fbpx
Wikipedia

Republic (Plato)

Republic (Greek: Πολιτεία, translit. Politeia; Latin: De Republica[1]) is a Socratic dialogue, authored by Plato around 375 BC, concerning justice (δικαιοσύνη), the order and character of the just city-state, and the just man.[2] It is Plato's best-known work, and one of the world's most influential works of philosophy and political theory, both intellectually and historically.[3][4]

Republic
Title page of the oldest complete manuscript: Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale, Gr. 1807 (late 9th century)
AuthorPlato
Original titleΠολιτεία
CountryAncient Greece
LanguageGreek
SubjectPolitical philosophy
Publishedc. 375 BC
TextRepublic at Wikisource

In the dialogue, Socrates discusses the meaning of justice and whether the just man is happier than the unjust man with various Athenians and foreigners.[5] He considers the natures of existing regimes and then proposes a series of hypothetical cities in comparison, culminating in Kallipolis (Καλλίπολις), a utopian city-state ruled by a class of philosopher-kings. They also discuss ageing, love, theory of forms, the immortality of the soul, and the role of the philosopher and of poetry in society.[6] The dialogue's setting seems to be the time of the Peloponnesian War.[7]

Place in Plato's corpus edit

Republic is generally placed in the middle period of Plato's dialogues. However, the distinction of this group from the early dialogues is not as clear as the distinction of the late dialogues from all the others. Nonetheless, Ritter, Arnim, and Baron—with their separate methodologies—all agreed that the Republic was well distinguished, along with Parmenides, Phaedrus and Theaetetus.[8]

However, the first book of the Republic, which shares many features with earlier dialogues, is thought to have originally been written as a separate work, and then the remaining books were conjoined to it, perhaps with modifications to the original of the first book.[8]

Outline edit

Book I: Aging, Love and the Definitions of Justice edit

While visiting Athen's port, Piraeus, with Glaucon, Socrates is invited to join Polemarchus for a dinner and festival. They eventually end up at Polemarchus' house where Socrates encounters Polemarchus' father Cephalus.

In his first philosophical conversation with the group members, Socrates gets into a conversation with Cephalus. The first real philosophical question posed by Plato in the book is when Socrates asks "is life painful at that age, or what report do you make of it?"[9] when speaking to the aged Cephalus.

Cephalus answers by saying that many are unhappy about old age because they miss their youth, but he finds that "old age brings us profound repose and freedom from this and other passions. When the appetites have abated, and their force is diminished, the description of Sophocles is perfectly realized. It is like being delivered from a multitude of furious masters."[9] The repose gives him time to dedicate himself to sacrifices and justice so that he is prepared for the afterlife.

Socrates then asks his interlocutors for a definition of justice. Three are suggested:

  • Cephalus: To give each what is owed to them (331c)
  • Polemarchus: To give to each what is appropriate to him (332c)
  • Thrasymachus: What is advantageous for the stronger (338c)

Socrates refutes each definition in turn:

  • One may owe it to someone to return them a knife one has borrowed, but if he has since gone mad and would only harm himself with it, returning the knife would not be just.
  • Polemarchus suggests that what is appropriate is to do good to friends and bad to enemies, but harming someone tends to make them unjust, and so on his definition, justice would tend to create injustice.
  • If it is just to do what rulers (the stronger) say and rulers make mistakes about their advantage, then it is just to do what is disadvantageous for the stronger.

Thrasymachus then responds to this refutation by claiming that insofar as the stronger make mistakes, they are not in that regard the stronger. Socrates refutes Thrasymachus with a further argument: Crafts aim at the good of their object, and therefore to rule is for the benefit of the ruled and not the ruler.

At this point, Thrasymachus claims that the unjust person is wiser than the just person, and Socrates gives three arguments refuting Thrasymachus. However, Thrasymachus ceases to engage actively with Socrates's arguments, and Socrates himself seems to think that his arguments are inadequate, since he has not offered any definition of justice. The first book ends in aporia concerning the essence of justice.

Book II: Glaucon and Adeimantus's Challenge edit

Glaucon and Adeimantus are unsatisfied with Socrates's defense of justice. They ask Socrates to defend justice against an alternative view that they attribute to many. According to this view, the origin of justice is in social contracts. Everyone would prefer to get away with harm to others without suffering it themselves, but since they cannot, they agree not to do harm to others so as not to suffer it themselves. Moreover, according to this view, all those who practice justice do so unwillingly and out of fear of punishment, and the life of the unpunished unjust man is far more blessed than that of the just man. Glaucon would like Socrates to prove that justice is not only desirable for its consequences, but also for its own sake. To demonstrate the problem, he tells the story of Gyges, who – with the help of a ring that turns him invisible – achieves great advantages for himself by committing injustices. Many think that anyone would and should use the ring as Gyges did if they had it. Glaucon uses this argument to challenge Socrates to defend the position that the just life is better than the unjust life.

Adeimantus supplements Glaucon's speech with further arguments. He suggests that the unjust should not fear divine judgement, since the very poets who wrote about such judgement also wrote that the gods would grant forgiveness to those who made religious sacrifice.

Book II–IV: The city and the soul edit

Socrates suggests that they use the city as an image to seek how justice comes to be in the soul of an individual. After attributing the origin of society to the individual not being self-sufficient and having many needs which he cannot supply himself, Socrates first describes a "healthy state" made up of producers who make enough for a modest subsistence, but Glaucon considers this hardly different than "a city of pigs." Socrates then goes on to describe the luxurious city, which he calls "a fevered state".[10] Acquiring and defending these luxuries requires a guardian class to wage wars.

They then explore how to obtain guardians who will not become tyrants to the people they guard. Socrates proposes that they solve the problem with an education from their early years. He then prescribes the necessary education, beginning with the kind of stories that are appropriate for training guardians. They conclude that stories that ascribe evil to the gods or heroes or portray the afterlife as bad are untrue and should not be taught. They also decide to regulate narrative and musical style so as to encourage the four cardinal virtues: wisdom, courage, justice and temperance. Socrates avers that beautiful style and morally good style are the same. In proposing their program of censored education, they are repurifying the luxurious or feverish city. Socrates counters the objection that people raised in censorship will be too naive to judge concerning vice by arguing that adults can learn about vice once their character has been formed; before that, they are too impressionable to encounter vice without danger.

They suggest that the second part of the guardians' education should be in gymnastics. With physical training they will be able to live without needing frequent medical attention: physical training will help prevent illness and weakness. Socrates claims that any illness requiring constant medical attention is too unhealthy to be worth living. By analogy, any society that requires constant litigation is too unhealthy to be worth maintaining.

Socrates asserts that both male and female guardians be given the same education, that all wives and children be shared, and that they be prohibited from owning private property so that guardians will not become possessive and keep their focus on the good of the whole city. He adds a third class distinction between auxiliaries (rank and file soldiers) and guardians (the leaders who rule the city).

In the fictional tale known as the myth or parable of the metals, Socrates presents the Noble Lie (γενναῖον ψεῦδος, gennaion pseudos), to convince everyone in the city to perform their social role. All are born from the womb of their mother country, so that all are siblings, but their natures are different, each containing either gold (guardians), silver (auxiliaries), or bronze or iron (producers). If anyone with a bronze or iron nature rules the city, it will be destroyed. Socrates claims that if the people believed "this myth...[it] would have a good effect, making them more inclined to care for the state and one another."[11] Socrates claims the city will be happiest if each citizen engages in the occupation that suits them best. If the city as a whole is happy, then individuals are happy.

In the physical education and diet of the guardians, the emphasis is on moderation, since both poverty and excessive wealth will corrupt them (422a1). He argues that a city without wealth can defend itself successfully against wealthy aggressors. Socrates says that it is pointless to worry over specific laws, like those pertaining to contracts, since proper education ensures lawful behavior, and poor education causes lawlessness (425a–425c).[12]

Socrates proceeds to search for wisdom, courage, and temperance in the city, on the grounds that justice will be easier to discern in what remains (427e). They find wisdom among the guardian rulers, courage among the guardian warriors (or auxiliaries), temperance among all classes of the city in agreeing about who should rule and who should be ruled. Finally, Socrates defines justice in the city as the state in which each class performs only its own work, not meddling in the work of the other classes (433b).

The virtues discovered in the city are then sought in the individual soul. For this purpose, Socrates creates an analogy between the parts of the city and the soul (the city–soul analogy).[13] He argues that psychological conflict points to a divided soul, since a completely unified soul could not behave in opposite ways towards the same object, at the same time, and in the same respect (436b).[14] He gives examples of possible conflicts between the rational, spirited, and appetitive parts of the soul, corresponding to the rulers, auxiliaries, and producing classes in the city.[15] Having established the tripartite soul, Socrates defines the virtues of the individual. A person is wise if he is ruled by the part of the soul that knows "what is beneficial for each part and for the whole," courageous if his spirited part "preserves in the midst of pleasures and pains" the decisions reached by the rational part, and temperate if the three parts agree that the rational part lead (442c–d).[16] They are just if each part of the soul attends to its function and not the function of another. It follows from this definition that one cannot be just if one does not have the other cardinal virtues.[14] In this regard, Plato can be seen as a progenitor of the concept of 'social structures'.

Book V–VI: The Ship of State edit

Socrates, having to his satisfaction defined the just constitution of both city and psyche, moves to elaborate upon the four unjust constitutions of these. Adeimantus and Polemarchus interrupt, asking Socrates instead first to explain how the sharing of wives and children in the guardian class is to be defined and legislated, a theme first touched on in Book III. Socrates is overwhelmed at their request, categorizing it as three "waves" of attack against which his reasoning must stand firm. These three waves challenge Socrates' claims that

  • both male and female guardians ought to receive the same education
  • human reproduction ought to be regulated by the state and all offspring should be ignorant of their actual biological parents
  • such a city and its corresponding philosopher-king could actually come to be in the real world.

In Books V–VII the abolition of riches among the guardian class (not unlike Max Weber's bureaucracy) leads controversially to the abandonment of the typical family, and as such no child may know his or her parents and the parents may not know their own children. Socrates tells a tale which is the "allegory of the good government". The rulers assemble couples for reproduction, based on breeding criteria. Thus, stable population is achieved through eugenics and social cohesion is projected to be high because familial links are extended towards everyone in the city. Also the education of the youth is such that they are taught of only works of writing that encourage them to improve themselves for the state's good, and envision (the) god(s) as entirely good, just, and the author(s) of only that which is good.

Socrates' argument is that in the ideal city, a true philosopher with understanding of forms will facilitate the harmonious co-operation of all the citizens of the city—the governance of a city-state is likened to the command of a ship, the Ship of State. This philosopher-king must be intelligent, reliable, and willing to lead a simple life. However, these qualities are rarely manifested on their own, and so they must be encouraged through education and the study of the Good.

Book VI–VII: Allegories of the Sun, Divided Line, and Cave edit

The Allegory of the Cave primarily depicts Plato's distinction between the world of appearances and the 'real' world of the Forms.,[17] Just as visible objects must be illuminated in order to be seen, so must also be true of objects of knowledge if light is cast on them.

