fbpx
Wikipedia

Retributive justice

Retributive justice is a legal punishment that requires the offender to receive a punishment for a crime proportional or similar to its offense.

As opposed to revenge, retribution—and thus retributive justice—is not personal, is directed only at wrongdoing, has inherent limits, involves no pleasure at the suffering of others (i.e., schadenfreude, sadism), and employs procedural standards.[1][2] Retributive justice contrasts with other purposes of punishment such as deterrence (prevention of future crimes), exile (prevention of opportunity) and rehabilitation of the offender.

The concept is found in most world cultures and in many ancient texts. Classical texts advocating the retributive view include Cicero's De Legibus (1st century BC), Kant's Science of Right (1790),[3] and Hegel's Philosophy of Right (1821).[4] The presence of retributive justice in ancient Jewish culture is shown by its mention in the law of Moses,[5][6] which refers to the punishments of "life for life, eye for eye, tooth for tooth, hand for hand, foot for foot" as also attested in the Code of Hammurabi. Documents assert similar values in other cultures, though the judgment of whether a particular punishment is appropriately severe can vary greatly across cultures and individuals in accord with circumstance.

Purposes edit

Some purposes of official retribution include:[7]

  • to channel the retributive sentiments of the public into the political and legal systems. The intent is to deter people from resorting to lynchings, blood feuds, and other forms of vigilante self-help.
  • to promote social solidarity through participation in the act of punishing, under the theory that "the society that slays together stays together."
  • to prevent a situation in which a citizen who would have preferred to obey the law as part of his civic responsibility decides that he would be a fool to not violate it, when so many others are getting away with lawlessness that the point of his obedience is mostly defeated.

History edit

In all ancient legal systems, retribution for wrongdoing took precedence over the enforcement of rights. A sense of natural law demanded that a criminal should be punished with similar loss and pain as they inflicted on their victim. Therefore, the concept of lex talionis (an eye for an eye) was common in ancient law. The Hebrew Bible includes the oldest extent example of lex talionis: middah ke-neged middah (law of 'measure for measure'). The Roman lawyer and philosopher Cicero proposed that "the punishment shalt fit the offence" (Latin: noxiae poena par esto), giving examples of violence being punished by death, fines being imposed on those convicted of greed etc.[8]

In the 19th century, the philosopher Immanuel Kant argued that retribution is the only legitimate form of punishment the court can prescribe:[9]

Judicial punishment can never be used merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society, but instead it must in all cases be imposed on him only on the ground that he has committed a crime.

— Metaphysics of Morals § 49 E.

Kant regarded punishment as a matter of justice, which must be carried out by the state for the sake of the law, not for the sake of the criminal or the victim. He argues that if the guilty are not punished, justice is not done and if justice is not done, then the idea of law itself is undermined.[10]

One of the reasons for the abandonment of retribution by many legal systems in the 20th century was the abandonment of the concept of personal autonomy, which had become discredited.[7] While retributive justice is usually considered as a cornerstone of criminal punishment, it has been shown that it also plays a role in private law.[11]

Principles edit

According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, retributive justice is committed to three principles:[12]

  • "Those who commit certain kinds of wrongful acts, paradigmatically serious crimes, morally deserve to suffer a proportionate punishment."
  • It is "intrinsically morally good—good without reference to any other goods that might arise—if some legitimate punisher gives [those who commit certain kinds of wrongful acts] the punishment they deserve."
  • "It is morally impermissible intentionally to punish the innocent or to inflict disproportionately large punishments on wrongdoers."

Proportionality edit

Proportionality requires that the level of punishment be related to the severity of the offending behaviour. An accurate reading of the biblical phrase "an eye for an eye" in Exodus and Leviticus is said to be: "only one eye for one eye",[13] or "an eye in place of an eye." However, this does not mean that the punishment has to be equivalent to the crime. A retributive system must punish severe crimes more harshly than minor crimes, but retributivists differ about how harsh or soft the system should be overall. The crime's level of severity can be determined in multiple ways. Severity can be determined by the amount of harm, unfair advantage or the moral imbalance that the crime caused.

