fbpx
Wikipedia

Total order

In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation on some set , which satisfies the following for all and in :

  1. (reflexive).
  2. If and then (transitive).
  3. If and then (antisymmetric).
  4. or (strongly connected, formerly called total).

Reflexivity (1.) already follows from connectedness (4.), but is required explicitly by many authors nevertheless, to indicate the kinship to partial orders.[1] Total orders are sometimes also called simple,[2] connex,[3] or full orders.[4]

A set equipped with a total order is a totally ordered set;[5] the terms simply ordered set,[2] linearly ordered set,[3][5] and loset[6][7] are also used. The term chain is sometimes defined as a synonym of totally ordered set,[5] but refers generally to some sort of totally ordered subsets of a given partially ordered set.

An extension of a given partial order to a total order is called a linear extension of that partial order.

Strict and non-strict total orders

A strict total order on a set   is a strict partial order on   in which any two distinct elements are comparable. That is, a strict total order is a binary relation   on some set  , which satisfies the following for all   and   in  :

  1. Not   (irreflexive).
  2. If   then not   (asymmetric).
  3. If   and   then   (transitive).
  4. If  , then   or   (connected).

Asymmetry follows from transitivity and irreflexivity;[8] moreover, irreflexivity follows from asymmetry.[9]

For delimitation purposes, a total order as defined in the lead is sometimes called non-strict order. For each (non-strict) total order   there is an associated relation  , called the strict total order associated with   that can be defined in two equivalent ways:

  •   if   and   (reflexive reduction).
  •   if not   (i.e.,   is the complement of the converse of  ).

Conversely, the reflexive closure of a strict total order   is a (non-strict) total order.

Examples

  • Any subset of a totally ordered set X is totally ordered for the restriction of the order on X.
  • The unique order on the empty set, , is a total order.
  • Any set of cardinal numbers or ordinal numbers (more strongly, these are well-orders).
  • If X is any set and f an injective function from X to a totally ordered set then f induces a total ordering on X by setting x1x2 if and only if f(x1) ≤ f(x2).
  • The lexicographical order on the Cartesian product of a family of totally ordered sets, indexed by a well ordered set, is itself a total order.
  • The set of real numbers ordered by the usual "less than or equal to" (≤) or "greater than or equal to" (≥) relations is totally ordered. Hence each subset of the real numbers is totally ordered, such as the natural numbers, integers, and rational numbers. Each of these can be shown to be the unique (up to an order isomorphism) "initial example" of a totally ordered set with a certain property, (here, a total order A is initial for a property, if, whenever B has the property, there is an order isomorphism from A to a subset of B):[10][citation needed]
    • The natural numbers form an initial non-empty totally ordered set with no upper bound.
    • The integers form an initial non-empty totally ordered set with neither an upper nor a lower bound.
    • The rational numbers form an initial totally ordered set which is dense in the real numbers. Moreover, the reflexive reduction < is a dense order on the rational numbers.
    • The real numbers form an initial unbounded totally ordered set that is connected in the order topology (defined below).
  • Ordered fields are totally ordered by definition. They include the rational numbers and the real numbers. Every ordered field contains an ordered subfield that is isomorphic to the rational numbers. Any Dedekind-complete ordered field is isomorphic to the real numbers.
  • The letters of the alphabet ordered by the standard dictionary order, e.g., A < B < C etc., is a strict total order.

Chains

The term chain is sometimes defined as a synonym for a totally ordered set, but it is generally used for referring to a subset of a partially ordered set that is totally ordered for the induced order.[1][11] Typically, the partially ordered set is a set of subsets of a given set that is ordered by inclusion, and the term is used for stating properties of the set of the chains. This high number of nested levels of sets explains the usefulness of the term.

A common example of the use of chain for referring to totally ordered subsets is Zorn's lemma which asserts that, if every chain in a partially ordered set X has an upper bound in X, then X contains at least one maximal element.[12] Zorn's lemma is commonly used with X being a set of subsets; in this case, the upperbound is obtained by proving that the union of the elements of a chain in X is in X. This is the way that is generally used to prove that a vector space has Hamel bases and that a ring has maximal ideals.

