fbpx
Wikipedia

British philosophy

British philosophy refers to the philosophical tradition of the British people. "The native characteristics of British philosophy are these: common sense, dislike of complication, a strong preference for the concrete over the abstract and a certain awkward honesty of method in which an occasional pearl of poetry is embedded".[1]

David Hume, a profoundly influential 18th-century Scottish philosopher

Medieval edit

Anselm of Canterbury edit

 
A colourised 16th-century portrait of Anselm, Archbishop of Canterbury

Saint Anselm of Canterbury (c. 1033 – 1109) was an important philosopher and theologian of the Catholic Church, who held the office of Archbishop of Canterbury from 1093 to 1109. Anselm is famed as the originator of the ontological argument for the existence of God and of the satisfaction theory of atonement. Anselm's works are considered philosophical as well as theological since they endeavour to render Christian tenets of faith, traditionally taken as a revealed truth, as a rational system.[2]

William of Sherwood edit

William of Sherwood (c. 1200 – c. 1272) was a medieval English scholastic philosopher, logician, and teacher. Little is known of his life, but he is thought to have studied in Paris and he was a master at Oxford in 1252. He was the author of two books which were an important influence on the development of scholastic logic: Introductiones in Logicam (Introduction to Logic), and Syncategoremata. These are the first known works to deal in a systematic way with what is now called supposition theory, and were influential on the development of logic in both England and on the continent. According to Roger Bacon, Sherwood was among "the more famous wise men of Christendom", of whom he names another as Albertus Magnus. Bacon judged Sherwood to be "much wiser than Albert".[3]

Roger Bacon edit

Roger Bacon (c. 1214–1294), also known as Doctor Mirabilis (Latin: "Wondrous Doctor"), was an English philosopher and Franciscan friar who placed considerable emphasis on empirical methods. He is sometimes credited as one of the earliest European advocates of the modern scientific method[4] inspired by the works of Plato and Aristotle via early Islamic scientists such as Avicenna and Averroes.[5][6][7]

Duns Scotus edit

John Duns Scotus (c. 1265 – 8 November 1308) was an important philosopher and theologian of the High Middle Ages. Scotus was born around 1265,[8] at Duns, in Berwickshire, Scotland. In 1291 he was ordained as a priest in Northampton, England. A note in Codex 66 of Merton College, Oxford, records that Scotus "flourished at Cambridge, Oxford and Paris". He died in Cologne in 1308. He is buried in the "Minoritenkirche", the Church of the Franciscans (or Minor Friars) in Cologne. He was beatified by Pope John Paul II on 20 March 1993.

Nicknamed Doctor Subtilis (the subtle doctor), he is well known for the "univocity of being," the formal distinction, and the idea of haecceity. The univocity of being holds that existence is the most abstract concept we have and is applicable to everything that exists. The formal distinction is a way of distinguishing between different aspects of the same thing such that the distinction is intermediate between what is merely conceptual, and what is fully real or mind-independent. Haecceity (from the Latin haecceitas) is the idea of "thisness," a concept which denotes the discrete qualities, properties or characteristics of a thing which make it a particular thing.

William of Ockham edit

William of Ockham (c. 1288 – c. 1348) was an English Franciscan friar and scholastic philosopher. He is perhaps most well known for his principle of parsimony, famously known as Occam's razor. This actual term is claimed not to appear in his writings,[9] but rather summarizes the principle he expressed in passages such as Numquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necessitate [Plurality must never be posited without necessity][10][11] and Frustra fit per plura quod potest fieri per pauciora (It is futile to do with more things that which can be done with fewer).[12] Generally it refers to distinguishing between two hypotheses either by "shaving away" unnecessary assumptions or cutting apart two similar conclusions.

The words often attributed to Occam: entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem ("entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity") are absent in his extant works;[13] This particular phrasing comes from John Punch who used it in describing a "common axiom" (axioma vulgare) of the Scholastics.[14]

Modern edit

Francis Bacon edit

 
Francis Bacon

Francis Bacon (1561–1626) was an Englishman who was a statesman, scientist, lawyer, jurist and author in addition to being a philosopher. He famously died of pneumonia contracted while studying the effects of freezing on the preservation of meat. He served both as Attorney General and Lord Chancellor of England. Although his political career ended in disgrace, he remained extremely influential through his works, especially as philosophical advocate and practitioner of the scientific method and pioneer in the scientific revolution.

Bacon has been called the father of empiricism.[15] His works established and popularized deductive methodologies for scientific inquiry, often called the Baconian method or simply, the scientific method. His demand for a planned procedure of investigating all things natural marked a new turn in the rhetorical and theoretical framework for science, much of which still surrounds conceptions of proper methodology today. His dedication probably led to his death, so bringing him into a rare historical group of scientists who were killed by their own experiments.