Plato imagines a group of people who have lived their entire lives as prisoners, chained to the wall of a cave in the subterranean so they are unable to see the outside world behind them. However a constant flame illuminates various moving objects outside, which are silhouetted on the wall of the cave visible to the prisoners. These prisoners, through having no other experience of reality, ascribe forms to these shadows such as either "dog" or "cat". Plato then goes on to explain how the philosopher is akin to a prisoner who is freed from the cave. The prisoner is initially blinded by the light, but when he adjusts to the brightness he sees the fire and the statues and how they caused the images witnessed inside the cave. He sees that the fire and statues in the cave were just copies of the real objects; merely imitations. This is analogous to the Forms. What we see from day to day are merely appearances, reflections of the Forms. The philosopher, however, will not be deceived by the shadows and will hence be able to see the 'real' world, the world above that of appearances; the philosopher will gain knowledge of things in themselves. At the end of this allegory, Plato asserts that it is the philosopher's burden to reenter the cave. Those who have seen the ideal world, he says, have the duty to educate those in the material world. Since the philosopher recognizes what is truly good only he is fit to rule society according to Plato.

Book VIII–IX: Plato's five regimes edit

In Books VIII–IX stand Plato's criticism of the forms of government. Plato categorized governments into five types of regimes: aristocracy, timocracy, oligarchy, democracy, and tyranny.

The starting point is an imagined, alternate aristocracy (ruled by a philosopher-king); a just government ruled by a philosopher king, dominated by the wisdom-loving element. Aristocracy degenerates into timocracy when, due to miscalculation on the part of its governing class, the next generation includes persons of an inferior nature, inclined not just to cultivating virtues but also producing wealth. In a timocracy, governors will apply great effort in gymnastics and the arts of war, as well as the virtue that pertains to them, that of courage. As the emphasis on honor is compromised by wealth accumulation, it is replaced by oligarchy. The oligarchic government is dominated by the desiring element, in which the rich are the ruling class. Oligarchs do, however, value at least one virtue, that of temperance and moderation—not out of an ethical principle or spiritual concern, but because by dominating wasteful tendencies they succeed in accumulating money.

As this socioeconomic divide grows, so do tensions between social classes. From the conflicts arising out of such tensions, the poor majority overthrow the wealthy minority, and democracy replaces the oligarchy preceding it. In democracy, the lower class grows bigger and bigger. A visually appealing demagogue is soon lifted up to protect the interests of the lower class, who can exploit them to take power in order to maintain order. Democracy then degenerates into tyranny where no one has discipline and society exists in chaos. In a tyrannical government, the city is enslaved to the tyrant, who uses his guards to remove the best social elements and individuals from the city to retain power (since they pose a threat), while leaving the worst. He will also provoke warfare to consolidate his position as leader. In this way, tyranny is the most unjust regime of all.

In parallel to this, Socrates considers the individual or soul that corresponds to each of these regimes. He describes how an aristocrat may become weak or detached from political and material affluence, and how his son will respond to this by becoming overly ambitious.The timocrat in turn may be defeated by the courts or vested interests; his son responds by accumulating wealth in order to gain power in society and defend himself against the same predicament, thereby becoming an oligarch. The oligarch's son will grow up with wealth without having to practice thrift or stinginess, and will be tempted and overwhelmed by his desires,[18] so that he becomes democratic, valuing freedom above all.[18] The democratic man is torn between tyrannical passions and oligarchic discipline, and ends up in the middle ground: valuing all desires, both good and bad. The tyrant will be tempted in the same way as the democrat, but without an upbringing in discipline or moderation to restrain him. Therefore, his most base desires and wildest passions overwhelm him, and he becomes driven by lust, using force and fraud to take whatever he wants. The tyrant is both a slave to his lusts, and a master to whomever he can enslave. Socrates points out the human tendency to be corrupted by power leads down the road to timocracy, oligarchy, democracy and tyranny. From this, he concludes that ruling should be left to philosophers, who are the most just and therefore least susceptible to corruption. This "good city" is depicted as being governed by philosopher-kings; disinterested persons who rule not for their personal enjoyment but for the good of the city-state (polis). The philosophers have seen the "Forms" and therefore know what is good. They understand the corrupting effect of greed and own no property and receive no salary. They also live in sober communism, eating and sleeping together.

Book X: Myth of Er edit

Concluding a theme brought up most explicitly in the Analogies of the Sun and Divided Line in Book VI, Socrates finally rejects any form of imitative art and concludes that such artists have no place in the just city. He continues on to argue for the immortality of the psyche and espouses a theory of reincarnation. He finishes by detailing the rewards of being just, both in this life and the next. Artists create things but they are only different copies of the idea of the original. "And whenever any one informs us that he has found a man who knows all the arts, and all things else that anybody knows, and every single thing with a higher degree of accuracy than any other man—whoever tells us this, I think that we can only imagine to be a simple creature who is likely to have been deceived by some wizard or actor whom he met, and whom he thought all-knowing, because he himself was unable to analyze the nature of knowledge and ignorance and imitation."[19]

And the same object appears straight when looked at out of the water, and crooked when in the water; and the concave becomes convex, owing to the illusion about colours to which the sight is liable. Thus every sort of confusion is revealed within us; and this is that weakness of the human mind on which the art of conjuring and deceiving by light and shadow and other ingenious devices imposes, having an effect upon us like magic.[19]

He speaks about illusions and confusion. Things can look very similar, but be different in reality. Because we are human, at times we cannot tell the difference between the two.

And does not the same hold also of the ridiculous? There are jests which you would be ashamed to make yourself, and yet on the comic stage, or indeed in private, when you hear them, you are greatly amused by them, and are not at all disgusted at their unseemliness—the case of pity is repeated—there is a principle in human nature which is disposed to raise a laugh, and this which you once restrained by reason, because you were afraid of being thought a buffoon, is now let out again; and having stimulated the risible faculty at the theatre, you are betrayed unconsciously to yourself into playing the comic poet at home.

With all of us, we may approve of something, as long we are not directly involved with it. If we joke about it, we are supporting it.

Quite true, he said. And the same may be said of lust and anger and all the other affections, of desire and pain and pleasure, which are held to be inseparable from every action—in all of them poetry feeds and waters the passions instead of drying them up; she lets them rule, although they ought to be controlled, if mankind are ever to increase in happiness and virtue.[19]

Sometimes we let our passions rule our actions or way of thinking, although they should be controlled, so that we can increase our happiness.

Legacy edit

Ancient Greece and Rome edit

Aristotle systematises many of Plato's analyses in his Politics, and criticizes the propositions of several political philosophers for the ideal city-state.

Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism, wrote his version of an ideal society, Zeno's Republic, in opposition to Plato's Republic.[20] Zeno's Republic was controversial and was viewed with some embarrassment by some of the later Stoics due to its defenses of free love, incest, and cannibalism and due to its opposition to ordinary education and the building of temples, law-courts, and gymnasia.

The English title of Plato's dialogue is derived from Cicero's De re publica, written some three centuries later.[21][citation needed] Cicero's dialogue imitates Plato's style and treats many of the same topics, and Cicero's main character Scipio Aemilianus expresses his esteem for Plato and Socrates.

Augustine of Hippo wrote his The City of God; Augustine equally described a model of the "ideal city", in his case the eternal Jerusalem, using a visionary language not unlike that of the preceding philosophers.

Middle Ages edit

Ibn Rushd edit

Islamic philosophers were much more interested in Aristotle than Plato, but not having access to Aristotle's Politics, Ibn Rushd (Averroes) produced instead a commentary on Plato's Republic. He advances an authoritarian ideal, following Plato's paternalistic model. Absolute monarchy, led by a philosopher-king, creates a justly ordered society. This requires extensive use of coercion,[22] although persuasion is preferred and is possible if the young are properly raised.[23] Rhetoric, not logic, is the appropriate road to truth for the common man. Demonstrative knowledge via philosophy and logic requires special study. Rhetoric aids religion in reaching the masses.[24]

Following Plato, Ibn Rushd accepts the principle of women's equality. They should be educated and allowed to serve in the military; the best among them might be tomorrow's philosophers or rulers.[25][26] He also accepts Plato's illiberal measures such as the censorship of literature. He uses examples from Arab history to illustrate just and degenerate political orders.[27]

Gratian edit

The medieval jurist Gratian in his Decretum (ca 1140) quotes Plato as agreeing with him that "by natural law all things are common to all people."[28] He identifies Plato's ideal society with the early Church as described in the Acts of the Apostles. "Plato lays out the order", Gratian comments, "for a very just republic in which no one considers anything his own."[29]

Thomas More edit

Thomas More, when writing his Utopia, invented the technique of using the portrayal of a "utopia" as the carrier of his thoughts about the ideal society. More's island Utopia is also similar to Plato's Republic in some aspects, among them common property and the lack of privacy.[30][31][32][33]

Hegel edit

Hegel respected Plato's theories of state and ethics much more than those of the early modern philosophers such as Locke, Hobbes and Rousseau, whose theories proceeded from a fictional "state of nature" defined by humanity's "natural" needs, desires and freedom. For Hegel this was a contradiction: since nature and the individual are contradictory, the freedoms which define individuality as such are latecomers on the stage of history. Therefore, these philosophers unwittingly projected man as an individual in modern society onto a primordial state of nature. Plato however had managed to grasp the ideas specific to his time:

Plato is not the man to dabble in abstract theories and principles; his truth-loving mind has recognized and represented the truth of the world in which he lived, the truth of the one spirit that lived in him as in Greece itself. No man can overleap his time, the spirit of his time is his spirit also; but the point at issue is, to recognize that spirit by its content.[34]

For Hegel, Plato's Republic is not an abstract theory or ideal which is too good for the real nature of man, but rather is not ideal enough, not good enough for the ideals already inherent or nascent in the reality of his time; a time when Greece was entering decline. One such nascent idea was about to crush the Greek way of life: modern freedoms—or Christian freedoms in Hegel's view—such as the individual's choice of his social class, or of what property to pursue, or which career to follow. Such individual freedoms were excluded from Plato's Republic:

Plato recognized and caught up the true spirit of his times, and brought it forward in a more definite way, in that he desired to make this new principle an impossibility in his Republic.[35]

Greece being at a crossroads, Plato's new "constitution" in the Republic was an attempt to preserve Greece: it was a reactionary reply to the new freedoms of private property etc., that were eventually given legal form through Rome. Accordingly, in ethical life, it was an attempt to introduce a religion that elevated each individual not as an owner of property, but as the possessor of an immortal soul.

20th century edit

 
P. Oxy. 3679, manuscript from the 3rd century AD, containing fragments of Plato's Republic.

Mussolini admired Plato's The Republic, which he often read for inspiration.[36] The Republic expounded a number of ideas that fascism promoted, such as rule by an elite promoting the state as the ultimate end, opposition to democracy, protecting the class system and promoting class collaboration, rejection of egalitarianism, promoting the militarization of a nation by creating a class of warriors, demanding that citizens perform civic duties in the interest of the state, and utilizing state intervention in education to promote the development of warriors and future rulers of the state.[37] Plato was an idealist, focused on achieving justice and morality, while Mussolini and fascism were realist, focused on achieving political goals.[38]

Martin Luther King Jr. nominated The Republic as the one book he would have taken to a deserted island, alongside the Bible.[39]

21st century edit

In 2001, a survey of over 1,000 academics and students voted the Republic the greatest philosophical text ever written. Julian Baggini argued that although the work "was wrong on almost every point, the questions it raises and the methods it uses are essential to the western tradition of philosophy. Without it we might not have philosophy as we know it."[40] In 2021, a survey showed that The Republic is the most studied book in the top universities in the United States.[41][42]

Cultural influence edit

Plato's Republic has been influential in literature and art.