In some contexts, the chains that are considered are order isomorphic to the natural numbers with their usual order or its opposite order. In this case, a chain can be identified with a monotone sequence, and is called an ascending chain or a descending chain, depending whether the sequence is increasing or decreasing.[13]

A partially ordered set has the descending chain condition if every descending chain eventually stabilizes.[14] For example, an order is well founded if it has the descending chain condition. Similarly, the ascending chain condition means that every ascending chain eventually stabilizes. For example, a Noetherian ring is a ring whose ideals satisfy the ascending chain condition.

In other contexts, only chains that are finite sets are considered. In this case, one talks of a finite chain, often shortened as a chain. In this case, the length of a chain is the number of inequalities (or set inclusions) between consecutive elements of the chain; that is, the number minus one of elements in the chain.[15] Thus a singleton set is a chain of length zero, and an ordered pair is a chain of length one. The dimension of a space is often defined or characterized as the maximal length of chains of subspaces. For example, the dimension of a vector space is the maximal length of chains of linear subspaces, and the Krull dimension of a commutative ring is the maximal length of chains of prime ideals.

"Chain" may also be used for some totally ordered subsets of structures that are not partially ordered sets. An example is given by regular chains of polynomials. Another example is the use of "chain" as a synonym for a walk in a graph.

Further concepts

Lattice theory

One may define a totally ordered set as a particular kind of lattice, namely one in which we have

  for all a, b.

We then write ab if and only if  . Hence a totally ordered set is a distributive lattice.

Finite total orders

A simple counting argument will verify that any non-empty finite totally ordered set (and hence any non-empty subset thereof) has a least element. Thus every finite total order is in fact a well order. Either by direct proof or by observing that every well order is order isomorphic to an ordinal one may show that every finite total order is order isomorphic to an initial segment of the natural numbers ordered by <. In other words, a total order on a set with k elements induces a bijection with the first k natural numbers. Hence it is common to index finite total orders or well orders with order type ω by natural numbers in a fashion which respects the ordering (either starting with zero or with one).

Category theory

Totally ordered sets form a full subcategory of the category of partially ordered sets, with the morphisms being maps which respect the orders, i.e. maps f such that if ab then f(a) ≤ f(b).

A bijective map between two totally ordered sets that respects the two orders is an isomorphism in this category.

Order topology

For any totally ordered set X we can define the open intervals

  • (a, b) = {x | a < x and x < b},
  • (−∞, b) = {x | x < b},
  • (a, ∞) = {x | a < x}, and
  • (−∞, ∞) = X.

We can use these open intervals to define a topology on any ordered set, the order topology.

When more than one order is being used on a set one talks about the order topology induced by a particular order. For instance if N is the natural numbers, < is less than and > greater than we might refer to the order topology on N induced by < and the order topology on N induced by > (in this case they happen to be identical but will not in general).

The order topology induced by a total order may be shown to be hereditarily normal.

Completeness

A totally ordered set is said to be complete if every nonempty subset that has an upper bound, has a least upper bound. For example, the set of real numbers R is complete but the set of rational numbers Q is not. In other words, the various concepts of completeness (not to be confused with being "total") do not carry over to restrictions. For example, over the real numbers a property of the relation is that every non-empty subset S of R with an upper bound in R has a least upper bound (also called supremum) in R. However, for the rational numbers this supremum is not necessarily rational, so the same property does not hold on the restriction of the relation to the rational numbers.

There are a number of results relating properties of the order topology to the completeness of X:

  • If the order topology on X is connected, X is complete.
  • X is connected under the order topology if and only if it is complete and there is no gap in X (a gap is two points a and b in X with a < b such that no c satisfies a < c < b.)
  • X is complete if and only if every bounded set that is closed in the order topology is compact.

A totally ordered set (with its order topology) which is a complete lattice is compact. Examples are the closed intervals of real numbers, e.g. the unit interval [0,1], and the affinely extended real number system (extended real number line). There are order-preserving homeomorphisms between these examples.

