fbpx
Wikipedia

Existence

Existence is the state of being real or participating in reality. The terms "being", "reality", and "actuality" are often used as close synonyms. Existence contrasts with nonexistence, nothingness, and nonbeing. A common distinction is between the existence of an entity and its essence, which refers to the entity's nature or essential qualities.

Ontology is the philosophical discipline studying what existence is. The orthodox view is that it is a second-order property or a property of properties. According to this view, to say that a thing exists means that its properties are instantiated. A different view holds that existence is a first-order property or a property of individuals. This means that existence has the same ontological status as other properties of individuals, like color and shape. Meinongians accept this idea and hold that not all individuals have this property: they state that there are some individuals that do not exist. This view is rejected by universalists, who see existence as a universal property of every individual.

Various types of existence are discussed in the academic literature. Singular existence is the existence of individual entities while general existence refers to the existence of concepts or universals. Other distinctions are between abstract and concrete existence, between possible, contingent, and necessary existence, and between physical and mental existence. A closely related issue is whether different types of entities exist in different ways or to different degrees.

A key question in ontology is whether there is a reason for existence in general or why anything at all exists. The concept of existence is relevant to various fields, including logic, epistemology, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, and existentialism.

Definition and related terms edit

Existence is the state of being real. To exist means to have being or to participate in reality.[1] Existence is what sets real entities apart from imaginary ones.[2] It can refer both to individual entities or to the totality of reality.[3] The word "existence" entered the English language in the late 14th century from old French. It has its roots in the medieval Latin term ex(s)istere, which means to stand forth, to appear, and to arise.[4] Existence is studied by the subdiscipline of metaphysics known as ontology.[5]

The terms "being", "reality", and "actuality" are closely related to existence.[6] They are usually used as synonyms of "existence" but their meanings as technical terms may come apart.[7] According to metaphysicist Alexius Meinong, for example, all entities have being but not all have existence. He argues that merely possible objects, like Santa Clause, have being but lack existence.[8] Ontologist Takashi Yagisawa contrasts existence with reality. He sees "reality" as the more fundamental term since it characterizes all entities equally. He defines existence as a relative term that connects an entity to the world that it inhabits.[9] According to Gottlob Frege, actuality is more narrow than existence. He holds that actual entities can produce and undergo changes. He states that some existing entities are non-actual, like numbers and sets.[10]

Existence contrasts with nonexistence, which refers to a lack of reality. It is controversial whether objects can be divided into existent and nonexistent objects. This distinction is sometimes used to explain how it is possible to think of fictional objects, like dragons and unicorns. But the concept of nonexistent objects is not generally accepted.[11] Closely related contrasting terms are nothingness and nonbeing.[12]

Another contrast is between existence and essence. Essence refers to the intrinsic nature or defining qualities of an entity. The essence of something determines what kind of entity it is and how it differs from other kinds of entities. Essence corresponds to what an entity is while existence corresponds to the fact that it is. For instance, it is possible to understand what an object is and grasp its nature even if one does not know whether this object exists.[13]

Some philosophers, like Edmund Husserl and Quentin Boyce Gibson, hold that existence is an elementary concept. This means that it cannot be defined in other terms without involving circularity. This would imply that it may be difficult or impossible to characterize existence or to talk about its nature in a non-trivial manner.[14]

A closely related issue concerns the distinction between thin and thick concepts of existence. Thin concepts understand existence as a logical property that every existing thing shares. It does not include any substantial content about the metaphysical implications of having existence. An example of a thin concept of existence is to state that existence is the same as the logical property of self-identity.[15] Thick concepts of existence encompass a metaphysical analysis of what it means that something exists and what essential features existence implies. For example, George Berkeley's claim that esse est percipi presents a thick concept of existence. It can be translated as "to be is to be perceived" and highlights the mental nature of all existence.[16]

Some philosophers emphasize that there is a difference between the entities that exist and existence itself.[17] This distinction plays a central role in the philosophy of Martin Heidegger, who calls it the ontological difference.[18]

Theories of the nature of existence edit

 
One of the topics covered by theories of the nature of existence concerns the ontological status of fictional objects like Pegasus.[19]

Theories of the nature of existence aim to explain what it means for something to exist. The central dispute regarding the nature of existence is whether it should be understood as a property of individuals.[20]

The two main theories of existence are first-order theories and second-order theories. First-order theories understand existence as a property of individuals. Some first-order theories see it as a property of all individuals while others hold that there are some individuals that do not exist. Second-order theories hold that existence is a second-order property, that is, a property of properties.[21]

A central challenge for the different theories of the nature of existence is to understand how it is possible to coherently deny the existence of something. An example is the sentence "Santa Claus does not exist". One difficulty consists in explaining how the name "Santa Claus" can be meaningful even though there is no Santa Claus.[22]

Second-order theories edit

Second-order theories are often seen as the orthodox position. They understand existence as a second-order property rather than a first-order property.[23] For instance, the Empire State Building is an individual object and being 443.2 meters tall is a first-order property of it. Being instantiated is a property of being 443.2 meters tall and therefore a second-order property. According to second-order theories, to talk about existence is to talk about which properties have instances.[24] For example, this view states that the sentence "God exists" does not claim that God has the property of existing. Instead, it means "Godhood is instantiated".[2]

A key motivation of second-order theories is that existence is in important ways different from regular properties like being a building and being 443.2 meters tall: regular properties express what an object is like but existence does not.[25] According to this view, existence is more fundamental than regular properties since, without it, objects cannot instantiate any properties.[26]

Second-order theorists usually hold that quantifiers rather than predicates express existence.[27] Quantifiers are terms that talk about the quantity of objects that have certain properties. Existential quantifiers express that there is at least one object. Examples are expressions like "some" and "there exists", as in "some cows eat grass" and "there exists an even prime number".[28] In this regard, existence is closely related to counting since to claim that something exists is to claim that the corresponding concept has one or more instances.[29]

Second-order views imply that a sentence like "egg-laying mammals exist" is misleading since the word "exist" is used as a predicate in them. They hold instead that their true logical form is better expressed in reformulations like "there exist entities that are egg-laying mammals". This way, existence has the role of a quantifier while egg-laying mammals is the predicate. Quantifier constructions can also be used to express negative existential statements. For instance, the sentence "talking tigers do not exist" can be expressed as "it is not the case that there exist talking tigers".[30]

Many ontologists accept that second-order theories provide a correct analysis of many types of existential sentences. However, it is controversial whether it is correct for all cases.[31] One difficulty is caused by so-called negative singular existentials. Negative singular existentials are statements that deny that a particular object exists. An example is the sentence "Ronald McDonald does not exist". Singular terms, like Ronald McDonald, seem to refer to individuals. This poses a difficulty since negative singular existentials deny that this individual exists. This makes it unclear how the singular term can refer to the individual in the first place. One influential solution to this problem was proposed by Bertrand Russell. He holds that singular terms do not directly refer to individuals but are instead descriptions of individuals. Positive singular existentials affirm that an object matching the descriptions exists while negative singular existentials deny that an object matching the descriptions exists. According to this view, the sentence "Ronald McDonald does not exist" expresses the idea that "it is not the case that there is a unique happy hamburger clown".[32]

First-order theories edit

First-order theories claim that existence is a property of individuals. They are less widely accepted than second-order theories but also have some influential proponents. There are two types of first-order theories. According to Meinongianism, existence is a property of some but not all entities. This view implies that there are nonexistent entities. According to universalism, existence is a universal property instantiated by every entity.[33]

Meinongianism edit

Meinongianism is a view about existence defended by Meinong and his followers. Its main claim is that there are some entities that do not exist. This means that objecthood is independent of existence. Proposed examples of nonexistent objects are merely possible objects, like flying pigs, as well as fictional and mythical objects, like Sherlock Holmes and Zeus. According to this view, these objects are real and have being even though they do not exist.[34] Meinong states that there is an object for any combination of properties. For example, there is an object that only has the single property of being a singer without any additional properties. This object neither has the property of wearing a dress nor the property of not wearing a dress. Meinong also includes impossible objects, like round squares.[35]

Meinongians state that sentences describing what Sherlock Holmes and Zeus are like refer to nonexisting objects. They are true or false depending on whether these objects have the properties ascribed to them.[36] For instance, the sentence "Pegasus has wings" is true because having wings is a property of Pegasus, even though Pegasus lacks the property of existing.[37]

One key motivation of Meinongianism is to explain how negative singular existentials, like "Ronald McDonald does not exist", can be true. Meinongians accept the idea that singular terms, like "Ronald McDonald" refer to individuals. For them, a negative singular existential is true if the individual it refers to does not exist.[38]

Meinongianism has important implications for how to understand quantification. According to an influential view defended by Willard Van Orman Quine, the domain of quantification is restricted to existing objects. This view implies that quantifiers carry ontological commitments about what exists and what does not exist. Meinongianism differs from this view by holding that the widest domain of quantification includes both existing and nonexisting objects.[19]

Some aspects of Meinongianism are controversial and have received substantial criticism. According to one objection, one cannot distinguish between being an object and being an existing object.[37] A closely related criticism rests on the idea that objects cannot have properties if they do not exist.[37] A further objection is that Meinongianism leads to an "overpopulated universe" since there is an object corresponding to any combination of properties.[19] A more specific criticism rejects the idea that there are incomplete and impossible objects.[39]

Universalism edit

Universalists agree with Meinongians that existence is a property of individuals. But they deny that there are nonexistent entities. They state instead that existence is a universal property: all entities have it, meaning that everything exists. One approach is to hold that existence is the same as self-identity. According to the law of identity, every object is identical to itself or has the property of self-identity. This can be expressed in predicate logic as  .[40]

An influential argument in favor of universalism rests on the claim that to deny the existence of something is contradictory. This conclusion follows from the premises that one can only deny the existence of something by referring to that entity and that one can only refer to entities that exist.[40]

Universalists have proposed different ways of interpreting negative singular existentials. According to one view, names of fictional entities like "Ronald McDonald" refer to abstract objects. Abstract objects exist even though they do not exist in space and time. This means that, when understood in a strict sense, all negative singular existentials are false, including the claim that "Ronald McDonald does not exist". However, universalists can interpret such sentences slightly differently in relation to the context. In everyday life, for example, people use sentences like "Ronald McDonald does not exist" to express the idea that Ronald McDonald does not exist as a concrete object, which is true.[41] A different approach is to claim that negative singular existentials lack a truth value since their singular terms do not refer to anything. According to this view, they are neither true nor false but meaningless.[42]

Types of existing entities edit

Different types of existing entities are discussed in the academic literature. Many discussions revolve around the questions of what those types are, whether entities of a specific type exist, how entities of different types are related to each other, and whether some types are more fundamental than others.[43] Examples are questions like whether souls exist, whether there are abstract, fictional, and universal entities, and whether besides the actual world and its objects, there are also possible worlds and objects.[44]

Singular and general edit

One distinction is between singular and general existence. Singular existence is the existence of individual entities. For example, the sentence "Angela Merkel exists" expresses the existence of one particular person. General existence pertains to general concepts, properties, or universals. For instance, the sentence "politicians exist" states that the general term "politician" has instances without referring to any one politician in particular.[45]

Singular and general existence are closely related to each other and some philosophers have tried to explain one as a special case of the other. For example, Frege held that general existence is more basic. One argument in favor of this position is that general existence can be expressed in terms of singular existence. For instance, the sentence "Angela Merkel exists" can be expressed as "entities exist that are identical to Angela Merkel", where the expression "being identical to Angela Merkel" is understood as a general term. A different position is defended by Quine, who gives primacy to singular existence.[46] A related question is whether there can be general existence without singular existence. According to philosophers like Henry S. Leonard, a property only has general existence if there is at least one actual object that instantiates it. A different view, defended by Nicholas Rescher, holds that properties can even exist if they have no actual instances, like the property of being a unicorn.[47]

This question has a long philosophical tradition in relation to the existence of universals. Platonists claim that universals have general existence as Platonic forms independently of the particulars that instantiate them. According to this view, the universal of redness exists independent of whether there are any red objects.[48] Aristotelianism also accepts that universals exist. However, it holds that their existence depends on particulars that instantiate them and that they are unable to exist by themselves. According to this view, a universal that has no instances in the spacio-temporal world does not exist.[49] Nominalists claim that only particulars have existence and deny that universals exist.[50]

Concrete and abstract edit

Another influential distinction in ontology is between concrete and abstract objects. Many concrete objects are encountered in regular everyday life, like rocks, plants, and other people. They exist in space and time and influence each other: they have causal powers and are affected by other concrete objects. Abstract objects exist outside space and time and lack causal powers. Examples of abstract objects are numbers, sets, and types.[51] The distinction between concrete and abstract objects is sometimes treated as the most general division of being.[52]