Thomas Hobbes edit

Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) was an English philosopher, remembered today for his work on political philosophy. His 1651 book Leviathan established the foundation for most of Western political philosophy from the perspective of social contract theory.[16]

Hobbes was a champion of absolutism for the sovereign but he also developed some of the fundamentals of European liberal thought: the right of the individual; the natural equality of all men; the artificial character of the political order (which led to the later distinction between civil society and the state); the view that all legitimate political power must be "representative" and based on the consent of the people; and a liberal interpretation of law which leaves people free to do whatever the law does not explicitly forbid.[17]

Hobbes also contributed to a diverse array of fields, including history, geometry, physics of gases, theology, ethics, general philosophy, and political science. His account of human nature as self-interested cooperation has proved to be an enduring theory in the field of philosophical anthropology. He was one of the key founders of philosophical materialism.

The classic trio of British empiricists edit

The three 'classic' British empiricists in the early modern era were John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume. The term "British empiricism" refers to the philosophical tradition in Britain that was epitomised by these thinkers (though this tradition did have precursors in Britain stretching back to Roger Bacon). Berkeley, despite being Irish, was referred to as British as County Kilkenny, where he lived in Ireland, was a part of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland at the time.

John Locke edit

 
John Locke

John Locke (1632–1704) was an empiricist at the beginning of the Modern period of philosophy. As such (and in contrast to René Descartes), he held that all of the objects of the understanding are ideas, where ideas exist in the mind. One of his goals in his work An Essay Concerning Human Understanding is to trace the origin of ideas. There are no innate ideas “stamped upon the mind” from birth, and all knowledge is rooted in experience. Further, there are also simple ideas and complex ideas. Simple ideas enter by the senses, and they are simple and unmixed. Complex ideas are simple ideas that have been combined and related together using the abstracting activity of the mind.

John Locke embodied the idea of religious tolerance and said "no mans knowledge can exceed his experience" based on his background in epistemology.

Locke is also responsible for an early theory of personal identity. He thought that our being the same person from one time to another consists, not in our having the same soul or the same body, but rather the same series of psychological connections. For Locke, to be a person is to be an intelligent thinking being that can know itself as itself, the same thinking thing in different times and places.

George Berkeley edit

George Berkeley (1685–1753) was an Irish philosopher who served as Bishop of Cloyne from 1734 until his death. He was a British empiricist,[18] an immaterialist, and an idealist. Many of his most important ideas were first put forth in A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, a work which was critical of John Locke's philosophy. Berkeley agreed with Locke that there was an outside world which caused the ideas within the mind, but Berkeley sought to prove that the outside world was also composed solely of ideas. Berkeley thought that the ideas that we possessed could only resemble other ideas (not physical objects) and thus the external world consisted not of physical form, but rather of ideas. This world was given logic and regularity by some other force, which Berkeley concluded was God.

Berkeley is famous for his motto "esse est percipi aut percipere", or otherwise, "to exist is to be perceived, or to perceive". This means that there are no things other than ideas and the minds that house them. There is no such thing as a mind-independent entity.

David Hume edit

David Hume (1711–1776) was a Scottish philosopher, economist, and historian. His major works, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739–1740), the An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (1748), An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (1751), and Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779) remain widely influential.[19] His ideas regarding free will and determinism, causation, personal identity, induction, and morality still inspire discussion.

Hume famously described the problem of induction. He argues that inductive reasoning cannot be rationally employed, since, in order to justify induction, one would either have to provide a sound deductive argument or an inductively strong argument. But there is no sound deductive argument for induction, and to ask for an inductive argument to justify induction would be to beg the question.

Hume's problem of causation is related to his problem of induction. He held that there is no empirical access to the supposed necessary connection between cause and effect. In seeking to justify the belief that A causes B, one would point out that, in the past, B has always closely followed A in both space and time. But the special necessary connection that is supposed to be causation is never given to us in experience. We only observe a constant conjunction of events, with no necessity whatsoever.

In personal identity, Hume was a bundle theorist. He said that there is no robust self to which properties adhere. Experience only shows us that there is only a bundle of perceptions.

Adam Smith edit

Adam Smith (1723–1790) was a Scottish moral philosopher and a pioneer of political economics. Smith wrote The Theory of Moral Sentiments and An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. The latter, usually abbreviated as The Wealth of Nations, is considered his magnum opus and the first modern work of economics. Smith is widely cited as the father of modern economics.

Smith studied moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow and the University of Oxford. After graduating, he delivered a successful series of public lectures at Edinburgh, leading him to collaborate with David Hume during the Scottish Enlightenment. Smith obtained a professorship at Glasgow teaching moral philosophy, and during this time he wrote and published The Theory of Moral Sentiments.

19th century edit

Jeremy Bentham edit

Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) is well known for beginning the tradition of classical utilitarianism in Britain. Utilitarianism is a consequentialist theory of normative ethics which holds that an act is morally right if and only if that act maximizes happiness or pleasure. Classical utilitarianism is said to be hedonistic because it regards pleasure as the only intrinsic good and pain as the only intrinsic evil.[20]

Utilitarianism was described by Bentham as "the greatest happiness or greatest felicity principle".[21] Bentham's utilitarianism is known for arguing that the felicific calculus should be used to determine the rightness and wrongness of acts. It does this by measuring the amount of pain and pleasure for various acts. Bentham thought that pleasure and pain be broke down in distinct units called hedons and dolors.