Sums of orders

For any two disjoint total orders   and  , there is a natural order   on the set  , which is called the sum of the two orders or sometimes just  :

For  ,   holds if and only if one of the following holds:
  1.   and  
  2.   and  
  3.   and  

Intuitively, this means that the elements of the second set are added on top of the elements of the first set.

More generally, if   is a totally ordered index set, and for each   the structure   is a linear order, where the sets   are pairwise disjoint, then the natural total order on   is defined by

For  ,   holds if:
  1. Either there is some   with  
  2. or there are some   in   with  ,  

Decidability

The first-order theory of total orders is decidable, i.e. there is an algorithm for deciding which first-order statements hold for all total orders. Using interpretability in S2S, the monadic second-order theory of countable total orders is also decidable.[16]

Orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets

In order of increasing strength, i.e., decreasing sets of pairs, three of the possible orders on the Cartesian product of two totally ordered sets are:

  • Lexicographical order: (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if a < c or (a = c and bd). This is a total order.
  • (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if ac and bd (the product order). This is a partial order.
  • (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if (a < c and b < d) or (a = c and b = d) (the reflexive closure of the direct product of the corresponding strict total orders). This is also a partial order.

All three can similarly be defined for the Cartesian product of more than two sets.

Applied to the vector space Rn, each of these make it an ordered vector space.

See also examples of partially ordered sets.

A real function of n real variables defined on a subset of Rn defines a strict weak order and a corresponding total preorder on that subset.

Related structures

A binary relation that is antisymmetric, transitive, and reflexive (but not necessarily total) is a partial order.

A group with a compatible total order is a totally ordered group.

There are only a few nontrivial structures that are (interdefinable as) reducts of a total order. Forgetting the orientation results in a betweenness relation. Forgetting the location of the ends results in a cyclic order. Forgetting both data results in a separation relation.[17]

See also

  • Artinian ring – ring that satisfies the descending chain condition on ideals
  • Countryman line
  • Order theory – Branch of mathematics
  • Permutation – Mathematical version of an order change
  • Prefix order – generalization of the notion of prefix of a string, and of the notion of a tree – a downward total partial order
  • Suslin's problem – the proposition, independent of ZFC, that a nonempty unbounded complete dense total order satisfying the countable chain condition is isomorphic to the reals
  • Well-order – Class of mathematical orderings

Notes

  1. ^ a b Halmos 1968, Ch.14.
  2. ^ a b Birkhoff 1967, p. 2.
  3. ^ a b Schmidt & Ströhlein 1993, p. 32.
  4. ^ Fuchs 1963, p. 2.
  5. ^ a b c Davey & Priestley 1990, p. 3.
  6. ^ Strohmeier, Alfred; Genillard, Christian; Weber, Mats (1 August 1990). "Ordering of characters and strings". ACM SIGAda Ada Letters (7): 84. doi:10.1145/101120.101136. S2CID 38115497.
  7. ^ Ganapathy, Jayanthi (1992). "Maximal Elements and Upper Bounds in Posets". Pi Mu Epsilon Journal. 9 (7): 462–464. ISSN 0031-952X. JSTOR 24340068.
  8. ^ Let  , assume for contradiction that also  . Then   by transitivity, which contradicts irreflexivity.
  9. ^ If  , the not   by asymmetry.
  10. ^ This definition resembles that of an initial object of a category, but is weaker.
  11. ^ Roland Fraïssé (December 2000). Theory of Relations. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol. 145 (1st ed.). Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-444-50542-2. Here: p. 35
  12. ^ Brian A. Davey and Hilary Ann Priestley (1990). Introduction to Lattices and Order. Cambridge Mathematical Textbooks. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-36766-2. LCCN 89009753. Here: p. 100
  13. ^ Yiannis N. Moschovakis (2006) Notes on set theory, Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics (Birkhäuser) ISBN 0-387-28723-X, p. 116
  14. ^ that is, beyond some index, all further sequence members are equal
  15. ^ Davey and Priestly 1990, Def.2.24, p. 37
  16. ^ Weyer, Mark (2002). "Decidability of S1S and S2S". Automata, Logics, and Infinite Games. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 2500. Springer. pp. 207–230. doi:10.1007/3-540-36387-4_12. ISBN 978-3-540-00388-5.
  17. ^ Macpherson, H. Dugald (2011), "A survey of homogeneous structures", Discrete Mathematics, 311 (15): 1599–1634, doi:10.1016/j.disc.2011.01.024