  • Aldous Huxley's Brave New World has a dystopian government that bears a resemblance to the form of government described in the Republic, featuring the separation of people by professional class, assignment of profession and purpose by the state, and the absence of traditional family units, replaced by state-organized breeding.[43]
  • The Orwellian dystopia depicted in the novel 1984 had many characteristics in common with Plato's description of the allegory of the Cave as Winston Smith strives to liberate himself from it.[44]
  • In the early 1970s the Dutch composer Louis Andriessen composed a vocal work called De Staat, based on the text of Plato's Republic.[45]
  • In Robert A. Heinlein's Starship Troopers, his citizen can be compared to a Platonic Guardian, without the communal breeding and property, but still having a militaristic base. Although there are significant differences in the specifics of the system, Heinlein and Plato both describe systems of limited franchise, with a political class that has supposedly earned their power and wisely governs the whole. Republic is specifically attacked in Starship Troopers. The arachnids can be seen as much closer to a Republic society than the humans.[46]
  • The film The Matrix models Plato's Allegory of the Cave.[47]
  • In fiction, Jo Walton's 2015 novel The Just City explored the consequences of establishing a city-state based on the Republic in practice.
  • See also Ring of Gyges: Cultural influences

Criticism edit

Gadamer edit

In his 1934 Plato und die Dichter (Plato and the Poets), as well as several other works, Hans-Georg Gadamer describes the utopic city of the Republic as a heuristic utopia that should not be pursued or even be used as an orientation-point for political development. Rather, its purpose is said to be to show how things would have to be connected, and how one thing would lead to another—often with highly problematic results—if one would opt for certain principles and carry them through rigorously. This interpretation argues that large passages in Plato's writing are ironic, a line of thought initially pursued by Kierkegaard.

Popper edit

The city portrayed in Republic struck some critics as harsh, rigid, and unfree; indeed, as totalitarian. Karl Popper gave a voice to that view in his 1945 book The Open Society and Its Enemies, where he singled out Plato's state as a dystopia. Popper distinguished Plato's ideas from those of Socrates, claiming that the former in his later years expressed none of the humanitarian and democratic tendencies of his teacher.[48][49][50] Popper thought Plato's envisioned state totalitarian as it advocated a government composed only of a distinct hereditary ruling class, with the working class—who Popper argues Plato regards as "human cattle"—given no role in decision making. He argues that Plato has no interest in what are commonly regarded as the problems of justice—the resolution of disputes between individuals—because Plato has redefined justice as "keeping one's place".[51]

Popper insists that Republic "was meant by its author not so much as a theoretical treatise, but as a topical political manifesto",[52] and Bertrand Russell argues that at least in intent, and all in all not so far from what was possible in ancient Greek city-states, the form of government portrayed in the Republic was meant as a practical one by Plato.[53]

Voegelin edit

Many critics have suggested that the dialogue's political discussion actually serves as an analogy for the individual soul, in which there are also many different "members" that can either conflict or else be integrated and orchestrated under a just and productive "government." Among other things, this analogical reading would solve the problem of certain implausible statements Plato makes concerning an ideal political republic.[54] Norbert Blössner (2007)[55] argues that the Republic is best understood as an analysis of the workings and moral improvement of the individual soul with remarkable thoroughness and clarity. This view, of course, does not preclude a legitimate reading of Republic as a political treatise (the work could operate at both levels). It merely implies that it deserves more attention as a work on psychology and moral philosophy than it has sometimes received.

Eric Voegelin in Plato and Aristotle (Baton Rouge, 1957), gave meaning to the concept of 'Just City in Speech' (Books II–V). For instance, there is evidence in the dialogue that Socrates himself would not be a member of his 'ideal' state. His life was almost solely dedicated to the private pursuit of knowledge. More practically, Socrates suggests that members of the lower classes could rise to the higher ruling class, and vice versa, if they had 'gold' in their veins—a version of the concept of social mobility. The exercise of power is built on the 'noble lie' that all men are brothers, born of the earth, yet there is a clear hierarchy and class divisions. There is a tripartite explanation of human psychology that is extrapolated to the city, the relation among peoples. There is no family among the guardians, another crude version of Max Weber's concept of bureaucracy as the state non-private concern. Together with Leo Strauss, Voegelin considered Popper's interpretation to be a gross misunderstanding not only of the dialogue itself, but of the very nature and character of Plato's entire philosophic enterprise.

The paradigm of the city—the idea of the Good, the Agathon—has manifold historical embodiments, undertaken by those who have seen the Agathon, and are ordered via the vision. The centerpiece of the Republic, Part II, nos. 2–3, discusses the rule of the philosopher, and the vision of the Agathon with the Allegory of the Cave, which is clarified in the theory of forms. The centerpiece is preceded and followed by the discussion of the means that will secure a well-ordered polis (city). Part II, no. 1, concerns marriage, the community of people and goods for the guardians, and the restraints on warfare among the Hellenes. It describes a partially communistic polis. Part II, no. 4, deals with the philosophical education of the rulers who will preserve the order and character of the city-state.

In part II, the Embodiment of the Idea, is preceded by the establishment of the economic and social orders of a polis (part I), followed by an analysis (part III) of the decline the order must traverse. The three parts compose the main body of the dialogues, with their discussions of the "paradigm", its embodiment, its genesis, and its decline.

The introduction and the conclusion are the frame for the body of Republic. The discussion of right order is occasioned by the questions: "Is justice better than injustice?" and "Will an unjust man fare better than a just man?" The introductory question is balanced by the concluding answer: "Justice is preferable to injustice". In turn, the foregoing are framed with the Prologue (Book I) and the Epilogue (Book X). The prologue is a short dialogue about the common public doxai (opinions) about justice. Based upon faith, and not reason, the Epilogue describes the new arts and the immortality of the soul.

Strauss and Bloom edit

Some of Plato's proposals have led theorists like Leo Strauss and Allan Bloom to ask readers to consider the possibility that Socrates was creating not a blueprint for a real city, but a learning exercise for the young men in the dialogue. There are many points in the construction of the "Just City in Speech" that seem contradictory, which raise the possibility Socrates is employing irony to make the men in the dialogue question for themselves the ultimate value of the proposals. In turn, Plato has immortalized this 'learning exercise' in Republic.

One of many examples is that Socrates calls the marriages of the ruling class 'sacred'; however, they last only one night and are the result of manipulating and drugging couples into predetermined intercourse with the aim of eugenically breeding guardian-warriors. Strauss and Bloom's interpretations, however, involve more than just pointing out inconsistencies; by calling attention to these issues they ask readers to think more deeply about whether Plato is being ironic or genuine, for neither Strauss nor Bloom present an unequivocal opinion, preferring to raise philosophic doubt over interpretive fact.

Strauss's approach developed out of a belief that Plato wrote esoterically. The basic acceptance of the exoteric-esoteric distinction revolves around whether Plato really wanted to see the "Just City in Speech" of Books V–VI come to pass, or whether it is just an allegory. Strauss never regarded this as the crucial issue of the dialogue. He argued against Karl Popper's literal view, citing Cicero's opinion that Republic's true nature was to bring to light the nature of political things.[56] In fact, Strauss undermines the justice found in the "Just City in Speech" by implying the city is not natural, it is a man-made conceit that abstracts away from the erotic needs of the body. The city founded in Republic "is rendered possible by the abstraction from eros".[57]

An argument that has been used against ascribing ironic intent to Plato is that Plato's Academy produced a number of tyrants who seized political power and abandoned philosophy for ruling a city. Despite being well-versed in Greek and having direct contact with Plato himself, some of Plato's former students like Clearchus, tyrant of Heraclea; Chaeron, tyrant of Pellene; Erastus and Coriscus, tyrants of Skepsis; Hermias of Atarneus and Assos; and Calippus, tyrant of Syracuse ruled people and did not impose anything like a philosopher-kingship. However, it can be argued whether these men became "tyrants" through studying in the academy. Plato's school had an elite student body, some of whom would by birth, and family expectation, end up in the seats of power. Additionally, it is important that it is by no means obvious that these men were tyrants in the modern, totalitarian sense of the concept. Finally, since very little is actually known about what was taught at Plato's Academy, there is no small controversy over whether it was even in the business of teaching politics at all.[58]

Fragments edit

Several Oxyrhynchus Papyri fragments were found to contain parts of Republic, and from other works such as Phaedo, or the dialogue Gorgias, written around 200–300 CE.[59] Fragments of a different version of Plato's Republic were discovered in 1945, part of the Nag Hammadi library, written c. 350 CE.[60] These findings highlight the influence of Plato during those times in Egypt.

