Linee del sistema sovrannazionale romano Torino 1965 pp 14ff W V Harris War and imperialism in Republican Rome 327 70 B C Oxford 1979 pp 161 ff Livy 1 32 31 8 3 36 3 9 Cicero De officiis 3 17 69 Marcia L Colish The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages Brill 1980 p 150 a b c John L Esposito ed 2014 Jihad The Oxford Dictionary of Islam Oxford Oxford University Press Archived from the original on 3 September 2014 Retrieved 29 August 2014 a b c d Peters Rudolph Cook David 2014 Jihad The Oxford Encyclopedia of Islam and Politics Oxford Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acref oiso 9780199739356 001 0001 ISBN 9780199739356 Archived from the original on 23 January 2017 Retrieved 24 January 2017 a b c Tyan E 1965 D j ihad In Bosworth C E van Donzel E J Heinrichs W P Lewis B Pellat Ch Schacht J eds Encyclopaedia of Islam Second Edition Vol 2 Leiden Brill Publishers doi 10 1163 1573 3912 islam COM 0189 ISBN 978 90 04 16121 4 a b Roy Jackson 2014 What is Islamic philosophy Routledge p 173 ISBN 978 1317814047 jihad Literally struggle which has many meanings though most frequently associated with war a b c d e DeLong Bas Natana J 22 February 2018 10 May 2017 Jihad Oxford Bibliographies Islamic Studies Oxford Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 obo 9780195390155 0045 Archived from the original on 29 June 2016 Retrieved 25 October 2021 Gerhard Bowering Patricia Crone ed 2013 Jihad The Princeton Encyclopedia of Islamic Political Thought Princeton NJ Princeton University Press Literally meaning struggle jihad may be associated with almost any activity by which Muslims attempt to bring personal and social life into a pattern of conformity with the guidance of God a b Badara Mohamed Nagata Masaki November 2017 Modern Extremist Groups and the Division of the World A Critique from an Islamic Perspective Arab Law Quarterly Leiden Brill Publishers 31 4 305 335 doi 10 1163 15730255 12314024 ISSN 1573 0255 a b c Wael B Hallaq 2009 Shari a Theory Practice Transformations Cambridge University Press Kindle edition pp 334 38 Peters Rudolph 2015 Islam and Colonialism The Doctrine of Jihad in Modern History De Gruyter Mouton p 124 doi 10 1515 9783110824858 ISBN 9783110824858 Archived from the original on 25 October 2016 Retrieved 24 January 2017 via De Gruyter a b Rudolph Peters 2005 Jihad In Lindsay Jones ed Encyclopedia of Religion Vol 7 2nd ed MacMillan Reference p 4917 Cook David 2015 2005 Radical Islam and Contemporary Jihad Theory Understanding Jihad 2nd ed Berkeley University of California Press pp 93 127 ISBN 9780520287327 JSTOR 10 1525 j ctv1xxt55 10 LCCN 2015010201 a b Jalal Ayesha 2009 Islam Subverted Jihad as Terrorism Partisans of Allah Jihad in South Asia Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press pp 239 240 doi 10 4159 9780674039070 007 ISBN 9780674039070 S2CID 152941120 Al Dawoody 2011 p 56harvnb error no target CITEREFAl Dawoody2011 help Seventeen derivatives of jihad occur altogether forty one times in eleven Meccan texts and thirty Medinan ones with the following five meanings striving because of religious belief 21 war 12 non Muslim parents exerting pressure that is jihad to make their children abandon Islam 2 solemn oaths 5 and physical strength 1 Morgan Diane 2010 Essential Islam A Comprehensive Guide to Belief and Practice ABC CLIO p 87 ISBN 978 0313360251 Retrieved 5 January 2011 Josef W Meri ed 2005 Medieval Islamic Civilization Medieval Islamic Civilization An Encyclopedia Routledge ISBN 978 0415966900 Jihad p 419 Esposito 1988 p 54 sfn error no target CITEREFEsposito1988 help Bernard Lewis 27 September 2001 Jihad vs Crusade Opinionjournal com Archived from the original on 16 August 2016 Retrieved 4 August 2016 Blankinship Khalid Yahya 2011 Parity of Muslim and Western Concepts of Just War The Muslim World 101 3 416 doi 10 1111 j 1478 1913 2011 01384 x ISSN 1478 1913 In classical Muslim doctrine on war likewise genuine non combatants are not to be harmed These include women minors servants and slaves who do not take part in the fighting the blind monks hermits the aged those physically unable to fight the insane the delirious farmers who do not fight traders merchants and contractors The main criterion distinguishing combatants from non combatants is that the latter do not fight and do not contribute to the war effort a b Bonner 2006 p 13 sfn error no target CITEREFBonner2006 help Esposito 1988 p 30 sfn error no target CITEREFEsposito1988 help Part 2 Islamic Practices al Islam org Archived from the original on 7 September 2014 Retrieved 27 August 2014 Lloyd Steffen Lloyd 2007 Holy War Just War Exploring the Moral Meaning of Religious Violence