There is wide agreement that concrete objects exist but opinions are divided in regard to abstract objects. Realists accept the idea that abstract objects have independent existence.[53] Some of them claim that abstract objects have the same mode of existence as concrete objects while others maintain that they exist but in a different way.[54] Antirealists state that abstract objects do not exist. This is often combined with the view that existence requires a location in space and time or the ability to causally interact.[55]

Fictional objects, like dragons and centaurs, are closely related to abstract objects and pose similar problems. However, the two terms are not identical. For example, the expression "the integer between two and three" refers to a fictional abstract object while the expression "integer between two and four" refers to a non-fictional abstract object. In a similar sense, there are also concrete fictional objects besides abstract fictional objects, like the winged horse of Bellerophon.[56]

Possible, contingent, and necessary edit

A further distinction is between merely possible, contingent, and necessary existence.[57] An entity has necessary existence if it must exist or could not fail to exist. Entities that exist but could fail to exist are contingent. Merely possible entities are entities that do not exist but could exist.[58]

Most entities encountered in ordinary experience, like telephones, sticks, and flowers, have contingent existence.[59] It is an open question whether any entities have necessary existence. According to one view, all concrete objects have contingent existence while all abstract objects have necessary existence.[60] According to some theorists, one or several necessary beings are required as the explanatory foundation of the cosmos. For instance, philosophers like Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas follow this idea and claim that God has necessary existence.[61]

There are many academic debates about whether there are merely possible objects. According to actualism, only actual entities have being. This includes both contingent and necessary entities. But it excludes merely possible entities.[62] This view is rejected by possibilists, who state that there are also merely possible objects besides actual objects.[63] For example, David Lewis argues that possible objects exist in the same way as actual objects. According to him, possible objects exist in possible worlds while actual objects exist in the actual world. Lewis holds that the only difference between possible worlds and the actual world is the location of the speaker: the term "actual" refers to the world of the speaker, similar to how the terms "here" and "now" refer to the spatial and temporal location of the speaker.[2]

Physical and mental edit

A further distinction is between entities that exist on a physical level in contrast to mental entities.[64] Physical entities include objects of regular perception, like stones, trees, and human bodies as well as entities discussed in modern physics, like electrons and protons. Physical entities can be observed and measured. They possess mass and a location in space and time.[65] Mental entities belong to the realm of the mind, like perceptions, experiences of pleasure and pain as well as beliefs, desires, and emotions. They are primarily associated with conscious experiences but also include unconscious states, like unconscious beliefs, desires, and memories.[66]

The ontological status of physical and mental entities is a frequent topic in metaphysics and philosophy of mind. According to materialists, only physical entities exist on the most fundamental level. Materialists usually explain mental entities in terms of physical processes, for example, as brain states or as patterns of neural activation. Idealists reject this view and state that mind is the ultimate foundation of existence. They hold that physical entities have a derivative form of existence, for instance, that they are mental representations or products of consciousness. Dualists believe that both physical and mental entities exist on the most fundamental level. They state that they are connected to one another in various ways but that one cannot be reduced to the other.[67]

Modes and degrees of existence edit

Closely related to the problem of different types of entities is the question of whether they differ also concerning their mode of existence. This is the case according to ontological pluralism. In this view, entities belonging to different types do not just differ in their essential features but also in the way they exist.[68]

This position is sometimes found in theology. It states that God is radically different from his creation and emphasizes his uniqueness by holding that the difference affects not just God's features but also God's mode of existence.[69]

Another form of ontological pluralism distinguishes the existence of material objects from the existence of spacetime. This view holds that material objects have relative existence since they exist in spacetime. It further states that the existence of spacetime itself is not relative in this sense since it just exists without existing within another spacetime.[70]

The topic of degrees of existence is closely related to the issue of modes of existence. This topic is based on the idea that some entities exist to a higher degree or have more being than other entities. It is similar to how some properties have degrees, like heat and mass. According to Plato, for example, unchangeable Platonic forms have a higher degree of existence than physical objects.[71]

While the view that there are different types of entities is common in metaphysics, the idea they differ from each other concerning their modes or degrees of existence is not generally accepted.[72] For instance, philosopher Quentin Gibson maintains that a thing either exists or does not exist. This means that there is no alternative in between and that there are no degrees of existence.[73] Peter van Inwagen uses the idea that there is an intimate relation between existence and quantification to argue against different modes of existence. Quantification is related to how people count objects. Inwagen argues that if there were different modes of entities then people would need different types of numbers to count them. Since the same numbers can be used to count different types of entities, he concludes that all entities have the same mode of existence.[74]

Why anything exists at all edit

A central question in ontology is why anything exists at all or why there is something rather than nothing.[75] Similar questions are "why is there a world?" and "why are there individual things?". These questions focus on the idea that many things that exist are contingent, meaning they could have failed to exist. It asks whether this applies to existence as a whole as well or whether there is a reason why something exists instead of nothing.[76]

This question is different from scientific questions that seek to explain the existence of one thing, like life, in relation to the existence of another thing, like the primordial soup which may have been its origin. It is also different from most religious creation myths that explain the existence of the material world in relation to a god or gods that created it. The difference lies in the fact that these theories explain the existence of one thing in terms of the existence of another thing instead of trying to explain existence in general. The additional difficulty of the ontological question lies in the fact that one cannot refer to any other existing entity without engaging in circular reasoning.[77]

One answer to the question of why there is anything at all is called the statistical argument. It is based on the idea that besides the actual world, there are many possible worlds. They differ from the actual world in various respects. For example, the Eiffel Tower exists in the actual world but there are possible worlds without the Eiffel Tower. There are countless variations of possible worlds but there is only one possible world that is empty, i.e., that does not contain any entities. This means that, if it was up to chance which possible world becomes actual, the chance that there is nothing is exceedingly small.[78] A closely related argument in physics explains the existence of the world as the result of random quantum fluctuations.[79]

Another response is to deny that a reason or an explanation for existence in general can be found. According to this view, existence as a whole is absurd since it is there without a reason for being there.[80]

Not all theorists accept this question as a valid or philosophically interesting question. Some philosophers, like Graham Priest and Kris McDaniel, have suggested that the term nothing refers to a global absence, which can itself be understood as a form of existence. According to this view, the answer to the question is trivial, since there is always something, even if this something is just a global absence.[81] A closely related response is to claim that an empty world is metaphysically impossible. According to this view, there is something rather than nothing because it is necessary for some things to exist.[82]

History edit

Western philosophy edit

Western philosophy originated with the Presocratic philosophers, who explored the foundational principles of all existence. Some, like Thales and Heraclitus, suggested that concrete principles, like water or fire, are the root of existence. This position was opposed by Anaximander, who held that the source must lie in an abstract principle beyond the world of human perception.[83]

Plato argued that different types of entities have different degrees of existence. He held that shadows and images exist in a weaker sense than regular material objects. He claimed that the unchangeable Platonic forms have the highest type of existence. He saw material objects as imperfect and impermanent copies of Platonic forms.[84]

 
Aristotle held that different types of entities have different modes of existence.

While Aristotle accepted Plato's idea that forms are different from matter, he challenged the idea that forms have a higher type of existence. Instead, he held that forms cannot exist without matter.[85] Aristotle further claimed that different entities have different modes of existence. For example, he distinguished between substances and their accidents and between potentiality and actuality.[86]

Neoplatonists, like Plotinus, suggested that reality has a hierarchical structure. They held that a transcendent entity called "the One" or "the Good" is responsible for all existence. From it emerges the intellect, which in turn gives rise to the soul and the material world.[87]

 
Anselm of Canterbury is known for his formulation of the ontological argument aiming to prove the existence of God.

In medieval philosophy, Anselm of Canterbury formulated the influential ontological argument. This argument aims to deduce the existence of God from the concept of God. Anselm defined God as the greatest conceivable being. He reasoned that an entity that did not exist outside his mind would not be the greatest conceivable being. This led him to the conclusion that God exists.[88]

Thomas Aquinas distinguished between the essence of a thing and its existence. According to him, the essence of a thing constitutes its fundamental nature. He argued that it is possible to understand what an object is and grasp its essence even if one does not know whether this object exists. He concluded from this observation that existence is not part of the qualities of an object and should instead be understood as a separate property.[20] Aquinas also considered the problem of creation from nothing. He claimed that only God has the power to truly bring new entities into existence. These ideas later inspired Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz's theory of creation. He held that to create is to confer actual existence to possible objects.[89]

Both David Hume and Immanuel Kant rejected the idea that existence is a property. According to Hume, objects are bundles of qualities. He held that existence is not a property since there is no impression of existence besides the bundled qualities.[90] Kant came to a similar conclusion in his criticism of the ontological argument. According to him, this proof fails because one cannot deduce from the definition of a concept whether entities described by this concept exist. He held that existence does not add anything to the concept of the object, it only indicates that this concept is instantiated.[91]

 
Franz Brentano defended the idea that all judgments are existential judgments.

Franz Brentano agreed with Kant's criticism and his claim that existence is not a real predicate. He used this idea to develop his theory of judgments. According to him, all judgments are existential judgments: they either affirm or deny the existence of something. He stated that judgments like "some zebras are striped" have the logical form "there is a striped zebra" while judgments like "all zebras are striped" have the logical form "there is not a non-striped zebra".[92]

Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell aimed to refine the idea of what it means that existence is not a regular property. They distinguished between regular first-order properties of individuals and second-order properties of other properties. According to this view, to talk about existence is to talk about the second-order property of being instantiated. For instance, to deny that dinosaurs exist means that the property of being a dinosaur has the property of not being instantiated.[93] According to Russell, the fundamental form of predication happens by applying a predicate to the proper name of an individual. An example of this type of atomic proposition is "Laika is a dog". Russell held that talk of existence in the form of sentences like "dogs exist" is less fundamental since it means that there is an individual to which this predicate applies without naming this individual.[94]

Willard Van Orman Quine followed Frege and Russell in accepting that existence is a second-order property. He drew a close link between existence and the role of quantification in formal logic.[95] He applied this idea to scientific theories and stated that a scientific theory is committed to the existence of an entity if the theory quantifies over this entity. For example, if a theory in biology claims that "there are populations with genetic diversity" then this theory has an ontological commitment to the existence of populations with genetic diversity.[96]

Despite the influence of second-order theories, this view was not universally accepted. Alexius Meinong rejected it and claimed that existence is a property of individuals and that not all individuals have this property. This led him to the thesis that there is a difference between being and existence: all individuals have being but only some of them also exist. This implies that there are some things that do not exist, like merely possible objects and impossible objects.[97]

Eastern philosophy edit

 
Adi Shankara taught that only the divine exists on the most fundamental level and that the impression of a multiplicity of different entities is an illusion.

Many schools of thought in Eastern philosophy discuss the problem of existence and its implications. For instance, the ancient Hindu school of Samkhya developed a metaphysical dualism. According to this view, there are two types of existence: pure consciousness (Purusha) and matter (Prakriti). Samkhya explains the manifestation of the universe as the interaction between these two principles.[98] A different approach was developed by Adi Shankara in his school of Advaita Vedanta. He defended a metaphysical monism by claiming that the divine (Brahman) is the ultimate reality and the only existent. According to this view, the impression that there is a universe consisting of many distinct entities is an illusion (Maya).[99] The essential features of ultimate reality are described as Sat Chit Ananda, meaning existence, consciousness, and bliss.[100]

A central doctrine in Buddhist philosophy is called the three marks of existence. The three marks are aniccā (impermanence), anattā (absence of a permanent self), and dukkha (suffering). Aniccā is the doctrine that all of existence is subject to change. This means everything transforms at some point and nothing lasts forever. Anattā expresses a similar state in relation to persons. It is the claim that people do not have a permanent identity or a separate self. Ignorance about aniccā and anattā is seen as the main cause of dukkha by leading people to form attachments that cause suffering.[101]

 
Laozi saw the dao as a fundamental principle that constitutes the root of all existence.

