fbpx
Wikipedia

Thought

In their most common sense, the terms thought and thinking refer to conscious cognitive processes that can happen independently of sensory stimulation. Their most paradigmatic forms are judging, reasoning, concept formation, problem solving, and deliberation. But other mental processes, like considering an idea, memory, or imagination, are also often included. These processes can happen internally independent of the sensory organs, unlike perception. But when understood in the widest sense, any mental event may be understood as a form of thinking, including perception and unconscious mental processes. In a slightly different sense, the term thought refers not to the mental processes themselves but to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes.

The Thinker by Rodin (1840–1917), in the garden of the Musée Rodin.

Various theories of thinking have been proposed, some of which aim to capture the characteristic features of thought. Platonists hold that thinking consists in discerning and inspecting Platonic forms and their interrelations. It involves the ability to discriminate between the pure Platonic forms themselves and the mere imitations found in the sensory world. According to Aristotelianism, to think about something is to instantiate in one's mind the universal essence of the object of thought. These universals are abstracted from sense experience and are not understood as existing in a changeless intelligible world, in contrast to Platonism. Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism: it identifies thinking with mentally evoking concepts instead of instantiating essences. Inner speech theories claim that thinking is a form of inner speech in which words are silently expressed in the thinker's mind. According to some accounts, this happens in a regular language, like English or French. The language of thought hypothesis, on the other hand, holds that this happens in the medium of a unique mental language called Mentalese. Central to this idea is that linguistic representational systems are built up from atomic and compound representations and that this structure is also found in thought. Associationists understand thinking as the succession of ideas or images. They are particularly interested in the laws of association that govern how the train of thought unfolds. Behaviorists, by contrast, identify thinking with behavioral dispositions to engage in public intelligent behavior as a reaction to particular external stimuli. Computationalism is the most recent of these theories. It sees thinking in analogy to how computers work in terms of the storage, transmission, and processing of information.

Various types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature. A judgment is a mental operation in which a proposition is evoked and then either affirmed or denied. Reasoning, on the other hand, is the process of drawing conclusions from premises or evidence. Both judging and reasoning depend on the possession of the relevant concepts, which are acquired in the process of concept formation. In the case of problem solving, thinking aims at reaching a predefined goal by overcoming certain obstacles. Deliberation is an important form of practical thought that consists in formulating possible courses of action and assessing the reasons for and against them. This may lead to a decision by choosing the most favorable option. Both episodic memory and imagination present objects and situations internally, in an attempt to accurately reproduce what was previously experienced or as a free rearrangement, respectively. Unconscious thought is thought that happens without being directly experienced. It is sometimes posited to explain how difficult problems are solved in cases where no conscious thought was employed.

Thought is discussed in various academic disciplines. Phenomenology is interested in the experience of thinking. An important question in this field concerns the experiential character of thinking and to what extent this character can be explained in terms of sensory experience. Metaphysics is, among other things, interested in the relation between mind and matter. This concerns the question of how thinking can fit into the material world as described by the natural sciences. Cognitive psychology aims to understand thought as a form of information processing. Developmental psychology, on the other hand, investigates the development of thought from birth to maturity and asks which factors this development depends on. Psychoanalysis emphasizes the role of the unconscious in mental life. Other fields concerned with thought include linguistics, neuroscience, artificial intelligence, biology, and sociology. Various concepts and theories are closely related to the topic of thought. The term "law of thought" refers to three fundamental laws of logic: the law of contradiction, the law of excluded middle, and the principle of identity. Counterfactual thinking involves mental representations of non-actual situations and events in which the thinker tries to assess what would be the case if things had been different. Thought experiments often employ counterfactual thinking in order to illustrate theories or to test their plausibility. Critical thinking is a form of thinking that is reasonable, reflective, and focused on determining what to believe or how to act. Positive thinking involves focusing one's attention on the positive aspects of one's situation and is intimately related to optimism.

Definition edit

The terms "thought" and "thinking" refer to a wide variety of psychological activities.[1][2][3] In their most common sense, they are understood as conscious processes that can happen independently of sensory stimulation.[4][5] This includes various different mental processes, like considering an idea or proposition or judging it to be true. In this sense, memory and imagination are forms of thought but perception is not.[6] In a more restricted sense, only the most paradigmatic cases are considered thought. These involve conscious processes that are conceptual or linguistic and sufficiently abstract, like judging, inferring, problem solving, and deliberating.[1][7][8] Sometimes the terms "thought" and "thinking" are understood in a very wide sense as referring to any form of mental process, conscious or unconscious.[9][10] In this sense, they may be used synonymously with the term "mind". This usage is encountered, for example, in the Cartesian tradition, where minds are understood as thinking things, and in the cognitive sciences.[6][11][12][13] But this sense may include the restriction that such processes have to lead to intelligent behavior to be considered thought.[14] A contrast sometimes found in the academic literature is that between thinking and feeling. In this context, thinking is associated with a sober, dispassionate, and rational approach to its topic while feeling involves a direct emotional engagement.[15][16][17]

The terms "thought" and "thinking" can also be used to refer not to the mental processes themselves but to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes.[18] In this sense, they are often synonymous with the term "belief" and its cognates and may refer to the mental states which either belong to an individual or are common among a certain group of people.[19][20] Discussions of thought in the academic literature often leave it implicit which sense of the term they have in mind.

The word thought comes from Old English þoht, or geþoht, from the stem of þencan "to conceive of in the mind, consider".[21]

Theories of thinking edit

Various theories of thinking have been proposed.[22] They aim to capture the characteristic features of thinking. The theories listed here are not exclusive: it may be possible to combine some without leading to a contradiction.

Platonism edit

According to Platonism, thinking is a spiritual activity in which Platonic forms and their interrelations are discerned and inspected.[22][23] This activity is understood as a form of silent inner speech in which the soul talks to itself.[24] Platonic forms are seen as universals that exist in a changeless realm different from the sensible world. Examples include the forms of goodness, beauty, unity, and sameness.[25][26][27] On this view, the difficulty of thinking consists in being unable to grasp the Platonic forms and to distinguish them as the original from the mere imitations found in the sensory world. This means, for example, distinguishing beauty itself from derivative images of beauty.[23] One problem for this view is to explain how humans can learn and think about Platonic forms belonging to a different realm.[22] Plato himself tries to solve this problem through his theory of recollection, according to which the soul already was in contact with the Platonic forms before and is therefore able to remember what they are like.[23] But this explanation depends on various assumptions usually not accepted in contemporary thought.[23]

Aristotelianism and conceptualism edit

Aristotelians hold that the mind is able to think about something by instantiating the essence of the object of thought.[22] So while thinking about trees, the mind instantiates tree-ness. This instantiation does not happen in matter, as is the case for actual trees, but in mind, though the universal essence instantiated in both cases is the same.[22] In contrast to Platonism, these universals are not understood as Platonic forms existing in a changeless intelligible world.[28] Instead, they only exist to the extent that they are instantiated. The mind learns to discriminate universals through abstraction from experience.[29] This explanation avoids various of the objections raised against Platonism.[28]

Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism. It states that thinking consists in mentally evoking concepts. Some of these concepts may be innate, but most have to be learned through abstraction from sense experience before they can be used in thought.[22]

It has been argued against these views that they have problems in accounting for the logical form of thought. For example, to think that it will either rain or snow, it is not sufficient to instantiate the essences of rain and snow or to evoke the corresponding concepts. The reason for this is that the disjunctive relation between the rain and the snow is not captured this way.[22] Another problem shared by these positions is the difficulty of giving a satisfying account of how essences or concepts are learned by the mind through abstraction.[22]

Inner speech theory edit

Inner speech theories claim that thinking is a form of inner speech.[6][30][24][1] This view is sometimes termed psychological nominalism.[22] It states that thinking involves silently evoking words and connecting them to form mental sentences. The knowledge a person has of their thoughts can be explained as a form of overhearing one's own silent monologue.[31] Three central aspects are often ascribed to inner speech: it is in an important sense similar to hearing sounds, it involves the use of language and it constitutes a motor plan that could be used for actual speech.[24] This connection to language is supported by the fact that thinking is often accompanied by muscle activity in the speech organs. This activity may facilitate thinking in certain cases but is not necessary for it in general.[1] According to some accounts, thinking happens not in a regular language, like English or French, but has its own type of language with the corresponding symbols and syntax. This theory is known as the language of thought hypothesis.[30][32]

Inner speech theory has a strong initial plausibility since introspection suggests that indeed many thoughts are accompanied by inner speech. But its opponents usually contend that this is not true for all types of thinking.[22][5][33] It has been argued, for example, that forms of daydreaming constitute non-linguistic thought.[34] This issue is relevant to the question of whether animals have the capacity to think. If thinking is necessarily tied to language then this would suggest that there is an important gap between humans and animals since only humans have a sufficiently complex language. But the existence of non-linguistic thoughts suggests that this gap may not be that big and that some animals do indeed think.[33][35][36]

Language of thought hypothesis edit

There are various theories about the relation between language and thought. One prominent version in contemporary philosophy is called the language of thought hypothesis.[30][32][37][38][39] It states that thinking happens in the medium of a mental language. This language, often referred to as Mentalese, is similar to regular languages in various respects: it is composed of words that are connected to each other in syntactic ways to form sentences.[30][32][37][38] This claim does not merely rest on an intuitive analogy between language and thought. Instead, it provides a clear definition of the features a representational system has to embody in order to have a linguistic structure.[37][32][38] On the level of syntax, the representational system has to possess two types of representations: atomic and compound representations. Atomic representations are basic whereas compound representations are constituted either by other compound representations or by atomic representations.[37][32][38] On the level of semantics, the semantic content or the meaning of the compound representations should depend on the semantic contents of its constituents. A representational system is linguistically structured if it fulfills these two requirements.[37][32][38]

The language of thought hypothesis states that the same is true for thinking in general. This would mean that thought is composed of certain atomic representational constituents that can be combined as described above.[37][32][40] Apart from this abstract characterization, no further concrete claims are made about how human thought is implemented by the brain or which other similarities to natural language it has.[37] The language of thought hypothesis was first introduced by Jerry Fodor.[32][37] He argues in favor of this claim by holding that it constitutes the best explanation of the characteristic features of thinking. One of these features is productivity: a system of representations is productive if it can generate an infinite number of unique representations based on a low number of atomic representations.[37][32][40] This applies to thought since human beings are capable of entertaining an infinite number of distinct thoughts even though their mental capacities are quite limited. Other characteristic features of thinking include systematicity and inferential coherence.[32][37][40] Fodor argues that the language of thought hypothesis is true as it explains how thought can have these features and because there is no good alternative explanation.[37] Some arguments against the language of thought hypothesis are based on neural networks, which are able to produce intelligent behavior without depending on representational systems. Other objections focus on the idea that some mental representations happen non-linguistically, for example, in the form of maps or images.[37][32]

Computationalists have been especially interested in the language of thought hypothesis since it provides ways to close the gap between thought in the human brain and computational processes implemented by computers.[37][32][41] The reason for this is that processes over representations that respect syntax and semantics, like inferences according to the modus ponens, can be implemented by physical systems using causal relations. The same linguistic systems may be implemented through different material systems, like brains or computers. In this way, computers can think.[37][32]

Associationism edit

An important view in the empiricist tradition has been associationism, the view that thinking consists in the succession of ideas or images.[1][42][43] This succession is seen as being governed by laws of association, which determine how the train of thought unfolds.[1][44] These laws are different from logical relations between the contents of thoughts, which are found in the case of drawing inferences by moving from the thought of the premises to the thought of the conclusion.[44] Various laws of association have been suggested. According to the laws of similarity and contrast, ideas tend to evoke other ideas that are either very similar to them or their opposite. The law of contiguity, on the other hand, states that if two ideas were frequently experienced together, then the experience of one tends to cause the experience of the other.[1][42] In this sense, the history of an organism's experience determines which thoughts the organism has and how these thoughts unfold.[44] But such an association does not guarantee that the connection is meaningful or rational. For example, because of the association between the terms "cold" and "Idaho", the thought "this coffee shop is cold" might lead to the thought "Russia should annex Idaho".[44]

One form of associationism is imagism. It states that thinking involves entertaining a sequence of images where earlier images conjure up later images based on the laws of association.[22] One problem with this view is that we can think about things that we cannot imagine. This is especially relevant when the thought involves very complex objects or infinities, which is common, for example, in mathematical thought.[22] One criticism directed at associationism in general is that its claim is too far-reaching. There is wide agreement that associative processes as studied by associationists play some role in how thought unfolds. But the claim that this mechanism is sufficient to understand all thought or all mental processes is usually not accepted.[43][44]