Rowman amp Littlefield p 221 ISBN 978 1461637394 cf e g Libya s Gaddafi urges holy war against Switzerland BBC News 26 February 2010 Archived from the original on 4 March 2010 Retrieved 27 March 2010 Rudolph F Peters Jihad in Medieval and Modern Islam Brill 1977 p 3 Crone Patricia 2005 Medieval Islamic Political Thought Edinburgh University Press p 363 ISBN 0 7486 2194 6 OCLC 61176687 Khaled Abou El Fadl stresses that the Islamic theological tradition did not have a notion of Holy war in Arabic al harb al muqaddasa which is not an expression used by the Quranic text or Muslim theologians He further states that in Islamic theology war is never holy it is either justified or not He then writes that the Quran does not use the word jihad to refer to warfare or fighting such acts are referred to as qital Source Abou El Fadl Khaled 23 January 2007 The Great Theft Wrestling Islam from the Extremists HarperOne p 222 ISBN 978 0061189036 Christians and War Augustine of Hippo and the Just War theory Archived 28 November 2006 at the Wayback Machine What is a just war BBC Retrieved 11 May 2020 Robert L Holmes A Time For War ChristianityToday com Retrieved 25 April 2015 a b City of God Archived from the original on 25 July 2013 Retrieved 25 April 2015 Augustine Political and Social Philosophy 3 c War and Peace The Just War a b Gregory M Reichberg 2017 Thomas Aquinas on War and Peace Cambridge University Press p viii ISBN 9781107019904 Gregory M Reichberg 2017 Thomas Aquinas on War and Peace Cambridge University Press p vii ISBN 9781107019904 Aquinas Thomas Summa Theologica Christian Classics Ethereal Library pp pt II sec 2 q 40 a 1 Seth Lazar Helen Frowe eds 2018 The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War Oxford University Press p 114 ISBN 9780199943418 Seth Lazar Helen Frowe eds 2018 The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War Oxford University Press p 115 ISBN 9780199943418 Mews Stuart Davidson Randall Thomas Baron Davidson of Lambeth 1848 1930 Archbishop of Canterbury Oxford Dictionary of National Biography Oxford University Press 2011 Catechism of the Catholic Church 2 ed Liberia Editrice Vaticana 2000 ISBN 1574551108 Retrieved 25 April 2015 Just War Theory Catholic Morality And The Response To International Terrorism Retrieved 11 May 2020 Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church Retrieved 25 April 2015 Saunders William The Church s Just War Theory Catholic Education Resource Center Retrieved 10 May 2020 Knorre Boris Zygmont Aleksei 2019 Militant Piety in 21st Century Orthodox Christianity Return to Classical Traditions or Formation of a New Theology of War Religions 11 2 doi 10 3390 rel11010002 Text was copied from this source which is available under a Creative Commons Attribution 4 0 International License Social Concepts Chapter VIII Retrieved 10 May 2020 John Dear 23 February 2010 Ben Salmon and the Army of Peace National Catholic Reporter C T Bridgeman 1962 A History of the Parish of Trinity Church in the City of New York The rectorship of Dr William Thomas Manning 1908 to 1921 p 256 David Saul 1 October 2009 Ethics of War The Encyclopedia of War from Ancient Egypt to Iraq Dorling Kindersley Limited p 345 ISBN 978 1 4053 4778 5 Victor M Salas Jr 2012 Francisco de Vitoria on the Ius Gentium and the American Indios PDF Ave Maria Law Review Gutman R Rieff D Crimes of War What the Public Should Know New York NY W W Norton amp Company 1999 JustWarTheory com JustWarTheory com Retrieved 16 March 2010 Home gt Publications gt Eppc org 1 September 1998 Archived from the original on 9 May 2009 Retrieved 16 March 2010 Leer Genrikh Antonovich 1869 Opyt kritiko istoricheskogo issledovaniya zakonov isskusstva vedeniya voyny Opyt kritiko istoricheskogo issledovaniya zakonov iskusstva vedeniya vojny Critico historical research into the laws of the art of the conduct of war in Russian Nikolayevskaya inzhenernaya akademiya Saint Petersburg p 1ff ISBN 9785458055901 Retrieved 3 September 2022 Wollenberg Erich Just Wars in the Light of Marxism Marxists Internet Archive Lenin Vladimir The Revolution in Russia and the Tasks of the Workers of All Countries Marxists Internet Archive Lenin Vladimir Socialism and War ch 1 Marxists Internet Archive Murray N Rothbard Just War lewrockwell com Retrieved 26 June 2019 Smith Jonathan R Rethinking the Crusades Catholic Education Resource Center Archived from the original on 23 July 2001 Childress James F 1978 Just War Theories The Bases Interrelations Priorities and Functions of Their Criteria PDF Theological Studies 39 3 427 445 doi 10 1177 004056397803900302 S2CID 159493143 Just War Theory Archived from the original on 7 September 2013 