References

External links

total, order, linear, order, redirects, here, confused, with, linear, order, linguistics, this, article, includes, list, general, references, lacks, sufficient, corresponding, inline, citations, please, help, improve, this, article, introducing, more, precise,. Linear order redirects here Not to be confused with Linear order linguistics This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations February 2016 Learn how and when to remove this template message In mathematics a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable That is a total order is a binary relation leq on some set X X which satisfies the following for all a b a b and c c in X X a a displaystyle a leq a reflexive If a b a leq b and b c displaystyle b leq c then a c displaystyle a leq c transitive If a b a leq b and b a displaystyle b leq a then a b a b antisymmetric a b a leq b or b a displaystyle b leq a strongly connected formerly called total Reflexivity 1 already follows from connectedness 4 but is required explicitly by many authors nevertheless to indicate the kinship to partial orders 1 Total orders are sometimes also called simple 2 connex 3 or full orders 4 A set equipped with a total order is a totally ordered set 5 the terms simply ordered set 2 linearly ordered set 3 5 and loset 6 7 are also used The term chain is sometimes defined as a synonym of totally ordered set 5 but refers generally to some sort of totally ordered subsets of a given partially ordered set An extension of a given partial order to a total order is called a linear extension of that partial order Contents 1 Strict and non strict total orders 2 Examples 3 Chains 4 Further concepts 4 1 Lattice theory 4 2 Finite total orders 4 3 Category theory 4 4 Order topology 4 5 Completeness 4 6 Sums of orders 4 7 Decidability 5 Orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets 6 Related structures 7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 10 External linksStrict and non strict total orders EditA strict total order on a set X X is a strict partial order on X X in which any two distinct elements are comparable That is a strict total order is a binary relation lt lt on some set X X which satisfies the following for all a b a b and c c in X X Not a lt a displaystyle a lt a irreflexive If a lt b a lt b then not b lt a displaystyle b lt a asymmetric If a lt b a lt b and b lt c b lt c then a lt c a lt c transitive If a b a neq b then a lt b a lt b or b lt a b lt a connected Asymmetry follows from transitivity and irreflexivity 8 moreover irreflexivity follows from asymmetry 9 For delimitation purposes a total order as defined in the lead is sometimes called non strict order For each non strict total order leq there is an associated relation lt lt called the strict total order associated with leq that can be defined in two equivalent ways a lt b a lt b if a b a leq b and a b a neq b reflexive reduction a lt b a lt b if not b a displaystyle b leq a i e lt lt is the complement of the converse of leq Conversely the reflexive closure of a strict total order lt lt is a non strict total order Examples EditAny subset of a totally ordered set X is totally ordered for the restriction of the order on X The unique order on the empty set is a total order Any set of cardinal numbers or ordinal numbers more strongly these are well orders If X is any set and f an injective function from X to a totally ordered set then f induces a total ordering on X by setting x1 x2 if and only if f x1 f x2 The lexicographical order on the Cartesian product of a family of totally ordered sets indexed by a well ordered set is itself a total order The set of real numbers ordered by the usual less than or equal to or greater than or equal to relations is totally ordered Hence each subset of the real numbers is totally ordered such as the natural numbers integers and rational numbers Each of these can be shown to be the unique up to an order isomorphism initial example of a totally ordered set with a certain property here a total order A is initial for a property if whenever B has the property there is an order isomorphism from A to a subset of B 10 citation needed The natural numbers form an initial non empty totally ordered set with no upper bound The integers form an initial non empty totally ordered set with neither an upper nor a lower bound The rational numbers form an initial totally ordered set which is dense in the real numbers Moreover the reflexive reduction lt is a dense order on the rational numbers The real numbers form an initial unbounded totally ordered set that is connected in the order topology defined below Ordered fields are totally ordered by definition They include the rational