John Stuart Mill edit

 
John Stuart Mill

John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) was an influential contributor to social theory, political theory, and political economy. His conception of liberty justified the freedom of the individual in opposition to unlimited state control.[22]

Mill also continued Bentham's tradition of advancing and defending utilitarianism. Mill's book Utilitarianism is a philosophical defense of utilitarianism. The essay first appeared as a series of three articles published in Fraser's Magazine in 1861; the articles were collected and reprinted as a single book in 1863.

Henry Sidgwick edit

Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) also focused on utilitarian ethics and was one of the founders and first president of the Society for Psychical Research, was a member of the Metaphysical Society, and promoted the higher education of women. The Methods of Ethics is a book on utilitarianism written by Sidgwick that was first published in 1874.[23] The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy indicates that The Methods of Ethics "in many ways marked the culmination of the classical utilitarian tradition." Well-known contemporary utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer has said that the Methods "is simply the best book on ethics ever written."[24]

British idealism edit

As an area of absolute idealism, British idealism was a philosophical movement that was influential in Britain from the mid-nineteenth century to the early twentieth century. Important representatives included T. H. Green, F. H. Bradley, Bernard Bosanquet, J. M. E. McTaggart, H. H. Joachim, J. H. Muirhead, and G. R. G. Mure. Two British philosophers, G. E. Moore and Bertrand Russell, were brought up in this tradition and then reacted against it by pioneering analytic philosophy.

20th century and beyond edit

Analytic philosophy edit

Analytic philosophy was based on traditional British empiricism, updated to accommodate the new developments in logic pioneered by German mathematician Gottlob Frege. It has dominated philosophy in the English-speaking world since the early 20th century.

G. E. Moore edit

George Edward Moore (1873–1958) was an English philosopher. One of the founders of the analytic tradition, he led the British 'revolt against idealism' at the turn of the twentieth century, along with Bertrand Russell - while Russell is better known, he stated that it was in fact Moore who "led the way".[25]

Moore is best known today for his defence of ethical non-naturalism, his emphasis on common sense in philosophical method, and the paradox that bears his name. He was admired by and influential among other philosophers, and also by the Bloomsbury Group, but is (unlike his colleague Russell) mostly unknown today outside of academic philosophy. Moore's essays are known for his clear, circumspect writing style, and for his methodical and patient approach to philosophical problems. He was critical of philosophy for its lack of progress, which he believed was in stark contrast to the dramatic advances in the natural sciences since the Renaissance. He often praised the analytic reasoning of Thales of Miletus, an early Greek philosopher, for his analysis of the meaning of the term "landscaping". Moore thought Thales' reasoning was one of the few historical examples of philosophical inquiry resulting in practical advances. Among his most famous works are his book Principia Ethica, and his essays, "The Refutation of Idealism", "A Defence of Common Sense", and "A Proof of the External World".

He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1918 to 1919.[26]

Bertrand Russell edit

 
Bertrand Russell

Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) led the British "revolt against idealism" in the early 1900s, along with G. E. Moore. He was influenced by Gottlob Frege, and was the mentor of Ludwig Wittgenstein. He is widely held to be one of the 20th century's premier logicians.[27] He co-authored, with Alfred North Whitehead, Principia Mathematica, an attempt to derive all mathematical truths from a set of axioms using rules of inference in symbolic logic. His philosophical essay "On Denoting" has been considered a "paradigm of philosophy."[28] Both works have had a considerable influence on logic, mathematics, set theory, linguistics, and philosophy.

Russell's theory of descriptions has been profoundly influential in the philosophy of language and the analysis of definite descriptions. His theory was first developed in his 1905 paper "On Denoting".

Russell was a prominent anti-war activist; he championed free trade and anti-imperialism.[29][30] Russell went to prison for his pacifist activism during World War I. Later, he campaigned against Adolf Hitler, then criticised Stalinist totalitarianism, attacked the United States of America's involvement in the Vietnam War, and finally became an outspoken proponent of nuclear disarmament.[31]

In 1950, Russell was awarded the Nobel Prize in Literature, "in recognition of his varied and significant writings in which he champions humanitarian ideals and freedom of thought."[32]

A. J. Ayer edit

Sir Alfred Jules Ayer (29 October 1910, London – 27 June 1989, London), better known as A. J. Ayer or "Freddie" to friends, was a British analytic philosopher known for his promotion of logical positivism, particularly in his books Language, Truth and Logic (1936) and The Problem of Knowledge (1956).

Ordinary language philosophy edit

Ordinary language philosophy is a philosophical school that approaches traditional philosophical problems as rooted in misunderstandings that philosophers develop by forgetting what words mean in their everyday use.