Behaviorism edit

According to behaviorism, thinking consists in behavioral dispositions to engage in certain publicly observable behavior as a reaction to particular external stimuli.[45][46][47] On this view, having a particular thought is the same as having a disposition to behave in a certain way. This view is often motivated by empirical considerations: it is very difficult to study thinking as a private mental process but it is much easier to study how organisms react to a certain situation with a given behavior.[47] In this sense, the capacity to solve problems not through existing habits but through creative new approaches is particularly relevant.[48] The term "behaviorism" is also sometimes used in a slightly different sense when applied to thinking to refer to a specific form of inner speech theory.[49] This view focuses on the idea that the relevant inner speech is a derivative form of regular outward speech.[1] This sense overlaps with how behaviorism is understood more commonly in philosophy of mind since these inner speech acts are not observed by the researcher but merely inferred from the subject's intelligent behavior.[49] This remains true to the general behaviorist principle that behavioral evidence is required for any psychological hypothesis.[47]

One problem for behaviorism is that the same entity often behaves differently despite being in the same situation as before.[50][51] This problem consists in the fact that individual thoughts or mental states usually do not correspond to one particular behavior. So thinking that the pie is tasty does not automatically lead to eating the pie, since various other mental states may still inhibit this behavior, for example, the belief that it would be impolite to do so or that the pie is poisoned.[52][53]

Computationalism edit

Computationalist theories of thinking, often found in the cognitive sciences, understand thinking as a form of information processing.[41][54][45] These views developed with the rise of computers in the second part of the 20th century, when various theorists saw thinking in analogy to computer operations.[54] On such views, the information may be encoded differently in the brain, but in principle, the same operations take place there as well, corresponding to the storage, transmission, and processing of information.[1][13] But while this analogy has some intuitive attraction, theorists have struggled to give a more explicit explanation of what computation is. A further problem consists in explaining the sense in which thinking is a form of computing.[45] The traditionally dominant view defines computation in terms of Turing machines, though contemporary accounts often focus on neural networks for their analogies.[41] A Turing machine is capable of executing any algorithm based on a few very basic principles, such as reading a symbol from a cell, writing a symbol to a cell, and executing instructions based on the symbols read.[41] This way it is possible to perform deductive reasoning following the inference rules of formal logic as well as simulating many other functions of the mind, such as language processing, decision making, and motor control.[54][45] But computationalism does not only claim that thinking is in some sense similar to computation. Instead, it is claimed that thinking just is a form of computation or that the mind is a Turing machine.[45]

Computationalist theories of thought are sometimes divided into functionalist and representationalist approaches.[45] Functionalist approaches define mental states through their causal roles but allow both external and internal events in their causal network.[55][56][57] Thought may be seen as a form of program that can be executed in the same way by many different systems, including humans, animals, and even robots. According to one such view, whether something is a thought only depends on its role "in producing further internal states and verbal outputs".[58][55] Representationalism, on the other hand, focuses on the representational features of mental states and defines thoughts as sequences of intentional mental states.[59][45] In this sense, computationalism is often combined with the language of thought hypothesis by interpreting these sequences as symbols whose order is governed by syntactic rules.[45][32]

Various arguments have been raised against computationalism. In one sense, it seems trivial since almost any physical system can be described as executing computations and therefore as thinking. For example, it has been argued that the molecular movements in a regular wall can be understood as computing an algorithm since they are "isomorphic to the formal structure of the program" in question under the right interpretation.[45] This would lead to the implausible conclusion that the wall is thinking. Another objection focuses on the idea that computationalism captures only some aspects of thought but is unable to account for other crucial aspects of human cognition.[45][54]

Types of thinking edit

A great variety of types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature. A common approach divides them into those forms that aim at the creation of theoretical knowledge and those that aim at producing actions or correct decisions,[22] but there is no universally accepted taxonomy summarizing all these types.

Entertaining, judging, and reasoning edit

Thinking is often identified with the act of judging. A judgment is a mental operation in which a proposition is evoked and then either affirmed or denied.[6][60] It involves deciding what to believe and aims at determining whether the judged proposition is true or false.[61][62] Various theories of judgment have been proposed. The traditionally dominant approach is the combination theory. It states that judgments consist in the combination of concepts.[63] On this view, to judge that "all men are mortal" is to combine the concepts "man" and "mortal". The same concepts can be combined in different ways, corresponding to different forms of judgment, for example, as "some men are mortal" or "no man is mortal".[64]

Other theories of judgment focus more on the relation between the judged proposition and reality. According to Franz Brentano, a judgment is either a belief or a disbelief in the existence of some entity.[63][65] In this sense, there are only two fundamental forms of judgment: "A exists" and "A does not exist". When applied to the sentence "all men are mortal", the entity in question is "immortal men", of whom it is said that they do not exist.[63][65] Important for Brentano is the distinction between the mere representation of the content of the judgment and the affirmation or the denial of the content.[63][65] The mere representation of a proposition is often referred to as "entertaining a proposition". This is the case, for example, when one considers a proposition but has not yet made up one's mind about whether it is true or false.[63][65] The term "thinking" can refer both to judging and to mere entertaining. This difference is often explicit in the way the thought is expressed: "thinking that" usually involves a judgment whereas "thinking about" refers to the neutral representation of a proposition without an accompanying belief. In this case, the proposition is merely entertained but not yet judged.[19] Some forms of thinking may involve the representation of objects without any propositions, as when someone is thinking about their grandmother.[6]

Reasoning is one of the most paradigmatic forms of thinking. It is the process of drawing conclusions from premises or evidence. Types of reasoning can be divided into deductive and non-deductive reasoning. Deductive reasoning is governed by certain rules of inference, which guarantee the truth of the conclusion if the premises are true.[1][66] For example, given the premises "all men are mortal" and "Socrates is a man", it follows deductively that "Socrates is mortal". Non-deductive reasoning, also referred to as defeasible reasoning or non-monotonic reasoning, is still rationally compelling but the truth of the conclusion is not ensured by the truth of the premises.[67] Induction is one form of non-deductive reasoning, for example, when one concludes that "the sun will rise tomorrow" based on one's experiences of all the previous days. Other forms of non-deductive reasoning include the inference to the best explanation and analogical reasoning.[68]

Fallacies are faulty forms of thinking that go against the norms of correct reasoning. Formal fallacies concern faulty inferences found in deductive reasoning.[69][70] Denying the antecedent is one type of formal fallacy, for example, "If Othello is a bachelor, then he is male. Othello is not a bachelor. Therefore, Othello is not male".[1][71] Informal fallacies, on the other hand, apply to all types of reasoning. The source of their flaw is to be found in the content or the context of the argument.[72][69][73] This is often caused by ambiguous or vague expressions in natural language, as in "Feathers are light. What is light cannot be dark. Therefore, feathers cannot be dark".[74] An important aspect of fallacies is that they seem to be rationally compelling on the first look and thereby seduce people into accepting and committing them.[69] Whether an act of reasoning constitutes a fallacy does not depend on whether the premises are true or false but on their relation to the conclusion and, in some cases, on the context.[1]

Concept formation edit

Concepts are general notions that constitute the fundamental building blocks of thought.[75][76] They are rules that govern how objects are sorted into different classes.[77][78] A person can only think about a proposition if they possess the concepts involved in this proposition.[79] For example, the proposition "wombats are animals" involves the concepts "wombat" and "animal". Someone who does not possess the concept "wombat" may still be able to read the sentence but cannot entertain the corresponding proposition. Concept formation is a form of thinking in which new concepts are acquired.[78] It involves becoming familiar with the characteristic features shared by all instances of the corresponding type of entity and developing the ability to identify positive and negative cases. This process usually corresponds to learning the meaning of the word associated with the type in question.[77][78] There are various theories concerning how concepts and concept possession are to be understood.[75]

According to one popular view, concepts are to be understood in terms of abilities. On this view, two central aspects characterize concept possession: the ability to discriminate between positive and negative cases and the ability to draw inferences from this concept to related concepts. Concept formation corresponds to acquiring these abilities.[79][80][75] It has been suggested that animals are also able to learn concepts to some extent, due to their ability to discriminate between different types of situations and to adjust their behavior accordingly.[77][81]

Problem solving edit

In the case of problem solving, thinking aims at reaching a predefined goal by overcoming certain obstacles.[7][1][78] This process often involves two different forms of thinking. On the one hand, divergent thinking aims at coming up with as many alternative solutions as possible. On the other hand, convergent thinking tries to narrow down the range of alternatives to the most promising candidates.[1][82][83] Some researchers identify various steps in the process of problem solving. These steps include recognizing the problem, trying to understand its nature, identifying general criteria the solution should meet, deciding how these criteria should be prioritized, monitoring the progress, and evaluating the results.[1]

An important distinction concerns the type of problem that is faced. For well-structured problems, it is easy to determine which steps need to be taken to solve them, but executing these steps may still be difficult.[1][84] For ill-structured problems, on the other hand, it is not clear what steps need to be taken, i.e. there is no clear formula that would lead to success if followed correctly. In this case, the solution may sometimes come in a flash of insight in which the problem is suddenly seen in a new light.[1][84] Another way to categorize different forms of problem solving is by distinguishing between algorithms and heuristics.[78] An algorithm is a formal procedure in which each step is clearly defined. It guarantees success if applied correctly.[1][78] The long multiplication usually taught in school is an example of an algorithm for solving the problem of multiplying big numbers. Heuristics, on the other hand, are informal procedures. They are rough rules-of-thumb that tend to bring the thinker closer to the solution but success is not guaranteed in every case even if followed correctly.[1][78] Examples of heuristics are working forward and working backward. These approaches involve planning one step at a time, either starting at the beginning and moving forward or starting at the end and moving backward. So when planning a trip, one could plan the different stages of the trip from origin to destiny in the chronological order of how the trip will be realized, or in the reverse order.[1]

Obstacles to problem solving can arise from the thinker's failure to take certain possibilities into account by fixating on one specific course of action.[1] There are important differences between how novices and experts solve problems. For example, experts tend to allocate more time for conceptualizing the problem and work with more complex representations whereas novices tend to devote more time to executing putative solutions.[1]

Deliberation and decision edit

Deliberation is an important form of practical thinking. It aims at formulating possible courses of action and assessing their value by considering the reasons for and against them.[85] This involves foresight to anticipate what might happen. Based on this foresight, different courses of action can be formulated in order to influence what will happen. Decisions are an important part of deliberation. They are about comparing alternative courses of action and choosing the most favorable one.[66][22] Decision theory is a formal model of how ideal rational agents would make decisions.[78][86][87] It is based on the idea that they should always choose the alternative with the highest expected value. Each alternative can lead to various possible outcomes, each of which has a different value. The expected value of an alternative consists in the sum of the values of each outcome associated with it multiplied by the probability that this outcome occurs.[86][87] According to decision theory, a decision is rational if the agent chooses the alternative associated with the highest expected value, as assessed from the agent's own perspective.[86][87]

Various theorists emphasize the practical nature of thought, i.e. that thinking is usually guided by some kind of task it aims to solve. In this sense, thinking has been compared to trial-and-error seen in animal behavior when faced with a new problem. On this view, the important difference is that this process happens inwardly as a form of simulation.[1] This process is often much more efficient since once the solution is found in thought, only the behavior corresponding to the found solution has to be outwardly carried out and not all the others.[1]

Episodic memory and imagination edit

When thinking is understood in a wide sense, it includes both episodic memory and imagination.[20] In episodic memory, events one experienced in the past are relived.[88][89][90] It is a form of mental time travel in which the past experience is re-experienced.[90][91] But this does not constitute an exact copy of the original experience since the episodic memory involves additional aspects and information not present in the original experience. This includes both a feeling of familiarity and chronological information about the past event in relation to the present.[88][90] Memory aims at representing how things actually were in the past, in contrast to imagination, which presents objects without aiming to show how things actually are or were.[92] Because of this missing link to actuality, more freedom is involved in most forms of imagination: its contents can be freely varied, changed, and recombined to create new arrangements never experienced before.[93] Episodic memory and imagination have in common with other forms of thought that they can arise internally without any stimulation of the sensory organs.[94][93] But they are still closer to sensation than more abstract forms of thought since they present sensory contents that could, at least in principle, also be perceived.