Translations edit

  • Burges, George (1854). Plato: The Republic, Timaeus and Critias. New and literal version. London: H.G. Bohn.
  • Jowett, Benjamin (1871). Plato: The Republic.
  • Bloom, Allan (1991) [1968]. The Republic of Plato. Translated, with notes and an interpretive essay. New York: Basic Books.
  • Grube, G.M.A. (1992). Plato: The Republic. Revised by C.D.C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Waterfield, Robin (1994). Plato: Republic. Translated, with notes and an introduction. Oxford: Oxford World's Classics.
  • Griffith, Tom (2000). Plato: The Republic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Allen, R.E. (2006). Plato: The Republic. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Sachs, Joe (2007). Plato: Republic. Newburyport: Focus Publishing.
  • Rowe, Christopher (2012). Plato: Republic. London: Penguin.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Henri Estienne (ed.), Platonis opera quae extant omnia, Vol. 2, 1578, p. 327.
  2. ^ Brickhouse, Thomas and Smith, Nicholas D. Plato (c. 427–347 BC), The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, University of Tennessee, cf. Dating Plato's Dialogues.
  3. ^ National Public Radio (8 August 2007). Plato's 'Republic' Still Influential, Author Says 20 September 2018 at the Wayback Machine. Talk of the Nation.
  4. ^ Plato: The Republic 20 September 2018 at the Wayback Machine. Plato: His Philosophy and his life, allphilosophers.com
  5. ^ In ancient times, the book was alternately titled On Justice (not to be confused with the spurious dialogue of the same name). Lorenz, Hendrik (22 April 2009). "Ancient Theories of Soul". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 December 2013.
  6. ^ Baird, Forrest E.; Walter Kaufmann (2008). From Plato to Derrida. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-158591-1.
  7. ^ Although "there would be jarring anachronisms if any of the candidate specific dates between 432 and 404 were assigned". Nails, Debra (2002), The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 0-87220-564-9, p. 324
  8. ^ a b Brandwood, Leonard, The Chronology of Plato's Dialogues (Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 251.
  9. ^ a b John Llewelyn, Davies (1921). The Republic of Plato. Macmillan and Company. p. 3.
  10. ^ Plato; Harold North Fowler; Paul Shorey (1977). Plato in Twelve Volumes. Vol. 5–6. W. Heinemann. ISBN 978-0-674-99040-1.
  11. ^ Book 3, 415c–d
  12. ^ Julia Annas, "Law in the Republic" from Virtue and Law in Plato and Beyond (Oxford Scholarship Online, 2017). DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198755746.003.0002
  13. ^ Calian, Florin George (2012). "Plato's Psychology of Action and the Origin of Agency". philpapers.org. Retrieved 15 January 2024.
  14. ^ a b Brown, Eric (2017), "Plato's Ethics and Politics in The Republic", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, from the original on 10 April 2020, retrieved 2 October 2018
  15. ^ Calian, Florin George (2012). "Plato's Psychology of Action and the Origin of Agency". philpapers.org. Retrieved 15 January 2024.
  16. ^ Plato. Plato in Twelve Volumes, Vols. 5 & 6 translated by Paul Shorey. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd. 1969.
  17. ^ Silverman, Allan (2014), "Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2 October 2018
  18. ^ a b McAleer, Sean (2020). Plato's 'Republic': An Introduction. OpenBook Publishers. pp. 229–251. doi:10.11647/obp.0229. ISBN 978-1-80064-053-5. S2CID 228927159.
  19. ^ a b c The Republic, Book X
  20. ^ Plutarch, On Stoic self-contradictions, 1034F
  21. ^ Res publica is not an exact translation of Plato's Greek title politeia. Rather, politeia is a general term for the actual and potential forms of government for a polis or city-state, and Plato attempts to survey all possible forms of the state, while Cicero's discussion focuses more on the improvement of the Roman Republic.
  22. ^ Black, Antony (2011). The History of Islamic Political Thought (2nd ed.). Edinburgh University Press. p. 122. ISBN 978-0-7486-3987-8.
  23. ^ Fakhry, Majid (2001), Averroes (Ibn Rushd) His Life, Works and Influence, Oneworld Publications, p. 106, ISBN 978-1-85168-269-0
  24. ^ Robert Pasnau (November–December 2011). "The Islamic Scholar Who Gave Us Modern Philosophy". Humanities. 32 (6).
  25. ^ Rosenthal, Erwin I.J. (26 December 2017). "Averroës". Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica, inc. p. xix.
  26. ^ (Fakhry 2001, p. 110)
  27. ^ (Fakhry 2001, p. 114)
  28. ^ GRAT. Decr. D. 8 dicta Gratiani § 1 ante c. 1: Nam jure naturali omnia sunt communia omnibus.
  29. ^ GRAT. Decr. D. 8 dicta Gratiani § 1 ante c. 1: Unde apud Platonem illa civitas justissime ordinata traditur, in qua quisque proprios nescit affectus.
  30. ^ Interpreting Thomas More's Utopia By John Charles Olin Fordham Univ Press, 1989. ISBN 0-8232-1233-5
  31. ^ "The Function of the Ideal in Plato's 'Republic' and St. Thomas More's 'Utopia' " by K. Corrigan Moreana 1990, vol. 27, no.104, pp. 27–49
  32. ^ "Thomas More: On the Margins of Modernity " by J. H. Hexter The Journal of British Studies, Vol. 1 (Nov., 1961), pp. 20–37 JSTOR "We find it in Plato's Republic, and in Utopia More acknowledges his debt to that book."
  33. ^ "More on Utopia" by Brendan Bradshaw The Historical Journal, Vol. 24, No. 1 (Mar., 1981), pp. 1–27 JSTOR "claims that Utopia not merely emulated Plato's Republic but excelled it."
  34. ^ Hegel, "Lectures on the Philosophy of History", vol II, p. 96
  35. ^ Hegel, "Lectures on the Philosophy of History", vol II, p. 99
  36. ^ Moseley, Ray (2004). Mussolini: The Last 600 Days of Il Duce. Taylor Trade. p. 39. ISBN 978-1-58979-095-7. from the original on 25 September 2020. Retrieved 3 June 2020.
  37. ^ Sharma, Urmila. Western Political Thought. Atlantic Publishers and Distributors (P) Ltd, 1998. p. 66.
  38. ^ Sharma, Urmila. Western Political Thought. Atlantic Publishers and Distributors (P) Ltd, 1998. pp. 66–67.
  39. ^ Sharpe, Matthew (16 December 2019). "Guide to the classics: Plato's Republic". The Conversation.
  40. ^ Gibbons, Fiachra (7 September 2001). "The thinking person's favourite thinkers". TheGuardian.com. Retrieved 14 March 2016.
  41. ^ Ha, Thu-Huong (27 January 2016). "These are the books students at the top US colleges are required to read". Quartz. from the original on 28 May 2021.
  42. ^ Jackson, Abby (5 February 2016). "The most popular required reading at America's top 10 colleges". Business Insider. from the original on 7 May 2021.
  43. ^ Franck, Matthew. "Aldous Huxley’s City in Speech: Brave New World and the Republic of Plato" Paper presented at the annual meeting of The Midwest Political Science Association, Palmer House Hilton, Chicago, Illinois, Apr 15, 2004 abstract
  44. ^ Deatherage, Scott (5–8 November 1987). From Plato to Orwell: Utopian Rhetoric in a Dystopian World. Annual Meeting of the Speech Communication Association (73rd). Boston, MA.
  45. ^ Adlington, Robert. Louis Andriessen: De Staat. Ashgate, 2004. ISBN 0-7546-0925-1 [1] – In 1992 a CD-recording by the Schoenberg Ensemble, conducted by Reinbert de Leeuw appeared [2] – In 1977 Andriessen had been awarded several prizes for this composition [3]
  46. ^ Donald McQuarie "Utopia and Transcendence: An Analysis of Their Decline in Contemporary Science Fiction" The Journal of Popular Culture xiv (2), 242–250. (1980) Digital object identifier
  47. ^ The Matrix and Philosophy: Welcome to the Desert of the Real By William Irwin. Open Court Publishing, 2002/ ISBN 0-8126-9501-1 "written for those fans of the film who are already philosophers."
  48. ^ Popper accuses Plato of betraying Socrates. He was not the first to do so. Thomas Jefferson made the same statement in a letter to his friend John Adams in 1814, "Socrates had reason indeed to complain of the misrepresentations of Plato; for in truth his dialogues are libels on Socrates." (Jefferson, Thomas. "To John Adams Monticello, July 5, 1814". University of Groningen.)
  49. ^ Gilbert Ryle, reviewing Popper's text just two years after its publication (Ryle, G. (1 April 1947). "Popper, K.R. – The Open Society and its Enemies". Mind. 56 (222): 167–172. doi:10.1093/mind/LVI.222.167. JSTOR 2250518.) and agreeing with him, wrote that Plato "was Socrates' Judas." (Ryle, G. (1947). p. 169)
  50. ^ Burke, T.E. (1983). The Philosophy of Popper. Manchester: Manchester University Press. p. 141. ISBN 978-0-71900911-2.
  51. ^ Popper, Karl (1950) The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1: The Spell of Plato, New York: Routledge.
  52. ^ Popper, Karl (1950) The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1: The Spell of Plato, New York: Routledge. p. 162.
  53. ^ Russell, B. (2004) History of Western Philosophy, end of Book I, part 2, ch. 14.
  54. ^ For an oft-cited argument that the analogy does not work, see T. Penner, "Thought and Desire in Plato." in G Vlastos ed., Plato, Vol. 2. Anchor Books, 1971
  55. ^ Blössner, Norbert. The City-Soul Analogy, G. R. F. Ferrari (Translator). In: G. R. F. Ferrari (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic, Cambridge University Press, 2007. (Ch. 13; pp. 345–385).
  56. ^ History of Political Philosophy, co-editor with Joseph Cropsey, 3rd. ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987, p.68
  57. ^ History of Political Philosophy, co-editor with Joseph Cropsey, 3rd. ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987, p. 60
  58. ^ Malcolm Schofield, "Plato and Practical Politics", in C. Rowe and M. Schofield (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Political Thought, Cambridge University Press 2005, pp. 293–302.
  59. ^ Grenfall, Bernard Pyne; Hunt, Arthur Surridge (1898). "The Oxyrhynchus papyri". p. 187. from the original on 3 May 2016. Retrieved 21 October 2017.
  60. ^ Mountain Man Graphics. "Plato's Republic at Nag Hammadi c.350 CE".

Further reading edit

  • Annas, Julia (1981). An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Benardete, Seth (1989). Socrates' Second Sailing: On Plato's Republic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Blackburn, Simon (2007). Plato's Republic: A Biography. New York: Atlantic Monthly Press.
  • Bosanquet, B. (1895). A Companion to Plato's Republic. London: Rivington, Percival & Co.
  • Cairns, Douglas, ed. (2007). Pursuing the good. University of Edinburgh Press.
  • Craig, Leon (1994). The War Lover: A Study of Plato's Republic. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. ISBN 9780802005861.
  • Cross, R.C. (1964). Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London: Macmillan.
  • Dixsaut, Monique (2005). études sur la république de platon. france: vrin.
  • Ferrari, G.R.F., ed. (2007). The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Howland, Jacob (1993). The Republic: The Odyssey of Philosophy. Philadelphia: Paul Dry Books.
  • Hyland, Drew (1995). Finitude and transcendence in the Platonic dialogues.
  • Kraut, Richard, ed. (1997). Plato's Republic: Critical Essays. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • LeMoine, Rebecca (2020). Plato's Caves: The Liberating Sting of Cultural Diversity. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Levinson, Ronald (1953). In Defense of Plato. Cambridge: Harvard.
  • Lisi, Francisco, ed. (2007). The Ascent to the Good. London: Academia Verlag.
  • Mayhew, Robert (1997). Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Republic. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • McNeill, David (2010). An Image of the Soul in Speech. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  • Mitchell, Basil; Lucas, J.R. (2003). An Engagement with Plato's Republic: A Companion to Plato's Republic. Aldershot: Ashgate.
  • Murphy, N.R. (1951). The Interpretation of Plato's Republic. Oxford: Oxford U.P.
  • Nettleship, Richard. (1898). Lectures on The Republic of Plato. London.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  • Nethercott, Frances (2000). Russia's Plato: Plato and the Platonic Tradition in Russian Education, Science, and Ideology (1840–1930). Ashgate. ISBN 978-0-7546-1463-0. Retrieved 25 January 2023.
  • Nettleship, Richard. (1935). The Theory of Education in Plato's Republic. London: Oxford.
  • Ophir, Adi (1991). Plato's Invisible Cities. London: Routledge.
  • Pappas, Nikolas (1995). Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Plato and the Republic. London: Routledge.
  • Piechowiak, Marek (2021). Plato's Conception of Justice and the Question of Human Dignity. Berlin: Peter Lang.
  • Purshouse, Luke (2007). Plato's Republic. London: Continuum.
  • Reeve, C.D.C. (1988). Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato's Republic. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Rice, Daryl H. (1998). A Guide to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Roochnik, David (2003). Beautiful City. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Rosen, Stanley (2005). Plato's Republic: A Study. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Santas, Gerasimos, ed. (2006). The Blackwell Guide to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Santas, Gerasimos, ed. (2010). understanding Plato's Republic. Oxford: wiley-Blackwell.
  • Sayers, Sean (1999). Plato's Republic: An Introduction. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
  • Sesonske, Alexander, ed. (1966). Plato's Republic: Interpretation and Criticism. Belmont: Wadsworth.
  • Sinaiko, Herman (1998). Reclaiming the Canon. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 9780300065299.
  • Strauss, Leo (1964). The City and Man. Chicago: Rand McNally.
  • White, Nicholas P. (1979). A Companion to Plato's Republic. Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Wild, John (1946). Plato's Theory of Man. Cambridge: Harvard.
  • Wild, John (1953). Plato's Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law. Chicago: University of Chicago.