This approach typically involves eschewing philosophical theories in favour of close attention to the detail of everyday language. Sometimes also called "Oxford philosophy", it is generally associated with the work of a number of mid-century Oxford professors: mainly J. L. Austin, but also Gilbert Ryle, H. L. A. Hart, and P.F. Strawson.

It was a major philosophic school between 1930 and 1970.

Contemporary times edit

Recent British philosophers particularly active in the philosophy of religion have included Antony Flew, C. S. Lewis, and John Hick.

Important moral and political philosophers have included R. M. Hare, Alasdair MacIntyre, and Roger Scruton.

Other recent figures in the British analytic tradition include David Wiggins, Derek Parfit, and P. F. Strawson, who have focused on fields such as metaphysics, philosophy of mind, logic, and the philosophy of language.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Matthews, Kenneth (1943). British Philosophers. Great Britain: William Collins. p. 7.
  2. ^ Davies, Brian; et al. (2004). The Cambridge Companion to Anselm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 2. ISBN 0-521-00205-2.
  3. ^ Bacon, Roger (1859). "Preface". In Brewer, J.S. (ed.). Fr. Rogeri Bacon opera quædam hactenus inedita. Vol. I. Translated by Kretzmann, Norman. London.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  4. ^ Randall Noon (1992). Introduction to Forensic Engineering. CRC Press. ISBN 0-8493-8102-9.
  5. ^ Glick, Thomas F.; Livesey, Steven John; Wallis, Faith: Medieval Science, Technology, and Medicine: An Encyclopedia, first edition, Routledge, September 29, 2005, ISBN 978-0-415-96930-7
  6. ^ Moorstein, Mark: Frameworks: Conflict in Balance, page 237, iUniverse, Inc., June 9, 2004, 308 pp, ISBN 978-0-595-31824-7
  7. ^ Sayed Khatab and Gary D. Bouma (2007). Democracy in Islam. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-42574-2.
  8. ^ Brampton 'Duns Scotus at Oxford, 1288-1301', Franciscan Studies, 24 (1964) 17.
  9. ^ "What Ockham really said". Boing Boing. 2013-02-11. Retrieved 2013-03-26.
  10. ^ 'Sentences of Peter Lombard', Quaestiones et decisiones in quattuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi (ed. Lugd., 1495), i, dist. 27, qu. 2, K)
  11. ^ "Ockham's razor". Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. 2010. Retrieved 12 June 2010.
  12. ^ Summa Totius Logicae, i. 12, Thorburn, 1918, pp.352–53; Kneale and Kneale, 1962, p.243.)
  13. ^ Flew, Antony (1979). A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Pan Books. p. 253.
  14. ^ Alistair Cameron Crombie (1959), Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard, Vol. 2, p. 30.
  15. ^ Home | Sweet Briar College July 8, 2013, at the Wayback Machine. Psychology.sbc.edu. Retrieved on 2013-07-29.
  16. ^ "Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2020. . Retrieved March 11, 2009.
  17. ^ Pierre Manent, An Intellectual History of Liberalism (1994) pp 20–38
  18. ^ Berkeley, George 2015-12-08 at the Wayback MachineInternet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  19. ^ "David Hume" at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved May 15, 2010
  20. ^ "Consequentialism" at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved April 10, 2011
  21. ^ AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION, Jeremy Bentham, 1789 (“printed” in 1780, “first published” in 1789, "corrected by the Author" in 1823.) See Chapter I: Of the Principle of Utility. For Bentham on animals, see Ch. XVII Note 122.
  22. ^ "John Stuart Mill's On Liberty". victorianweb. Retrieved 2009-07-23. On Liberty is a rational justification of the freedom of the individual in opposition to the claims of the state to impose unlimited control and is thus a defence of the rights of the individual against the state.
  23. ^ "Henry Sidgwick, 1838-1900" at The History of Economic Thought Website 2010-08-07 at the Wayback Machine Retrieved April 10, 2011
  24. ^ Peter Singer - Interview at NormativeEthics.com 2011-07-14 at the Wayback Machine Retrieved April 10, 2011
  25. ^ Analytic Philosophy And Return Hegelian Thought :: Philosophy: general interest :: Cambridge University Press. Cambridge.org. Retrieved on 2013-07-29.
  26. ^ The Aristotelian Society – The Council
  27. ^ "Bertrand Russell" at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philososophy Retrieved May 15, 2010
  28. ^ Ludlow, Peter, "Descriptions", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = [1].
  29. ^ Richard Rempel (1979). "From Imperialism to Free Trade: Couturat, Halevy and Russell's First Crusade". Journal of the History of Ideas. University of Pennsylvania Press. 40 (3): 423–443. doi:10.2307/2709246. JSTOR 2709246.
  30. ^ Bertrand Russell (1988) [1917]. Political Ideals. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-10907-8.
  31. ^ The Nobel Foundation (1950). Bertrand Russell: The Nobel Prize in Literature 1950. Retrieved on 11 June 2007.