Traditionally, philosophers of punishment have contrasted retributivism with utilitarianism. For utilitarians, punishment is forward-looking, justified by a purported ability to achieve future social benefits, such as crime reduction. For retributionists, punishment is backward-looking, justified by the crime that has already been committed. Therefore, punishment is carried out to atone for the damage already done.[14]

Subtypes edit

Retributive justice is of two distinct types. The classical definition embraces the idea that the amount of punishment must be proportionate to the amount of harm caused by the offence. A more recent version advocated by philosopher Michael Davis asserts that the amount of punishment must be proportionate to the amount of unfair advantage gained by the wrongdoer. Davis introduced this version of retributive justice in the early 1980s, at a time when retributive justice was resurging within the philosophy of law community, perhaps due to the failings[original research?] of reform theory in prior decades.[citation needed]

A retributive justice system's assessment of blameworthiness (or lack thereof) can either justify punishment or serve merely to limit the punishments society imposes for other reasons.[7]

Criticisms edit

Many jurisdictions that adopt retributive justice, especially in the United States, use mandatory sentencing, where judges impose a penalty for a crime within the range set by the law. However, judges have limited discretion to consider mitigating factors, leading to lesser penalties under certain circumstances.[citation needed]

When the punishment involves a fine, the theory does not allow the financial position of an offender to be considered, leading to situations in which a poor individual and a millionaire could be forced to pay the same amount. Such a fine would be punitive for the poor offender while insignificant for the millionaire.[15] Instead of pure retribution, many jurisdictions use variants such as the European Union's emphasis on punitive equality, which base the amount of a fine not just on the offense but also on the offender's income, salary, and ability to pay. Consequently, in 2002, a senior Finnish executive at Nokia was given a fine of 116,000 (US$103,000) on a traffic ticket issued for driving 75 km/h (47 mph) in a 50 km/h (31 mph) zone,[16] based on his income of €14 million (US $12.5 million) per year. Similarly, a Finnish businessman was required to pay €54,000 based on his yearly income of €6.5 million, making the fine equally punitive as a typical €200 (US$246) fine for the same offense would have been had it been issued to a Finn earning an average salary.[17] The retributive theory's lack of consideration of the perpetrator's and victim's status has led many jurisdictions to move away from it in various ways, including punitive equality and taking into consideration the status and wealth, or lack of status and wealth, of an offender and their consequent ability to both pay fines and defend themselves effectively in court.

One critique of some concepts of just deserts is that they are primitive, emphasizing social harm rather than the character and culpability of offenders, e.g., California's 1976 statute calling for "terms proportionate to the seriousness of the offense with provision for uniformity in the sentences of offenders committing the same offense under similar circumstances." More generally, prioritizing justice for the public over crime control goals has come under criticism as attributable more to the relative ease of writing sentencing guidelines as crime tariffs (as opposed to describing the appropriate influence of situational and personal characteristics on punishment) than to any sound arguments about penological theory.[7]

Alternatives edit

Traditional alternatives to retributive justice have been exile and shunning. In pre-modern societies such sentences were often the equivalent of the death penalty as individuals would find it impossible to survive without the support and protection of the society that they had wronged.[citation needed]

Modern alternatives to retributive measures include psychiatric imprisonment, restorative justice and transformative justice. A general overview of criminal justice puts each of these ideals in context.