numbers and the real numbers Every ordered field contains an ordered subfield that is isomorphic to the rational numbers Any Dedekind complete ordered field is isomorphic to the real numbers The letters of the alphabet ordered by the standard dictionary order e g A lt B lt C etc is a strict total order Chains EditThe term chain is sometimes defined as a synonym for a totally ordered set but it is generally used for referring to a subset of a partially ordered set that is totally ordered for the induced order 1 11 Typically the partially ordered set is a set of subsets of a given set that is ordered by inclusion and the term is used for stating properties of the set of the chains This high number of nested levels of sets explains the usefulness of the term A common example of the use of chain for referring to totally ordered subsets is Zorn s lemma which asserts that if every chain in a partially ordered set X has an upper bound in X then X contains at least one maximal element 12 Zorn s lemma is commonly used with X being a set of subsets in this case the upperbound is obtained by proving that the union of the elements of a chain in X is in X This is the way that is generally used to prove that a vector space has Hamel bases and that a ring has maximal ideals In some contexts the chains that are considered are order isomorphic to the natural numbers with their usual order or its opposite order In this case a chain can be identified with a monotone sequence and is called an ascending chain or a descending chain depending whether the sequence is increasing or decreasing 13 A partially ordered set has the descending chain condition if every descending chain eventually stabilizes 14 For example an order is well founded if it has the descending chain condition Similarly the ascending chain condition means that every ascending chain eventually stabilizes For example a Noetherian ring is a ring whose ideals satisfy the ascending chain condition In other contexts only chains that are finite sets are considered In this case one talks of a finite chain often shortened as a chain In this case the length of a chain is the number of inequalities or set inclusions between consecutive elements of the chain that is the number minus one of elements in the chain 15 Thus a singleton set is a chain of length zero and an ordered pair is a chain of length one The dimension of a space is often defined or characterized as the maximal length of chains of subspaces For example the dimension of a vector space is the maximal length of chains of linear subspaces and the Krull dimension of a commutative ring is the maximal length of chains of prime ideals Chain may also be used for some totally ordered subsets of structures that are not partially ordered sets An example is given by regular chains of polynomials Another example is the use of chain as a synonym for a walk in a graph Further concepts EditLattice theory Edit One may define a totally ordered set as a particular kind of lattice namely one in which we have a b a b a b a vee b a wedge b a b for all a b We then write a b if and only if a a b a a wedge b Hence a totally ordered set is a distributive lattice Finite total orders Edit A simple counting argument will verify that any non empty finite totally ordered set and hence any non empty subset thereof has a least element Thus every finite total order is in fact a well order Either by direct proof or by observing that every well order is order isomorphic to an ordinal one may show that every finite total order is order isomorphic to an initial segment of the natural numbers ordered by lt In other words a total order on a set with k elements induces a bijection with the first k natural numbers Hence it is common to index finite total orders or well orders with order type w by natural numbers in a fashion which respects the ordering either starting with zero or with one Category theory Edit Totally ordered sets form a full subcategory of the category of partially ordered sets with the morphisms being maps which respect the orders i e maps f such that if a b then f a f b A bijective map between two totally ordered sets that respects the two orders is an isomorphism in this category Order topology Edit For any totally ordered set X we can define the open intervals a b x a lt x and x lt b b x x lt b a x a lt x and X We can use these open intervals to define a topology on any ordered set the order topology When more than one order is being used on a set one talks about the order topology induced by a particular order For instance if N is the natural numbers lt is less than and gt greater than we might refer to the order topology on N induced by lt and the order topology on N induced by