Unconscious thought edit

Conscious thought is the paradigmatic form of thinking and is often the focus of the corresponding research. But it has been argued that some forms of thought also happen on the unconscious level.[9][10][4][5] Unconscious thought is thought that happens in the background without being experienced. It is therefore not observed directly. Instead, its existence is usually inferred by other means.[10] For example, when someone is faced with an important decision or a difficult problem, they may not be able to solve it straight away. But then, at a later time, the solution may suddenly flash before them even though no conscious steps of thinking were taken towards this solution in the meantime.[10][9] In such cases, the cognitive labor needed to arrive at a solution is often explained in terms of unconscious thoughts. The central idea is that a cognitive transition happened and we need to posit unconscious thoughts to be able to explain how it happened.[10][9]

It has been argued that conscious and unconscious thoughts differ not just concerning their relation to experience but also concerning their capacities. According to unconscious thought theorists, for example, conscious thought excels at simple problems with few variables but is outperformed by unconscious thought when complex problems with many variables are involved.[10][9] This is sometimes explained through the claim that the number of items one can consciously think about at the same time is rather limited whereas unconscious thought lacks such limitations.[10] But other researchers have rejected the claim that unconscious thought is often superior to conscious thought.[95][96] Other suggestions for the difference between the two forms of thinking include that conscious thought tends to follow formal logical laws while unconscious thought relies more on associative processing and that only conscious thinking is conceptually articulated and happens through the medium of language.[10][97]

In various disciplines edit

Phenomenology edit

Phenomenology is the science of the structure and contents of experience.[98][99] The term "cognitive phenomenology" refers to the experiential character of thinking or what it feels like to think.[4][100][101][6][102] Some theorists claim that there is no distinctive cognitive phenomenology. On such a view, the experience of thinking is just one form of sensory experience.[102][103][104] According to one version, thinking just involves hearing a voice internally.[103] According to another, there is no experience of thinking apart from the indirect effects thinking has on sensory experience.[4][100] A weaker version of such an approach allows that thinking may have a distinct phenomenology but contends that thinking still depends on sensory experience because it cannot occur on its own. On this view, sensory contents constitute the foundation from which thinking may arise.[4][103][104]

An often-cited thought experiment in favor of the existence of a distinctive cognitive phenomenology involves two persons listening to a radio broadcast in French, one who understands French and the other who does not.[4][100][101][105] The idea behind this example is that both listeners hear the same sounds and therefore have the same non-cognitive experience. In order to explain the difference, a distinctive cognitive phenomenology has to be posited: only the experience of the first person has this additional cognitive character since it is accompanied by a thought that corresponds to the meaning of what is said.[4][100][101][106] Other arguments for the experience of thinking focus on the direct introspective access to thinking or on the thinker's knowledge of their own thoughts.[4][100][101]

Phenomenologists are also concerned with the characteristic features of the experience of thinking. Making a judgment is one of the prototypical forms of cognitive phenomenology.[101][107] It involves epistemic agency, in which a proposition is entertained, evidence for and against it is considered, and, based on this reasoning, the proposition is either affirmed or rejected.[101] It is sometimes argued that the experience of truth is central to thinking, i.e. that thinking aims at representing how the world is.[6][100] It shares this feature with perception but differs from it in the way how it represents the world: without the use of sensory contents.[6]

One of the characteristic features often ascribed to thinking and judging is that they are predicative experiences, in contrast to the pre-predicative experience found in immediate perception.[108][109] On such a view, various aspects of perceptual experience resemble judgments without being judgments in the strict sense.[4][110][111] For example, the perceptual experience of the front of a house brings with it various expectations about aspects of the house not directly seen, like the size and shape of its other sides. This process is sometimes referred to as apperception.[4][110] These expectations resemble judgments and can be wrong. This would be the case when it turns out upon walking around the "house" that it is no house at all but only a front facade of a house with nothing behind it. In this case, the perceptual expectations are frustrated and the perceiver is surprised.[4] There is disagreement as to whether these pre-predicative aspects of regular perception should be understood as a form of cognitive phenomenology involving thinking.[4] This issue is also important for understanding the relation between thought and language. The reason for this is that the pre-predicative expectations do not depend on language, which is sometimes taken as an example for non-linguistic thought.[4] Various theorists have argued that pre-predicative experience is more basic or fundamental since predicative experience is in some sense built on top of it and therefore depends on it.[111][108][109]

Another way how phenomenologists have tried to distinguish the experience of thinking from other types of experiences is in relation to empty intentions in contrast to intuitive intentions.[112][113] In this context, "intention" means that some kind of object is experienced. In intuitive intentions, the object is presented through sensory contents. Empty intentions, on the other hand, present their object in a more abstract manner without the help of sensory contents.[112][4][113] So when perceiving a sunset, it is presented through sensory contents. The same sunset can also be presented non-intuitively when merely thinking about it without the help of sensory contents.[113] In these cases, the same properties are ascribed to objects. The difference between these modes of presentation concerns not what properties are ascribed to the presented object but how the object is presented.[112] Because of this commonality, it is possible for representations belonging to different modes to overlap or to diverge.[6] For example, when searching one's glasses one may think to oneself that one left them on the kitchen table. This empty intention of the glasses lying on the kitchen table are then intuitively fulfilled when one sees them lying there upon arriving in the kitchen. This way, a perception can confirm or refute a thought depending on whether the empty intuitions are later fulfilled or not.[6][113]

Metaphysics edit

The mind–body problem concerns the explanation of the relationship that exists between minds, or mental processes, and bodily states or processes.[114] The main aim of philosophers working in this area is to determine the nature of the mind and mental states/processes, and how—or even if—minds are affected by and can affect the body.

Human perceptual experiences depend on stimuli which arrive at one's various sensory organs from the external world and these stimuli cause changes in one's mental state, ultimately causing one to feel a sensation, which may be pleasant or unpleasant. Someone's desire for a slice of pizza, for example, will tend to cause that person to move his or her body in a specific manner and in a specific direction to obtain what he or she wants. The question, then, is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to arise out of a lump of gray matter endowed with nothing but electrochemical properties. A related problem is to explain how someone's propositional attitudes (e.g. beliefs and desires) can cause that individual's neurons to fire and his muscles to contract in exactly the correct manner. These comprise some of the puzzles that have confronted epistemologists and philosophers of mind from at least the time of René Descartes.[115]

The above reflects a classical, functional description of how we work as cognitive, thinking systems. However the apparently irresolvable mind–body problem is said to be overcome, and bypassed, by the embodied cognition approach, with its roots in the work of Heidegger, Piaget, Vygotsky, Merleau-Ponty and the pragmatist John Dewey.[116][117]

This approach states that the classical approach of separating the mind and analysing its processes is misguided: instead, we should see that the mind, actions of an embodied agent, and the environment it perceives and envisions, are all parts of a whole which determine each other. Therefore, functional analysis of the mind alone will always leave us with the mind–body problem which cannot be solved.[118]

Psychology edit

 
Man thinking on a train journey

Psychologists have concentrated on thinking as an intellectual exertion aimed at finding an answer to a question or the solution of a practical problem. Cognitive psychology is a branch of psychology that investigates internal mental processes such as problem solving, memory, and language; all of which are used in thinking. The school of thought arising from this approach is known as cognitivism, which is interested in how people mentally represent information processing. It had its foundations in the Gestalt psychology of Max Wertheimer, Wolfgang Köhler, and Kurt Koffka,[119] and in the work of Jean Piaget, who provided a theory of stages/phases that describes children's cognitive development.

Cognitive psychologists use psychophysical and experimental approaches to understand, diagnose, and solve problems, concerning themselves with the mental processes which mediate between stimulus and response. They study various aspects of thinking, including the psychology of reasoning, and how people make decisions and choices, solve problems, as well as engage in creative discovery and imaginative thought. Cognitive theory contends that solutions to problems either take the form of algorithms: rules that are not necessarily understood but promise a solution, or of heuristics: rules that are understood but that do not always guarantee solutions. Cognitive science differs from cognitive psychology in that algorithms that are intended to simulate human behavior are implemented or implementable on a computer. In other instances, solutions may be found through insight, a sudden awareness of relationships.

In developmental psychology, Jean Piaget was a pioneer in the study of the development of thought from birth to maturity. In his theory of cognitive development, thought is based on actions on the environment. That is, Piaget suggests that the environment is understood through assimilations of objects in the available schemes of action and these accommodate to the objects to the extent that the available schemes fall short of the demands. As a result of this interplay between assimilation and accommodation, thought develops through a sequence of stages that differ qualitatively from each other in mode of representation and complexity of inference and understanding. That is, thought evolves from being based on perceptions and actions at the sensorimotor stage in the first two years of life to internal representations in early childhood. Subsequently, representations are gradually organized into logical structures which first operate on the concrete properties of the reality, in the stage of concrete operations, and then operate on abstract principles that organize concrete properties, in the stage of formal operations.[120] In recent years, the Piagetian conception of thought was integrated with information processing conceptions. Thus, thought is considered as the result of mechanisms that are responsible for the representation and processing of information. In this conception, speed of processing, cognitive control, and working memory are the main functions underlying thought. In the neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive development, the development of thought is considered to come from increasing speed of processing, enhanced cognitive control, and increasing working memory.[121]

Positive psychology emphasizes the positive aspects of human psychology as equally important as the focus on mood disorders and other negative symptoms. In Character Strengths and Virtues, Peterson and Seligman list a series of positive characteristics. One person is not expected to have every strength, nor are they meant to fully capsulate that characteristic entirely. The list encourages positive thought that builds on a person's strengths, rather than how to "fix" their "symptoms".[122]

Psychoanalysis edit

The "id", "ego" and "super-ego" are the three parts of the "psychic apparatus" defined in Sigmund Freud's structural model of the psyche; they are the three theoretical constructs in terms of whose activity and interaction mental life is described. According to this model, the uncoordinated instinctual trends are encompassed by the "id", the organized realistic part of the psyche is the "ego", and the critical, moralizing function is the "super-ego".[123]

For psychoanalysis, the unconscious does not include all that is not conscious, rather only what is actively repressed from conscious thought or what the person is averse to knowing consciously. In a sense this view places the self in relationship to their unconscious as an adversary, warring with itself to keep what is unconscious hidden. If a person feels pain, all he can think of is alleviating the pain. Any of his desires, to get rid of pain or enjoy something, command the mind what to do. For Freud, the unconscious was a repository for socially unacceptable ideas, wishes or desires, traumatic memories, and painful emotions put out of mind by the mechanism of psychological repression. However, the contents did not necessarily have to be solely negative. In the psychoanalytic view, the unconscious is a force that can only be recognized by its effects—it expresses itself in the symptom.[124]

The collective unconscious, sometimes known as collective subconscious, is a term of analytical psychology, coined by Carl Jung. It is a part of the unconscious mind, shared by a society, a people, or all humanity, in an interconnected system that is the product of all common experiences and contains such concepts as science, religion, and morality. While Freud did not distinguish between "individual psychology" and "collective psychology", Jung distinguished the collective unconscious from the personal subconscious particular to each human being. The collective unconscious is also known as "a reservoir of the experiences of our species".[125]

In the "Definitions" chapter of Jung's seminal work Psychological Types, under the definition of "collective" Jung references representations collectives, a term coined by Lucien Lévy-Bruhl in his 1910 book How Natives Think. Jung says this is what he describes as the collective unconscious. Freud, on the other hand, did not accept the idea of a collective unconscious.

Related concepts and theories edit

Laws of thought edit

Traditionally, the term "laws of thought" refers to three fundamental laws of logic: the law of contradiction, the law of excluded middle, and the principle of identity.[126][127] These laws by themselves are not sufficient as axioms of logic but they can be seen as important precursors to the modern axiomatization of logic. The law of contradiction states that for any proposition, it is impossible that both it and its negation are true:  . According to the law of excluded middle, for any proposition, either it or its opposite is true:  . The principle of identity asserts that any object is identical to itself:  .[126][127] There are different conceptions of how the laws of thought are to be understood. The interpretations most relevant to thinking are to understand them as prescriptive laws of how one should think or as formal laws of propositions that are true only because of their form and independent of their content or context.[127] Metaphysical interpretations, on the other hand, see them as expressing the nature of "being as such".[127]

While there is a very wide acceptance of these three laws among logicians, they are not universally accepted.[126][127] Aristotle, for example, held that there are some cases in which the law of excluded middle is false. This concerns primarily uncertain future events. On his view, it is currently "not ... either true or false that there will be a naval battle tomorrow".[126][127] Modern intuitionist logic also rejects the law of excluded middle. This rejection is based on the idea that mathematical truth depends on verification through a proof. The law fails for cases where no such proof is possible, which exist in every sufficiently strong formal system, according to Gödel's incompleteness theorems.[128][129][126][127] Dialetheists, on the other hand, reject the law of contradiction by holding that some propositions are both true and false. One motivation of this position is to avoid certain paradoxes in classical logic and set theory, like the liar's paradox and Russell's paradox. One of its problems is to find a formulation that circumvents the principle of explosion, i.e. that anything follows from a contradiction.[130][131][132]

Some formulations of the laws of thought include a fourth law: the principle of sufficient reason.[127] It states that everything has a sufficient reason, ground, or cause. It is closely connected to the idea that everything is intelligible or can be explained in reference to its sufficient reason.[133][134] According to this idea, there should always be a full explanation, at least in principle, to questions like why the sky is blue or why World War II happened. One problem for including this principle among the laws of thought is that it is a metaphysical principle, unlike the other three laws, which pertain primarily to logic.[134][127][133]