One libertarian approach to this issue argues that full restitution (in the broad, rather than technical legal, sense) is compatible with both retributivism and a utilitarian degree of deterrence.[18]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Nozick, Robert (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. pp. 366–368. ISBN 978-0674664791. retributive justice revenge.
  2. ^ "'Positive' Retributivism and the Meaning of Desert". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on July 11, 2010. Retrieved June 2, 2014.
  3. ^ Kant, Immanuel. Science of Right.
  4. ^ Hegel. "Contents of Hegel's Philosophy of Right". www.marxists.org. from the original on October 19, 2017. Retrieved March 6, 2018.
  5. ^ Deuteronomy 19:17–21
  6. ^ Exodus 21:23–27
  7. ^ a b c d Alschuler, Albert (Winter 2003). "The changing purposes of criminal punishment: A retrospective on the past century and some thoughts about the next". The University of Chicago Law Review. 70 (1): 1–22. doi:10.2307/1600541. JSTOR 1600541. from the original on December 1, 2018. Retrieved January 25, 2022.
  8. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius (1928) [c. 50 BC]. De Legibus [On the Laws]. Loeb Classical Library. Vol. 213. Translated by Keyes, Clinton. Harvard University Press. Book III, paragraph XX.
  9. ^ Martin, Jacqueline. 2005. The English Legal System (4th ed.). London: Hodder Arnold. ISBN 0-340-89991-3. p. 174.
  10. ^ Rachels, James. 2007. The Elements of Moral Philosophy
  11. ^ Perry, Ronen. 2006. "The Role of Retributive Justice in the Common Law of Torts: A Descriptive Theory (PDF)." Tennessee Law Review 73:177–236. SSRN 846309. p. 177.
  12. ^ Walen, Alec (January 1, 2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Retributive Justice (Summer 2015 ed.). from the original on January 17, 2018. Retrieved May 3, 2016.
  13. ^ Plaut (1981). The Torah – A Modern Commentary. New York: Union of American Hebrew Congregations. p. 571ff.
  14. ^ Cavadino, M., and J. Dignan. 1997. The Penal System: An Introduction (2nd ed.). London: Sage. p. 39.
  15. ^ Martin, pp. 174–175.
  16. ^ "Nokia boss gets record speeding fine". BBC News. January 14, 2002. from the original on June 18, 2018. Retrieved June 18, 2018.
  17. ^ Pinsker, Joe (March 12, 2015). "Finland, Home of the $103,000 Speeding Ticket". The Atlantic. from the original on March 6, 2018. Retrieved June 18, 2018.
  18. ^ J. C. Lester. "Why Libertarian Restitution Beats State-Retribution and State-Leniency". from the original on September 4, 2006. Retrieved January 13, 2008.