gt in this case they happen to be identical but will not in general The order topology induced by a total order may be shown to be hereditarily normal Completeness Edit A totally ordered set is said to be complete if every nonempty subset that has an upper bound has a least upper bound For example the set of real numbers R is complete but the set of rational numbers Q is not In other words the various concepts of completeness not to be confused with being total do not carry over to restrictions For example over the real numbers a property of the relation is that every non empty subset S of R with an upper bound in R has a least upper bound also called supremum in R However for the rational numbers this supremum is not necessarily rational so the same property does not hold on the restriction of the relation to the rational numbers There are a number of results relating properties of the order topology to the completeness of X If the order topology on X is connected X is complete X is connected under the order topology if and only if it is complete and there is no gap in X a gap is two points a and b in X with a lt b such that no c satisfies a lt c lt b X is complete if and only if every bounded set that is closed in the order topology is compact A totally ordered set with its order topology which is a complete lattice is compact Examples are the closed intervals of real numbers e g the unit interval 0 1 and the affinely extended real number system extended real number line There are order preserving homeomorphisms between these examples Sums of orders Edit For any two disjoint total orders A 1 1 A 1 leq 1 and A 2 2 A 2 leq 2 there is a natural order leq on the set A 1 A 2 A 1 cup A 2 which is called the sum of the two orders or sometimes just A 1 A 2 A 1 A 2 For x y A 1 A 2 x y in A 1 cup A 2 x y x leq y holds if and only if one of the following holds x y A 1 x y in A 1 and x 1 y x leq 1 y x y A 2 x y in A 2 and x 2 y x leq 2 y x A 1 x in A 1 and y A 2 y in A 2 Intuitively this means that the elements of the second set are added on top of the elements of the first set More generally if I I leq is a totally ordered index set and for each i I i in I the structure A i i A i leq i is a linear order where the sets A i A i are pairwise disjoint then the natural total order on i A i bigcup i A i is defined by For x y i I A i x y in bigcup i in I A i x y x leq y holds if Either there is some i I i in I with x i y x leq i y or there are some i lt j i lt j in I I with x A i x in A i y A j y in A j Decidability Edit The first order theory of total orders is decidable i e there is an algorithm for deciding which first order statements hold for all total orders Using interpretability in S2S the monadic second order theory of countable total orders is also decidable 16 Orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets EditIn order of increasing strength i e decreasing sets of pairs three of the possible orders on the Cartesian product of two totally ordered sets are Lexicographical order a b c d if and only if a lt c or a c and b d This is a total order a b c d if and only if a c and b d the product order This is a partial order a b c d if and only if a lt c and b lt d or a c and b d the reflexive closure of the direct product of the corresponding strict total orders This is also a partial order All three can similarly be defined for the Cartesian product of more than two sets Applied to the vector space Rn each of these make it an ordered vector space See also examples of partially ordered sets A real function of n real variables defined on a subset of Rn defines a strict weak order and a corresponding total preorder on that subset Related structures EditTransitive binary relations vteSymmetricAntisymmetricConnectedWell foundedHas joinsHas meetsReflexiveIrreflexiveAsymmetricTotal SemiconnexAnti reflexiveEquivalence relation Y Y Preorder Quasiorder Y Partial order Y Y Total preorder Y Y Total order Y Y Y Prewellordering Y Y Y Well quasi ordering Y Y Well ordering Y Y Y Y Lattice Y Y Y Y Join semilattice Y Y Y Meet semilattice Y Y Y Strict partial order Y Y YStrict weak order Y Y YStrict total order Y Y Y YSymmetricAntisymmetricConnectedWell foundedHas joinsHas meetsReflexiveIrreflexiveAsymmetricDefinitions for all a b a b and S displaystyle S neq varnothing a R b b R a displaystyle begin aligned amp aRb Rightarrow amp bRa end aligned a R b and b R a a b displaystyle begin aligned aRb text and amp bRa Rightarrow a amp b end aligned a b a R b or b R a displaystyle begin aligned a neq amp b Rightarrow aRb text or amp bRa end aligned min S exists displaystyle begin aligned min S text exists end aligned a b exists displaystyle begin aligned a vee b text exists end