Counterfactual thinking edit

Counterfactual thinking involves mental representations of non-actual situations and events, i.e. of what is "contrary to the facts".[135][136] It is usually conditional: it aims at assessing what would be the case if a certain condition had obtained.[137][138] In this sense, it tries to answer "What if"-questions. For example, thinking after an accident that one would be dead if one had not used the seatbelt is a form of counterfactual thinking: it assumes, contrary to the facts, that one had not used the seatbelt and tries to assess the result of this state of affairs.[136] In this sense, counterfactual thinking is normally counterfactual only to a small degree since just a few facts are changed, like concerning the seatbelt, while most other facts are kept in place, like that one was driving, one's gender, the laws of physics, etc.[135] When understood in the widest sense, there are forms of counterfactual thinking that do not involve anything contrary to the facts at all.[138] This is the case, for example, when one tries to anticipate what might happen in the future if an uncertain event occurs and this event actually occurs later and brings with it the anticipated consequences.[137] In this wider sense, the term "subjunctive conditional" is sometimes used instead of "counterfactual conditional".[138] But the paradigmatic cases of counterfactual thinking involve alternatives to past events.[135]

Counterfactual thinking plays an important role since we evaluate the world around us not only by what actually happened but also by what could have happened.[136] Humans have a greater tendency to engage in counterfactual thinking after something bad happened because of some kind of action the agent performed.[137][135] In this sense, many regrets are associated with counterfactual thinking in which the agent contemplates how a better outcome could have been obtained if only they had acted differently.[136] These cases are known as upward counterfactuals, in contrast to downward counterfactuals, in which the counterfactual scenario is worse than actuality.[137][135] Upward counterfactual thinking is usually experienced as unpleasant, since it presents the actual circumstances in a bad light. This contrasts with the positive emotions associated with downward counterfactual thinking.[136] But both forms are important since it is possible to learn from them and to adjust one's behavior accordingly to get better results in the future.[136][135]

Thought experiments edit

Thought experiments involve thinking about imaginary situations, often with the aim of investigating the possible consequences of a change to the actual sequence of events.[139][140][141] It is a controversial issue to what extent thought experiments should be understood as actual experiments.[142][143][144] They are experiments in the sense that a certain situation is set up and one tries to learn from this situation by understanding what follows from it.[145][142] They differ from regular experiments in that imagination is used to set up the situation and counterfactual reasoning is employed to evaluate what follows from it, instead of setting it up physically and observing the consequences through perception.[146][140][142][141] Counterfactual thinking, therefore, plays a central role in thought experiments.[147]

The Chinese room argument is a famous thought experiment proposed by John Searle.[148][149] It involves a person sitting inside a closed-off room, tasked with responding to messages written in Chinese. This person does not know Chinese but has a giant rule book that specifies exactly how to reply to any possible message, similar to how a computer would react to messages. The core idea of this thought experiment is that neither the person nor the computer understands Chinese. This way, Searle aims to show that computers lack a mind capable of deeper forms of understanding despite acting intelligently.[148][149]

Thought experiments are employed for various purposes, for example, for entertainment, education, or as arguments for or against theories. Most discussions focus on their use as arguments. This use is found in fields like philosophy, the natural sciences, and history.[140][144][143][142] It is controversial since there is a lot of disagreement concerning the epistemic status of thought experiments, i.e. how reliable they are as evidence supporting or refuting a theory.[140][144][143][142] Central to the rejection of this usage is the fact that they pretend to be a source of knowledge without the need to leave one's armchair in search of any new empirical data. Defenders of thought experiments usually contend that the intuitions underlying and guiding the thought experiments are, at least in some cases, reliable.[140][142] But thought experiments can also fail if they are not properly supported by intuitions or if they go beyond what the intuitions support.[140][141] In the latter sense, sometimes counter thought experiments are proposed that modify the original scenario in slight ways in order to show that initial intuitions cannot survive this change.[140] Various taxonomies of thought experiments have been suggested. They can be distinguished, for example, by whether they are successful or not, by the discipline that uses them, by their role in a theory, or by whether they accept or modify the actual laws of physics.[141][140]

Critical thinking edit

Critical thinking is a form of thinking that is reasonable, reflective, and focused on determining what to believe or how to act.[150][151][152] It holds itself to various standards, like clarity and rationality. In this sense, it involves not just cognitive processes trying to solve the issue at hand but at the same time meta-cognitive processes ensuring that it lives up to its own standards.[151] This includes assessing both that the reasoning itself is sound and that the evidence it rests on is reliable.[151] This means that logic plays an important role in critical thinking. It concerns not just formal logic, but also informal logic, specifically to avoid various informal fallacies due to vague or ambiguous expressions in natural language.[151][74][73] No generally accepted standard definition of "critical thinking" exists but there is significant overlap between the proposed definitions in their characterization of critical thinking as careful and goal-directed.[152] According to some versions, only the thinker's own observations and experiments are accepted as evidence in critical thinking. Some restrict it to the formation of judgments but exclude action as its goal.[152]

A concrete everyday example of critical thinking, due to John Dewey, involves observing foam bubbles moving in a direction that is contrary to one's initial expectations. The critical thinker tries to come up with various possible explanations of this behavior and then slightly modifies the original situation in order to determine which one is the right explanation.[152][153] But not all forms of cognitively valuable processes involve critical thinking. Arriving at the correct solution to a problem by blindly following the steps of an algorithm does not qualify as critical thinking. The same is true if the solution is presented to the thinker in a sudden flash of insight and accepted straight away.[152]

Critical thinking plays an important role in education: fostering the student's ability to think critically is often seen as an important educational goal.[152][151][154] In this sense, it is important to convey not just a set of true beliefs to the student but also the ability to draw one's own conclusions and to question pre-existing beliefs.[154] The abilities and dispositions learned this way may profit not just the individual but also society at large.[151] Critics of the emphasis on critical thinking in education have argued that there is no universal form of correct thinking. Instead, they contend that different subject matters rely on different standards and education should focus on imparting these subject-specific skills instead of trying to teach universal methods of thinking.[152][155] Other objections are based on the idea that critical thinking and the attitude underlying it involve various unjustified biases, like egocentrism, distanced objectivity, indifference, and an overemphasis of the theoretical in contrast to the practical.[152]

Positive thinking edit

Positive thinking is an important topic in positive psychology.[156] It involves focusing one's attention on the positive aspects of one's situation and thereby withdrawing one's attention from its negative sides.[156] This is usually seen as a global outlook that applies especially to thinking but includes other mental processes, like feeling, as well.[156] In this sense, it is closely related to optimism. It includes expecting positive things to happen in the future.[157][156] This positive outlook makes it more likely for people to seek to attain new goals.[156] It also increases the probability of continuing to strive towards pre-existing goals that seem difficult to reach instead of just giving up.[157][156]

The effects of positive thinking are not yet thoroughly researched, but some studies suggest that there is a correlation between positive thinking and well-being.[156] For example, students and pregnant women with a positive outlook tend to be better at dealing with stressful situations.[157][156] This is sometimes explained by pointing out that stress is not inherent in stressful situations but depends on the agent's interpretation of the situation. Reduced stress may therefore be found in positive thinkers because they tend to see such situations in a more positive light.[156] But the effects also include the practical domain in that positive thinkers tend to employ healthier coping strategies when faced with difficult situations.[156] This effects, for example, the time needed to fully recover from surgeries and the tendency to resume physical exercise afterward.[157]

But it has been argued that whether positive thinking actually leads to positive outcomes depends on various other factors. Without these factors, it may lead to negative results. For example, the tendency of optimists to keep striving in difficult situations can backfire if the course of events is outside the agent's control.[157] Another danger associated with positive thinking is that it may remain only on the level of unrealistic fantasies and thereby fail to make a positive practical contribution to the agent's life.[158] Pessimism, on the other hand, may have positive effects since it can mitigate disappointments by anticipating failures.[157][159]