Further reading edit

retributive, justice, legal, punishment, that, requires, offender, receive, punishment, crime, proportional, similar, offense, opposed, revenge, retribution, thus, retributive, justice, personal, directed, only, wrongdoing, inherent, limits, involves, pleasure. Retributive justice is a legal punishment that requires the offender to receive a punishment for a crime proportional or similar to its offense As opposed to revenge retribution and thus retributive justice is not personal is directed only at wrongdoing has inherent limits involves no pleasure at the suffering of others i e schadenfreude sadism and employs procedural standards 1 2 Retributive justice contrasts with other purposes of punishment such as deterrence prevention of future crimes exile prevention of opportunity and rehabilitation of the offender The concept is found in most world cultures and in many ancient texts Classical texts advocating the retributive view include Cicero s De Legibus 1st century BC Kant s Science of Right 1790 3 and Hegel s Philosophy of Right 1821 4 The presence of retributive justice in ancient Jewish culture is shown by its mention in the law of Moses 5 6 which refers to the punishments of life for life eye for eye tooth for tooth hand for hand foot for foot as also attested in the Code of Hammurabi Documents assert similar values in other cultures though the judgment of whether a particular punishment is appropriately severe can vary greatly across cultures and individuals in accord with circumstance Contents 1 Purposes 2 History 3 Principles 3 1 Proportionality 4 Subtypes 5 Criticisms 6 Alternatives 7 See also 8 References 9 Further readingPurposes editSome purposes of official retribution include 7 to channel the retributive sentiments of the public into the political and legal systems The intent is to deter people from resorting to lynchings blood feuds and other forms of vigilante self help to promote social solidarity through participation in the act of punishing under the theory that the society that slays together stays together to prevent a situation in which a citizen who would have preferred to obey the law as part of his civic responsibility decides that he would be a fool to not violate it when so many others are getting away with lawlessness that the point of his obedience is mostly defeated History editIn all ancient legal systems retribution for wrongdoing took precedence over the enforcement of rights A sense of natural law demanded that a criminal should be punished with similar loss and pain as they inflicted on their victim Therefore the concept of lex talionis an eye for an eye was common in ancient law The Hebrew Bible includes the oldest extent example of lex talionis middah ke neged middah law of measure for measure The Roman lawyer and philosopher Cicero proposed that the punishment shalt fit the offence Latin noxiae poena par esto giving examples of violence being punished by death fines being imposed on those convicted of greed etc 8 In the 19th century the philosopher Immanuel Kant argued that retribution is the only legitimate form of punishment the court can prescribe 9 Judicial punishment can never be used merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society but instead it must in all cases be imposed on him only on the ground that he has committed a crime Metaphysics of Morals 49 E Kant regarded punishment as a matter of justice which must be carried out by the state for the sake of the law not for the sake of the criminal or the victim He argues that if the guilty are not punished justice is not done and if justice is not done then the idea of law itself is undermined 10 One of the reasons for the abandonment of retribution by many legal systems in the 20th century was the abandonment of the concept of personal autonomy which had become discredited 7 While retributive justice is usually considered as a cornerstone of criminal punishment it has been shown that it also plays a role in private law 11 Principles editAccording to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy retributive justice is committed to three principles 12 Those who commit certain kinds of wrongful acts paradigmatically serious crimes morally deserve to suffer a proportionate punishment It is intrinsically morally good good without reference to any other goods that might arise if some legitimate punisher gives those who commit certain kinds of wrongful acts the punishment they deserve It is morally impermissible intentionally to punish the innocent or to inflict disproportionately large punishments on wrongdoers Proportionality edit Proportionality requires that the level of punishment be related to the severity of the offending behaviour An accurate reading of the biblical phrase an eye for an eye in Exodus and Leviticus is said to be only one eye for one eye 13 or an eye in place of an eye However this does not mean that the punishment has to be equivalent to the crime A retributive system must punish severe crimes more harshly than minor crimes but retributivists differ about how harsh or soft the system should be overall The crime s level of severity can be determined in multiple ways Severity can be determined by the amount of harm unfair advantage or the moral imbalance that the crime caused Traditionally philosophers of punishment have contrasted retributivism with utilitarianism For utilitarians punishment is forward looking justified by a purported ability to achieve future social benefits such as crime reduction For retributionists punishment is backward looking justified by the crime that has already been committed Therefore punishment is carried out to atone for the damage already done 14 Subtypes editRetributive justice is of two distinct types The classical definition embraces the idea that the amount of punishment must be proportionate to the amount of harm caused by the offence A more recent version advocated by philosopher Michael Davis asserts that the amount of punishment must be proportionate to the amount of unfair advantage gained by the wrongdoer Davis introduced this version of retributive justice in the