A central idea in many schools of Chinese philosophy, like Laozi's Daoism, is that a fundamental principle known as dao is the source of all existence. The term is often translated as "the Way" and is understood as a cosmic force that governs the natural order of the world. One position in Chinese metaphysics holds that dao is itself a form of being while another contends that it is non-being that gives rise to being.[102]

The concept of existence played a central role in Arabic-Persian philosophy. Avicenna and Al-Ghazali discussed the relation between existence and essence. According to them, the essence of an entity is prior to its existence. The additional step of instantiating the essence is required for the entity to come into existence. Mulla Sadra rejected this priority of essence over existence. He argued that essence is only a concept used by the mind to grasp existence. Existence, by contrast, encompasses the whole of reality, according to his view.[103]

In various disciplines edit

Formal logic edit

Formal logic studies which arguments are deductively valid.[104] First-order logic is the most commonly used system of formal logic. In it, existence is expressed using the existential quantifier ( ). For example, the formula   can be used to state that horses exist. The variable x ranges over all elements in the domain of quantification and the existential quantifier expresses that at least one element in this domain is a horse. In first-order logic, all singular terms, like names, refer to objects in the domain and imply that the object exists. Because of this, one can deduce that   (someone is honest) from   (Bill is honest).[105]

Many logical systems that are based on first-order logic also follow this idea. Free logic is an exception. It allows there to be empty names that do not refer to any object in the domain.[106] One motivation for this modification is that reasoning is not limited to regular objects but can also be applied to fictional objects.[107] In free logic, for instance, one can express that Pegasus is a flying horse using the formula  . One consequence of this modification is that one cannot infer from this type of statement that something exists. This means that the inference from   to   is invalid in free logic even though it would be valid in first-order logic. Free logic uses an additional existence predicate ( ) to express that a singular term refers to an existing object. For example, the formula   can be used to express that Homer exists while the formula   states that Pegasus does not exist.[108]

Epistemology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language edit

The disciplines of epistemology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language aim to understand the nature of knowledge, mind, and language.[109] A key issue in these fields is the problem of reference. This problem concerns the question of how mental or linguistic representations can refer to existing objects. Examples of such representations are beliefs, thoughts, perceptions, words, and sentences. For instance, in the sentence "Barack Obama is a Democrat", the name "Barack Obama" refers to a particular individual. In relation to perception, the problem of reference concerns the question of whether or to what extent perceptual impressions bring the perceiver in contact with reality by presenting existing objects rather than illusions.[110]

Closely related to the problem of reference is the relation between truth and existence. Representations can be true or false. According to truthmaker theory, true representations require a truthmaker. A truthmaker of a representation is the entity whose existence is responsible for the fact that the representation is true. For example, the sentence "kangaroos live in Australia" is true because there are kangaroos in Australia: the existence of these kangaroos is the truthmaker of the sentence. Truthmaker theory states that there is a close relation between truth and existence: there exists a truthmaker for every true representation.[111]

Existentialism edit

Existentialism is a school of thought that explores the nature of human existence. One of its key ideas is that existence precedes essence. This claim expresses the notion that existence is more basic than essence and that the nature and purpose of human beings are not pregiven but develop in the process of living. According to this view, humans are thrown into a world that lacks preexistent intrinsic meaning. They have to determine for themselves what their purpose is and what meaning their life should have. Existentialists use this idea to focus on the role of freedom and responsibility in actively shaping one's life.[112]

See also edit

References edit

Citations edit

  1. ^
  2. ^ a b c Lowe 2005, existence.
  3. ^
  4. ^
  5. ^
  6. ^
  7. ^
  8. ^
  9. ^
  10. ^ Chakrabarti 2013, pp. 106–107.
  11. ^
  12. ^
  13. ^
  14. ^
  15. ^
  16. ^
  17. ^
  18. ^
  19. ^ a b c Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism.
  20. ^ a b Nelson 2022, lead section.
  21. ^
  22. ^
  23. ^
  24. ^
  25. ^
  26. ^ Nelson 2022, §1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals.
  27. ^
  28. ^ Fierro 2012, p. 37.
  29. ^
  30. ^ Penelope 1998, §2 The quantifier account of existence.
  31. ^
  32. ^
    • Nelson 2022, 1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals
    • Penelope 1998, §2 The quantifier account of existence
    • Nelson 2022, 1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals
  33. ^
  34. ^
  35. ^
  36. ^
  37. ^ a b c Penelope 1998, §1 Objects and existence.
  38. ^
  39. ^
  40. ^ a b Casati & Fujikawa, §2b. Universalism.
  41. ^
  42. ^ Nelson 2022, 3. An Anti-Meinongian First-Order View.
  43. ^
  44. ^
  45. ^
  46. ^ Lambert 1994, pp. 3–4.
  47. ^
  48. ^
  49. ^ Gibson 1998, p. 138.
  50. ^ Gibson 1998, pp. 3–4, 137.
  51. ^
  52. ^ Honderich 2005, Ontology.
  53. ^
  54. ^
  55. ^
  56. ^ Prior 2006, pp. 493, Existences.
  57. ^
  58. ^
  59. ^ Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 1–2.
  60. ^ Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 1–4.
  61. ^
  62. ^
  63. ^
  64. ^ Penelope 1998, lead section.
  65. ^
  66. ^
  67. ^
  68. ^
  69. ^
  70. ^ Casati & Fujikawa, §3. How Many Ways of Being Existent?.
  71. ^
  72. ^
  73. ^ Gibson 1998, pp. 5–8.
  74. ^
  75. ^
  76. ^
  77. ^
  78. ^
  79. ^ He, Gao & Cai 2014, p. 083510-1.
  80. ^
  81. ^ Casati & Fujikawa, §4. Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?.
  82. ^ Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 4–5.
  83. ^
  84. ^
  85. ^
  86. ^
  87. ^
  88. ^
  89. ^ Prior 2006, pp. 494, Existences.
  90. ^
  91. ^
  92. ^
  93. ^
  94. ^ Prior 2006, pp. 496–498, Existences.
  95. ^
  96. ^ Casati & Fujikawa, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification, §2a. Meinongianism.
  97. ^
  98. ^
  99. ^
  100. ^
  101. ^
  102. ^
  103. ^
  104. ^
  105. ^
  106. ^ Nolt 2021, lead section, §1. The Basics.
  107. ^ Nolt 2021, §5.4 Logics of Fiction.
  108. ^
  109. ^
  110. ^
  111. ^
  112. ^