Positive thinking is a recurrent topic in the self-help literature.[160] Here, often the claim is made that one can significantly improve one's life by trying to think positively, even if this means fostering beliefs that are contrary to evidence.[161] Such claims and the effectiveness of the suggested methods are controversial and have been criticized due to their lack of scientific evidence.[161][162] In the New Thought movement, positive thinking figures in the law of attraction, the pseudoscientific claim that positive thoughts can directly influence the external world by attracting positive outcomes.[163]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x "Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021.
  2. ^ Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary, 2nd ed., 2001, Published by Random House, Inc., ISBN 978-0-375-42599-8, p. 1975
  3. ^ Webster's II New College Dictionary, Webster Staff, Webster, Houghton Mifflin Company, 2nd ed., illustrated, revised Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 1999, ISBN 978-0-395-96214-5, p. 1147
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. pp. 1–24.
  5. ^ a b c Nida-rümelin, Martine (2010). "Thinking Without Language. A Phenomenological Argument for Its Possibility and Existence". Grazer Philosophische Studien. 81 (1): 55–75. doi:10.1163/9789042030190_005.
  6. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-14. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4.
  7. ^ a b Mole, Christopher (2021). "Attention: 2.3 Coherence Theories". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  8. ^ Katsafanas, Paul (2015). "Nietzsche on the Nature of the Unconscious". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 58 (3): 327–352. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2013.855658. S2CID 38776513.
  9. ^ a b c d e Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5498519. PMID 28729844.
  10. ^ a b c d e f g h Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280.
  11. ^ Skirry, Justin. "Descartes, Rene: Mind-Body Distinction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021.
  12. ^ Smith, Kurt (2021). "Descartes' Theory of Ideas: 1. Ideas Understood as Modes of Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  13. ^ a b Baum, Eric B. (2004). "1. Introduction". What Is Thought?. Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.
  14. ^ Block, Ned (1981). "Psychologism and Behaviorism". Philosophical Review. 90 (1): 5–43. doi:10.2307/2184371. JSTOR 2184371.
  15. ^ Romer, Paul M. (May 2000). "Thinking and Feeling". American Economic Review. 90 (2): 439–443. doi:10.1257/aer.90.2.439. ISSN 0002-8282.
  16. ^ Planalp, Sally; Fitness, Julie (1 December 1999). "Thinking/Feeling about Social and Personal Relationships". Journal of Social and Personal Relationships. 16 (6): 731–750. doi:10.1177/0265407599166004. ISSN 0265-4075. S2CID 145750153.
  17. ^ Phelan, Mark; Arico, Adam; Nichols, Shaun (2013). "Thinking Things and Feeling Things: On an Alleged Discontinuity in Folk Metaphysics of Mind". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 12 (4): 703–725. doi:10.1007/s11097-012-9278-7. S2CID 15856600.
  18. ^ "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: thought". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October 2021.
  19. ^ a b Mandelbaum, Eric (2014). "Thinking is Believing". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 57 (1): 55–96. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2014.858417. S2CID 52968342.
  20. ^ a b "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: think". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October 2021.
  21. ^ Harper, Douglas. "Etymology of Thought". Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved 2009-05-22.
  22. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
  23. ^ a b c d Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). "Plato and the Norms of Thought". Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012. ISSN 0026-4423.
  24. ^ a b c Langland-Hassan, Peter; Vicente, Agustin (2018). "Introduction". Inner Speech: New Voices. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  25. ^ Kraut, Richard (2017). "Plato". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 April 2021.
  26. ^ Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. "Plato: 6b. The Theory of Forms". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 24 April 2021.
  27. ^ Nehamas, Alexander (1975). "Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World". American Philosophical Quarterly. 12 (2): 105–117. ISSN 0003-0481. JSTOR 20009565.
  28. ^ a b Sellars, Wilfrid (1949). "Aristotelian Philosophies of Mind". Philosophy for The Future, The Quest of Modern Materialism.
  29. ^ Klima, Gyula (2017). "The Medieval Problem of Universals: 1. Introduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  30. ^ a b c d Harman, Gilbert (1973). "4. Thought and meaning". Thought. Princeton University Press.
  31. ^ Roessler, Johannes (2016). "Thinking, Inner Speech, and Self-Awareness". Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 7 (3): 541–557. doi:10.1007/s13164-015-0267-y. S2CID 15028459.
  32. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021.
  33. ^ a b Bermudez, Jose Luis (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford University Press USA.
  34. ^ Lohmar, Dieter (2012). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). "Language and non-linguistic thinking". The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199594900.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-959490-0.
  35. ^ Andrews, Kristin; Monsó, Susana (2021). "Animal Cognition: 3.4 Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 25 October 2021.
  36. ^ Premack, David (28 August 2007). "Human and animal cognition: Continuity and discontinuity". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 104 (35): 13861–13867. Bibcode:2007PNAS..10413861P. doi:10.1073/pnas.0706147104. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 1955772. PMID 17717081.
  37. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021.
  38. ^ a b c d e Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought". Retrieved 27 October 2021.
  39. ^ Fodor, Jerry A. (2008). Lot 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford University Press.
  40. ^ a b c Borchert, Donald (2006). "Language of thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
  41. ^ a b c d Milkowski, Marcin. "Computational Theory of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  42. ^ a b Doorey, Marie. "Conditioning". The Gale Encyclopedia of Science.
  43. ^ a b Van der Veldt, J. H. "Associationism". New Catholic Encyclopedia.
  44. ^ a b c d e Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021.
  45. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021.
  46. ^ Lazzeri, Filipe (2019-08-16). "O que é Behaviorismo sobre a mente?". Principia (in Portuguese). 23 (2): 249–277. doi:10.5007/1808-1711.2019v23n2p249. ISSN 1808-1711. S2CID 212888121.
  47. ^ a b c Graham, George (2019). "Behaviorism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 31 May 2021.
  48. ^ Audet, Jean-Nicolas; Lefebvre, Louis (18 February 2017). "What's flexible in behavioral flexibility?". Behavioral Ecology. 28 (4): 943–947. doi:10.1093/beheco/arx007. ISSN 1045-2249.
  49. ^ a b Reese, Hayne W. (2000). "Thinking as the Behaviorist Views It". Behavioral Development Bulletin. 9 (1): 10–12. doi:10.1037/h0100531.
  50. ^ Mele, Alfred R. (2003). "Introduction". Motivation and Agency. Oxford University Press.
  51. ^ Mele, Alfred R. (1995). "Motivation: Essentially Motivation-Constituting Attitudes". Philosophical Review. 104 (3): 387–423. doi:10.2307/2185634. JSTOR 2185634.
  52. ^ Schwitzgebel, Eric (2019). "Belief". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 15 November 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020.
  53. ^ Borchert, Donald (2006). "Belief". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. from the original on 12 January 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021.
  54. ^ a b c d "Philosophy of mind – The computational-representational theory of thought (CRTT)". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
  55. ^ a b Polger, Thomas W. "Functionalism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 31 May 2021.
  56. ^ Gulick, Robert Van (2009). Beckermann, Ansgar; McLaughlin, Brian P; Walter, Sven (eds.). "Functionalism". The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-926261-8.
  57. ^ Honderich, Ted (2005). "Mind". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  58. ^ Levin, Janet (2021). "Functionalism: 2.2 Thinking Machines and the "Turing Test"". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021.
  59. ^ Pitt, David (2020). "Mental Representation: 1. The Representational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021.
  60. ^ Schmidt, R. W. "Judgment". New Catholic Encyclopedia.
  61. ^ Sgarbi, Marco (2006). "Theories of Judgment. Historical and Theoretical Perspectives". Quaestio. 6 (1): 589–592. doi:10.1484/J.QUAESTIO.2.302491.
  62. ^ Robins, E. P. (1898). "Modern Theories of Judgment". Philosophical Review. 7 (6): 583–603. doi:10.2307/2176171. JSTOR 2176171.
  63. ^ a b c d e Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment". The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013. ISBN 978-0521591041.
  64. ^ Hanna, Robert (2018). "Kant's Theory of Judgment". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021.
  65. ^ a b c d Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2020). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021.
  66. ^ a b Vinacke, W. Edgar. "Thought". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences.
  67. ^ Pollock, John L. (1987). "Defeasible Reasoning". Cognitive Science. 11 (4): 481–518. doi:10.1207/s15516709cog1104_4.
  68. ^ Koons, Robert (2021). "Defeasible Reasoning". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 16 October 2021.
  69. ^ a b c Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March 2021.
  70. ^ Vleet, Van Jacob E. (2010). "Introduction". Informal Logical Fallacies: A Brief Guide. Upa.
  71. ^ Stone, Mark A. (2012). "Denying the Antecedent: Its Effective Use in Argumentation". Informal Logic. 32 (3): 327–356. doi:10.22329/il.v32i3.3681.
  72. ^ Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 March 2021.
  73. ^ a b Walton, Douglas N. (1987). "1. A new model of argument". Informal Fallacies: Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms. John Benjamins.
  74. ^ a b Engel, S. Morris (1982). "2. The medium of language". With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies.
  75. ^ a b c Margolis, Eric; Laurence, Stephen (2021). "Concepts". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 September 2021.
  76. ^ "Philosophy of mind – Thoughts and attitudes". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021.
  77. ^ a b c "Concept formation". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021.
  78. ^ a b c d e f g h Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5.
  79. ^ a b Fodor, Jerry (2004). "Having Concepts: A Brief Refutation of the Twentieth Century". Mind and Language. 19 (1): 29–47. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00245.x.
  80. ^ Weiskopf, Daniel A.; Bechtel, William (2004). "Remarks on Fodor on Having Concepts". Mind and Language. 19 (1): 48–56. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00246.x.
  81. ^ "Learning theory". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021.
  82. ^ Kim, Kyung Hee; Pierce, Robert A. (2013). "Convergent Versus Divergent Thinking". Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention, Innovation and Entrepreneurship. Springer. pp. 245–250. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-3858-8_22. ISBN 978-1-4614-3857-1. Retrieved 24 October 2021. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  83. ^ Razumnikova, Olga M. (2013). "Divergent Versus Convergent Thinking". Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention, Innovation and Entrepreneurship. Springer. pp. 546–552. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-3858-8_362. ISBN 978-1-4614-3857-1. Retrieved 24 October 2021. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
  84. ^ a b Reed, Stephen K. (1 December 2016). "The Structure of Ill-Structured (and Well-Structured) Problems Revisited". Educational Psychology Review. 28 (4): 691–716. doi:10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1. ISSN 1573-336X. S2CID 146496245.
  85. ^ Arpaly, N.; Schroeder, T. (2012). "Deliberation and Acting for Reasons". Philosophical Review. 121 (2): 209–239. doi:10.1215/00318108-1539089.
  86. ^ a b c Steele, Katie; Stefánsson, H. Orri (2020). "Decision Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021.
  87. ^ a b c Buchak, Lara (2016). "Decision Theory". The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  88. ^ a b Perrin, Denis; Michaelian, Kourken; Sant’Anna, André (2020). "The Phenomenology of Remembering Is an Epistemic Feeling". Frontiers in Psychology. 11: 1531. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01531. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 7350950. PMID 32719642.
  89. ^ Gardiner, J. M. (29 September 2001). "Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness: a first-person approach". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences. 356 (1413): 1351–1361. doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.0955. ISSN 0962-8436. PMC 1088519. PMID 11571027.
  90. ^ a b c Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 3. Episodicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 October 2021.
  91. ^ Tulving, Endel. "Learning and Memory: Episodic Memory".
  92. ^ Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 4. Mnemicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 October 2021.
  93. ^ a b Manser, A. R. "Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Imagination". Retrieved 3 October 2021.
  94. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1915). "Sensation and Imagination". The Monist. 25 (1): 28–44. doi:10.5840/monist191525136.
  95. ^ Abbott, Alison (1 January 2015). "Unconscious thought not so smart after all". Nature. 517 (7536): 537–538. Bibcode:2015Natur.517..537A. doi:10.1038/517537a. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 25631423.
  96. ^ Mealor, Andy David; Dienes, Zoltan (2012). "Conscious and Unconscious Thought in Artificial Grammar Learning". Consciousness and Cognition. 21 (2): 865–874. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2012.03.001. PMID 22472202. S2CID 40114660.
  97. ^ Fowles, Christopher (2 January 2019). "Nietzsche on conscious and unconscious thought". Inquiry. 62 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2019.1527537. ISSN 0020-174X. S2CID 171812391.
  98. ^ Smith, David Woodruff (2018). "Phenomenology: 1. What is Phenomenology?". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 20 September 2021.
  99. ^ Smith, Joel. "Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 October 2021.
  100. ^ a b c d e f Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021.
  101. ^ a b c d e f Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43.
  102. ^ a b Carruthers, Peter; Veillet, Bénédicte (2011). "The Case Against Cognitive Phenomenology". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
  103. ^ a b c Prinz, Jesse J. (2011). "The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
  104. ^ a b Levine, Joseph (2011). "On the Phenomenology of Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
  105. ^ Siewert, Charles (2011). "Phenomenal Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
  106. ^ Pitt, David (2004). "The Phenomenology of Cognition: Or What Is It Like to Think That P?". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 69 (1): 1–36. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2004.tb00382.x.
  107. ^ Smith, David Woodruff (2011). "The Phenomenology of Consciously Thinking". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
  108. ^ a b Dastur, Françoise; Vallier, Robert (2017). "The Problem of Pre-Predicative Experience: Husserl". Questions of Phenomenology. Fordham University Press. doi:10.5422/fordham/9780823233731.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-8232-3373-1. S2CID 148619048.
  109. ^ a b Staiti, Andrea (2018). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). Pre-Predicative Experience and Life-World. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.12. ISBN 978-0-19-875534-0.
  110. ^ a b Diaz, Emiliano (2020). "Transcendental Anticipation: A Reconsideration of Husserl's Type and Kant's Schemata". Husserl Studies. 36 (1): 1–23. doi:10.1007/s10743-019-09249-3. S2CID 203547989.
  111. ^ a b Doyon, Maxime (2015). "The "As-Structure" of Intentional Experience in Husserl and Heidegger". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 122–139. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-10. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4.
  112. ^ a b c Hopp, Walter (2015). "Empty Intentions and Phenomenological Character: A Defense of Inclusivism". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 50–67. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-6. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4.
  113. ^ a b c d Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content: 2ai Act-Character". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 October 2021.
  114. ^ Kim, J. (1995). Honderich, Ted (ed.). Problems in the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
  115. ^ Companion to Metaphysics, By Jaegwon Kim, Gary S. Rosenkrantz, Ernest Sosa, Contributor Jaegwon Kim, 2nd ed., Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, ISBN 978-1-4051-5298-3
  116. ^ Varela, Francisco J., Thompson, Evan T., and Rosch, Eleanor. (1992). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-72021-3
  117. ^ Cowart, Monica (2004). "Embodied Cognition". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 27 February 2012.
  118. ^ Di Paolo, Ezequiel (2009). "Shallow and Deep Embodiment" (Video, duration: 1:11:38). University of Sussex. Retrieved 27 February 2012.
  119. ^ Gestalt Theory, By Max Wertheimer. Hayes Barton Press, 1944, ISBN 978-1-59377-695-4
  120. ^ Piaget, J. (1951). Psychology of Intelligence. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
  121. ^ Demetriou, A. (1998). Cognitive development. In A. Demetriou, W. Doise, K. F. M. van Lieshout (Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology. pp. 179–269. London: Wiley.
  122. ^ Schacter, Daniel L. (2011). Psychology Second Edition, "Positive Psychology". New York.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) 584 pp.
  123. ^ Snowden, Ruth (2006). Teach Yourself Freud (illustrated ed.). McGraw-Hill. p. 107. ISBN 978-0-07-147274-6.
  124. ^ The Cambridge companion to Freud, By Jerome Neu. Cambridge University Press, 1991, p. 29, ISBN 978-0-521-37779-9
  125. ^ Jensen, Peter S., Mrazek, David, Knapp, Penelope K., Steinberg, Laurence, Pfeffer, Cynthia, Schowalter, John, & Shapiro, Theodore. (Dec 1997) "Evolution and revolution in child psychiatry: ADHD as a disorder of adaptation. (attention-deficit hyperactivity syndrome)". Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry. 36. p. 1672. (10). July 14, 2007.
  126. ^ a b c d e "Laws of thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  127. ^ a b c d e f g h i Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
  128. ^ Moschovakis, Joan (2021). "Intuitionistic Logic: 1. Rejection of Tertium Non Datur". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  129. ^ McKubre-Jordens, Maarten. "Constructive Mathematics: 1b Constructivism as Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  130. ^ Priest, Graham; Berto, Francesco; Weber, Zach (2018). "Dialetheism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  131. ^ Horn, Laurence R. (2018). "Contradiction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  132. ^ Weber, Zach. "Dialetheism". Oxford Bibliographies. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  133. ^ a b "principle of sufficient reason". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  134. ^ a b Melamed, Yitzhak Y.; Lin, Martin (2021). "Principle of Sufficient Reason". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  135. ^ a b c d e f Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895.
  136. ^ a b c d e f Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5.
  137. ^ a b c d Van Hoeck, Nicole; Watson, Patrick D.; Barbey, Aron K. (2015). "Cognitive neuroscience of human counterfactual reasoning". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 9: 420. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00420. ISSN 1662-5161. PMC 4511878. PMID 26257633.
  138. ^ a b c Starr, William (2021). "Counterfactuals: 1.1 What are Counterfactuals?". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
  139. ^ "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: thought experiment". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 30 October 2021.
  140. ^ a b c d e f g h Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
  141. ^ a b c d Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment". Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 978-9004201774. S2CID 260640180.
  142. ^ a b c d e f Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7.
  143. ^ a b c Bishop, Michael A. (1999). "Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments". Philosophy of Science. 66 (4): 534–541. doi:10.1086/392753. S2CID 170519663.
  144. ^ a b c Norton, John D. (1996). "Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 26 (3): 333–366. doi:10.1080/00455091.1996.10717457. S2CID 143017404.
  145. ^ Sorensen, Roy (1 January 1995). "Roy Sorensen's Thought Experiments". Informal Logic. 17 (3). doi:10.22329/il.v17i3.2425. ISSN 2293-734X.
  146. ^ Reiss, Julian (1 December 2009). "Counterfactuals, Thought Experiments, and Singular Causal Analysis in History". Philosophy of Science. 76 (5): 712–723. doi:10.1086/605826. ISSN 0031-8248. S2CID 43496954.
  147. ^ Aligica, Paul Dragos; Evans, Anthony J. (1 September 2009). "Thought experiments, counterfactuals and comparative analysis". The Review of Austrian Economics. 22 (3): 225–239. doi:10.1007/s11138-009-0082-8. ISSN 1573-7128. S2CID 144831020.
  148. ^ a b Cole, David (2020). "The Chinese Room Argument". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
  149. ^ a b Hauser, Larry. "Chinese Room Argument". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
  150. ^ Ennis, Robert H. (2015). "Critical Thinking: A Streamlined Conception". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 31–47. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_2. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7.
  151. ^ a b c d e f Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7.
  152. ^ a b c d e f g h Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021.
  153. ^ Dewey, John (1910). "6: The Analysis of a Complete Act of Thought". How We Think.
  154. ^ a b Siegel, Harvey (2006). "Philosophy if Education, Epistemological Issues In". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
  155. ^ Monteiro, Sandra; Sherbino, Jonathan; Sibbald, Matthew; Norman, Geoff (2020). "Critical thinking, biases and dual processing: The enduring myth of generalisable skills". Medical Education. 54 (1): 66–73. doi:10.1111/medu.13872. ISSN 1365-2923. PMID 31468581. S2CID 201674464.
  156. ^ a b c d e f g h i j Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61.
  157. ^ a b c d e f Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172.
  158. ^ Oettingen, Gabriele; Cachia, Julie Y. A. (2017). "30. Problems with Positive Thinking and How to Overcome Them". Handbook of Self-Regulation: Third Edition: Research, Theory, and Applications.
  159. ^ Thomas, Sandra P. (2020). "Defensive Pessimism". Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1036–1038. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_1061. ISBN 978-3-319-24612-3. S2CID 243736790.
  160. ^ Peale, Norman Vincent. The Power of Positive Thinking. Om Books International. ISBN 978-93-85609-89-3.
  161. ^ a b Seligman, Martin E. P. (2002). "6. Optimism about the Future". Authentic Happiness: Using the New Positive Psychology to Realize Your Potential for Lasting Fulfillment. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-7432-4788-7.
  162. ^ Woodstock, Louise (1 April 2007). "Think About It: The Misbegotten Promise of Positive Thinking Discourse". Journal of Communication Inquiry. 31 (2): 166–189. doi:10.1177/0196859906298177. ISSN 0196-8599. S2CID 145436993.
  163. ^ Chabris, Christopher F.; Simons, Daniel J. (24 September 2010). "Fight 'The Power'". The New York Times.