External links edit

republic, plato, this, article, possibly, contains, original, research, please, improve, verifying, claims, made, adding, inline, citations, statements, consisting, only, original, research, should, removed, april, 2022, learn, when, remove, this, template, me. This article possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed April 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Republic Greek Politeia translit Politeia Latin De Republica 1 is a Socratic dialogue authored by Plato around 375 BC concerning justice dikaiosynh the order and character of the just city state and the just man 2 It is Plato s best known work and one of the world s most influential works of philosophy and political theory both intellectually and historically 3 4 RepublicTitle page of the oldest complete manuscript Paris Bibliotheque Nationale Gr 1807 late 9th century AuthorPlatoOriginal titlePoliteiaCountryAncient GreeceLanguageGreekSubjectPolitical philosophyPublishedc 375 BCTextRepublic at WikisourceIn the dialogue Socrates discusses the meaning of justice and whether the just man is happier than the unjust man with various Athenians and foreigners 5 He considers the natures of existing regimes and then proposes a series of hypothetical cities in comparison culminating in Kallipolis Kallipolis a utopian city state ruled by a class of philosopher kings They also discuss ageing love theory of forms the immortality of the soul and the role of the philosopher and of poetry in society 6 The dialogue s setting seems to be the time of the Peloponnesian War 7 Contents 1 Place in Plato s corpus 2 Outline 2 1 Book I Aging Love and the Definitions of Justice 2 2 Book II Glaucon and Adeimantus s Challenge 2 3 Book II IV The city and the soul 2 4 Book V VI The Ship of State 2 5 Book VI VII Allegories of the Sun Divided Line and Cave 2 6 Book VIII IX Plato s five regimes 2 7 Book X Myth of Er 3 Legacy 3 1 Ancient Greece and Rome 3 2 Middle Ages 3 2 1 Ibn Rushd 3 2 2 Gratian 3 3 Thomas More 3 4 Hegel 3 5 20th century 3 6 21st century 3 7 Cultural influence 4 Criticism 4 1 Gadamer 4 2 Popper 4 3 Voegelin 4 4 Strauss and Bloom 5 Fragments 6 Translations 7 See also 8 Notes 9 Further reading 10 External linksPlace in Plato s corpus editRepublic is generally placed in the middle period of Plato s dialogues However the distinction of this group from the early dialogues is not as clear as the distinction of the late dialogues from all the others Nonetheless Ritter Arnim and Baron with their separate methodologies all agreed that the Republic was well distinguished along with Parmenides Phaedrus and Theaetetus 8 However the first book of the Republic which shares many features with earlier dialogues is thought to have originally been written as a separate work and then the remaining books were conjoined to it perhaps with modifications to the original of the first book 8 Outline editThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed November 2010 Learn how and when to remove this template message Book I Aging Love and the Definitions of Justice edit See also Thrasymachus and List of speakers in Plato s dialogues While visiting Athen s port Piraeus with Glaucon Socrates is invited to join Polemarchus for a dinner and festival They eventually end up at Polemarchus house where Socrates encounters Polemarchus father Cephalus In his first philosophical conversation with the group members Socrates gets into a conversation with Cephalus The first real philosophical question posed by Plato in the book is when Socrates asks is life painful at that age or what report do you make of it 9 when speaking to the aged Cephalus Cephalus answers by saying that many are unhappy about old age because they miss their youth but he finds that old age brings us profound repose and freedom from this and other passions When the appetites have abated and their force is diminished the description of Sophocles is perfectly realized It is like being delivered from a multitude of furious masters 9 The repose gives him time to dedicate himself to sacrifices and justice so that he is prepared for the afterlife Socrates then asks his interlocutors for a definition of justice Three are suggested Cephalus To give each what is owed to them 331c Polemarchus To give to each what is appropriate to him 332c Thrasymachus What is advantageous for the stronger 338c Socrates refutes each definition in turn One may owe it to someone to return them a knife one has borrowed but if he has since gone mad and would only harm himself with it returning the knife would not be just Polemarchus suggests that what is appropriate is to do good to friends and bad to enemies but harming someone tends to make them unjust and so on his definition justice would tend to create injustice If it is just to do what rulers the stronger say and rulers make mistakes about their advantage then it is just to do what is disadvantageous for the stronger Thrasymachus then responds to this refutation by claiming that insofar as the stronger make mistakes they are not in that regard the stronger Socrates refutes Thrasymachus with a further argument Crafts aim at the good of their object and therefore to rule is for the benefit of the ruled and not the ruler At this point Thrasymachus claims that the unjust person is wiser than the just person and Socrates gives three arguments refuting Thrasymachus However Thrasymachus ceases to engage actively with Socrates s arguments and Socrates himself seems to think that his arguments are inadequate since he has not offered any definition of justice The first book ends in aporia concerning the essence of justice Book II Glaucon and Adeimantus s Challenge edit Main article Ring of Gyges Glaucon and Adeimantus are unsatisfied with Socrates s defense of justice They ask Socrates to defend justice against an alternative view that they attribute to many According to this view the origin of justice is in social contracts Everyone would prefer to get away with harm to others without suffering it themselves but since they cannot they agree not to do harm to others so as not to suffer it themselves Moreover according to this view all those who practice justice do so unwillingly and out of fear of punishment and the life of the unpunished unjust man is far more blessed than that of the just man Glaucon would like Socrates to prove that justice is not only desirable for its consequences but also for its own sake To demonstrate the problem he tells the story of Gyges who with the help of a ring that turns him invisible achieves great advantages for himself by committing injustices Many think that anyone would and should use the ring as Gyges did if they had it Glaucon uses this argument to challenge Socrates to defend the position that the just life is better than the unjust life Adeimantus supplements Glaucon s speech with further arguments He suggests that the unjust should not fear divine judgement since the very poets who wrote about such judgement also wrote that the gods would grant forgiveness to those who made religious sacrifice Book II IV The city and the soul edit See also Plato s theory of soul and Cardinal virtues Socrates suggests that they use the city as an image to seek how justice comes to be in the soul of an individual After attributing the origin of society to the individual not being self sufficient and having many needs which he cannot supply himself Socrates first describes a healthy state made up of producers who make enough for a modest subsistence but Glaucon considers this hardly different than a city of pigs Socrates then goes on to describe the luxurious city which he calls a fevered state 10 Acquiring and defending these luxuries requires a guardian class to wage wars They then explore how to obtain guardians who will not become tyrants to the people they guard Socrates proposes that they solve the problem with an education from their early years He then prescribes the necessary education beginning with the kind of stories that are appropriate for training guardians They conclude that stories that ascribe evil to the gods or heroes or portray the afterlife as bad are untrue and should not be taught They also decide to regulate narrative and musical style so as to encourage the four cardinal virtues wisdom courage justice and temperance Socrates avers that beautiful style and morally good style are the same In proposing their program of censored education they are repurifying the luxurious or feverish city Socrates counters the objection that people raised in censorship will be too naive to judge concerning vice by arguing that adults can learn about vice once their character has been formed before that they are too impressionable to encounter vice without danger They suggest that the second part of the guardians education should be in gymnastics With physical training they will be able to live without needing frequent medical attention physical training will help prevent illness and weakness Socrates claims that any illness requiring constant medical attention is too unhealthy to be worth living By analogy any society that requires constant litigation is too unhealthy to be worth maintaining Socrates asserts that both male and female guardians be given the same education that all wives and children be shared and that they be prohibited from owning private property so that guardians will not become possessive and keep their focus on the good of the whole city He adds a third class distinction between auxiliaries rank and file soldiers and guardians the leaders who rule the city In the fictional tale known as the myth or parable of the metals Socrates presents the Noble Lie gennaῖon pseῦdos gennaion pseudos to convince everyone in the city to perform their social role All are born from the womb of their mother country so that all are siblings but their natures are different each containing either gold guardians silver auxiliaries or bronze or iron producers If anyone with a bronze or iron nature rules the city it will be destroyed Socrates claims that if the people believed this myth it would have a good effect making them more inclined to care for the state and one another 11 Socrates claims the city will be happiest if each citizen engages in the occupation that suits them best If the city as a whole is happy then individuals are happy In the physical education and diet of the guardians the emphasis is on moderation since both poverty and excessive wealth will corrupt them 422a1 He argues that a city without wealth can defend itself successfully against wealthy aggressors Socrates says that it is pointless to worry over specific laws like those pertaining to contracts since proper education ensures lawful behavior and poor education causes lawlessness 425a 425c 12 Socrates proceeds to search for wisdom courage and temperance in the city on the grounds that justice will be easier to discern in what remains 427e They find wisdom among the guardian rulers courage among the guardian warriors or auxiliaries temperance among all classes of the city in agreeing about who should rule and who should be ruled Finally Socrates defines justice in the city as the state in which each class performs only its own work not meddling in the work of the other classes 433b The virtues discovered in the city are then sought in the individual soul For this purpose Socrates creates an analogy between the parts of the city and the soul the city soul analogy 13 He argues that psychological conflict points to a divided soul since a completely unified soul could not behave in opposite ways towards the same object at the same time and in the same respect 436b 14 He gives examples of possible conflicts between the rational spirited and appetitive parts of the soul corresponding to the rulers auxiliaries and producing classes in the city 15 Having established the tripartite soul Socrates defines the virtues of the individual A person is wise if he is ruled by the part of the soul that knows what is beneficial for each part and for the whole courageous if his spirited part preserves in the midst of pleasures and pains the decisions reached by the rational part and temperate if the three parts agree that the rational part lead 442c d 16 They are just if each part of the soul attends to its function and not the function of another It follows from this definition that one cannot be just if one does not have the other cardinal virtues 14 In this regard Plato can be seen as a progenitor of the concept of social structures Book V VI The Ship of State edit Main article Ship of State See also Form of the Good and Plato s political philosophy Socrates having to his satisfaction defined the just constitution of both city and psyche moves to elaborate upon the four unjust constitutions of these Adeimantus and Polemarchus interrupt asking Socrates instead first to explain how the sharing of wives and children in the guardian class is to be defined and legislated a theme first touched on in Book III Socrates is overwhelmed at their request categorizing it as three waves of attack against which his reasoning must stand firm These three waves challenge Socrates claims that both male and female guardians ought to receive the same education human reproduction ought to be regulated by the state and all offspring should be ignorant of their actual biological parents such a city and its corresponding philosopher king could actually come to be in the real world In Books V VII the abolition of riches among the guardian class not unlike Max Weber s bureaucracy leads controversially to the abandonment of the typical family and as such no child may know his or