Retrieved 25 April 2015 Brooks Thom October 2012 Studies in Moral philosophy Just War Theory Brill p 187 ISBN 978 9004228504 Further reading EditBenson Richard The Just War Theory A Traditional Catholic Moral View The Tidings 2006 Showing the Catholic view in three points including John Paul II s position concerning war Blattberg Charles Taking War Seriously A critique of just war theory Brough Michael W John W Lango Harry van der Linden eds Rethinking the Just War Tradition Albany NY SUNY Press 2007 Discusses the contemporary relevance of just war theory Offers an annotated bibliography of current writings on just war theory Brunsletter D amp D O Driscoll Just war thinkers from Cicero to the 21st century Routledge 2017 Butler Paul 2002 2003 By Any Means Necessary Using Violence and Subversion to Change Unjust Law UCLA Law Review 50 721 via HeinOnline Churchman David Just War Theory Across Time and Culture in Oliver Richmond and Gezim Visoka eds The Palgrave Encyclopedia of Peace and Conflict Studies 2022 https doi org 10 1007 978 3 030 77954 2 59 Churchman David Why we fight the origins nature and management of human conflict University Press of America 2013 online Crawford Neta Just War Theory and the US Countertenor War Perspectives on Politics 1 1 2003 online Elshtain Jean Bethke ed Just war theory NYU Press 1992 online Evans Mark editor Just War Theory A Reappraisal Edinburgh University Press 2005 Fotion Nicholas War and Ethics London New York Continuum 2007 ISBN 0 8264 9260 6 A defence of an updated form of just war theory Heindel Max The Rosicrucian Philosophy in Questions and Answers Volume II The Philosophy of War World War I reference ed 1918 ISBN 0 911274 90 1 Describing a philosophy of war and just war concepts from the point of view of his Rosicrucian Fellowship Gutbrod Hans Assembling the Moral Puzzle Just War Tradition and Karabakh Global Policy Journal February 2021 illustrates how the just war theory can offer a comprehensive assessment of the 2020 conflict around Nagorno Karabakh Gutbrod Hans Russia s Recent Invasion of Ukraine and Just War Theory Global Policy Journal March 2022 applies the concept to Russia s February 2022 invasion of Ukraine Kelsay John Lo PC and Morkevicius Valerie Comparative Ethics of War Islamic Chinese and Hindu Perspectives McCain Conference Stockdale Center United States Naval Academy 2011 Khawaja Irfan Review of Larry May War Crimes and Just War in Democratiya 10 1 an extended critique of just war theory Lazar Seth Spring 2020 War In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy MacDonald David Roberts Padre E C Crosse and the Devonshire Epitaph The Astonishing Story of One Man at the Battle of the Somme with Antecedents to Today s Just War Dialogue 2007 Cloverdale Books South Bend ISBN 978 1 929569 45 8 McMahan Jeff Just Cause for War Ethics and International Affairs 2005 Najera Luna Myth and Prophecy in Juan Gines de Sepulveda s Crusading Exhortacion Archived 11 March 2011 at the Wayback Machine in Bulletin for Spanish and Portuguese Historical Studies 35 1 2011 Discusses Sepulveda s theories of war in relation to the war against the Ottoman Turks Nardin Terry ed The ethics of war and peace Religious and secular perspectives Princeton University Press 1998 online O Donovan Oliver The Just War Revisited Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2003 Ramsey Paul The Just War New York Scribners 1969 Steinhoff Uwe On the Ethics of War and Terrorism Oxford Oxford University Press 2007 Covers the basics and some of the most controversial current debates v Starck Christian Ed Kann es heute noch gerechte Kriege geben Gottingen Wallstein Verlag 2008 ISBN 9783835302617 Walzer Michael Just and Unjust Wars A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations 4th ed New York Basic Books 1977 ISBN 0 465 03707 0 Walzer Michael Arguing about War Yale University Press 2004 ISBN 978 0 300 10978 8External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Just war theory Just war theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Just War Theory Archived 7 September 2013 at the Wayback Machine Oregon State University Text of Cicero s Just War Theory in De Officiis Catholic Teaching Concerning Just War at Catholicism org A Catholic Petition based on the Just War Doctrine Jeff McMahon Rethinking the Just War Part 1 New York Times American Solidarity Party New 3rd Party which applies Just War Theory in foreign policy Just War In Our Time BBC Radio 4 discussion with John Keane and Niall Ferguson 3 June 1999 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Just war theory amp oldid 1146979033, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.