british, philosophy, refers, philosophical, tradition, british, people, native, characteristics, these, common, sense, dislike, complication, strong, preference, concrete, over, abstract, certain, awkward, honesty, method, which, occasional, pearl, poetry, emb. British philosophy refers to the philosophical tradition of the British people The native characteristics of British philosophy are these common sense dislike of complication a strong preference for the concrete over the abstract and a certain awkward honesty of method in which an occasional pearl of poetry is embedded 1 David Hume a profoundly influential 18th century Scottish philosopher Contents 1 Medieval 1 1 Anselm of Canterbury 1 2 William of Sherwood 1 3 Roger Bacon 1 4 Duns Scotus 1 5 William of Ockham 2 Modern 2 1 Francis Bacon 2 2 Thomas Hobbes 2 3 The classic trio of British empiricists 2 3 1 John Locke 2 3 2 George Berkeley 2 3 3 David Hume 2 4 Adam Smith 3 19th century 3 1 Jeremy Bentham 3 2 John Stuart Mill 3 3 Henry Sidgwick 3 4 British idealism 4 20th century and beyond 4 1 Analytic philosophy 4 1 1 G E Moore 4 1 2 Bertrand Russell 4 1 3 A J Ayer 4 1 4 Ordinary language philosophy 4 2 Contemporary times 5 See also 6 ReferencesMedieval editAnselm of Canterbury edit Main article Anselm of Canterbury nbsp A colourised 16th century portrait of Anselm Archbishop of CanterburySaint Anselm of Canterbury c 1033 1109 was an important philosopher and theologian of the Catholic Church who held the office of Archbishop of Canterbury from 1093 to 1109 Anselm is famed as the originator of the ontological argument for the existence of God and of the satisfaction theory of atonement Anselm s works are considered philosophical as well as theological since they endeavour to render Christian tenets of faith traditionally taken as a revealed truth as a rational system 2 William of Sherwood edit Main article William of Sherwood William of Sherwood c 1200 c 1272 was a medieval English scholastic philosopher logician and teacher Little is known of his life but he is thought to have studied in Paris and he was a master at Oxford in 1252 He was the author of two books which were an important influence on the development of scholastic logic Introductiones in Logicam Introduction to Logic and Syncategoremata These are the first known works to deal in a systematic way with what is now called supposition theory and were influential on the development of logic in both England and on the continent According to Roger Bacon Sherwood was among the more famous wise men of Christendom of whom he names another as Albertus Magnus Bacon judged Sherwood to be much wiser than Albert 3 Roger Bacon edit Main article Roger Bacon Roger Bacon c 1214 1294 also known as Doctor Mirabilis Latin Wondrous Doctor was an English philosopher and Franciscan friar who placed considerable emphasis on empirical methods He is sometimes credited as one of the earliest European advocates of the modern scientific method 4 inspired by the works of Plato and Aristotle via early Islamic scientists such as Avicenna and Averroes 5 6 7 Duns Scotus edit Main article Duns Scotus John Duns Scotus c 1265 8 November 1308 was an important philosopher and theologian of the High Middle Ages Scotus was born around 1265 8 at Duns in Berwickshire Scotland In 1291 he was ordained as a priest in Northampton England A note in Codex 66 of Merton College Oxford records that Scotus flourished at Cambridge Oxford and Paris He died in Cologne in 1308 He is buried in the Minoritenkirche the Church of the Franciscans or Minor Friars in Cologne He was beatified by Pope John Paul II on 20 March 1993 Nicknamed Doctor Subtilis the subtle doctor he is well known for the univocity of being the formal distinction and the idea of haecceity The univocity of being holds that existence is the most abstract concept we have and is applicable to everything that exists The formal distinction is a way of distinguishing between different aspects of the same thing such that the distinction is intermediate between what is merely conceptual and what is fully real or mind independent Haecceity from the Latin haecceitas is the idea of thisness a concept which denotes the discrete qualities properties or characteristics of a thing which make it a particular thing William of Ockham edit Main article William of Ockham William of Ockham c 1288 c 1348 was an English Franciscan friar and scholastic philosopher He is perhaps most well known for his principle of parsimony famously known as Occam s razor This actual term is claimed not to appear in his writings 9 but rather summarizes the principle he expressed in passages such as Numquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necessitate Plurality must never be posited without necessity 10 11 and Frustra fit per plura quod potest fieri per pauciora It is futile to do with more things that which can be done with fewer 12 Generally it refers to distinguishing between two hypotheses either by shaving away unnecessary assumptions or cutting apart two similar conclusions The words often attributed to Occam entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity are absent in his extant works 13 This particular phrasing comes from John Punch who used it in describing a common axiom axioma vulgare of the Scholastics 14 Modern editFrancis Bacon edit Main article Francis Bacon nbsp Francis BaconFrancis Bacon 1561 1626 was an Englishman who was a statesman scientist lawyer jurist and author in addition to being a philosopher He famously died of pneumonia contracted while studying the effects of freezing on the preservation of meat He served both as Attorney General and Lord Chancellor of England Although his political career ended in disgrace he remained extremely influential through his works especially as philosophical advocate and practitioner of the scientific method and pioneer in the scientific revolution Bacon has been called the father of empiricism 15 His works established and popularized deductive methodologies for scientific inquiry often called the Baconian method or simply the scientific