her parents and the parents may not know their own children Socrates tells a tale which is the allegory of the good government The rulers assemble couples for reproduction based on breeding criteria Thus stable population is achieved through eugenics and social cohesion is projected to be high because familial links are extended towards everyone in the city Also the education of the youth is such that they are taught of only works of writing that encourage them to improve themselves for the state s good and envision the god s as entirely good just and the author s of only that which is good Socrates argument is that in the ideal city a true philosopher with understanding of forms will facilitate the harmonious co operation of all the citizens of the city the governance of a city state is likened to the command of a ship the Ship of State This philosopher king must be intelligent reliable and willing to lead a simple life However these qualities are rarely manifested on their own and so they must be encouraged through education and the study of the Good Book VI VII Allegories of the Sun Divided Line and Cave edit Main articles Analogy of the Sun Analogy of the Divided Line and Allegory of the Cave See also Problem of universals Platonic epistemology and Theory of Forms The Allegory of the Cave primarily depicts Plato s distinction between the world of appearances and the real world of the Forms 17 Just as visible objects must be illuminated in order to be seen so must also be true of objects of knowledge if light is cast on them Plato imagines a group of people who have lived their entire lives as prisoners chained to the wall of a cave in the subterranean so they are unable to see the outside world behind them However a constant flame illuminates various moving objects outside which are silhouetted on the wall of the cave visible to the prisoners These prisoners through having no other experience of reality ascribe forms to these shadows such as either dog or cat Plato then goes on to explain how the philosopher is akin to a prisoner who is freed from the cave The prisoner is initially blinded by the light but when he adjusts to the brightness he sees the fire and the statues and how they caused the images witnessed inside the cave He sees that the fire and statues in the cave were just copies of the real objects merely imitations This is analogous to the Forms What we see from day to day are merely appearances reflections of the Forms The philosopher however will not be deceived by the shadows and will hence be able to see the real world the world above that of appearances the philosopher will gain knowledge of things in themselves At the end of this allegory Plato asserts that it is the philosopher s burden to reenter the cave Those who have seen the ideal world he says have the duty to educate those in the material world Since the philosopher recognizes what is truly good only he is fit to rule society according to Plato Book VIII IX Plato s five regimes edit In Books VIII IX stand Plato s criticism of the forms of government Plato categorized governments into five types of regimes aristocracy timocracy oligarchy democracy and tyranny The starting point is an imagined alternate aristocracy ruled by a philosopher king a just government ruled by a philosopher king dominated by the wisdom loving element Aristocracy degenerates into timocracy when due to miscalculation on the part of its governing class the next generation includes persons of an inferior nature inclined not just to cultivating virtues but also producing wealth In a timocracy governors will apply great effort in gymnastics and the arts of war as well as the virtue that pertains to them that of courage As the emphasis on honor is compromised by wealth accumulation it is replaced by oligarchy The oligarchic government is dominated by the desiring element in which the rich are the ruling class Oligarchs do however value at least one virtue that of temperance and moderation not out of an ethical principle or spiritual concern but because by dominating wasteful tendencies they succeed in accumulating money As this socioeconomic divide grows so do tensions between social classes From the conflicts arising out of such tensions the poor majority overthrow the wealthy minority and democracy replaces the oligarchy preceding it In democracy the lower class grows bigger and bigger A visually appealing demagogue is soon lifted up to protect the interests of the lower class who can exploit them to take power in order to maintain order Democracy then degenerates into tyranny where no one has discipline and society exists in chaos In a tyrannical government the city is enslaved to the tyrant who uses his guards to remove the best social elements and individuals from the city to retain power since they pose a threat while leaving the worst He will also provoke warfare to consolidate his position as leader In this way tyranny is the most unjust regime of all In parallel to this Socrates considers the individual or soul that corresponds to each of these regimes He describes how an aristocrat may become weak or detached from political and material affluence and how his son will respond to this by becoming overly ambitious The timocrat in turn may be defeated by the courts or vested interests his son responds by accumulating wealth in order to gain power in society and defend himself against the same predicament thereby becoming an oligarch The oligarch s son will grow up with wealth without having to practice thrift or stinginess and will be tempted and overwhelmed by his desires 18 so that he becomes democratic valuing freedom above all 18 The democratic man is torn between tyrannical passions and oligarchic discipline and ends up in the middle ground valuing all desires both good and bad The tyrant will be tempted in the same way as the democrat but without an upbringing in discipline or moderation to restrain him Therefore his most base desires and wildest passions overwhelm him and he becomes driven by lust using force and fraud to take whatever he wants The tyrant is both a slave to his lusts and a master to whomever he can enslave Socrates points out the human tendency to be corrupted by power leads down the road to timocracy oligarchy democracy and tyranny From this he concludes that ruling should be left to philosophers who are the most just and therefore least susceptible to corruption This good city is depicted as being governed by philosopher kings disinterested persons who rule not for their personal enjoyment but for the good of the city state polis The philosophers have seen the Forms and therefore know what is good They understand the corrupting effect of greed and own no property and receive no salary They also live in sober communism eating and sleeping together Book X Myth of Er edit See also Myth of Er Concluding a theme brought up most explicitly in the Analogies of the Sun and Divided Line in Book VI Socrates finally rejects any form of imitative art and concludes that such artists have no place in the just city He continues on to argue for the immortality of the psyche and espouses a theory of reincarnation He finishes by detailing the rewards of being just both in this life and the next Artists create things but they are only different copies of the idea of the original And whenever any one informs us that he has found a man who knows all the arts and all things else that anybody knows and every single thing with a higher degree of accuracy than any other man whoever tells us this I think that we can only imagine to be a simple creature who is likely to have been deceived by some wizard or actor whom he met and whom he thought all knowing because he himself was unable to analyze the nature of knowledge and ignorance and imitation 19 And the same object appears straight when looked at out of the water and crooked when in the water and the concave becomes convex owing to the illusion about colours to which the sight is liable Thus every sort of confusion is revealed within us and this is that weakness of the human mind on which the art of conjuring and deceiving by light and shadow and other ingenious devices imposes having an effect upon us like magic 19 He speaks about illusions and confusion Things can look very similar but be different in reality Because we are human at times we cannot tell the difference between the two And does not the same hold also of the ridiculous There are jests which you would be ashamed to make yourself and yet on the comic stage or indeed in private when you hear them you are greatly amused by them and are not at all disgusted at their unseemliness the case of pity is repeated there is a principle in human nature which is disposed to raise a laugh and this which you once restrained by reason because you were afraid of being thought a buffoon is now let out again and having stimulated the risible faculty at the theatre you are betrayed unconsciously to yourself into playing the comic poet at home With all of us we may approve of something as long we are not directly involved with it If we joke about it we are supporting it Quite true he said And the same may be said of lust and anger and all the other affections of desire and pain and pleasure which are held to be inseparable from every action in all of them poetry feeds and waters the passions instead of drying them up she lets them rule although they ought to be controlled if mankind are ever to increase in happiness and virtue 19 Sometimes we let our passions rule our actions or way of thinking although they should be controlled so that we can increase our happiness Legacy editAncient Greece and Rome edit This section needs expansion You can help by adding to it May 2021 You can help expand this section with text translated from the corresponding article in German October 2023 Click show for important translation instructions View a machine translated version of the German article Machine translation like DeepL or Google Translate is a useful starting point for translations but translators must revise errors as necessary and confirm that the translation is accurate rather than simply copy pasting machine translated text into the English Wikipedia Consider adding a topic to this template there are already 8 987 articles in the main category and specifying topic will aid in categorization Do not translate text that appears unreliable or low quality If possible verify the text with references provided in the foreign language article You must provide copyright attribution in the edit summary accompanying your translation by providing an interlanguage link to the source of your translation A model attribution edit summary is Content in this edit is translated from the existing German Wikipedia article at de Politeia see its history for attribution You should also add the template Translated de Politeia to the talk page For more guidance see Wikipedia Translation Aristotle systematises many of Plato s analyses in his Politics and criticizes the propositions of several political philosophers for the ideal city state Zeno of Citium the founder of Stoicism wrote his version of an ideal society Zeno s Republic in opposition to Plato s Republic 20 Zeno s Republic was controversial and was viewed with some embarrassment by some of the later Stoics due to its defenses of free love incest and cannibalism and due to its opposition to ordinary education and the building of temples law courts and gymnasia The English title of Plato s dialogue is derived from Cicero s De re publica written some three centuries later 21 citation needed Cicero s dialogue imitates Plato s style and treats many of the same topics and Cicero s main character Scipio Aemilianus expresses his esteem for Plato and Socrates Augustine of Hippo wrote his The City of God Augustine equally described a model of the ideal city in his case the eternal Jerusalem using a visionary language not unlike that of the preceding philosophers Middle Ages edit Ibn Rushd edit Islamic philosophers were much more interested in Aristotle than Plato but not having access to Aristotle s Politics Ibn Rushd Averroes produced instead a commentary on Plato s Republic He advances an authoritarian ideal following Plato s paternalistic model Absolute monarchy led by a philosopher king creates a justly ordered society This requires extensive use of coercion 22 although persuasion is preferred and is possible if the young are properly raised 23 Rhetoric not logic is the appropriate road to truth for the common man Demonstrative knowledge via philosophy and logic requires special study Rhetoric aids religion in reaching the masses 24 Following Plato Ibn Rushd accepts the principle of women s equality They should be educated and allowed to serve in the military the best among them might be tomorrow s philosophers or rulers 25 26 He also accepts Plato s illiberal measures such as the censorship of literature He uses examples from Arab history to illustrate just and degenerate political orders 27 Gratian edit The medieval jurist Gratian in his Decretum ca 1140 quotes Plato as agreeing with him that by natural law all things are common to all people 28 He identifies Plato s ideal society with the early Church as described in the Acts of the Apostles Plato lays out the order Gratian comments for a very just republic in which no one considers anything his own 29 Thomas More edit Thomas More when writing his Utopia invented the technique of using the portrayal of a utopia as the carrier of his thoughts about the ideal society More s island Utopia is also similar to Plato s Republic in some aspects among them common