Sources edit

  • Adamson, Peter (2015). Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 2. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-872802-3. from the original on 2023-07-11. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
  • Addis, Laird (2 May 2013). Mind: Ontology and Explanation: Collected Papers 1981-2005. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032715-1.
  • AHD staff (2022). "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: existence". www.ahdictionary.com. HarperCollins. Retrieved 10 August 2023.
  • Aho, Kevin (2023). "Existentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 August 2023.
  • Albertazzi, Liliana; Jacquette, Dale (5 July 2017). The School of Alexius Meinong. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-88226-2.
  • Asay, Jamin. "Truthmaker Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 August 2023.
  • Audi, Robert (2006). "Philosophy". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 7: Oakeshott - Presupposition (2. ed.). Thomson Gale, Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-865787-5. from the original on 2022-02-14.
  • Balaguer, Mark (2016). "Platonism in Metaphysics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 1. What is Platonism?.
  • Balthasar, Hans Urs von (1 January 2000). Theo-Logic, Vol. 1: Truth of the World. Ignatius Press. ISBN 978-0-89870-718-2.
  • Belfiore, Francesco (17 November 2016). The Triadic Structure of the Mind: Outlines of a Philosophical System. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7618-6857-6.
  • Berto, Francesco; Plebani, Matteo (29 January 2015). Ontology and Metaontology: A Contemporary Guide. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4725-7330-8.
  • Berto, Francesco (17 October 2012). Existence as a Real Property: The Ontology of Meinongianism. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-007-4206-2.
  • Blackburn, Simon (1 January 2008). "existence". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954143-0.
  • Blair, J. Anthony; Johnson, Ralph H. (2000). "Informal Logic: An Overview". Informal Logic. 20 (2). doi:10.22329/il.v20i2.2262. from the original on 9 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  • Bottani, Andrea; Davies, Richard (2 May 2013). Modes of Existence: Papers in Ontology and Philosophical Logic. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032753-3.
  • Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2022). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 16 August 2023.
  • Burnham, Douglas; Papandreopoulos, George. "Existentialism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 August 2023.
  • Camus, Albert (2007). Christian Metaphysics and Neoplatonism. University of Missouri Press. ISBN 978-0-8262-6622-4. from the original on 2023-05-28. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
  • Casati, Filippo; Fujikawa, Naoya. "Existence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 7 August 2023.
  • Ceylan, Yasin (1993). "A Critical Approach to the Avicennian Distinction of Essence and Existence". Islamic Studies. 32 (3). ISSN 0578-8072. JSTOR 20840134.
  • Chakrabarti, A. (14 March 2013). Denying Existence: The Logic, Epistemology and Pragmatics of Negative Existentials and Fictional Discourse. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-017-1223-1.
  • Coakley, Sarah; Shelemay, Kay Kaufman (2007). Pain and Its Transformations: The Interface of Biology and Culture. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-02456-4.
  • Cook, Roy T. (20 March 2009). Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-3197-1.
  • Corkum, Philip (2015). "Generality and Logical Constancy". Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia. 71 (4). doi:10.17990/rpf/2015_71_4_0753. ISSN 0870-5283. JSTOR 43744657.
  • Cornwell, Neil (19 July 2013). The absurd in literature. Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-1-84779-657-8.
  • Csikszentmihalyi, Mark; Ivanhoe, Philip J. (1 January 1999). Religious and Philosophical Aspects of the Laozi. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-4111-4.
  • CUP staff. "existence". Cambridge Dictionary. Cambridge University Press. Retrieved 10 August 2023.
  • Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 27 January 2022. Retrieved 19 June 2023.
  • Darvill, Timothy (1 January 2009). "idealism". The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Archaeology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953404-3.
  • DeGrood, David H. (1 January 1976). Philosophies of Essence: An Examination of the Category of Essence. John Benjamins Publishing. ISBN 978-90-6032-076-1.
  • Dehsen, Christian von (13 September 2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3. from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • Divers, J. (2011). "Worlds and Individuals, Possible and Otherwise, by Takashi Yagisawa". Mind. 120 (478). doi:10.1093/mind/fzr027.
  • Dobrez, L. A. C. (13 January 2014). The Existential and its Exits: Literary and Philosophical Perspectives on the Works of Beckett, Ionesco, Genet and Pinter. A&C Black. ISBN 978-1-4725-1467-7.
  • Duignan, Brian, ed. (15 August 2010). Ancient Philosophy: From 600 BCE to 500 CE. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-141-6. from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • EB staff (2017). "Chinese philosophy". www.britannica.com. from the original on 2 May 2015. Retrieved 12 June 2023.
  • EB staff (3 July 2023). "Mind". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 17 August 2023.
  • Falguera, José L.; Martínez-Vidal, Concha; Rosen, Gideon (2022). "Abstract Objects". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. lead section, §1. Introduction. Retrieved 12 August 2023.
  • Faulkner, Nicholas; Gregersen, Erik (15 December 2017). The History of Mathematics. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-68048-777-0.
  • Favaretti, Camposampiero, Matteo; Plebani, Matteo (2 May 2013). Existence and Nature: New Perspectives. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032180-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  • Fierro, Ricardo D. (13 January 2012). Mathematics for Elementary School Teachers. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-1-133-71210-7.
  • Furley, David, ed. (2005). II. From Aristotle to Augustine. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02845-2.
  • Gibson, Q. B. (31 July 1998). The Existence Principle. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-0-7923-5188-7.
  • Goldschmidt, Tyron; Pearce, Kenneth L. (1 December 2017). Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-106399-2.
  • Graham, Jacob N. "Ancient Greek Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 16 August 2023.
  • Grayling, A. C. (20 June 2019). The History of Philosophy. Penguin UK. ISBN 978-0-241-98086-6. from the original on 3 July 2023. Retrieved 24 May 2023.
  • Haan, Daniel D. De (10 August 2020). Necessary Existence and the Doctrine of Being in Avicenna's Metaphysics of the Healing. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-43452-3.
  • Hailperin, Theodore (August 1967). "Nicholas Rescher. Definitions of "existence." Philosophical studies (Minneapolis), vol. 8 (1957), pp. 65–69. - Karel Lambert. Notes on "E!". Philosophical studies (Minneapolis), vol. 9 (1958), pp. 60–63". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 32 (2). doi:10.2307/2271672. JSTOR 2271672. S2CID 121302904.
  • Harper, Douglas (2017). "existence". www.etymonline.com. Retrieved 10 August 2023.
  • He, Dongshan; Gao, Dongfeng; Cai, Qing-yu (3 April 2014). "Spontaneous creation of the universe from nothing". Physical Review D. 89 (8). arXiv:1404.1207. Bibcode:2014PhRvD..89h3510H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.89.083510. S2CID 118371273.
  • Heisig, James W.; Kasulis, Thomas P.; Maraldo, John C. (31 July 2011). Japanese Philosophy: A Sourcebook. University of Hawaii Press. ISBN 978-0-8248-3707-5.
  • Hoad, T. F. (1993). The concise Oxford dictionary of english etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.
  • Hofweber, Thomas (2023). "Logic and Ontology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 19 August 2023.
  • Honderich, Ted, ed. (2005). "Ontology". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. from the original on 29 January 2021. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
  • Husserl, Edmund (1 October 2019). Logic and General Theory of Science. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-14529-3.
  • Jacquette, Dale (2015). Alexius Meinong, The Shepherd of Non-Being. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-18074-8.
  • Kelly, Eugene (30 March 2004). The Basics of Western Philosophy. Greenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-313-32352-2.
  • Kim, Jaegwon (2006). "1. Introduction". Philosophy of Mind (2nd ed.). Boulder: Westview Press. from the original on 2021-06-02. Retrieved 2021-06-01.
  • Kind, Amy (6 July 2018). Philosophy of Mind in the Twentieth and Twenty-First Centuries: The History of the Philosophy of Mind, Volume 6. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-01938-8.
  • Kriegel, Uriah (13 February 2018). Brentano's Philosophical System: Mind, Being, Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-250910-9.
  • Lambert, Karel (1 January 1994). "A Note on Singular and General Existence". KRITERION – Journal of Philosophy. 7 (1). doi:10.1515/krt-1994-010704. S2CID 251981034.
  • Lawson, Russell M. (2004). Science in the Ancient World: An Encyclopedia. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-85109-534-6. from the original on 2023-05-28. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
  • Leaman, Oliver (11 September 2002). Key Concepts in Eastern Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-68905-7.
  • Leclerc, Ivor (2002). The Nature of Physical Existence. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-29561-1.
  • Liu, Jeeloo; Berger, Douglas (13 June 2014). Nothingness in Asian Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-68383-4.
  • Livingston, Paul; Cutrofello, Andrew (8 December 2015). The Problems of Contemporary Philosophy: A Critical Guide for the Unaffiliated. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-5095-0144-1.
  • Lowe, E. J. (1 January 2005). "existence". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
  • MacFarlane, John (2017). "Logical Constants". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 17 March 2020. Retrieved 21 November 2021.
  • Magnus, P. D. (2005). Forall X: An Introduction to Formal Logic. Victoria, BC, Canada: State University of New York Oer Services. ISBN 978-1-64176-026-3. from the original on 7 December 2021. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
  • Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobinda (14 May 2020). The Philosophy of Sri Aurobindo: Indian Philosophy and Yoga in the Contemporary World. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-12487-5.
  • Markosian, Ned (13 April 2009). "Physical object". In Kim, Jaekwon; Sosa, Ernest; Rosenkrantz, Gary S. (eds.). A Companion to Metaphysics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-5298-3.
  • Martinich, A.P.; Stroll, Avrum (2023). "Epistemology". Encyclopædia Britannica. from the original on 10 July 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020.
  • McDaniel, Kris (28 July 2017). The Fragmentation of Being. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-103037-6.
  • Menn, Stephen (2021). "Aristotle On The Many Senses Of Being". In Caston, Victor (ed.). Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 59 Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 59. OUP. ISBN 978-0-19-189162-5.
  • Menon, Sangeetha. "Vedanta, Advaita". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 August 2023.
  • Michaelson, Eliot; Reimer, Marga (2022). "Reference". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 August 2023.
  • Morin, Marie-Eve (23 June 2017). Continental Realism and Its Discontents. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-1-4744-2115-7.
  • Morscher, E.; Hieke, A. (14 March 2013). New Essays in Free Logic: In Honour of Karel Lambert. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-015-9761-6.
  • MW staff (3 August 2023). "Definition of EXISTENCE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 10 August 2023.
  • Nelson, Michael (2022). "Existence". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 6 August 2023.
  • Nicholson, Graeme (1996). "The Ontological Difference". American Philosophical Quarterly. 33 (4). ISSN 0003-0481. JSTOR 20009875.
  • Nolt, John (2021). "Free Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 August 2023.
  • Novotný, Daniel D.; Novák, Lukáš (16 April 2014). Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-63009-7.
  • Penelope, Mackie (1998). "Existence". www.rep.routledge.com. Routledge. Retrieved 7 August 2023.
  • Perkins, Franklin (2019). "Metaphysics in Chinese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 16 August 2023.
  • Perrett, Roy W. (4 February 2016). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85356-9. from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Platter, Jonathan M. (5 July 2021). Divine Simplicity and the Triune Identity: A Critical Dialogue with the Theological Metaphysics of Robert W. Jenson. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-073601-4.
  • Poidevin, Robin Le; Peter, Simons; Andrew, McGonigal; Cameron, Ross P. (2 April 2009). The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-15585-9.
  • Prior, A. N. (2006). "Existences". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy Volume 3 (2nd ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5.
  • Pruss, Alexander R.; Rasmussen, Joshua L. (2018). Necessary Existence. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-874689-8.
  • Raftopoulos, Athanassios; Machamer, Peter (12 April 2012). Perception, Realism, and the Problem of Reference. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-19877-6.
  • Reicher, Maria (2022). "Nonexistent Objects". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. lead section, §1. The Concept of a Nonexistent Object. Retrieved 10 August 2023.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (October 1957). "Definitions of "existence"". Philosophical Studies. 8 (5). doi:10.1007/bf02304902. S2CID 170408608.
  • Robinson, Howard (2008). "7. Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God's Existence is Identical to His Essence?". In Stone, Martin William Francis (ed.). Reason, faith and history: philosophical essays for Paul Helm. Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-0926-1.
  • Rollinger, Robin D. (29 June 2013). Husserl's Position in the School of Brentano. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-017-1808-0.
  • Ruzsa, Ferenc (2023). "Sankhya". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 19 May 2019. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Searle, John R. (1 November 2004). Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-988268-7.
  • Shand, John (1 March 2004). Fundamentals of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-58831-2.
  • Shapiro, Stewart; Kouri Kissel, Teresa (2022). "Classical Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 August 2023.
  • Sider, Theodore (7 January 2010). Logic for Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-265881-4.
  • Smart, John Jamieson Carswell (28 July 2023). "Materialism". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 17 August 2023.
  • Smith, Barry; Mulligan, Kevin; Simons, Peter (2 May 2013). Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice (ed.). Metaphysics and Truthmakers. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032691-8.
  • Smith, Peter; Worden, David (2003). Key Beliefs, Ultimate Questions and Life Issues. Heinemann. ISBN 978-0-435-30699-1.
  • Sorensen, Roy (2023). "Nothingness". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 17 August 2023.
  • Søvik, Atle Ottesen (4 April 2022). A Basic Theory of Everything: A Fundamental Theoretical Framework for Science and Philosophy. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-077095-7.
  • Stadler, Friedrich; Stöltzner, Michael (2 May 2013). Time and History: Proceedings of the 28. International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium, Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria 2005. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-033321-3.
  • Trott, Adriel M. (8 October 2019). Aristotle on the Matter of Form: I Feminist Metaphysics of Generation. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-1-4744-5525-1.
  • Turner, Denys (16 September 2004). Faith, Reason and the Existence of God. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-60256-3.
  • Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa (6 December 2012). The Later Husserl and the Idea of Phenomenology: Idealism-Realism, Historicity and Nature Papers and Debate of the International Phenomenological Conference Held at the University of Waterloo, Canada, April 9–14, 1969. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-010-2882-0.
  • Urban, Wilbur Marshall (3 June 2014). Language and Reality: The Philosophy of Language and the Principles of Symbolism. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-85195-0.
  • Vallicella, William F. (2010). A Paradigm theory of existence: Onto-Theology vindicated. Kluwer Academic. ISBN 978-90-481-6128-7.
  • van Inwagen, Peter (2023). "Existence". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 7 August 2023.
  • Van Inwagen, Peter (2009). Metaphysics (3. ed.). Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-4356-3.
  • Vanamali (30 January 2015). The Science of the Rishis: The Spiritual and Material Discoveries of the Ancient Sages of India. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-62055-387-9.
  • Wang, Yueqing; Bao, Qinggang; Guan, Guoxing (16 March 2020). History of Chinese Philosophy Through Its Key Terms. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-15-2572-8. from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
  • Wheeler, Michael (2020). "Martin Heidegger". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 August 2023.
  • Yagisawa, Takashi (2011). "Précis of Worlds and Individuals, Possible and Otherwise". Analytic Philosophy. 52 (4). doi:10.1111/j.2153-960X.2011.00534.x.

Further reading edit

  • Aristotle (1998). The Metaphysics. Translated by Lawson-Tancred, Hugh. Penguin Books. ISBN 0-14-044619-2.
  • Thalheimer, Alvin (1920). The Meaning of the Terms: 'existence' and 'reality'. Princeton University Press.
  • Williams, Christopher John Fardo (1981). What is Existence?. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824429-5.
  • W. Kneale; G. E. Moore (July 15, 1936). Symposium: Is Existence a Predicate?. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume. Vol. 15. Oxford University Press. pp. 154–188. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/15.1.154.