aligned a b exists displaystyle begin aligned a wedge b text exists end aligned a R a displaystyle aRa not a R a displaystyle text not aRa a R b not b R a displaystyle begin aligned aRb Rightarrow text not bRa end aligned Y indicates that the column s property is always true the row s term at the very left while indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general it might or might not hold For example that every equivalence relation is symmetric but not necessarily antisymmetric is indicated by Y in the Symmetric column and in the Antisymmetric column respectively All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation R R be transitive for all a b c a b c if a R b displaystyle aRb and b R c displaystyle bRc then a R c displaystyle aRc A term s definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table A binary relation that is antisymmetric transitive and reflexive but not necessarily total is a partial order A group with a compatible total order is a totally ordered group There are only a few nontrivial structures that are interdefinable as reducts of a total order Forgetting the orientation results in a betweenness relation Forgetting the location of the ends results in a cyclic order Forgetting both data results in a separation relation 17 See also EditArtinian ring ring that satisfies the descending chain condition on idealsPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Countryman line Order theory Branch of mathematics Permutation Mathematical version of an order change Prefix order generalization of the notion of prefix of a string and of the notion of a treePages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback a downward total partial order Suslin s problem the proposition independent of ZFC that a nonempty unbounded complete dense total order satisfying the countable chain condition is isomorphic to the realsPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Well order Class of mathematical orderingsNotes Edit a b Halmos 1968 Ch 14 a b Birkhoff 1967 p 2 a b Schmidt amp Strohlein 1993 p 32 Fuchs 1963 p 2 a b c Davey amp Priestley 1990 p 3 Strohmeier Alfred Genillard Christian Weber Mats 1 August 1990 Ordering of characters and strings ACM SIGAda Ada Letters 7 84 doi 10 1145 101120 101136 S2CID 38115497 Ganapathy Jayanthi 1992 Maximal Elements and Upper Bounds in Posets Pi Mu Epsilon Journal 9 7 462 464 ISSN 0031 952X JSTOR 24340068 Let a lt b displaystyle a lt b assume for contradiction that also b lt a displaystyle b lt a Then a lt a displaystyle a lt a by transitivity which contradicts irreflexivity If a lt a displaystyle a lt a the not a lt a displaystyle a lt a by asymmetry This definition resembles that of an initial object of a category but is weaker Roland Fraisse December 2000 Theory of Relations Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics Vol 145 1st ed Elsevier ISBN 978 0 444 50542 2 Here p 35 Brian A Davey and Hilary Ann Priestley 1990 Introduction to Lattices and Order Cambridge Mathematical Textbooks Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 36766 2 LCCN 89009753 Here p 100 Yiannis N Moschovakis 2006 Notes on set theory Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics Birkhauser ISBN 0 387 28723 X p 116 that is beyond some index all further sequence members are equal Davey and Priestly 1990 Def 2 24 p 37 Weyer Mark 2002 Decidability of S1S and S2S Automata Logics and Infinite Games Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 2500 Springer pp 207 230 doi 10 1007 3 540 36387 4 12 ISBN 978 3 540 00388 5 Macpherson H Dugald 2011 A survey of homogeneous structures Discrete Mathematics 311 15 1599 1634 doi 10 1016 j disc 2011 01 024References EditBirkhoff Garrett 1967 Lattice Theory Colloquium Publications Vol 25 Providence Am Math Soc Davey Brian A Priestley Hilary Ann 1990 Introduction to Lattices and Order Cambridge Mathematical Textbooks Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 36766 2 LCCN 89009753 Fuchs L 1963 Partially Ordered Algebraic Systems Pergamon Press George Gratzer 1971 Lattice theory first concepts and distributive lattices W H Freeman and Co ISBN 0 7167 0442 0 Halmos Paul R 1968 Naive Set Theory Princeton Nostrand John G Hocking and Gail S Young 1961 Topology Corrected reprint Dover 1988 ISBN 0 486 65676 4 Rosenstein Joseph G 1982 Linear orderings New York Academic Press Schmidt Gunther Strohlein Thomas 1993 Relations and Graphs Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists Berlin Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 642 77970 1 External links Edit Totally ordered set Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Total order amp oldid 1167123253, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.