property and the lack of privacy 30 31 32 33 Hegel edit Hegel respected Plato s theories of state and ethics much more than those of the early modern philosophers such as Locke Hobbes and Rousseau whose theories proceeded from a fictional state of nature defined by humanity s natural needs desires and freedom For Hegel this was a contradiction since nature and the individual are contradictory the freedoms which define individuality as such are latecomers on the stage of history Therefore these philosophers unwittingly projected man as an individual in modern society onto a primordial state of nature Plato however had managed to grasp the ideas specific to his time Plato is not the man to dabble in abstract theories and principles his truth loving mind has recognized and represented the truth of the world in which he lived the truth of the one spirit that lived in him as in Greece itself No man can overleap his time the spirit of his time is his spirit also but the point at issue is to recognize that spirit by its content 34 For Hegel Plato s Republic is not an abstract theory or ideal which is too good for the real nature of man but rather is not ideal enough not good enough for the ideals already inherent or nascent in the reality of his time a time when Greece was entering decline One such nascent idea was about to crush the Greek way of life modern freedoms or Christian freedoms in Hegel s view such as the individual s choice of his social class or of what property to pursue or which career to follow Such individual freedoms were excluded from Plato s Republic Plato recognized and caught up the true spirit of his times and brought it forward in a more definite way in that he desired to make this new principle an impossibility in his Republic 35 Greece being at a crossroads Plato s new constitution in the Republic was an attempt to preserve Greece it was a reactionary reply to the new freedoms of private property etc that were eventually given legal form through Rome Accordingly in ethical life it was an attempt to introduce a religion that elevated each individual not as an owner of property but as the possessor of an immortal soul 20th century edit nbsp P Oxy 3679 manuscript from the 3rd century AD containing fragments of Plato s Republic Mussolini admired Plato s The Republic which he often read for inspiration 36 The Republic expounded a number of ideas that fascism promoted such as rule by an elite promoting the state as the ultimate end opposition to democracy protecting the class system and promoting class collaboration rejection of egalitarianism promoting the militarization of a nation by creating a class of warriors demanding that citizens perform civic duties in the interest of the state and utilizing state intervention in education to promote the development of warriors and future rulers of the state 37 Plato was an idealist focused on achieving justice and morality while Mussolini and fascism were realist focused on achieving political goals 38 Martin Luther King Jr nominated The Republic as the one book he would have taken to a deserted island alongside the Bible 39 21st century edit In 2001 a survey of over 1 000 academics and students voted the Republic the greatest philosophical text ever written Julian Baggini argued that although the work was wrong on almost every point the questions it raises and the methods it uses are essential to the western tradition of philosophy Without it we might not have philosophy as we know it 40 In 2021 a survey showed that The Republic is the most studied book in the top universities in the United States 41 42 Cultural influence edit Plato s Republic has been influential in literature and art Aldous Huxley s Brave New World has a dystopian government that bears a resemblance to the form of government described in the Republic featuring the separation of people by professional class assignment of profession and purpose by the state and the absence of traditional family units replaced by state organized breeding 43 The Orwellian dystopia depicted in the novel 1984 had many characteristics in common with Plato s description of the allegory of the Cave as Winston Smith strives to liberate himself from it 44 In the early 1970s the Dutch composer Louis Andriessen composed a vocal work called De Staat based on the text of Plato s Republic 45 In Robert A Heinlein s Starship Troopers his citizen can be compared to a Platonic Guardian without the communal breeding and property but still having a militaristic base Although there are significant differences in the specifics of the system Heinlein and Plato both describe systems of limited franchise with a political class that has supposedly earned their power and wisely governs the whole Republic is specifically attacked in Starship Troopers The arachnids can be seen as much closer to a Republic society than the humans 46 The film The Matrix models Plato s Allegory of the Cave 47 In fiction Jo Walton s 2015 novel The Just City explored the consequences of establishing a city state based on the Republic in practice See also Ring of Gyges Cultural influencesCriticism editGadamer edit In his 1934 Plato und die Dichter Plato and the Poets as well as several other works Hans Georg Gadamer describes the utopic city of the Republic as a heuristic utopia that should not be pursued or even be used as an orientation point for political development Rather its purpose is said to be to show how things would have to be connected and how one thing would lead to another often with highly problematic results if one would opt for certain principles and carry them through rigorously This interpretation argues that large passages in Plato s writing are ironic a line of thought initially pursued by Kierkegaard Popper edit The city portrayed in Republic struck some critics as harsh rigid and unfree indeed as totalitarian Karl Popper gave a voice to that view in his 1945 book The Open Society and Its Enemies where he singled out Plato s state as a dystopia Popper distinguished Plato s ideas from those of Socrates claiming that the former in his later years expressed none of the humanitarian and democratic tendencies of his teacher 48 49 50 Popper thought Plato s envisioned state totalitarian as it advocated a government composed only of a distinct hereditary ruling class with the working class who Popper argues Plato regards as human cattle given no role in decision making He argues that Plato has no interest in what are commonly regarded as the problems of justice the resolution of disputes between individuals because Plato has redefined justice as keeping one s place 51 Popper insists that Republic was meant by its author not so much as a theoretical treatise but as a topical political manifesto 52 and Bertrand Russell argues that at least in intent and all in all not so far from what was possible in ancient Greek city states the form of government portrayed in the Republic was meant as a practical one by Plato 53 Voegelin edit Many critics have suggested that the dialogue s political discussion actually serves as an analogy for the individual soul in which there are also many different members that can either conflict or else be integrated and orchestrated under a just and productive government Among other things this analogical reading would solve the problem of certain implausible statements Plato makes concerning an ideal political republic 54 Norbert Blossner 2007 55 argues that the Republic is best understood as an analysis of the workings and moral improvement of the individual soul with remarkable thoroughness and clarity This view of course does not preclude a legitimate reading of Republic as a political treatise the work could operate at both levels It merely implies that it deserves more attention as a work on psychology and moral philosophy than it has sometimes received Eric Voegelin in Plato and Aristotle Baton Rouge 1957 gave meaning to the concept of Just City in Speech Books II V For instance there is evidence in the dialogue that Socrates himself would not be a member of his ideal state His life was almost solely dedicated to the private pursuit of knowledge More practically Socrates suggests that members of the lower classes could rise to the higher ruling class and vice versa if they had gold in their veins a version of the concept of social mobility The exercise of power is built on the noble lie that all men are brothers born of the earth yet there is a clear hierarchy and class divisions There is a tripartite explanation of human psychology that is extrapolated to the city the relation among peoples There is no family among the guardians another crude version of Max Weber s concept of bureaucracy as the state non private concern Together with Leo Strauss Voegelin considered Popper s interpretation to be a gross misunderstanding not only of the dialogue itself but of the very nature and character of Plato s entire philosophic enterprise The paradigm of the city the idea of the Good the Agathon has manifold historical embodiments undertaken by those who have seen the Agathon and are ordered via the vision The centerpiece of the Republic Part II nos 2 3 discusses the rule of the philosopher and the vision of the Agathon with the Allegory of the Cave which is clarified in the theory of forms The centerpiece is preceded and followed by the discussion of the means that will secure a well ordered polis city Part II no 1 concerns marriage the community of people and goods for the guardians and the restraints on warfare among the Hellenes It describes a partially communistic polis Part II no 4 deals with the philosophical education of the rulers who will preserve the order and character of the city state In part II the Embodiment of the Idea is preceded by the establishment of the economic and social orders of a polis part I followed by an analysis part III of the decline the order must traverse The three parts compose the main body of the dialogues with their discussions of the paradigm its embodiment its genesis and its decline The introduction and the conclusion are the frame for the body of Republic The discussion of right order is occasioned by the questions Is justice better than injustice and Will an unjust man fare better than a just man The introductory question is balanced by the concluding answer Justice is preferable to injustice In turn the foregoing are framed with the Prologue Book I and the Epilogue Book X The prologue is a short dialogue about the common public doxai opinions about justice Based upon faith and not reason the Epilogue describes the new arts and the immortality of the soul Strauss and Bloom edit Some of Plato s proposals have led theorists like Leo Strauss and Allan Bloom to ask readers to consider the possibility that Socrates was creating not a blueprint for a real city but a learning exercise for the young men in the dialogue There are many points in the construction of the Just City in Speech that seem contradictory which raise the possibility Socrates is employing irony to make the men in the dialogue question for themselves the ultimate value of the proposals In turn Plato has immortalized this learning exercise in Republic One of many examples is that Socrates calls the marriages of the ruling class sacred however they last only one night and are the result of manipulating and drugging couples into predetermined intercourse with the aim of eugenically breeding guardian warriors Strauss and Bloom s interpretations however involve more than just pointing out inconsistencies by calling attention to these issues they ask readers to think more deeply about whether Plato is being ironic or genuine for neither Strauss nor Bloom present an unequivocal opinion preferring to raise philosophic doubt over interpretive fact Strauss s approach developed out of a belief that Plato wrote esoterically The basic acceptance of the exoteric esoteric distinction revolves around whether Plato really wanted to see the Just City in Speech of Books V VI come to pass or whether it is just an allegory Strauss never regarded this as the crucial issue of the dialogue He argued against Karl Popper s literal view citing Cicero s opinion that Republic s true nature was to bring to light the nature of political things 56 In fact Strauss undermines the justice found in the Just City in Speech by implying the city is not natural it is a man made conceit that abstracts away from the erotic needs of the body The city founded in Republic is rendered possible by the abstraction from eros 57 An argument that has been used against ascribing ironic intent to Plato is that Plato s Academy produced a number of tyrants who seized political power and abandoned philosophy for ruling a city Despite being well versed in Greek and having direct contact with Plato himself some of Plato s former students like Clearchus tyrant of Heraclea Chaeron tyrant of Pellene Erastus and Coriscus tyrants of Skepsis Hermias of Atarneus and Assos and Calippus tyrant of Syracuse ruled people and did not impose anything like a philosopher kingship However it can be argued whether these men became tyrants through studying in the academy Plato s school had an elite student body some of whom would by birth and family expectation end up in the seats of power Additionally it is important that it is by no means obvious that these men were tyrants in the modern totalitarian sense of the concept Finally since very little is actually known about what was taught at Plato s Academy there is no small controversy over whether it was even in the business of teaching politics at all 58 Fragments editSeveral Oxyrhynchus Papyri fragments were