External links edit

  • The Concept of Existence: History and Definitions from Leading Philosophers

existence, other, uses, disambiguation, being, redirects, here, other, uses, being, disambiguation, state, being, real, participating, reality, terms, being, reality, actuality, often, used, close, synonyms, contrasts, with, nonexistence, nothingness, nonbeing. For other uses see Existence disambiguation Being redirects here For other uses see Being disambiguation Existence is the state of being real or participating in reality The terms being reality and actuality are often used as close synonyms Existence contrasts with nonexistence nothingness and nonbeing A common distinction is between the existence of an entity and its essence which refers to the entity s nature or essential qualities From top left to bottom right Plato Avicenna Thomas Aquinas Gottlob Frege Alexius Meinong and Bertrand Russell Ontology is the philosophical discipline studying what existence is The orthodox view is that it is a second order property or a property of properties According to this view to say that a thing exists means that its properties are instantiated A different view holds that existence is a first order property or a property of individuals This means that existence has the same ontological status as other properties of individuals like color and shape Meinongians accept this idea and hold that not all individuals have this property they state that there are some individuals that do not exist This view is rejected by universalists who see existence as a universal property of every individual Various types of existence are discussed in the academic literature Singular existence is the existence of individual entities while general existence refers to the existence of concepts or universals Other distinctions are between abstract and concrete existence between possible contingent and necessary existence and between physical and mental existence A closely related issue is whether different types of entities exist in different ways or to different degrees A key question in ontology is whether there is a reason for existence in general or why anything at all exists The concept of existence is relevant to various fields including logic epistemology philosophy of mind philosophy of language and existentialism Contents 1 Definition and related terms 2 Theories of the nature of existence 2 1 Second order theories 2 2 First order theories 2 2 1 Meinongianism 2 2 2 Universalism 3 Types of existing entities 3 1 Singular and general 3 2 Concrete and abstract 3 3 Possible contingent and necessary 3 4 Physical and mental 4 Modes and degrees of existence 5 Why anything exists at all 6 History 6 1 Western philosophy 6 2 Eastern philosophy 7 In various disciplines 7 1 Formal logic 7 2 Epistemology philosophy of mind and philosophy of language 7 3 Existentialism 8 See also 9 References 9 1 Citations 9 2 Sources 10 Further reading 11 External linksDefinition and related terms editExistence is the state of being real To exist means to have being or to participate in reality 1 Existence is what sets real entities apart from imaginary ones 2 It can refer both to individual entities or to the totality of reality 3 The word existence entered the English language in the late 14th century from old French It has its roots in the medieval Latin term ex s istere which means to stand forth to appear and to arise 4 Existence is studied by the subdiscipline of metaphysics known as ontology 5 The terms being reality and actuality are closely related to existence 6 They are usually used as synonyms of existence but their meanings as technical terms may come apart 7 According to metaphysicist Alexius Meinong for example all entities have being but not all have existence He argues that merely possible objects like Santa Clause have being but lack existence 8 Ontologist Takashi Yagisawa contrasts existence with reality He sees reality as the more fundamental term since it characterizes all entities equally He defines existence as a relative term that connects an entity to the world that it inhabits 9 According to Gottlob Frege actuality is more narrow than existence He holds that actual entities can produce and undergo changes He states that some existing entities are non actual like numbers and sets 10 Existence contrasts with nonexistence which refers to a lack of reality It is controversial whether objects can be divided into existent and nonexistent objects This distinction is sometimes used to explain how it is possible to think of fictional objects like dragons and unicorns But the concept of nonexistent objects is not generally accepted 11 Closely related contrasting terms are nothingness and nonbeing 12 Another contrast is between existence and essence Essence refers to the intrinsic nature or defining qualities of an entity The essence of something determines what kind of entity it is and how it differs from other kinds of entities Essence corresponds to what an entity is while existence corresponds to the fact that it is For instance it is possible to understand what an object is and grasp its nature even if one does not know whether this object exists 13 Some philosophers like Edmund Husserl and Quentin Boyce Gibson hold that existence is an elementary concept This means that it cannot be defined in other terms without involving circularity This would imply that it may be difficult or impossible to characterize existence or to talk about its nature in a non trivial manner 14 A closely related issue concerns the distinction between thin and thick concepts of existence Thin concepts understand existence as a logical property that every existing thing shares It does not include any substantial content about the metaphysical implications of having existence An example of a thin concept of existence is to state that existence is the same as the logical property of self identity 15 Thick concepts of existence encompass a metaphysical analysis of what it means that something exists and what essential features existence implies For example George Berkeley s claim that esse est percipi presents a thick concept of existence It can be translated as to be is to be perceived and highlights the mental nature of all existence 16 Some philosophers emphasize that there is a difference between the entities that exist and existence itself 17 This distinction plays a central role in the philosophy of Martin Heidegger who calls it the ontological difference 18 Theories of the nature of existence edit nbsp One of the topics covered by theories of the nature of existence concerns the ontological status of fictional objects like Pegasus 19 Theories of the nature of existence aim to explain what it means for something to exist The central dispute regarding the nature of existence is whether it should be understood as a property of individuals 20 The two main theories of existence are first order theories and second order theories First order theories understand existence as a property of individuals Some first order theories see it as a property of all individuals while others hold that there are some individuals that do not exist Second order theories hold that existence is a second order property that is a property of properties 21 A central challenge for the different theories of the nature of existence is to understand how it is possible to coherently deny the existence of something An example is the sentence Santa Claus does not exist One difficulty consists in explaining how the name Santa Claus can be meaningful even though there is no Santa Claus 22 Second order theories edit Second order theories are often seen as the orthodox position They understand existence as a second order property rather than a first order property 23 For instance the Empire State Building is an individual object and being 443 2 meters tall is a first order property of it Being instantiated is a property of being 443 2 meters tall and therefore a second order property According to second order theories to talk about existence is to talk about which properties have instances 24 For example this view states that the sentence God exists does not claim that God has the property of existing Instead it means Godhood is instantiated 2 A key motivation of second order theories is that existence is in important ways different from regular properties like being a building and being 443 2 meters tall regular properties express what an object is like but existence does not 25 According to this view existence is more fundamental than regular properties since without it objects cannot instantiate any properties 26 Second order theorists usually hold that quantifiers rather than predicates express existence 27 Quantifiers are terms that talk about the quantity of objects that have certain properties Existential quantifiers express that there is at least one object Examples are expressions like some and there exists as in some cows eat grass and there exists an even prime number 28 In this regard existence is closely related to counting since to claim that something exists is to claim that the corresponding concept has one or more instances 29 Second order views imply that a sentence like egg laying mammals exist is misleading since the word exist is used as a predicate in them They hold instead that their true logical form is better expressed in reformulations like there exist entities that are egg laying mammals This way existence has the role of a quantifier while egg laying mammals is the predicate Quantifier constructions can also be used to express negative existential statements For instance the sentence talking tigers do not exist can be expressed as it is not the case that there exist talking tigers 30 Many ontologists accept that second order theories provide a correct analysis of many types of existential sentences However it is controversial whether it is correct for all cases 31 One difficulty is caused by so called negative singular existentials Negative singular existentials are statements that deny that a particular object exists An example is the sentence Ronald McDonald does not exist Singular terms like Ronald McDonald seem to refer to individuals This poses a difficulty since negative singular existentials deny that this individual exists This makes it unclear how the singular term can refer to the individual in the first place One influential solution to this problem was proposed by Bertrand Russell He holds that singular terms do not directly refer to individuals but are instead descriptions of individuals Positive singular existentials affirm that an object matching the descriptions exists while negative singular existentials deny that an object matching the descriptions exists According to this view the sentence Ronald McDonald does not exist expresses the idea that it is not the case that there is a unique happy hamburger clown 32 First order theories edit First order theories claim that existence is a property of individuals They are less widely accepted than second order theories but also have some influential proponents There are two types of first order theories According to Meinongianism existence is a property of some but not all entities This view implies that there are nonexistent entities According to universalism existence is a universal property instantiated by every entity 33 Meinongianism edit Meinongianism is a view about existence defended by Meinong and his followers Its main claim is that there are some entities that do not exist This means that objecthood is independent of existence Proposed examples of nonexistent objects are merely possible objects like flying pigs as well as fictional and mythical objects like Sherlock Holmes and Zeus According to this view these objects are real and have being even though they do not exist 34 Meinong states that there is an object for any combination of properties For example there is an object that only has the single property of being a singer without any additional properties This object neither has the property of wearing a dress nor the property of not wearing a dress Meinong also includes impossible objects like round squares 35 Meinongians state that sentences describing what Sherlock Holmes and Zeus are like refer to nonexisting objects They are true or false depending on whether these objects have the properties ascribed to them 36 For instance the sentence Pegasus has wings is true because having wings is a property of Pegasus even though Pegasus lacks the property of existing 37 One key motivation of Meinongianism is to explain how negative singular existentials like Ronald McDonald does not exist can be true Meinongians accept the idea that singular terms like Ronald McDonald refer to individuals For them a negative singular existential is true if the individual it refers to does not exist 38 Meinongianism has important implications for how to understand quantification According to an influential view defended by Willard Van Orman Quine the domain of quantification is restricted to existing objects This view implies that quantifiers carry ontological commitments about what exists and what does not exist Meinongianism differs from this view by holding that the widest domain of quantification includes both existing and nonexisting objects 19 Some aspects of Meinongianism are controversial and have received substantial criticism According to one objection one cannot distinguish between being an object and being an existing object 37 A closely related criticism rests on the idea that objects cannot have properties if they do not exist 37 A further objection is that Meinongianism leads to an overpopulated universe since there is an object corresponding to any combination of properties 19 A more specific criticism rejects the idea that there are incomplete and impossible objects 39 Universalism edit Universalists agree with Meinongians that existence is a property of individuals But they deny that there are nonexistent entities They state instead that existence is a universal property all entities have it meaning that everything exists One approach is to hold that existence is the same as self identity According to the law of identity every object is identical to itself or has the property of self identity This can be expressed in predicate logic as x x x displaystyle forall x x x nbsp 40 An influential argument in favor of universalism rests on the claim that to deny the existence of something is contradictory This conclusion follows from the premises that one can only deny the existence of something by referring to that entity and that one can only refer to entities that exist 40 Universalists have proposed different ways of interpreting negative singular existentials According to one view names of fictional entities like Ronald McDonald refer to abstract objects Abstract objects exist even though they do not exist in space and time This means that when understood in a strict sense all negative singular existentials are false including the claim that Ronald McDonald does not exist However universalists can interpret such sentences slightly differently in relation to the context In everyday life for example people use sentences like Ronald McDonald does not exist to express the idea that Ronald McDonald does not exist as a concrete object which is true 41 A different approach is to claim that negative singular existentials lack a truth value since their singular terms do not refer to anything According to this view they are neither true nor false but meaningless 42 Types of existing entities editDifferent types of existing entities are discussed in the academic literature Many discussions revolve around the questions of what those types are whether entities of a specific type exist how entities of different types are related to each other and whether some types are more fundamental than others 43 Examples are questions like whether souls exist whether there are abstract fictional and universal entities and whether besides the actual world and its objects there are also possible worlds and objects 44 Singular and general edit One distinction is between singular and general existence Singular existence is the existence of individual entities For example the sentence Angela Merkel exists expresses the existence of one particular person General existence pertains to general concepts properties or universals For instance the sentence politicians exist states that the general term politician has instances without referring to any one politician in particular 45 Singular and general existence are closely related to each other and some philosophers have tried to explain one as a special case of the other For example Frege held that general existence is more basic One argument in favor of this position is that general existence