early 1980s at a time when retributive justice was resurging within the philosophy of law community perhaps due to the failings original research of reform theory in prior decades citation needed A retributive justice system s assessment of blameworthiness or lack thereof can either justify punishment or serve merely to limit the punishments society imposes for other reasons 7 Criticisms editMany jurisdictions that adopt retributive justice especially in the United States use mandatory sentencing where judges impose a penalty for a crime within the range set by the law However judges have limited discretion to consider mitigating factors leading to lesser penalties under certain circumstances citation needed When the punishment involves a fine the theory does not allow the financial position of an offender to be considered leading to situations in which a poor individual and a millionaire could be forced to pay the same amount Such a fine would be punitive for the poor offender while insignificant for the millionaire 15 Instead of pure retribution many jurisdictions use variants such as the European Union s emphasis on punitive equality which base the amount of a fine not just on the offense but also on the offender s income salary and ability to pay Consequently in 2002 a senior Finnish executive at Nokia was given a fine of 116 000 US 103 000 on a traffic ticket issued for driving 75 km h 47 mph in a 50 km h 31 mph zone 16 based on his income of 14 million US 12 5 million per year Similarly a Finnish businessman was required to pay 54 000 based on his yearly income of 6 5 million making the fine equally punitive as a typical 200 US 246 fine for the same offense would have been had it been issued to a Finn earning an average salary 17 The retributive theory s lack of consideration of the perpetrator s and victim s status has led many jurisdictions to move away from it in various ways including punitive equality and taking into consideration the status and wealth or lack of status and wealth of an offender and their consequent ability to both pay fines and defend themselves effectively in court One critique of some concepts of just deserts is that they are primitive emphasizing social harm rather than the character and culpability of offenders e g California s 1976 statute calling for terms proportionate to the seriousness of the offense with provision for uniformity in the sentences of offenders committing the same offense under similar circumstances More generally prioritizing justice for the public over crime control goals has come under criticism as attributable more to the relative ease of writing sentencing guidelines as crime tariffs as opposed to describing the appropriate influence of situational and personal characteristics on punishment than to any sound arguments about penological theory 7 Alternatives editTraditional alternatives to retributive justice have been exile and shunning In pre modern societies such sentences were often the equivalent of the death penalty as individuals would find it impossible to survive without the support and protection of the society that they had wronged citation needed Modern alternatives to retributive measures include psychiatric imprisonment restorative justice and transformative justice A general overview of criminal justice puts each of these ideals in context One libertarian approach to this issue argues that full restitution in the broad rather than technical legal sense is compatible with both retributivism and a utilitarian degree of deterrence 18 See also edit nbsp Law portal nbsp Society portalCapital punishment Eye for an eye Penal harm Proportionality law Restorative justice Two wrongs make a right References edit Nozick Robert 1981 Philosophical Explanations Cambridge MA Harvard University Press pp 366 368 ISBN 978 0674664791 retributive justice revenge Positive Retributivism and the Meaning of Desert Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on July 11 2010 Retrieved June 2 2014 Kant Immanuel Science of Right Hegel Contents of Hegel s Philosophy of Right www marxists org Archived from the original on October 19 2017 Retrieved March 6 2018 Deuteronomy 19 17 21 Exodus 21 23 27 a b c d Alschuler Albert Winter 2003 The changing purposes of criminal punishment A retrospective on the past century and some thoughts about the next The University of Chicago Law Review 70 1 1 22 doi 10 2307 1600541 JSTOR 1600541 Archived from the original on December 1 2018 Retrieved January 25 2022 Cicero Marcus Tullius 1928 c 50 BC De Legibus On the Laws Loeb Classical Library Vol 213 Translated by Keyes Clinton Harvard University Press Book III paragraph XX Martin Jacqueline 2005 The English Legal System 4th ed London Hodder Arnold ISBN 0 340 89991 3 p 174 Rachels James 2007 The Elements of Moral Philosophy Perry Ronen 2006 The Role of Retributive Justice in the Common Law of Torts A Descriptive Theory PDF Tennessee Law Review 73 177 236 SSRN 846309 p 177 Walen Alec January 1 2015 Zalta Edward N ed Retributive Justice Summer 2015 ed Archived from the original on January 17 2018 Retrieved May 3 2016 Plaut 1981 The Torah A Modern Commentary New York Union of American Hebrew Congregations p 571ff Cavadino M and J Dignan 1997 The Penal System An Introduction 2nd ed London Sage p 39 Martin pp 174 175 Nokia boss gets record speeding fine BBC News January 14 2002 Archived from the original on June 18 2018 Retrieved June 18 2018 Pinsker Joe March 12 2015 Finland Home of the 103 000 Speeding Ticket The Atlantic Archived from the original on March 6 2018 Retrieved June 18 2018 J C Lester Why Libertarian Restitution Beats State Retribution and State Leniency Archived from the original on September 4 2006 Retrieved January 13 2008 Further reading editMack Eric 2008 Retribution for Crime In Hamowy Ronald ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA Sage Cato Institute pp 429 431 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 n263 ISBN 978 1412965804 OCLC 750831024 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Retributive justice amp oldid 1199982924, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.