Further reading edit

Listen to this article (18 minutes)
 
This audio file was created from a revision of this article dated 4 December 2010 (2010-12-04), and does not reflect subsequent edits.
  • Bayne, Tim (21 September 2013), "Thoughts", New Scientist. 7-page feature article on the topic.
  • Fields, R. Douglas, "The Brain Learns in Unexpected Ways: Neuroscientists have discovered a set of unfamiliar cellular mechanisms for making fresh memories", Scientific American, vol. 322, no. 3 (March 2020), pp. 74–79. "Myelin, long considered inert insulation on axons, is now seen as making a contribution to learning by controlling the speed at which signals travel along neural wiring." (p. 79.)
  • Rajvanshi, Anil K. (2010), Nature of Human Thought, ISBN 978-81-905781-2-7.
  • Simon, Herbert, Models of Thought, Vol I, 1979, ISBN 0-300-02347-2; Vol II, 1989, ISBN 0-300-04230-2, Yale University Press.

External links edit

  •   The dictionary definition of think at Wiktionary
  •   Media related to Thinking at Wikimedia Commons

thought, other, uses, disambiguation, think, thinking, redirect, here, other, uses, think, disambiguation, thinking, disambiguation, their, most, common, sense, terms, thought, thinking, refer, conscious, cognitive, processes, that, happen, independently, sens. For other uses see Thought disambiguation Think and Thinking redirect here For other uses see Think disambiguation and Thinking disambiguation In their most common sense the terms thought and thinking refer to conscious cognitive processes that can happen independently of sensory stimulation Their most paradigmatic forms are judging reasoning concept formation problem solving and deliberation But other mental processes like considering an idea memory or imagination are also often included These processes can happen internally independent of the sensory organs unlike perception But when understood in the widest sense any mental event may be understood as a form of thinking including perception and unconscious mental processes In a slightly different sense the term thought refers not to the mental processes themselves but to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes The Thinker by Rodin 1840 1917 in the garden of the Musee Rodin Various theories of thinking have been proposed some of which aim to capture the characteristic features of thought Platonists hold that thinking consists in discerning and inspecting Platonic forms and their interrelations It involves the ability to discriminate between the pure Platonic forms themselves and the mere imitations found in the sensory world According to Aristotelianism to think about something is to instantiate in one s mind the universal essence of the object of thought These universals are abstracted from sense experience and are not understood as existing in a changeless intelligible world in contrast to Platonism Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism it identifies thinking with mentally evoking concepts instead of instantiating essences Inner speech theories claim that thinking is a form of inner speech in which words are silently expressed in the thinker s mind According to some accounts this happens in a regular language like English or French The language of thought hypothesis on the other hand holds that this happens in the medium of a unique mental language called Mentalese Central to this idea is that linguistic representational systems are built up from atomic and compound representations and that this structure is also found in thought Associationists understand thinking as the succession of ideas or images They are particularly interested in the laws of association that govern how the train of thought unfolds Behaviorists by contrast identify thinking with behavioral dispositions to engage in public intelligent behavior as a reaction to particular external stimuli Computationalism is the most recent of these theories It sees thinking in analogy to how computers work in terms of the storage transmission and processing of information Various types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature A judgment is a mental operation in which a proposition is evoked and then either affirmed or denied Reasoning on the other hand is the process of drawing conclusions from premises or evidence Both judging and reasoning depend on the possession of the relevant concepts which are acquired in the process of concept formation In the case of problem solving thinking aims at reaching a predefined goal by overcoming certain obstacles Deliberation is an important form of practical thought that consists in formulating possible courses of action and assessing the reasons for and against them This may lead to a decision by choosing the most favorable option Both episodic memory and imagination present objects and situations internally in an attempt to accurately reproduce what was previously experienced or as a free rearrangement respectively Unconscious thought is thought that happens without being directly experienced It is sometimes posited to explain how difficult problems are solved in cases where no conscious thought was employed Thought is discussed in various academic disciplines Phenomenology is interested in the experience of thinking An important question in this field concerns the experiential character of thinking and to what extent this character can be explained in terms of sensory experience Metaphysics is among other things interested in the relation between mind and matter This concerns the question of how thinking can fit into the material world as described by the natural sciences Cognitive psychology aims to understand thought as a form of information processing Developmental psychology on the other hand investigates the development of thought from birth to maturity and asks which factors this development depends on Psychoanalysis emphasizes the role of the unconscious in mental life Other fields concerned with thought include linguistics neuroscience artificial intelligence biology and sociology Various concepts and theories are closely related to the topic of thought The term law of thought refers to three fundamental laws of logic the law of contradiction the law of excluded middle and the principle of identity Counterfactual thinking involves mental representations of non actual situations and events in which the thinker tries to assess what would be the case if things had been different Thought experiments often employ counterfactual thinking in order to illustrate theories or to test their plausibility Critical thinking is a form of thinking that is reasonable reflective and focused on determining what to believe or how to act Positive thinking involves focusing one s attention on the positive aspects of one s situation and is intimately related to optimism Contents 1 Definition 2 Theories of thinking 2 1 Platonism 2 2 Aristotelianism and conceptualism 2 3 Inner speech theory 2 3 1 Language of thought hypothesis 2 4 Associationism 2 5 Behaviorism 2 6 Computationalism 3 Types of thinking 3 1 Entertaining judging and reasoning 3 2 Concept formation 3 3 Problem solving 3 4 Deliberation and decision 3 5 Episodic memory and imagination 3 6 Unconscious thought 4 In various disciplines 4 1 Phenomenology 4 2 Metaphysics 4 3 Psychology 4 4 Psychoanalysis 5 Related concepts and theories 5 1 Laws of thought 5 2 Counterfactual thinking 5 3 Thought experiments 5 4 Critical thinking 5 5 Positive thinking 6 See also 7 References 8 Further reading 9 External linksDefinition editThe terms thought and thinking refer to a wide variety of psychological activities 1 2 3 In their most common sense they are understood as conscious processes that can happen independently of sensory stimulation 4 5 This includes various different mental processes like considering an idea or proposition or judging it to be true In this sense memory and imagination are forms of thought but perception is not 6 In a more restricted sense only the most paradigmatic cases are considered thought These involve conscious processes that are conceptual or linguistic and sufficiently abstract like judging inferring problem solving and deliberating 1 7 8 Sometimes the terms thought and thinking are understood in a very wide sense as referring to any form of mental process conscious or unconscious 9 10 In this sense they may be used synonymously with the term mind This usage is encountered for example in the Cartesian tradition where minds are understood as thinking things and in the cognitive sciences 6 11 12 13 But this sense may include the restriction that such processes have to lead to intelligent behavior to be considered thought 14 A contrast sometimes found in the academic literature is that between thinking and feeling In this context thinking is associated with a sober dispassionate and rational approach to its topic while feeling involves a direct emotional engagement 15 16 17 The terms thought and thinking can also be used to refer not to the mental processes themselves but to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes 18 In this sense they are often synonymous with the term belief and its cognates and may refer to the mental states which either belong to an individual or are common among a certain group of people 19 20 Discussions of thought in the academic literature often leave it implicit which sense of the term they have in mind The word thought comes from Old English thoht or gethoht from the stem of thencan to conceive of in the mind consider 21 Theories of thinking editVarious theories of thinking have been proposed 22 They aim to capture the characteristic features of thinking The theories listed here are not exclusive it may be possible to combine some without leading to a contradiction Platonism edit According to Platonism thinking is a spiritual activity in which Platonic forms and their interrelations are discerned and inspected 22 23 This activity is understood as a form of silent inner speech in which the soul talks to itself 24 Platonic forms are seen as universals that exist in a changeless realm different from the sensible world Examples include the forms of goodness beauty unity and sameness 25 26 27 On this view the difficulty of thinking consists in being unable to grasp the Platonic forms and to distinguish them as the original from the mere imitations found in the sensory world This means for example distinguishing beauty itself from derivative images of beauty 23 One problem for this view is to explain how humans can learn and think about Platonic forms belonging to a different realm 22 Plato himself tries to solve this problem through his theory of recollection according to which the soul already was in contact with the Platonic forms before and is therefore able to remember what they are like 23 But this explanation depends on various assumptions usually not accepted in contemporary thought 23 Aristotelianism and conceptualism edit Aristotelians hold that the mind is able to think about something by instantiating the essence of the object of thought 22 So while thinking about trees the mind instantiates tree ness This instantiation does not happen in matter as is the case for actual trees but in mind though the universal essence instantiated in both cases is the same 22 In contrast to Platonism these universals are not understood as Platonic forms existing in a changeless intelligible world 28 Instead they only exist to the extent that they are instantiated The mind learns to discriminate universals through abstraction from experience 29 This explanation avoids various of the objections raised against Platonism 28 Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism It states that thinking consists in mentally evoking concepts Some of these concepts may be innate but most have to be learned through abstraction from sense experience before they can be used in thought 22 It has been argued against these views that they have problems in accounting for the logical form of thought For example to think that it will either rain or snow it is not sufficient to instantiate the essences of rain and snow or to evoke the corresponding concepts The reason for this is that the disjunctive relation between the rain and the snow is not captured this way 22 Another problem shared by these positions is the difficulty of giving a satisfying account of how essences or concepts are learned by the mind through abstraction 22 Inner speech theory edit Inner speech theories claim that thinking is a form of inner speech 6 30 24 1 This view is sometimes termed psychological nominalism 22 It states that thinking involves silently evoking words and connecting them to form mental sentences The knowledge a person has of their thoughts can be explained as a form of overhearing one s own silent monologue 31 Three central aspects are often ascribed to inner speech it is in an important sense similar to hearing sounds it involves the use of language and it constitutes a motor plan that could be used for actual speech 24 This connection to language is supported by the fact that thinking is often accompanied by muscle activity in the speech organs This activity may facilitate thinking in certain cases but is not necessary for it in general 1 According to some accounts thinking happens not in a regular language like English or French but has its own type of language with the corresponding symbols and syntax This theory is known as the language of thought hypothesis 30 32 Inner speech theory has a strong initial plausibility since introspection suggests that indeed many thoughts are accompanied by inner speech But its opponents usually contend that this is not true for all types of thinking 22 5 33 It has been argued for example that forms of daydreaming constitute non linguistic thought 34 This issue is relevant to the question of whether animals have the capacity to think If thinking is necessarily tied to language then this would suggest that there is an important gap between humans and animals since only humans have a sufficiently complex language But the existence of non linguistic thoughts suggests that this gap may not be that big and that some animals do indeed think 33 35 36 Language of thought hypothesis edit There are various theories about the relation between language and thought One prominent version in contemporary philosophy is called the language of thought hypothesis 30 32 37 38 39 It states that thinking happens in the medium of a mental language This language often referred to as Mentalese is similar to regular languages in various respects it is composed of words that are connected to each other in syntactic ways to form sentences 30 32 37 38 This claim does not merely rest on an intuitive analogy between language and thought Instead it provides a clear definition of the features a representational system has to embody in order to have a linguistic structure 37 32 38 On the level of syntax the representational system has to possess two types of representations atomic and compound representations Atomic representations are basic whereas compound representations are constituted either by other compound representations or by atomic representations 37 32 38 On the level of semantics the semantic content or the meaning of the compound representations should depend on the semantic contents of its constituents A representational system is linguistically structured if it fulfills these two requirements 37 32 38 The language of thought hypothesis states that the same is true for thinking in general This would mean that thought is composed of certain atomic representational constituents that can be combined as described above 37 32 40 Apart from this abstract characterization no further concrete claims are made about how human thought is implemented by the brain or which other similarities to natural language it has 37 The language of thought hypothesis was first introduced by Jerry Fodor 32 37 He argues in favor of this claim by holding that it constitutes the best explanation of the characteristic features of thinking One of these features is productivity a system of representations is productive if it can generate an infinite number of unique representations based on a low number of atomic representations 37 32 40 This applies to thought since human beings are capable of entertaining an infinite number of distinct thoughts even though their mental capacities are quite limited Other characteristic features of thinking include systematicity and