can be expressed in terms of singular existence For instance the sentence Angela Merkel exists can be expressed as entities exist that are identical to Angela Merkel where the expression being identical to Angela Merkel is understood as a general term A different position is defended by Quine who gives primacy to singular existence 46 A related question is whether there can be general existence without singular existence According to philosophers like Henry S Leonard a property only has general existence if there is at least one actual object that instantiates it A different view defended by Nicholas Rescher holds that properties can even exist if they have no actual instances like the property of being a unicorn 47 This question has a long philosophical tradition in relation to the existence of universals Platonists claim that universals have general existence as Platonic forms independently of the particulars that instantiate them According to this view the universal of redness exists independent of whether there are any red objects 48 Aristotelianism also accepts that universals exist However it holds that their existence depends on particulars that instantiate them and that they are unable to exist by themselves According to this view a universal that has no instances in the spacio temporal world does not exist 49 Nominalists claim that only particulars have existence and deny that universals exist 50 Concrete and abstract edit Another influential distinction in ontology is between concrete and abstract objects Many concrete objects are encountered in regular everyday life like rocks plants and other people They exist in space and time and influence each other they have causal powers and are affected by other concrete objects Abstract objects exist outside space and time and lack causal powers Examples of abstract objects are numbers sets and types 51 The distinction between concrete and abstract objects is sometimes treated as the most general division of being 52 There is wide agreement that concrete objects exist but opinions are divided in regard to abstract objects Realists accept the idea that abstract objects have independent existence 53 Some of them claim that abstract objects have the same mode of existence as concrete objects while others maintain that they exist but in a different way 54 Antirealists state that abstract objects do not exist This is often combined with the view that existence requires a location in space and time or the ability to causally interact 55 Fictional objects like dragons and centaurs are closely related to abstract objects and pose similar problems However the two terms are not identical For example the expression the integer between two and three refers to a fictional abstract object while the expression integer between two and four refers to a non fictional abstract object In a similar sense there are also concrete fictional objects besides abstract fictional objects like the winged horse of Bellerophon 56 Possible contingent and necessary edit A further distinction is between merely possible contingent and necessary existence 57 An entity has necessary existence if it must exist or could not fail to exist Entities that exist but could fail to exist are contingent Merely possible entities are entities that do not exist but could exist 58 Most entities encountered in ordinary experience like telephones sticks and flowers have contingent existence 59 It is an open question whether any entities have necessary existence According to one view all concrete objects have contingent existence while all abstract objects have necessary existence 60 According to some theorists one or several necessary beings are required as the explanatory foundation of the cosmos For instance philosophers like Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas follow this idea and claim that God has necessary existence 61 There are many academic debates about whether there are merely possible objects According to actualism only actual entities have being This includes both contingent and necessary entities But it excludes merely possible entities 62 This view is rejected by possibilists who state that there are also merely possible objects besides actual objects 63 For example David Lewis argues that possible objects exist in the same way as actual objects According to him possible objects exist in possible worlds while actual objects exist in the actual world Lewis holds that the only difference between possible worlds and the actual world is the location of the speaker the term actual refers to the world of the speaker similar to how the terms here and now refer to the spatial and temporal location of the speaker 2 Physical and mental edit A further distinction is between entities that exist on a physical level in contrast to mental entities 64 Physical entities include objects of regular perception like stones trees and human bodies as well as entities discussed in modern physics like electrons and protons Physical entities can be observed and measured They possess mass and a location in space and time 65 Mental entities belong to the realm of the mind like perceptions experiences of pleasure and pain as well as beliefs desires and emotions They are primarily associated with conscious experiences but also include unconscious states like unconscious beliefs desires and memories 66 The ontological status of physical and mental entities is a frequent topic in metaphysics and philosophy of mind According to materialists only physical entities exist on the most fundamental level Materialists usually explain mental entities in terms of physical processes for example as brain states or as patterns of neural activation Idealists reject this view and state that mind is the ultimate foundation of existence They hold that physical entities have a derivative form of existence for instance that they are mental representations or products of consciousness Dualists believe that both physical and mental entities exist on the most fundamental level They state that they are connected to one another in various ways but that one cannot be reduced to the other 67 Modes and degrees of existence editClosely related to the problem of different types of entities is the question of whether they differ also concerning their mode of existence This is the case according to ontological pluralism In this view entities belonging to different types do not just differ in their essential features but also in the way they exist 68 This position is sometimes found in theology It states that God is radically different from his creation and emphasizes his uniqueness by holding that the difference affects not just God s features but also God s mode of existence 69 Another form of ontological pluralism distinguishes the existence of material objects from the existence of spacetime This view holds that material objects have relative existence since they exist in spacetime It further states that the existence of spacetime itself is not relative in this sense since it just exists without existing within another spacetime 70 The topic of degrees of existence is closely related to the issue of modes of existence This topic is based on the idea that some entities exist to a higher degree or have more being than other entities It is similar to how some properties have degrees like heat and mass According to Plato for example unchangeable Platonic forms have a higher degree of existence than physical objects 71 While the view that there are different types of entities is common in metaphysics the idea they differ from each other concerning their modes or degrees of existence is not generally accepted 72 For instance philosopher Quentin Gibson maintains that a thing either exists or does not exist This means that there is no alternative in between and that there are no degrees of existence 73 Peter van Inwagen uses the idea that there is an intimate relation between existence and quantification to argue against different modes of existence Quantification is related to how people count objects Inwagen argues that if there were different modes of entities then people would need different types of numbers to count them Since the same numbers can be used to count different types of entities he concludes that all entities have the same mode of existence 74 Why anything exists at all editMain article Why there is anything at all A central question in ontology is why anything exists at all or why there is something rather than nothing 75 Similar questions are why is there a world and why are there individual things These questions focus on the idea that many things that exist are contingent meaning they could have failed to exist It asks whether this applies to existence as a whole as well or whether there is a reason why something exists instead of nothing 76 This question is different from scientific questions that seek to explain the existence of one thing like life in relation to the existence of another thing like the primordial soup which may have been its origin It is also different from most religious creation myths that explain the existence of the material world in relation to a god or gods that created it The difference lies in the fact that these theories explain the existence of one thing in terms of the existence of another thing instead of trying to explain existence in general The additional difficulty of the ontological question lies in the fact that one cannot refer to any other existing entity without engaging in circular reasoning 77 One answer to the question of why there is anything at all is called the statistical argument It is based on the idea that besides the actual world there are many possible worlds They differ from the actual world in various respects For example the Eiffel Tower exists in the actual world but there are possible worlds without the Eiffel Tower There are countless variations of possible worlds but there is only one possible world that is empty i e that does not contain any entities This means that if it was up to chance which possible world becomes actual the chance that there is nothing is exceedingly small 78 A closely related argument in physics explains the existence of the world as the result of random quantum fluctuations 79 Another response is to deny that a reason or an explanation for existence in general can be found According to this view existence as a whole is absurd since it is there without a reason for being there 80 Not all theorists accept this question as a valid or philosophically interesting question Some philosophers like Graham Priest and Kris McDaniel have suggested that the term nothing refers to a global absence which can itself be understood as a form of existence According to this view the answer to the question is trivial since there is always something even if this something is just a global absence 81 A closely related response is to claim that an empty world is metaphysically impossible According to this view there is something rather than nothing because it is necessary for some things to exist 82 History editWestern philosophy edit Western philosophy originated with the Presocratic philosophers who explored the foundational principles of all existence Some like Thales and Heraclitus suggested that concrete principles like water or fire are the root of existence This position was opposed by Anaximander who held that the source must lie in an abstract principle beyond the world of human perception 83 Plato argued that different types of entities have different degrees of existence He held that shadows and images exist in a weaker sense than regular material objects He claimed that the unchangeable Platonic forms have the highest type of existence He saw material objects as imperfect and impermanent copies of Platonic forms 84 nbsp Aristotle held that different types of entities have different modes of existence While Aristotle accepted Plato s idea that forms are different from matter he challenged the idea that forms have a higher type of existence Instead he held that forms cannot exist without matter 85 Aristotle further claimed that different entities have different modes of existence For example he distinguished between substances and their accidents and between potentiality and actuality 86 Neoplatonists like Plotinus suggested that reality has a hierarchical structure They held that a transcendent entity called the One or the Good is responsible for all existence From it emerges the intellect which in turn gives rise to the soul and the material world 87 nbsp Anselm of Canterbury is known for his formulation of the ontological argument aiming to prove the existence of God In medieval philosophy Anselm of Canterbury formulated the influential ontological argument This argument aims to deduce the existence of God from the concept of God Anselm defined God as the greatest conceivable being He reasoned that an entity that did not exist outside his mind would not be the greatest conceivable being This led him to the conclusion that God exists 88 Thomas Aquinas distinguished between the essence of a thing and its existence According to him the essence of a thing constitutes its fundamental nature He argued that it is possible to understand what an object is and grasp its essence even if one does not know whether this object exists He concluded from this observation that existence is not part of the qualities of an object and should instead be understood as a separate property 20 Aquinas also considered the problem of creation from nothing He claimed that only God has the power to truly bring new entities into existence These ideas later inspired Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz s theory of creation He held that to create is to confer actual existence to possible objects 89 Both David Hume and Immanuel Kant rejected the idea that existence is a property According to Hume objects are bundles of qualities He held that existence is not a property since there is no impression of existence besides the bundled qualities 90 Kant came to a similar conclusion in his criticism of the ontological argument According to him this proof fails because one cannot deduce from the definition of a concept whether entities described by this concept exist He held that existence does not add anything to the concept of the object it only indicates that this concept is instantiated 91 nbsp Franz Brentano defended the idea that all judgments are existential judgments Franz Brentano agreed with Kant s criticism and his claim that existence is not a real predicate He used this idea to develop his theory of judgments According to him all judgments are existential judgments they either affirm or deny the existence of something He stated that judgments like some zebras are striped have the logical form there is a striped zebra while judgments like all zebras are striped have the logical form there is not a non striped zebra 92 Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell aimed to refine the idea of what it means that existence is not a regular property They distinguished between regular first order properties of individuals and second order properties of other properties According to this view to talk about existence is to talk about the second order property of being instantiated For instance to deny that dinosaurs exist means that the property of being a dinosaur has the property of not being instantiated 93 According to Russell the fundamental form of predication happens by applying a predicate to the proper name of an individual An example of this type of atomic proposition is Laika is a dog Russell held that talk of existence in the form of sentences like dogs exist is less fundamental since it means that there is an individual to which this predicate applies without naming this individual 94 Willard Van Orman Quine followed Frege and Russell in accepting that existence is a second order property He drew a close link between existence and the role of quantification in formal logic 95 He applied this idea to scientific theories and stated that a scientific theory is committed to the existence of an entity if the theory quantifies over this entity For example if a theory in biology claims that there are populations with genetic diversity then this theory has an ontological commitment to the existence of populations with genetic diversity 96 Despite the influence of second order theories this view was not universally accepted Alexius Meinong rejected it and claimed that existence is a property of individuals and that not all individuals have this property This led him to the thesis that there is a difference between being and existence all individuals have being but only some of them also exist This implies that there are some things that do not exist like merely