method His demand for a planned procedure of investigating all things natural marked a new turn in the rhetorical and theoretical framework for science much of which still surrounds conceptions of proper methodology today His dedication probably led to his death so bringing him into a rare historical group of scientists who were killed by their own experiments Thomas Hobbes edit Main article Thomas Hobbes Thomas Hobbes 1588 1679 was an English philosopher remembered today for his work on political philosophy His 1651 book Leviathan established the foundation for most of Western political philosophy from the perspective of social contract theory 16 Hobbes was a champion of absolutism for the sovereign but he also developed some of the fundamentals of European liberal thought the right of the individual the natural equality of all men the artificial character of the political order which led to the later distinction between civil society and the state the view that all legitimate political power must be representative and based on the consent of the people and a liberal interpretation of law which leaves people free to do whatever the law does not explicitly forbid 17 Hobbes also contributed to a diverse array of fields including history geometry physics of gases theology ethics general philosophy and political science His account of human nature as self interested cooperation has proved to be an enduring theory in the field of philosophical anthropology He was one of the key founders of philosophical materialism The classic trio of British empiricists edit The three classic British empiricists in the early modern era were John Locke George Berkeley and David Hume The term British empiricism refers to the philosophical tradition in Britain that was epitomised by these thinkers though this tradition did have precursors in Britain stretching back to Roger Bacon Berkeley despite being Irish was referred to as British as County Kilkenny where he lived in Ireland was a part of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland at the time John Locke edit Main article John Locke nbsp John LockeJohn Locke 1632 1704 was an empiricist at the beginning of the Modern period of philosophy As such and in contrast to Rene Descartes he held that all of the objects of the understanding are ideas where ideas exist in the mind One of his goals in his work An Essay Concerning Human Understanding is to trace the origin of ideas There are no innate ideas stamped upon the mind from birth and all knowledge is rooted in experience Further there are also simple ideas and complex ideas Simple ideas enter by the senses and they are simple and unmixed Complex ideas are simple ideas that have been combined and related together using the abstracting activity of the mind John Locke embodied the idea of religious tolerance and said no mans knowledge can exceed his experience based on his background in epistemology Locke is also responsible for an early theory of personal identity He thought that our being the same person from one time to another consists not in our having the same soul or the same body but rather the same series of psychological connections For Locke to be a person is to be an intelligent thinking being that can know itself as itself the same thinking thing in different times and places George Berkeley edit Main article George Berkeley George Berkeley 1685 1753 was an Irish philosopher who served as Bishop of Cloyne from 1734 until his death He was a British empiricist 18 an immaterialist and an idealist Many of his most important ideas were first put forth in A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge a work which was critical of John Locke s philosophy Berkeley agreed with Locke that there was an outside world which caused the ideas within the mind but Berkeley sought to prove that the outside world was also composed solely of ideas Berkeley thought that the ideas that we possessed could only resemble other ideas not physical objects and thus the external world consisted not of physical form but rather of ideas This world was given logic and regularity by some other force which Berkeley concluded was God Berkeley is famous for his motto esse est percipi aut percipere or otherwise to exist is to be perceived or to perceive This means that there are no things other than ideas and the minds that house them There is no such thing as a mind independent entity David Hume edit Main article David Hume See also Scottish Enlightenment David Hume 1711 1776 was a Scottish philosopher economist and historian His major works A Treatise of Human Nature 1739 1740 the An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding 1748 An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals 1751 and Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion 1779 remain widely influential 19 His ideas regarding free will and determinism causation personal identity induction and morality still inspire discussion Hume famously described the problem of induction He argues that inductive reasoning cannot be rationally employed since in order to justify induction one would either have to provide a sound deductive argument or an inductively strong argument But there is no sound deductive argument for induction and to ask for an inductive argument to justify induction would be to beg the question Hume s problem of causation is related to his problem of induction He held that there is no empirical access to the supposed necessary connection between cause and effect In seeking to justify the belief that A causes B one would point out that in the past B has always closely followed A in both space and time But the special necessary connection that is supposed to be causation is never given to us in experience We only observe a constant conjunction of events with no necessity whatsoever In personal identity Hume was a bundle theorist He said that there is no robust self to which properties adhere Experience only shows us that there is only a bundle of perceptions Adam Smith edit Main article Adam Smith Adam Smith 1723 1790 was a Scottish