found to contain parts of Republic and from other works such as Phaedo or the dialogue Gorgias written around 200 300 CE 59 Fragments of a different version of Plato s Republic were discovered in 1945 part of the Nag Hammadi library written c 350 CE 60 These findings highlight the influence of Plato during those times in Egypt Translations editBurges George 1854 Plato The Republic Timaeus and Critias New and literal version London H G Bohn Jowett Benjamin 1871 Plato The Republic Bloom Allan 1991 1968 The Republic of Plato Translated with notes and an interpretive essay New York Basic Books Grube G M A 1992 Plato The Republic Revised by C D C Reeve Indianapolis Hackett Waterfield Robin 1994 Plato Republic Translated with notes and an introduction Oxford Oxford World s Classics Griffith Tom 2000 Plato The Republic Cambridge Cambridge University Press Allen R E 2006 Plato The Republic New Haven Yale University Press Sachs Joe 2007 Plato Republic Newburyport Focus Publishing Rowe Christopher 2012 Plato Republic London Penguin See also editCollectivism and individualism Cultural influence of Plato s Republic Mixed government Nous Orthotes Onomaton Plato s numberNotes edit Henri Estienne ed Platonis opera quae extant omnia Vol 2 1578 p 327 Brickhouse Thomas and Smith Nicholas D Plato c 427 347 BC The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy University of Tennessee cf Dating Plato s Dialogues National Public Radio 8 August 2007 Plato s Republic Still Influential Author Says Archived 20 September 2018 at the Wayback Machine Talk of the Nation Plato The Republic Archived 20 September 2018 at the Wayback Machine Plato His Philosophy and his life allphilosophers com In ancient times the book was alternately titled On Justice not to be confused with the spurious dialogue of the same name Lorenz Hendrik 22 April 2009 Ancient Theories of Soul Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 10 December 2013 Baird Forrest E Walter Kaufmann 2008 From Plato to Derrida Upper Saddle River New Jersey Pearson Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 158591 1 Although there would be jarring anachronisms if any of the candidate specific dates between 432 and 404 were assigned Nails Debra 2002 The People of Plato A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics Hackett Publishing ISBN 0 87220 564 9 p 324 a b Brandwood Leonard The Chronology of Plato s Dialogues Cambridge University Press 1990 p 251 a b John Llewelyn Davies 1921 The Republic of Plato Macmillan and Company p 3 Plato Harold North Fowler Paul Shorey 1977 Plato in Twelve Volumes Vol 5 6 W Heinemann ISBN 978 0 674 99040 1 Book 3 415c d Julia Annas Law in the Republic from Virtue and Law in Plato and Beyond Oxford Scholarship Online 2017 DOI 10 1093 oso 9780198755746 003 0002 Calian Florin George 2012 Plato s Psychology of Action and the Origin of Agency philpapers org Retrieved 15 January 2024 a b Brown Eric 2017 Plato s Ethics and Politics in The Republic in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2017 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University archived from the original on 10 April 2020 retrieved 2 October 2018 Calian Florin George 2012 Plato s Psychology of Action and the Origin of Agency philpapers org Retrieved 15 January 2024 Plato Plato in Twelve Volumes Vols 5 amp 6 translated by Paul Shorey Cambridge MA Harvard University Press London William Heinemann Ltd 1969 Silverman Allan 2014 Plato s Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2014 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2 October 2018 a b McAleer Sean 2020 Plato s Republic An Introduction OpenBook Publishers pp 229 251 doi 10 11647 obp 0229 ISBN 978 1 80064 053 5 S2CID 228927159 a b c The Republic Book X Plutarch On Stoic self contradictions 1034F Res publica is not an exact translation of Plato s Greek title politeia Rather politeia is a general term for the actual and potential forms of government for a polis or city state and Plato attempts to survey all possible forms of the state while Cicero s discussion focuses more on the improvement of the Roman Republic Black Antony 2011 The History of Islamic Political Thought 2nd ed Edinburgh University Press p 122 ISBN 978 0 7486 3987 8 Fakhry Majid 2001 Averroes Ibn Rushd His Life Works and Influence Oneworld Publications p 106 ISBN 978 1 85168 269 0 Robert Pasnau November December 2011 The Islamic Scholar Who Gave Us Modern Philosophy Humanities 32 6 Rosenthal Erwin I J 26 December 2017 Averroes Encyclopaedia Britannica Encyclopaedia Britannica inc p xix Fakhry 2001 p 110 Fakhry 2001 p 114 GRAT Decr D 8 dicta Gratiani 1 ante c 1 Nam jure naturali omnia sunt communia omnibus GRAT Decr D 8 dicta Gratiani 1 ante c 1 Unde apud Platonem illa civitas justissime ordinata traditur in qua quisque proprios nescit affectus Interpreting Thomas More s Utopia By John Charles Olin Fordham Univ Press 1989 ISBN 0 8232 1233 5 The Function of the Ideal in Plato s Republic and St Thomas More s Utopia by K Corrigan Moreana 1990 vol 27 no 104 pp 27 49 Thomas More On the Margins of Modernity by J H Hexter The Journal of British Studies Vol 1 Nov 1961 pp 20 37 JSTOR We find it in Plato s Republic and in Utopia More acknowledges his debt to that book More on Utopia by Brendan Bradshaw The Historical Journal Vol 24 No 1 Mar 1981 pp 1 27 JSTOR claims that Utopia not merely emulated Plato s Republic but excelled it Hegel Lectures on the Philosophy of History vol II p 96 Hegel Lectures on the Philosophy of History vol II p 99 Moseley Ray 2004 Mussolini The Last 600 Days of Il Duce Taylor Trade p 39 ISBN 978 1 58979 095 7 Archived from the original on 25 September 2020 Retrieved 3 June 2020 Sharma Urmila Western Political Thought Atlantic Publishers and Distributors P Ltd 1998 p 66 Sharma Urmila Western Political Thought Atlantic Publishers and Distributors P Ltd 1998 pp 66 67 Sharpe Matthew 16 December 2019 Guide to the classics Plato s Republic The Conversation Gibbons Fiachra 7 September 2001 The thinking person s favourite thinkers TheGuardian com Retrieved 14 March 2016 Ha Thu Huong 27 January 2016 These are the books students at the top US colleges are required to read Quartz Archived from the original on 28 May 2021 Jackson Abby 5 February 2016 The most popular required reading at America s top 10 colleges Business Insider Archived from the original on 7 May 2021 Franck Matthew Aldous Huxley s City in Speech Brave New World and the Republic of Plato Paper presented at the annual meeting of The Midwest Political Science Association Palmer House Hilton Chicago Illinois Apr 15 2004 abstract Deatherage Scott 5 8 November 1987 From Plato to Orwell Utopian Rhetoric in a Dystopian World Annual Meeting of the Speech Communication Association 73rd Boston MA Adlington Robert Louis Andriessen De Staat Ashgate 2004 ISBN 0 7546 0925 1 1 In 1992 a CD recording by the Schoenberg Ensemble conducted by Reinbert de Leeuw appeared 2 In 1977 Andriessen had been awarded several prizes for this composition 3 Donald McQuarie Utopia and Transcendence An Analysis of Their Decline in Contemporary Science Fiction The Journal of Popular Culture xiv 2 242 250 1980 Digital object identifier The Matrix and Philosophy Welcome to the Desert of the Real By William Irwin Open Court Publishing 2002 ISBN 0 8126 9501 1 written for those fans of the film who are already philosophers Popper accuses Plato of betraying Socrates He was not the first to do so Thomas Jefferson made the same statement in a letter to his friend John Adams in 1814 Socrates had reason indeed to complain of the misrepresentations of Plato for in truth his dialogues are libels on Socrates Jefferson Thomas To John Adams Monticello July 5 1814 University of Groningen Gilbert Ryle reviewing Popper s text just two years after its publication Ryle G 1 April 1947 Popper K R The Open Society and its Enemies Mind 56 222 167 172 doi 10 1093 mind LVI 222 167 JSTOR 2250518 and agreeing with him wrote that Plato was Socrates Judas Ryle G 1947 p 169 Burke T E 1983 The Philosophy of Popper Manchester Manchester University Press p 141 ISBN 978 0 71900911 2 Popper Karl 1950 The Open Society and Its Enemies Vol 1 The Spell of Plato New York Routledge Popper Karl 1950 The Open Society and Its Enemies Vol 1 The Spell of Plato New York Routledge p 162 Russell B 2004 History of Western Philosophy end of Book I part 2 ch 14 For an oft cited argument that the analogy does not work see T Penner Thought and Desire in Plato in G Vlastos ed Plato Vol 2 Anchor Books 1971 Blossner Norbert The City Soul Analogy G R F Ferrari Translator In G R F Ferrari Ed The Cambridge Companion to Plato s Republic Cambridge University Press 2007 Ch 13 pp 345 385 History of Political Philosophy co editor with Joseph Cropsey 3rd ed Chicago University of Chicago Press 1987 p 68 History of Political Philosophy co editor with Joseph Cropsey 3rd ed Chicago University of Chicago Press 1987 p 60 Malcolm Schofield Plato and Practical Politics in C Rowe and M Schofield eds The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Political Thought Cambridge University Press 2005 pp 293 302 Grenfall Bernard Pyne Hunt Arthur Surridge 1898 The Oxyrhynchus papyri p 187 Archived from the original on 3 May 2016 Retrieved 21 October 2017 Mountain Man Graphics Plato s Republic at Nag Hammadi c 350 CE Further reading editAnnas Julia 1981 An Introduction to Plato s Republic Oxford Oxford University Press Benardete Seth 1989 Socrates Second Sailing On Plato s Republic Chicago University of Chicago Press Blackburn Simon 2007 Plato s Republic A Biography New York Atlantic Monthly Press Bosanquet B 1895 A Companion to Plato s Republic London Rivington Percival amp Co Cairns Douglas ed 2007 Pursuing the good University of Edinburgh Press Craig Leon 1994 The War Lover A Study of Plato s Republic Toronto University of Toronto Press ISBN 9780802005861 Cross R C 1964 Plato s Republic A Philosophical Commentary London Macmillan Dixsaut Monique 2005 etudes sur la republique de platon france vrin Ferrari G R F ed 2007 The Cambridge Companion to Plato s Republic Cambridge Cambridge University Press Howland Jacob 1993 The Republic The Odyssey of Philosophy Philadelphia Paul Dry Books Hyland Drew 1995 Finitude and transcendence in the Platonic dialogues Kraut Richard ed 1997 Plato s Republic Critical Essays Lanham Rowman amp Littlefield LeMoine Rebecca 2020 Plato s Caves The Liberating Sting of Cultural Diversity New York Oxford University Press Levinson Ronald 1953 In Defense of Plato Cambridge Harvard Lisi Francisco ed 2007 The Ascent to the Good London Academia Verlag Mayhew Robert 1997 Aristotle s Criticism of Plato s Republic Lanham Rowman amp Littlefield McNeill David 2010 An Image of the Soul in Speech University Park Pennsylvania State University Press Mitchell Basil Lucas J R 2003 An Engagement with Plato s Republic A Companion to Plato s Republic Aldershot Ashgate Murphy N R 1951 The Interpretation of Plato s Republic Oxford Oxford U P Nettleship Richard 1898 Lectures on The Republic of Plato London a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Nethercott Frances 2000 Russia s Plato Plato and the Platonic Tradition in Russian Education Science and Ideology 1840 1930 Ashgate ISBN 978 0 7546 1463 0 Retrieved 25 January 2023 Nettleship Richard 1935 The Theory of Education in Plato s Republic London Oxford Ophir Adi 1991 Plato s Invisible Cities London Routledge Pappas Nikolas 1995 Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Plato and the Republic London Routledge Piechowiak Marek 2021 Plato s Conception of Justice and the Question of Human Dignity Berlin Peter Lang Purshouse Luke 2007 Plato s Republic London Continuum Reeve C D C 1988 Philosopher Kings The Argument of Plato s Republic Princeton Princeton University Press Rice Daryl H 1998 A Guide to Plato s Republic Oxford Oxford University Press Roochnik David 2003 Beautiful City Ithaca Cornell University Press Rosen Stanley 2005 Plato s Republic A Study New Haven Yale University Press Santas Gerasimos ed 2006 The Blackwell Guide to Plato s Republic Oxford Blackwell Santas Gerasimos ed 2010 understanding Plato s Republic Oxford wiley Blackwell Sayers Sean 1999 Plato s Republic An Introduction Edinburgh Edinburgh University Press Sesonske Alexander ed 1966 Plato s Republic Interpretation and Criticism Belmont Wadsworth Sinaiko Herman 1998 Reclaiming the Canon New Haven Yale University Press ISBN 9780300065299 Strauss Leo 1964 The City and Man Chicago Rand McNally White Nicholas P 1979 A Companion to Plato s Republic Indianapolis Hackett Wild John 1946 Plato s Theory of Man Cambridge Harvard Wild John 1953 Plato s Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law Chicago University of Chicago External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Republic Plato nbsp Wikisource has original text related to this article The Republic nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Republic Plato nbsp Wikibooks has a book on the topic of Plato Republic Texts of the Republic e text Plato s Republic translated by Benjamin Jowett with introduction at Project Gutenberg The same translation with Stephanus numbers side notes and full index Plato s Republic translated by Paul Shorey 1935 annotated and hyperlinked text English and Greek at Perseus Project nbsp The Republic public domain audiobook at LibriVox Approaching Plato A Guide to the Early and Middle Dialogues at Belmont University Plato s Republic Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ethics and Politics in The Republic at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Republic Plato amp oldid 1197614726, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.