inferential coherence 32 37 40 Fodor argues that the language of thought hypothesis is true as it explains how thought can have these features and because there is no good alternative explanation 37 Some arguments against the language of thought hypothesis are based on neural networks which are able to produce intelligent behavior without depending on representational systems Other objections focus on the idea that some mental representations happen non linguistically for example in the form of maps or images 37 32 Computationalists have been especially interested in the language of thought hypothesis since it provides ways to close the gap between thought in the human brain and computational processes implemented by computers 37 32 41 The reason for this is that processes over representations that respect syntax and semantics like inferences according to the modus ponens can be implemented by physical systems using causal relations The same linguistic systems may be implemented through different material systems like brains or computers In this way computers can think 37 32 Associationism edit An important view in the empiricist tradition has been associationism the view that thinking consists in the succession of ideas or images 1 42 43 This succession is seen as being governed by laws of association which determine how the train of thought unfolds 1 44 These laws are different from logical relations between the contents of thoughts which are found in the case of drawing inferences by moving from the thought of the premises to the thought of the conclusion 44 Various laws of association have been suggested According to the laws of similarity and contrast ideas tend to evoke other ideas that are either very similar to them or their opposite The law of contiguity on the other hand states that if two ideas were frequently experienced together then the experience of one tends to cause the experience of the other 1 42 In this sense the history of an organism s experience determines which thoughts the organism has and how these thoughts unfold 44 But such an association does not guarantee that the connection is meaningful or rational For example because of the association between the terms cold and Idaho the thought this coffee shop is cold might lead to the thought Russia should annex Idaho 44 One form of associationism is imagism It states that thinking involves entertaining a sequence of images where earlier images conjure up later images based on the laws of association 22 One problem with this view is that we can think about things that we cannot imagine This is especially relevant when the thought involves very complex objects or infinities which is common for example in mathematical thought 22 One criticism directed at associationism in general is that its claim is too far reaching There is wide agreement that associative processes as studied by associationists play some role in how thought unfolds But the claim that this mechanism is sufficient to understand all thought or all mental processes is usually not accepted 43 44 Behaviorism edit According to behaviorism thinking consists in behavioral dispositions to engage in certain publicly observable behavior as a reaction to particular external stimuli 45 46 47 On this view having a particular thought is the same as having a disposition to behave in a certain way This view is often motivated by empirical considerations it is very difficult to study thinking as a private mental process but it is much easier to study how organisms react to a certain situation with a given behavior 47 In this sense the capacity to solve problems not through existing habits but through creative new approaches is particularly relevant 48 The term behaviorism is also sometimes used in a slightly different sense when applied to thinking to refer to a specific form of inner speech theory 49 This view focuses on the idea that the relevant inner speech is a derivative form of regular outward speech 1 This sense overlaps with how behaviorism is understood more commonly in philosophy of mind since these inner speech acts are not observed by the researcher but merely inferred from the subject s intelligent behavior 49 This remains true to the general behaviorist principle that behavioral evidence is required for any psychological hypothesis 47 One problem for behaviorism is that the same entity often behaves differently despite being in the same situation as before 50 51 This problem consists in the fact that individual thoughts or mental states usually do not correspond to one particular behavior So thinking that the pie is tasty does not automatically lead to eating the pie since various other mental states may still inhibit this behavior for example the belief that it would be impolite to do so or that the pie is poisoned 52 53 Computationalism edit Computationalist theories of thinking often found in the cognitive sciences understand thinking as a form of information processing 41 54 45 These views developed with the rise of computers in the second part of the 20th century when various theorists saw thinking in analogy to computer operations 54 On such views the information may be encoded differently in the brain but in principle the same operations take place there as well corresponding to the storage transmission and processing of information 1 13 But while this analogy has some intuitive attraction theorists have struggled to give a more explicit explanation of what computation is A further problem consists in explaining the sense in which thinking is a form of computing 45 The traditionally dominant view defines computation in terms of Turing machines though contemporary accounts often focus on neural networks for their analogies 41 A Turing machine is capable of executing any algorithm based on a few very basic principles such as reading a symbol from a cell writing a symbol to a cell and executing instructions based on the symbols read 41 This way it is possible to perform deductive reasoning following the inference rules of formal logic as well as simulating many other functions of the mind such as language processing decision making and motor control 54 45 But computationalism does not only claim that thinking is in some sense similar to computation Instead it is claimed that thinking just is a form of computation or that the mind is a Turing machine 45 Computationalist theories of thought are sometimes divided into functionalist and representationalist approaches 45 Functionalist approaches define mental states through their causal roles but allow both external and internal events in their causal network 55 56 57 Thought may be seen as a form of program that can be executed in the same way by many different systems including humans animals and even robots According to one such view whether something is a thought only depends on its role in producing further internal states and verbal outputs 58 55 Representationalism on the other hand focuses on the representational features of mental states and defines thoughts as sequences of intentional mental states 59 45 In this sense computationalism is often combined with the language of thought hypothesis by interpreting these sequences as symbols whose order is governed by syntactic rules 45 32 Various arguments have been raised against computationalism In one sense it seems trivial since almost any physical system can be described as executing computations and therefore as thinking For example it has been argued that the molecular movements in a regular wall can be understood as computing an algorithm since they are isomorphic to the formal structure of the program in question under the right interpretation 45 This would lead to the implausible conclusion that the wall is thinking Another objection focuses on the idea that computationalism captures only some aspects of thought but is unable to account for other crucial aspects of human cognition 45 54 Types of thinking editA great variety of types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature A common approach divides them into those forms that aim at the creation of theoretical knowledge and those that aim at producing actions or correct decisions 22 but there is no universally accepted taxonomy summarizing all these types Entertaining judging and reasoning edit Thinking is often identified with the act of judging A judgment is a mental operation in which a proposition is evoked and then either affirmed or denied 6 60 It involves deciding what to believe and aims at determining whether the judged proposition is true or false 61 62 Various theories of judgment have been proposed The traditionally dominant approach is the combination theory It states that judgments consist in the combination of concepts 63 On this view to judge that all men are mortal is to combine the concepts man and mortal The same concepts can be combined in different ways corresponding to different forms of judgment for example as some men are mortal or no man is mortal 64 Other theories of judgment focus more on the relation between the judged proposition and reality According to Franz Brentano a judgment is either a belief or a disbelief in the existence of some entity 63 65 In this sense there are only two fundamental forms of judgment A exists and A does not exist When applied to the sentence all men are mortal the entity in question is immortal men of whom it is said that they do not exist 63 65 Important for Brentano is the distinction between the mere representation of the content of the judgment and the affirmation or the denial of the content 63 65 The mere representation of a proposition is often referred to as entertaining a proposition This is the case for example when one considers a proposition but has not yet made up one s mind about whether it is true or false 63 65 The term thinking can refer both to judging and to mere entertaining This difference is often explicit in the way the thought is expressed thinking that usually involves a judgment whereas thinking about refers to the neutral representation of a proposition without an accompanying belief In this case the proposition is merely entertained but not yet judged 19 Some forms of thinking may involve the representation of objects without any propositions as when someone is thinking about their grandmother 6 Reasoning is one of the most paradigmatic forms of thinking It is the process of drawing conclusions from premises or evidence Types of reasoning can be divided into deductive and non deductive reasoning Deductive reasoning is governed by certain rules of inference which guarantee the truth of the conclusion if the premises are true 1 66 For example given the premises all men are mortal and Socrates is a man it follows deductively that Socrates is mortal Non deductive reasoning also referred to as defeasible reasoning or non monotonic reasoning is still rationally compelling but the truth of the conclusion is not ensured by the truth of the premises 67 Induction is one form of non deductive reasoning for example when one concludes that the sun will rise tomorrow based on one s experiences of all the previous days Other forms of non deductive reasoning include the inference to the best explanation and analogical reasoning 68 Fallacies are faulty forms of thinking that go against the norms of correct reasoning Formal fallacies concern faulty inferences found in deductive reasoning 69 70 Denying the antecedent is one type of formal fallacy for example If Othello is a bachelor then he is male Othello is not a bachelor Therefore Othello is not male 1 71 Informal fallacies on the other hand apply to all types of reasoning The source of their flaw is to be found in the content or the context of the argument 72 69 73 This is often caused by ambiguous or vague expressions in natural language as in Feathers are light What is light cannot be dark Therefore feathers cannot be dark 74 An important aspect of fallacies is that they seem to be rationally compelling on the first look and thereby seduce people into accepting and committing them 69 Whether an act of reasoning constitutes a fallacy does not depend on whether the premises are true or false but on their relation to the conclusion and in some cases on the context 1 Concept formation edit Concepts are general notions that constitute the fundamental building blocks of thought 75 76 They are rules that govern how objects are sorted into different classes 77 78 A person can only think about a proposition if they possess the concepts involved in this proposition 79 For example the proposition wombats are animals involves the concepts wombat and animal Someone who does not possess the concept wombat may still be able to read the sentence but cannot entertain the corresponding proposition Concept formation is a form of thinking in which new concepts are acquired 78 It involves becoming familiar with the characteristic features shared by all instances of the corresponding type of entity and developing the ability to identify positive and negative cases This process usually corresponds to learning the meaning of the word associated with the type in question 77 78 There are various theories concerning how concepts and concept possession are to be understood 75 According to one popular view concepts are to be understood in terms of abilities On this view two central aspects characterize concept possession the ability to discriminate between positive and negative cases and the ability to draw inferences from this concept to related concepts Concept formation corresponds to acquiring these abilities 79 80 75 It has been suggested that animals are also able to learn concepts to some extent due to their ability to discriminate between different types of situations and to adjust their behavior accordingly 77 81 Problem solving edit In the case of problem solving thinking aims at reaching a predefined goal by overcoming certain obstacles 7 1 78 This process often involves two different forms of thinking On the one hand divergent thinking aims at coming up with as many alternative solutions as possible On the other hand convergent thinking tries to narrow down the range of alternatives to the most promising candidates 1 82 83 Some researchers identify various steps in the process of problem solving These steps include recognizing the problem trying to understand its nature identifying general criteria the solution should meet deciding how these criteria should be prioritized monitoring the progress and evaluating the results 1 An important distinction concerns the type of problem that is faced For well structured problems it is easy to determine which steps need to be taken to solve them but executing these steps may still be difficult 1 84 For ill structured problems on the other hand it is not clear what steps need to be taken i e there is no clear formula that would lead to success if followed correctly In this case the solution may sometimes come in a flash of insight in which the problem is suddenly seen in a new light 1 84 Another way to categorize different forms of problem solving is by distinguishing between algorithms and heuristics 78 An algorithm is a formal procedure in which each step is clearly defined It guarantees success if applied correctly 1 78 The long multiplication usually taught in school is an example of an algorithm for solving the problem of multiplying big numbers Heuristics on the other hand are informal procedures They are rough rules of thumb that tend to bring the thinker closer to the solution but success is not guaranteed in every case even if followed correctly 1 78 Examples of heuristics are working forward and working backward These approaches involve planning one step at a time either starting at the beginning and moving forward or starting at the end and moving backward So when planning a trip one could plan the different stages of the trip from origin to destiny in the chronological order of how the trip will be realized or in the reverse order 1 Obstacles to problem solving can arise from the thinker s failure to take certain possibilities into account by fixating on one specific course of action 1 There are important differences between how novices and experts solve problems For example experts tend to allocate more time for conceptualizing the problem and work with more complex representations whereas novices tend to devote more time to executing putative solutions 1 Deliberation and decision edit Deliberation is an important form of