possible objects and impossible objects 97 Eastern philosophy edit Main article Eastern philosophy nbsp Adi Shankara taught that only the divine exists on the most fundamental level and that the impression of a multiplicity of different entities is an illusion Many schools of thought in Eastern philosophy discuss the problem of existence and its implications For instance the ancient Hindu school of Samkhya developed a metaphysical dualism According to this view there are two types of existence pure consciousness Purusha and matter Prakriti Samkhya explains the manifestation of the universe as the interaction between these two principles 98 A different approach was developed by Adi Shankara in his school of Advaita Vedanta He defended a metaphysical monism by claiming that the divine Brahman is the ultimate reality and the only existent According to this view the impression that there is a universe consisting of many distinct entities is an illusion Maya 99 The essential features of ultimate reality are described as Sat Chit Ananda meaning existence consciousness and bliss 100 A central doctrine in Buddhist philosophy is called the three marks of existence The three marks are anicca impermanence anatta absence of a permanent self and dukkha suffering Anicca is the doctrine that all of existence is subject to change This means everything transforms at some point and nothing lasts forever Anatta expresses a similar state in relation to persons It is the claim that people do not have a permanent identity or a separate self Ignorance about anicca and anatta is seen as the main cause of dukkha by leading people to form attachments that cause suffering 101 nbsp Laozi saw the dao as a fundamental principle that constitutes the root of all existence A central idea in many schools of Chinese philosophy like Laozi s Daoism is that a fundamental principle known as dao is the source of all existence The term is often translated as the Way and is understood as a cosmic force that governs the natural order of the world One position in Chinese metaphysics holds that dao is itself a form of being while another contends that it is non being that gives rise to being 102 The concept of existence played a central role in Arabic Persian philosophy Avicenna and Al Ghazali discussed the relation between existence and essence According to them the essence of an entity is prior to its existence The additional step of instantiating the essence is required for the entity to come into existence Mulla Sadra rejected this priority of essence over existence He argued that essence is only a concept used by the mind to grasp existence Existence by contrast encompasses the whole of reality according to his view 103 In various disciplines editFormal logic edit Main article Logic Formal logic studies which arguments are deductively valid 104 First order logic is the most commonly used system of formal logic In it existence is expressed using the existential quantifier displaystyle exists nbsp For example the formula x H o r s e x displaystyle exists xHorse x nbsp can be used to state that horses exist The variable x ranges over all elements in the domain of quantification and the existential quantifier expresses that at least one element in this domain is a horse In first order logic all singular terms like names refer to objects in the domain and imply that the object exists Because of this one can deduce that x H o n e s t x displaystyle exists xHonest x nbsp someone is honest from H o n e s t B i l l displaystyle Honest Bill nbsp Bill is honest 105 Many logical systems that are based on first order logic also follow this idea Free logic is an exception It allows there to be empty names that do not refer to any object in the domain 106 One motivation for this modification is that reasoning is not limited to regular objects but can also be applied to fictional objects 107 In free logic for instance one can express that Pegasus is a flying horse using the formula F l y i n g h o r s e P e g a s u s displaystyle Flyinghorse Pegasus nbsp One consequence of this modification is that one cannot infer from this type of statement that something exists This means that the inference from F l y i n g h o r s e P e g a s u s displaystyle Flyinghorse Pegasus nbsp to x F l y i n g h o r s e x displaystyle exists xFlyinghorse x nbsp is invalid in free logic even though it would be valid in first order logic Free logic uses an additional existence predicate E displaystyle E nbsp to express that a singular term refers to an existing object For example the formula E H o m e r displaystyle E Homer nbsp can be used to express that Homer exists while the formula E P e g a s u s displaystyle lnot E Pegasus nbsp states that Pegasus does not exist 108 Epistemology philosophy of mind and philosophy of language edit The disciplines of epistemology philosophy of mind and philosophy of language aim to understand the nature of knowledge mind and language 109 A key issue in these fields is the problem of reference This problem concerns the question of how mental or linguistic representations can refer to existing objects Examples of such representations are beliefs thoughts perceptions words and sentences For instance in the sentence Barack Obama is a Democrat the name Barack Obama refers to a particular individual In relation to perception the problem of reference concerns the question of whether or to what extent perceptual impressions bring the perceiver in contact with reality by presenting existing objects rather than illusions 110 Closely related to the problem of reference is the relation between truth and existence Representations can be true or false According to truthmaker theory true representations require a truthmaker A truthmaker of a representation is the entity whose existence is responsible for the fact that the representation is true For example the sentence kangaroos live in Australia is true because there are kangaroos in Australia the existence of these kangaroos is the truthmaker of the sentence Truthmaker theory states that there is a close relation between truth and existence there exists a truthmaker for every true representation 111 Existentialism edit Main article Existentialism Existentialism is a school of thought that explores the nature of human existence One of its key ideas is that existence precedes essence This claim expresses the notion that existence is more basic than essence and that the nature and purpose of human beings are not pregiven but develop in the process of living According to this view humans are thrown into a world that lacks preexistent intrinsic meaning They have to determine for themselves what their purpose is and what meaning their life should have Existentialists use this idea to focus on the role of freedom and responsibility in actively shaping one s life 112 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portalCogito ergo sum Existence theorem SolipsismReferences editCitations edit AHD staff 2022MW staff 2023CUP staff a b c Lowe 2005 existence AHD staff 2022MW staff 2023CUP staffLowe 2005 existence Harper 2017Hoad 1993 p 160 Lowe 2005 existenceSorensen 2023 lead sectionVallicella 2010 p xi AHD staff 2022MW staff 2023Gibson 1998 p 2 Prior 2006 pp 493 Existencesvan Inwagen 2023Nelson 2022 lead section 2 Meinongianism van Inwagen 2023Nelson 2022 lead section 2 MeinongianismShand 2004 p 49 Divers 2011 pp 570 574Yagisawa 2011 pp 270 272 Chakrabarti 2013 pp 106 107 Reicher 2022 lead section 1 The Concept of a Nonexistent ObjectGibson 1998 pp 8Liu amp Berger 2014 p 150 Dobrez 2014 p 109Heisig Kasulis amp Maraldo 2011 p 830Leclerc 2002 p 49Sorensen 2023 lead section Gibson 1998 p 2Ceylan 1993 pp 329 337Nelson 2022 lead sectionPlatter 2021 p 28 Gibson 1998 pp 1 2Vallicella 2010 p 16Balthasar 2000 p 82Shand 2004 pp 47 48 Robinson 2008 p 139 7 Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God s Existence is Identical to His Essence Novotny amp Novak 2014 pp 46 47Berto 2012 pp 31 32Bottani amp Davies 2013 p 126 Robinson 2008 p 139 7 Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God s Existence is Identical to His Essence Novotny amp Novak 2014 pp 46 47Berto 2012 pp 31 32 Nicholson 1996 pp 357 374Wheeler 2020 2 2 1 The QuestionVallicella 2010 p 1 Nicholson 1996 pp 357 374Wheeler 2020 2 2 1 The Question a b c Casati amp Fujikawa 2a Meinongianism a b Nelson 2022 lead section Nelson 2022 lead sectionPenelope 1998 lead sectionCasati amp Fujikawa lead sectionBlackburn 2008 existence Penelope 1998 1 Objects and existencePenelope 1998 1 Objects and existenceNelson 2022 lead sectionNelson 2022 1 Frege and Russell Existence is not a Property of Individuals Casati amp Fujikawa lead section 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to QuantificationBlackburn 2008 existence Blackburn 2008 existenceCasati amp Fujikawa 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification Casati amp Fujikawa 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to QuantificationLowe 2005 existence Nelson 2022 1 Frege and Russell Existence is not a Property of Individuals Casati amp Fujikawa lead section 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to QuantificationPenelope 1998 2 The quantifier account of existenceBlackburn 2008 existenceLowe 2005 existence Fierro 2012 p 37 Blackburn 2008 existenceCasati amp Fujikawa 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification Penelope 1998 2 The quantifier account of existence Penelope 1998 2 The quantifier account of existenceBlackburn 2008 existence Nelson 2022 1 Frege and Russell Existence is not a Property of IndividualsPenelope 1998 2 The quantifier account of existenceNelson 2022 1 Frege and Russell Existence is not a Property of Individuals Casati amp Fujikawa lead section 2 Existence as a First Order Property and Its Relation to QuantificationNelson 2022 lead section Casati amp Fujikawa 2a MeinongianismLowe 2005 existence Nelson 2022 2 MeinongianismCasati amp Fujikawa 2a Meinongianism Casati amp Fujikawa 2a MeinongianismLowe 2005 existenceTymieniecka 2012 p 208 a b c Penelope 1998 1 Objects and existence Nelson 2022 2 MeinongianismPenelope 1998 1 Objects and existence Nelson 2022 2 MeinongianismCasati amp Fujikawa 2a MeinongianismCasati amp Fujikawa 2a MeinongianismJacquette 2015 pp 78 79 180 a b Casati amp Fujikawa 2b Universalism Nelson 2022 3 An Anti Meinongian First Order ViewCasati amp Fujikawa 2b Universalism Nelson 2022 3 An Anti Meinongian First Order View van Inwagen 2023Hofweber 2023 3 1 Different conceptions of ontologyLivingston amp Cutrofello 2015 pp 63 64Gibson 1998 pp 3 4Nelson 2022 3 An Anti Meinongian First Order View van Inwagen 2023Prior 2006 pp 493 ExistencesGibson 1998 pp 3 4Nelson 2022 3 An Anti Meinongian First Order View Lambert 1994 pp 3 4Rescher 1957 pp 65 69Hailperin 1967 p 251Shand 2004 pp 52 53 Lambert 1994 pp 3 4 Rescher 1957 pp 65 69Hailperin 1967 p 251 Gibson 1998 pp 133 134Balaguer 2016 1 What is Platonism Gibson 1998 p 138 Gibson 1998 pp 3 4 137 Penelope 1998 lead sectionFalguera Martinez Vidal amp Rosen 2022 lead section 1 IntroductionStadler amp Stoltzner 2013 pp 89 91Prior 2006 pp 498 499 Existences Honderich 2005 Ontology Belfiore 2016 p 110Faulkner amp Gregersen 2017 p 298Prior 2006 pp 498 499 Existences van Inwagen 2023Prior 2006 pp 493 498 499 Existences Casati amp Fujikawa 2a MeinongianismFavaretti amp Plebani 2013 p 5 Prior 2006 pp 493 Existences Penelope 1998 lead sectionGibson 1998 pp 157 8Shand 2004 pp 49 52 Gibson 1998 pp 157 8Albertazzi amp Jacquette 2017 p 87Pruss amp Rasmussen 2018 pp 1 2Shand 2004 p 52 Pruss amp Rasmussen 2018 pp 1 2 Pruss amp Rasmussen 2018 pp 1 4 Gibson 1998 pp 157 8Pruss amp Rasmussen 2018 pp 1 6Haan 2020 p 381Turner 2004 p 238 Nelson 2022 3 An Anti Meinongian First Order ViewShand 2004 pp 49 50 Nelson 2022 2 MeinongianismShand 2004 pp 49 50 Penelope 1998 lead section Smart 2023 lead section Types of materialist theoryMarkosian 2009 pp 486 487 Physical object Kim 2006 1 IntroductionEB staff 2023Addis 2013 pp 49 50Searle 2004 p 183 Kelly 2004 pp 87 88Goldschmidt amp Pearce 2017 p ixDarvill 2009 idealismSmart 2023 lead section Types of materialist theory Casati amp Fujikawa lead section 3 How Many Ways of Being Existent McDaniel 2017 p 77 Casati amp Fujikawa lead section 3 How Many Ways of Being Existent McDaniel 2017 pp 5 6 Casati amp Fujikawa 3 How Many Ways of Being Existent Poidevin et al 2009 pp 227 228van Inwagen 2023 Casati amp Fujikawa 3 How Many Ways of Being Existent Gibson 1998 pp 5 8 Gibson 1998 pp 5 8 Casati amp Fujikawa 3 How Many Ways of Being Existent Berto amp Plebani 2015 p 60 Lowe 2005 existenceCasati amp Fujikawa lead section 4 Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing Van Inwagen 2009 pp 109 112Morin 2017 p 46Sorensen 2023 lead section 1 Why is there something rather than nothing Casati amp Fujikawa 4 Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing Van Inwagen 2009 pp 109 112Morin 2017 p 46Sorensen 2023 lead section 1 Why is there something rather than nothing Casati amp Fujikawa 4 Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing Van Inwagen 2009 pp 109 112Morin 2017 p 46Sorensen 2023 lead section 1 Why is there something rather than nothing Sovik 2022 p 482 Casati amp Fujikawa 4 Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing Sorensen 2023 lead section 1 Why is there something rather than nothing He Gao amp Cai 2014 p 083510 1 Lowe 2005 existenceCornwell 2013 p 16 Casati amp Fujikawa 4 Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing Pruss amp Rasmussen 2018 pp 4 5 Graham lead section 1a The Milesians 1d HeraclitusDuignan 2010 pp 9 11 van Inwagen 2023Poidevin et al 2009 pp 227 228 Trott 2019 pp 109 110Grayling 2019 Aristotle Poidevin et al 2009 pp 228 229Menn 2021 1 The senses of being and the necessity of D 7 Graham 6 Post Hellenistic ThoughtAdamson 2015 pp 209 215Furley 2005 pp 357 388Camus 2007 p 45Lawson 2004 p 200 Grayling 2019 AnselmDehsen 2013 p 10Prior 2006 pp 493 494 Existences Prior 2006 pp 494 Existences Nelson 2022 lead sectionPrior 2006 pp 495 Existences Nelson 2022 lead sectionCasati amp Fujikawa 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification Kriegel 2018 pp 103 104 119Brandl amp Textor 2022 lead section 1 3 Part III Existential Judgements 2 Brentano and His Precursors on Existential JudgementRollinger 2013 p 226Husserl 2019 p 184Prior 2006 pp 495 496 Existences Nelson 2022 lead sectionBlackburn 2008 existence Prior 2006 pp 496 498 Existences Lowe 2005 existenceCasati amp Fujikawa 2a Meinongianism Casati amp Fujikawa 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification 2a Meinongianism Nelson 2022 lead sectionCasati amp Fujikawa 2a Meinongianism Leaman 2002 pp 77 78Perrett 2016 The classical period of Indian philosophyRuzsa 2023 lead section 4 Metaphysics Perrett 2016 The medieval period of Indian philosophyDalal 2021 lead section 1 Life and WorksMenon lead sectionLeaman 2002 pp 77 78 Vanamali 2015 pp 53 54Mahapatra 2020 p 110 Smith amp Worden 2003 p 18Coakley amp Shelemay 2007 p 110 Perkins 2019 lead section 3 1 MonismEB staff 2017 Periods of development of Chinese philosophyWang Bao amp Guan 2020 pp 6 8Csikszentmihalyi amp Ivanhoe 1999 p 35 Leaman 2002 pp 77 78DeGrood 1976 p 37 MacFarlane 2017Corkum 2015 pp 753 767Blair amp Johnson 2000 pp 93 95Magnus 2005 pp 12 14 1 6 Formal languages Shapiro amp Kouri Kissel 2022 2 1 Building blocksCook 2009 p 111Kind 2018 p 236Casati amp Fujikawa lead section 1 Existence as a Second Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification Nolt 2021 lead section 1 The Basics Nolt 2021 5 4 Logics of Fiction Morscher amp Hieke 2013 p 118Nolt 2021 lead section 1 The Basics 5 4 Logics of FictionSider 2010 p 129 Martinich amp Stroll 2023 lead section The nature of epistemologyAudi 2006 Epistemology Philosophy of mind Philosophy of language Urban 2014 p 33Raftopoulos amp Machamer 2012 pp 1 2 142Michaelson amp Reimer 2022 lead section 1 Introduction Asay lead sectionSmith Mulligan amp Simons 2013 pp 9 10 Burnham amp Papandreopoulos lead section 1c Freedom 1e Existence 1f Irrationality AbsurdityAho 2023 lead section Sources edit Adamson Peter 2015 Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps Vol 2 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 872802 3 Archived from the original on 2023 07 11 Retrieved 2023 05 25 Addis Laird 2 May 2013 Mind Ontology and Explanation Collected Papers 1981 2005 Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 032715 1 AHD staff 2022 The American Heritage Dictionary entry existence www ahdictionary com HarperCollins Retrieved 10 August 2023 Aho Kevin 2023 Existentialism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 August 2023 Albertazzi Liliana Jacquette Dale 5 July 2017 The School of Alexius Meinong Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 351 88226 2 Asay Jamin