moral philosopher and a pioneer of political economics Smith wrote The Theory of Moral Sentiments and An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations The latter usually abbreviated as The Wealth of Nations is considered his magnum opus and the first modern work of economics Smith is widely cited as the father of modern economics Smith studied moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow and the University of Oxford After graduating he delivered a successful series of public lectures at Edinburgh leading him to collaborate with David Hume during the Scottish Enlightenment Smith obtained a professorship at Glasgow teaching moral philosophy and during this time he wrote and published The Theory of Moral Sentiments 19th century editJeremy Bentham edit Main article Jeremy Bentham Jeremy Bentham 1748 1832 is well known for beginning the tradition of classical utilitarianism in Britain Utilitarianism is a consequentialist theory of normative ethics which holds that an act is morally right if and only if that act maximizes happiness or pleasure Classical utilitarianism is said to be hedonistic because it regards pleasure as the only intrinsic good and pain as the only intrinsic evil 20 Utilitarianism was described by Bentham as the greatest happiness or greatest felicity principle 21 Bentham s utilitarianism is known for arguing that the felicific calculus should be used to determine the rightness and wrongness of acts It does this by measuring the amount of pain and pleasure for various acts Bentham thought that pleasure and pain be broke down in distinct units called hedons and dolors John Stuart Mill edit Main article John Stuart Mill nbsp John Stuart MillJohn Stuart Mill 1806 1873 was an influential contributor to social theory political theory and political economy His conception of liberty justified the freedom of the individual in opposition to unlimited state control 22 Mill also continued Bentham s tradition of advancing and defending utilitarianism Mill s book Utilitarianism is a philosophical defense of utilitarianism The essay first appeared as a series of three articles published in Fraser s Magazine in 1861 the articles were collected and reprinted as a single book in 1863 Henry Sidgwick edit Main article Henry Sidgwick Henry Sidgwick 1838 1900 also focused on utilitarian ethics and was one of the founders and first president of the Society for Psychical Research was a member of the Metaphysical Society and promoted the higher education of women The Methods of Ethics is a book on utilitarianism written by Sidgwick that was first published in 1874 23 The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy indicates that The Methods of Ethics in many ways marked the culmination of the classical utilitarian tradition Well known contemporary utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer has said that the Methods is simply the best book on ethics ever written 24 British idealism edit Main article British idealism As an area of absolute idealism British idealism was a philosophical movement that was influential in Britain from the mid nineteenth century to the early twentieth century Important representatives included T H Green F H Bradley Bernard Bosanquet J M E McTaggart H H Joachim J H Muirhead and G R G Mure Two British philosophers G E Moore and Bertrand Russell were brought up in this tradition and then reacted against it by pioneering analytic philosophy 20th century and beyond editAnalytic philosophy edit Main article Analytic philosophy Analytic philosophy was based on traditional British empiricism updated to accommodate the new developments in logic pioneered by German mathematician Gottlob Frege It has dominated philosophy in the English speaking world since the early 20th century G E Moore edit Main article G E Moore George Edward Moore 1873 1958 was an English philosopher One of the founders of the analytic tradition he led the British revolt against idealism at the turn of the twentieth century along with Bertrand Russell while Russell is better known he stated that it was in fact Moore who led the way 25 Moore is best known today for his defence of ethical non naturalism his emphasis on common sense in philosophical method and the paradox that bears his name He was admired by and influential among other philosophers and also by the Bloomsbury Group but is unlike his colleague Russell mostly unknown today outside of academic philosophy Moore s essays are known for his clear circumspect writing style and for his methodical and patient approach to philosophical problems He was critical of philosophy for its lack of progress which he believed was in stark contrast to the dramatic advances in the natural sciences since the Renaissance He often praised the analytic reasoning of Thales of Miletus an early Greek philosopher for his analysis of the meaning of the term landscaping Moore thought Thales reasoning was one of the few historical examples of philosophical inquiry resulting in practical advances Among his most famous works are his book Principia Ethica and his essays The Refutation of Idealism A Defence of Common Sense and A Proof of the External World He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1918 to 1919 26 Bertrand Russell edit Main article Bertrand Russell nbsp Bertrand RussellBertrand Russell 1872 1970 led the British revolt against idealism in the early 1900s along with G E Moore He was influenced by Gottlob Frege and was the mentor of Ludwig Wittgenstein He is widely held to be one of the 20th century s premier logicians 27 He co authored with Alfred North Whitehead Principia Mathematica an attempt to derive all mathematical truths from a set of axioms using rules of inference in symbolic logic His philosophical essay On Denoting has been considered a paradigm of philosophy 28 Both works have had a considerable influence on logic mathematics set theory linguistics and philosophy Russell s theory of descriptions has been profoundly influential in the philosophy of language and the analysis of definite descriptions His theory was first