Truthmaker Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 14 August 2023 Audi Robert 2006 Philosophy In Borchert Donald M ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy 7 Oakeshott Presupposition 2 ed Thomson Gale Macmillan Reference ISBN 978 0 02 865787 5 Archived from the original on 2022 02 14 Balaguer Mark 2016 Platonism in Metaphysics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 1 What is Platonism Balthasar Hans Urs von 1 January 2000 Theo Logic Vol 1 Truth of the World Ignatius Press ISBN 978 0 89870 718 2 Belfiore Francesco 17 November 2016 The Triadic Structure of the Mind Outlines of a Philosophical System Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7618 6857 6 Berto Francesco Plebani Matteo 29 January 2015 Ontology and Metaontology A Contemporary Guide Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 4725 7330 8 Berto Francesco 17 October 2012 Existence as a Real Property The Ontology of Meinongianism Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 007 4206 2 Blackburn Simon 1 January 2008 existence The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 954143 0 Blair J Anthony Johnson Ralph H 2000 Informal Logic An Overview Informal Logic 20 2 doi 10 22329 il v20i2 2262 Archived from the original on 9 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Bottani Andrea Davies Richard 2 May 2013 Modes of Existence Papers in Ontology and Philosophical Logic Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 032753 3 Brandl Johannes L Textor Mark 2022 Brentano s Theory of Judgement The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 16 August 2023 Burnham Douglas Papandreopoulos George Existentialism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 14 August 2023 Camus Albert 2007 Christian Metaphysics and Neoplatonism University of Missouri Press ISBN 978 0 8262 6622 4 Archived from the original on 2023 05 28 Retrieved 2023 05 28 Casati Filippo Fujikawa Naoya Existence Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 7 August 2023 Ceylan Yasin 1993 A Critical Approach to the Avicennian Distinction of Essence and Existence Islamic Studies 32 3 ISSN 0578 8072 JSTOR 20840134 Chakrabarti A 14 March 2013 Denying Existence The Logic Epistemology and Pragmatics of Negative Existentials and Fictional Discourse Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 017 1223 1 Coakley Sarah Shelemay Kay Kaufman 2007 Pain and Its Transformations The Interface of Biology and Culture Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 02456 4 Cook Roy T 20 March 2009 Dictionary of Philosophical Logic Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 0 7486 3197 1 Corkum Philip 2015 Generality and Logical Constancy Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 71 4 doi 10 17990 rpf 2015 71 4 0753 ISSN 0870 5283 JSTOR 43744657 Cornwell Neil 19 July 2013 The absurd in literature Manchester University Press ISBN 978 1 84779 657 8 Csikszentmihalyi Mark Ivanhoe Philip J 1 January 1999 Religious and Philosophical Aspects of the Laozi SUNY Press ISBN 978 0 7914 4111 4 CUP staff existence Cambridge Dictionary Cambridge University Press Retrieved 10 August 2023 Dalal Neil 2021 Saṅkara The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 27 January 2022 Retrieved 19 June 2023 Darvill Timothy 1 January 2009 idealism The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Archaeology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 953404 3 DeGrood David H 1 January 1976 Philosophies of Essence An Examination of the Category of Essence John Benjamins Publishing ISBN 978 90 6032 076 1 Dehsen Christian von 13 September 2013 Philosophers and Religious Leaders Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 95102 3 Archived from the original on 28 May 2023 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Divers J 2011 Worlds and Individuals Possible and Otherwise by Takashi Yagisawa Mind 120 478 doi 10 1093 mind fzr027 Dobrez L A C 13 January 2014 The Existential and its Exits Literary and Philosophical Perspectives on the Works of Beckett Ionesco Genet and Pinter A amp C Black ISBN 978 1 4725 1467 7 Duignan Brian ed 15 August 2010 Ancient Philosophy From 600 BCE to 500 CE The Rosen Publishing Group Inc ISBN 978 1 61530 141 6 Archived from the original on 28 May 2023 Retrieved 28 May 2023 EB staff 2017 Chinese philosophy www britannica com Archived from the original on 2 May 2015 Retrieved 12 June 2023 EB staff 3 July 2023 Mind www britannica com Retrieved 17 August 2023 Falguera Jose L Martinez Vidal Concha Rosen Gideon 2022 Abstract Objects The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University lead section 1 Introduction Retrieved 12 August 2023 Faulkner Nicholas Gregersen Erik 15 December 2017 The History of Mathematics The Rosen Publishing Group Inc ISBN 978 1 68048 777 0 Favaretti Camposampiero Matteo Plebani Matteo 2 May 2013 Existence and Nature New Perspectives Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 032180 7 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Fierro Ricardo D 13 January 2012 Mathematics for Elementary School Teachers Cengage Learning ISBN 978 1 133 71210 7 Furley David ed 2005 II From Aristotle to Augustine Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 02845 2 Gibson Q B 31 July 1998 The Existence Principle Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 0 7923 5188 7 Goldschmidt Tyron Pearce Kenneth L 1 December 2017 Idealism New Essays in Metaphysics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 106399 2 Graham Jacob N Ancient Greek Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 16 August 2023 Grayling A C 20 June 2019 The History of Philosophy Penguin UK ISBN 978 0 241 98086 6 Archived from the original on 3 July 2023 Retrieved 24 May 2023 Haan Daniel D De 10 August 2020 Necessary Existence and the Doctrine of Being in Avicenna s Metaphysics of the Healing BRILL ISBN 978 90 04 43452 3 Hailperin Theodore August 1967 Nicholas Rescher Definitions of existence Philosophical studies Minneapolis vol 8 1957 pp 65 69 Karel Lambert Notes on E Philosophical studies Minneapolis vol 9 1958 pp 60 63 Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 2 doi 10 2307 2271672 JSTOR 2271672 S2CID 121302904 Harper Douglas 2017 existence www etymonline com Retrieved 10 August 2023 He Dongshan Gao Dongfeng Cai Qing yu 3 April 2014 Spontaneous creation of the universe from nothing Physical Review D 89 8 arXiv 1404 1207 Bibcode 2014PhRvD 89h3510H doi 10 1103 PhysRevD 89 083510 S2CID 118371273 Heisig James W Kasulis Thomas P Maraldo John C 31 July 2011 Japanese Philosophy A Sourcebook University of Hawaii Press ISBN 978 0 8248 3707 5 Hoad T F 1993 The concise Oxford dictionary of english etymology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 283098 2 Hofweber Thomas 2023 Logic and Ontology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 19 August 2023 Honderich Ted ed 2005 Ontology The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on 29 January 2021 Retrieved 2 January 2022 Husserl Edmund 1 October 2019 Logic and General Theory of Science Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 14529 3 Jacquette Dale 2015 Alexius Meinong The Shepherd of Non Being Springer ISBN 978 3 319 18074 8 Kelly Eugene 30 March 2004 The Basics of Western Philosophy Greenwood Publishing Group ISBN 978 0 313 32352 2 Kim Jaegwon 2006 1 Introduction Philosophy of Mind 2nd ed Boulder Westview Press Archived from the original on 2021 06 02 Retrieved 2021 06 01 Kind Amy 6 July 2018 Philosophy of Mind in the Twentieth and Twenty First Centuries The History of the Philosophy of Mind Volume 6 Routledge ISBN 978 0 429 01938 8 Kriegel Uriah 13 February 2018 Brentano s Philosophical System Mind Being Value Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 250910 9 Lambert Karel 1 January 1994 A Note on Singular and General Existence KRITERION Journal of Philosophy 7 1 doi 10 1515 krt 1994 010704 S2CID 251981034 Lawson Russell M 2004 Science in the Ancient World An Encyclopedia ABC CLIO ISBN 978 1 85109 534 6 Archived from the original on 2023 05 28 Retrieved 2023 05 28 Leaman Oliver 11 September 2002 Key Concepts in Eastern Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 68905 7 Leclerc Ivor 2002 The Nature of Physical Existence Psychology Press ISBN 978 0 415 29561 1 Liu Jeeloo Berger Douglas 13 June 2014 Nothingness in Asian Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 68383 4 Livingston Paul Cutrofello Andrew 8 December 2015 The Problems of Contemporary Philosophy A Critical Guide for the Unaffiliated John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 5095 0144 1 Lowe E J 1 January 2005 existence The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 MacFarlane John 2017 Logical Constants The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 17 March 2020 Retrieved 21 November 2021 Magnus P D 2005 Forall X An Introduction to Formal Logic Victoria BC Canada State University of New York Oer Services ISBN 978 1 64176 026 3 Archived from the original on 7 December 2021 Retrieved 29 December 2021 Mahapatra Debidatta Aurobinda 14 May 2020 The Philosophy of Sri Aurobindo Indian Philosophy and Yoga in the Contemporary World Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 350 12487 5 Markosian Ned 13 April 2009 Physical object In Kim Jaekwon Sosa Ernest Rosenkrantz Gary S eds A Companion to Metaphysics John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4051 5298 3 Martinich A P Stroll Avrum 2023 Epistemology Encyclopaedia Britannica Archived from the original on 10 July 2019 Retrieved 22 June 2020 McDaniel Kris 28 July 2017 The Fragmentation of Being Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 103037 6 Menn Stephen 2021 Aristotle On The Many Senses Of Being In Caston Victor ed Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Volume 59 Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Volume 59 OUP ISBN 978 0 19 189162 5 Menon Sangeetha Vedanta Advaita Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 15 August 2023 Michaelson Eliot Reimer Marga 2022 Reference The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 August 2023 Morin Marie Eve 23 June 2017 Continental Realism and Its Discontents Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 1 4744 2115 7 Morscher E Hieke A 14 March 2013 New Essays in Free Logic In Honour of Karel Lambert Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 015 9761 6 MW staff 3 August 2023 Definition of EXISTENCE www merriam webster com Retrieved 10 August 2023 Nelson Michael 2022 Existence The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 6 August 2023 Nicholson Graeme 1996 The Ontological Difference American Philosophical Quarterly 33 4 ISSN 0003 0481 JSTOR 20009875 Nolt John 2021 Free Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 August 2023 Novotny Daniel D Novak Lukas 16 April 2014 Neo Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 63009 7 Penelope Mackie 1998 Existence www rep routledge com Routledge Retrieved 7 August 2023 Perkins Franklin 2019 Metaphysics in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 16 August 2023 Perrett Roy W 4 February 2016 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 85356 9 Archived from the original on 22 June 2023 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Platter Jonathan M 5 July 2021 Divine Simplicity and the Triune Identity A Critical Dialogue with the Theological Metaphysics of Robert W Jenson Walter de Gruyter GmbH amp Co KG ISBN 978 3 11 073601 4 Poidevin Robin Le Peter Simons Andrew McGonigal Cameron Ross P 2 April 2009 The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 15585 9 Prior A N 2006 Existences In Borchert Donald ed Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy Volume 3 2nd ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Pruss Alexander R Rasmussen Joshua L 2018 Necessary Existence Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 874689 8 Raftopoulos Athanassios Machamer Peter 12 April 2012 Perception Realism and the Problem of Reference Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 19877 6 Reicher Maria 2022 Nonexistent Objects The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University lead section 1 The Concept of a Nonexistent Object Retrieved 10 August 2023 Rescher Nicholas October 1957 Definitions of existence Philosophical Studies 8 5 doi 10 1007 bf02304902 S2CID 170408608 Robinson Howard 2008 7 Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God s Existence is Identical to His Essence In Stone Martin William Francis ed Reason faith and history philosophical essays for Paul Helm Ashgate Publishing ISBN 978 0 7546 0926 1 Rollinger Robin D 29 June 2013 Husserl s Position in the School of Brentano Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 017 1808 0 Ruzsa Ferenc 2023 Sankhya Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 19 May 2019 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Searle John R 1 November 2004 Mind A Brief Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 988268 7 Shand John 1 March 2004 Fundamentals of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 58831 2 Shapiro Stewart Kouri Kissel Teresa 2022 Classical Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 August 2023 Sider Theodore 7 January 2010 Logic for Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 265881 4 Smart John Jamieson Carswell 28 July 2023 Materialism Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 17 August 2023 Smith Barry Mulligan Kevin Simons Peter 2 May 2013 Monnoyer Jean Maurice ed Metaphysics and Truthmakers Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 032691 8 Smith Peter Worden David 2003 Key Beliefs Ultimate Questions and Life Issues Heinemann ISBN 978 0 435 30699 1 Sorensen Roy 2023 Nothingness The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 17 August 2023 Sovik Atle Ottesen 4 April 2022 A Basic Theory of Everything A Fundamental Theoretical Framework for Science and Philosophy Walter de Gruyter GmbH amp Co KG ISBN 978 3 11 077095 7 Stadler Friedrich Stoltzner Michael 2 May 2013 Time and History Proceedings of the 28 International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium Kirchberg am Wechsel Austria 2005 Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 033321 3 Trott Adriel M 8 October 2019 Aristotle on the Matter of Form I Feminist Metaphysics of Generation Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 1 4744 5525 1 Turner Denys 16 September 2004 Faith Reason and the Existence of God Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 60256 3 Tymieniecka Anna Teresa 6 December 2012 The Later Husserl and the Idea of Phenomenology Idealism Realism Historicity and Nature Papers and Debate of the International Phenomenological Conference Held at the University of Waterloo Canada April 9 14 1969 Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 010 2882 0 Urban Wilbur Marshall 3 June 2014 Language and Reality The Philosophy of Language and the Principles of Symbolism Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 85195 0 Vallicella William F 2010 A Paradigm theory of existence Onto Theology vindicated Kluwer Academic ISBN 978 90 481 6128 7 van Inwagen Peter 2023 Existence www britannica com Retrieved 7 August 2023 Van Inwagen Peter 2009 Metaphysics 3 ed Westview Press ISBN 978 0 8133 4356 3 Vanamali 30 January 2015 The Science of the Rishis The Spiritual and Material Discoveries of the Ancient Sages of India Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 1 62055 387 9 Wang Yueqing Bao Qinggang Guan Guoxing 16 March 2020 History of Chinese Philosophy Through Its Key Terms Springer Nature ISBN 978 981 15 2572 8 Archived from the original on 22 June 2023 Retrieved 13 June 2023 Wheeler Michael 2020 Martin Heidegger The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 August 2023 Yagisawa Takashi 2011 Precis of Worlds and Individuals Possible and Otherwise Analytic Philosophy 52 4 doi 10 1111 j 2153 960X 2011 00534 x Further reading editAristotle 1998 The Metaphysics Translated by Lawson Tancred Hugh Penguin Books ISBN 0 14 044619 2 Thalheimer Alvin 1920 The Meaning of the Terms existence and reality Princeton University Press Williams Christopher John Fardo 1981 What is Existence Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824429 5 W Kneale G E Moore July 15 1936 Symposium Is Existence a Predicate Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume Vol 15 Oxford University Press pp 154 188 doi 10 1093 aristoteliansupp 15 1 154 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Existence nbsp Look up existence in Wiktionary the free dictionary The Concept of Existence History and Definitions from Leading Philosophers Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Existence amp oldid 1186044155 Context in philosophy, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.