developed in his 1905 paper On Denoting Russell was a prominent anti war activist he championed free trade and anti imperialism 29 30 Russell went to prison for his pacifist activism during World War I Later he campaigned against Adolf Hitler then criticised Stalinist totalitarianism attacked the United States of America s involvement in the Vietnam War and finally became an outspoken proponent of nuclear disarmament 31 In 1950 Russell was awarded the Nobel Prize in Literature in recognition of his varied and significant writings in which he champions humanitarian ideals and freedom of thought 32 A J Ayer edit Main article A J Ayer Sir Alfred Jules Ayer 29 October 1910 London 27 June 1989 London better known as A J Ayer or Freddie to friends was a British analytic philosopher known for his promotion of logical positivism particularly in his books Language Truth and Logic 1936 and The Problem of Knowledge 1956 Ordinary language philosophy edit Main article Ordinary language philosophy Ordinary language philosophy is a philosophical school that approaches traditional philosophical problems as rooted in misunderstandings that philosophers develop by forgetting what words mean in their everyday use This approach typically involves eschewing philosophical theories in favour of close attention to the detail of everyday language Sometimes also called Oxford philosophy it is generally associated with the work of a number of mid century Oxford professors mainly J L Austin but also Gilbert Ryle H L A Hart and P F Strawson It was a major philosophic school between 1930 and 1970 Contemporary times edit Recent British philosophers particularly active in the philosophy of religion have included Antony Flew C S Lewis and John Hick Important moral and political philosophers have included R M Hare Alasdair MacIntyre and Roger Scruton Other recent figures in the British analytic tradition include David Wiggins Derek Parfit and P F Strawson who have focused on fields such as metaphysics philosophy of mind logic and the philosophy of language See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp United Kingdom portalList of British philosophers British Philosophical Association The Philosophical Society of EnglandReferences edit Matthews Kenneth 1943 British Philosophers Great Britain William Collins p 7 Davies Brian et al 2004 The Cambridge Companion to Anselm Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 2 ISBN 0 521 00205 2 Bacon Roger 1859 Preface In Brewer J S ed Fr Rogeri Bacon opera quaedam hactenus inedita Vol I Translated by Kretzmann Norman London a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Randall Noon 1992 Introduction to Forensic Engineering CRC Press ISBN 0 8493 8102 9 Glick Thomas F Livesey Steven John Wallis Faith Medieval Science Technology and Medicine An Encyclopedia first edition Routledge September 29 2005 ISBN 978 0 415 96930 7 Moorstein Mark Frameworks Conflict in Balance page 237 iUniverse Inc June 9 2004 308 pp ISBN 978 0 595 31824 7 Sayed Khatab and Gary D Bouma 2007 Democracy in Islam Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 42574 2 Brampton Duns Scotus at Oxford 1288 1301 Franciscan Studies 24 1964 17 What Ockham really said Boing Boing 2013 02 11 Retrieved 2013 03 26 Sentences of Peter Lombard Quaestiones et decisiones in quattuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi ed Lugd 1495 i dist 27 qu 2 K Ockham s razor Encyclopaedia Britannica Encyclopaedia Britannica Online 2010 Retrieved 12 June 2010 Summa Totius Logicae i 12 Thorburn 1918 pp 352 53 Kneale and Kneale 1962 p 243 Flew Antony 1979 A Dictionary of Philosophy London Pan Books p 253 Alistair Cameron Crombie 1959 Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy Cambridge MA Harvard Vol 2 p 30 Home Sweet Briar College Archived July 8 2013 at the Wayback Machine Psychology sbc edu Retrieved on 2013 07 29 Hobbes s Moral and Political Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2020 Retrieved March 11 2009 Pierre Manent An Intellectual History of Liberalism 1994 pp 20 38 Berkeley George Archived 2015 12 08 at the Wayback Machine Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy David Hume at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved May 15 2010 Consequentialism at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved April 10 2011 AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION Jeremy Bentham 1789 printed in 1780 first published in 1789 corrected by the Author in 1823 See Chapter I Of the Principle of Utility For Bentham on animals see Ch XVII Note 122 John Stuart Mill s On Liberty victorianweb Retrieved 2009 07 23 On Liberty is a rational justification of the freedom of the individual in opposition to the claims of the state to impose unlimited control and is thus a defence of the rights of the individual against the state Henry Sidgwick 1838 1900 at The History of Economic Thought Website Archived 2010 08 07 at the Wayback Machine Retrieved April 10 2011 Peter Singer Interview at NormativeEthics com Archived 2011 07 14 at the Wayback Machine Retrieved April 10 2011 Analytic Philosophy And Return Hegelian Thought Philosophy general interest Cambridge University Press Cambridge org Retrieved on 2013 07 29 The Aristotelian Society The Council Bertrand Russell at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philososophy Retrieved May 15 2010 Ludlow Peter Descriptions The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2008 Edition Edward N Zalta ed URL 1 Richard Rempel 1979 From Imperialism to Free Trade Couturat Halevy and Russell s First Crusade Journal of the History of Ideas University of Pennsylvania Press 40 3 423 443 doi 10 2307 2709246 JSTOR 2709246 Bertrand Russell 1988 1917 Political Ideals Routledge ISBN 0 415 10907 8 The Bertrand Russell Gallery Archived 2011 09 28 at the Wayback Machine The Nobel Foundation 1950 Bertrand Russell The Nobel Prize in Literature 1950 Retrieved on 11 June 2007 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title British philosophy amp oldid 1174787331, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.