practical thinking It aims at formulating possible courses of action and assessing their value by considering the reasons for and against them 85 This involves foresight to anticipate what might happen Based on this foresight different courses of action can be formulated in order to influence what will happen Decisions are an important part of deliberation They are about comparing alternative courses of action and choosing the most favorable one 66 22 Decision theory is a formal model of how ideal rational agents would make decisions 78 86 87 It is based on the idea that they should always choose the alternative with the highest expected value Each alternative can lead to various possible outcomes each of which has a different value The expected value of an alternative consists in the sum of the values of each outcome associated with it multiplied by the probability that this outcome occurs 86 87 According to decision theory a decision is rational if the agent chooses the alternative associated with the highest expected value as assessed from the agent s own perspective 86 87 Various theorists emphasize the practical nature of thought i e that thinking is usually guided by some kind of task it aims to solve In this sense thinking has been compared to trial and error seen in animal behavior when faced with a new problem On this view the important difference is that this process happens inwardly as a form of simulation 1 This process is often much more efficient since once the solution is found in thought only the behavior corresponding to the found solution has to be outwardly carried out and not all the others 1 Episodic memory and imagination edit When thinking is understood in a wide sense it includes both episodic memory and imagination 20 In episodic memory events one experienced in the past are relived 88 89 90 It is a form of mental time travel in which the past experience is re experienced 90 91 But this does not constitute an exact copy of the original experience since the episodic memory involves additional aspects and information not present in the original experience This includes both a feeling of familiarity and chronological information about the past event in relation to the present 88 90 Memory aims at representing how things actually were in the past in contrast to imagination which presents objects without aiming to show how things actually are or were 92 Because of this missing link to actuality more freedom is involved in most forms of imagination its contents can be freely varied changed and recombined to create new arrangements never experienced before 93 Episodic memory and imagination have in common with other forms of thought that they can arise internally without any stimulation of the sensory organs 94 93 But they are still closer to sensation than more abstract forms of thought since they present sensory contents that could at least in principle also be perceived Unconscious thought edit Conscious thought is the paradigmatic form of thinking and is often the focus of the corresponding research But it has been argued that some forms of thought also happen on the unconscious level 9 10 4 5 Unconscious thought is thought that happens in the background without being experienced It is therefore not observed directly Instead its existence is usually inferred by other means 10 For example when someone is faced with an important decision or a difficult problem they may not be able to solve it straight away But then at a later time the solution may suddenly flash before them even though no conscious steps of thinking were taken towards this solution in the meantime 10 9 In such cases the cognitive labor needed to arrive at a solution is often explained in terms of unconscious thoughts The central idea is that a cognitive transition happened and we need to posit unconscious thoughts to be able to explain how it happened 10 9 It has been argued that conscious and unconscious thoughts differ not just concerning their relation to experience but also concerning their capacities According to unconscious thought theorists for example conscious thought excels at simple problems with few variables but is outperformed by unconscious thought when complex problems with many variables are involved 10 9 This is sometimes explained through the claim that the number of items one can consciously think about at the same time is rather limited whereas unconscious thought lacks such limitations 10 But other researchers have rejected the claim that unconscious thought is often superior to conscious thought 95 96 Other suggestions for the difference between the two forms of thinking include that conscious thought tends to follow formal logical laws while unconscious thought relies more on associative processing and that only conscious thinking is conceptually articulated and happens through the medium of language 10 97 In various disciplines editPhenomenology edit Phenomenology is the science of the structure and contents of experience 98 99 The term cognitive phenomenology refers to the experiential character of thinking or what it feels like to think 4 100 101 6 102 Some theorists claim that there is no distinctive cognitive phenomenology On such a view the experience of thinking is just one form of sensory experience 102 103 104 According to one version thinking just involves hearing a voice internally 103 According to another there is no experience of thinking apart from the indirect effects thinking has on sensory experience 4 100 A weaker version of such an approach allows that thinking may have a distinct phenomenology but contends that thinking still depends on sensory experience because it cannot occur on its own On this view sensory contents constitute the foundation from which thinking may arise 4 103 104 An often cited thought experiment in favor of the existence of a distinctive cognitive phenomenology involves two persons listening to a radio broadcast in French one who understands French and the other who does not 4 100 101 105 The idea behind this example is that both listeners hear the same sounds and therefore have the same non cognitive experience In order to explain the difference a distinctive cognitive phenomenology has to be posited only the experience of the first person has this additional cognitive character since it is accompanied by a thought that corresponds to the meaning of what is said 4 100 101 106 Other arguments for the experience of thinking focus on the direct introspective access to thinking or on the thinker s knowledge of their own thoughts 4 100 101 Phenomenologists are also concerned with the characteristic features of the experience of thinking Making a judgment is one of the prototypical forms of cognitive phenomenology 101 107 It involves epistemic agency in which a proposition is entertained evidence for and against it is considered and based on this reasoning the proposition is either affirmed or rejected 101 It is sometimes argued that the experience of truth is central to thinking i e that thinking aims at representing how the world is 6 100 It shares this feature with perception but differs from it in the way how it represents the world without the use of sensory contents 6 One of the characteristic features often ascribed to thinking and judging is that they are predicative experiences in contrast to the pre predicative experience found in immediate perception 108 109 On such a view various aspects of perceptual experience resemble judgments without being judgments in the strict sense 4 110 111 For example the perceptual experience of the front of a house brings with it various expectations about aspects of the house not directly seen like the size and shape of its other sides This process is sometimes referred to as apperception 4 110 These expectations resemble judgments and can be wrong This would be the case when it turns out upon walking around the house that it is no house at all but only a front facade of a house with nothing behind it In this case the perceptual expectations are frustrated and the perceiver is surprised 4 There is disagreement as to whether these pre predicative aspects of regular perception should be understood as a form of cognitive phenomenology involving thinking 4 This issue is also important for understanding the relation between thought and language The reason for this is that the pre predicative expectations do not depend on language which is sometimes taken as an example for non linguistic thought 4 Various theorists have argued that pre predicative experience is more basic or fundamental since predicative experience is in some sense built on top of it and therefore depends on it 111 108 109 Another way how phenomenologists have tried to distinguish the experience of thinking from other types of experiences is in relation to empty intentions in contrast to intuitive intentions 112 113 In this context intention means that some kind of object is experienced In intuitive intentions the object is presented through sensory contents Empty intentions on the other hand present their object in a more abstract manner without the help of sensory contents 112 4 113 So when perceiving a sunset it is presented through sensory contents The same sunset can also be presented non intuitively when merely thinking about it without the help of sensory contents 113 In these cases the same properties are ascribed to objects The difference between these modes of presentation concerns not what properties are ascribed to the presented object but how the object is presented 112 Because of this commonality it is possible for representations belonging to different modes to overlap or to diverge 6 For example when searching one s glasses one may think to oneself that one left them on the kitchen table This empty intention of the glasses lying on the kitchen table are then intuitively fulfilled when one sees them lying there upon arriving in the kitchen This way a perception can confirm or refute a thought depending on whether the empty intuitions are later fulfilled or not 6 113 Metaphysics edit The mind body problem concerns the explanation of the relationship that exists between minds or mental processes and bodily states or processes 114 The main aim of philosophers working in this area is to determine the nature of the mind and mental states processes and how or even if minds are affected by and can affect the body Human perceptual experiences depend on stimuli which arrive at one s various sensory organs from the external world and these stimuli cause changes in one s mental state ultimately causing one to feel a sensation which may be pleasant or unpleasant Someone s desire for a slice of pizza for example will tend to cause that person to move his or her body in a specific manner and in a specific direction to obtain what he or she wants The question then is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to arise out of a lump of gray matter endowed with nothing but electrochemical properties A related problem is to explain how someone s propositional attitudes e g beliefs and desires can cause that individual s neurons to fire and his muscles to contract in exactly the correct manner These comprise some of the puzzles that have confronted epistemologists and philosophers of mind from at least the time of Rene Descartes 115 The above reflects a classical functional description of how we work as cognitive thinking systems However the apparently irresolvable mind body problem is said to be overcome and bypassed by the embodied cognition approach with its roots in the work of Heidegger Piaget Vygotsky Merleau Ponty and the pragmatist John Dewey 116 117 This approach states that the classical approach of separating the mind and analysing its processes is misguided instead we should see that the mind actions of an embodied agent and the environment it perceives and envisions are all parts of a whole which determine each other Therefore functional analysis of the mind alone will always leave us with the mind body problem which cannot be solved 118 Psychology edit Main article Cognitive psychology nbsp Man thinking on a train journeyPsychologists have concentrated on thinking as an intellectual exertion aimed at finding an answer to a question or the solution of a practical problem Cognitive psychology is a branch of psychology that investigates internal mental processes such as problem solving memory and language all of which are used in thinking The school of thought arising from this approach is known as cognitivism which is interested in how people mentally represent information processing It had its foundations in the Gestalt psychology of Max Wertheimer Wolfgang Kohler and Kurt Koffka 119 and in the work of Jean Piaget who provided a theory of stages phases that describes children s cognitive development Cognitive psychologists use psychophysical and experimental approaches to understand diagnose and solve problems concerning themselves with the mental processes which mediate between stimulus and response They study various aspects of thinking including the psychology of reasoning and how people make decisions and choices solve problems as well as engage in creative discovery and imaginative thought Cognitive theory contends that solutions to problems either take the form of algorithms rules that are not necessarily understood but promise a solution or of heuristics rules that are understood but that do not always guarantee solutions Cognitive science differs from cognitive psychology in that algorithms that are intended to simulate human behavior are implemented or implementable on a computer In other instances solutions may be found through insight a sudden awareness of relationships In developmental psychology Jean Piaget was a pioneer in the study of the development of thought from birth to maturity In his theory of cognitive development thought is based on actions on the environment That is Piaget suggests that the environment is understood through assimilations of objects in the available schemes of action and these accommodate to the objects to the extent that the available schemes fall short of the demands As a result of this interplay between assimilation and accommodation thought develops through a sequence of stages that differ qualitatively from each other in mode of representation and complexity of inference and understanding That is thought evolves from being based on perceptions and actions at the sensorimotor stage in the first two years of life to internal representations in early childhood Subsequently representations are gradually organized into logical structures which first operate on the concrete properties of the reality in the stage of concrete operations and then operate on abstract principles that organize concrete properties in the stage of formal operations 120 In recent years the Piagetian conception of thought was integrated with information processing conceptions Thus thought is considered as the result of mechanisms that are responsible for the representation and processing of information In this conception speed of processing cognitive control and working memory are the main functions underlying thought In the neo Piagetian theories of cognitive development the development of thought is considered to come from increasing speed of processing enhanced cognitive control and increasing working memory 121 Positive psychology emphasizes the positive aspects of human psychology as equally important as the focus on mood disorders and other negative symptoms In Character Strengths and Virtues Peterson and Seligman list a series of positive characteristics One person is not expected to have every strength nor are they meant to fully capsulate that characteristic entirely The list encourages positive thought that builds on a person s strengths rather than how to fix their symptoms 122 Psychoanalysis edit Main articles Id ego and super ego and Unconscious mind The id ego and super ego are the three parts of the psychic apparatus defined in Sigmund Freud s structural model of the psyche they are the three theoretical constructs in terms of whose activity and interaction mental life is described According to this model the uncoordinated instinctual trends are encompassed by the id the organized realistic part of the psyche is the ego and the critical moralizing function is the super ego 123 For psychoanalysis the unconscious does not include all that is not conscious rather only what is actively repressed from conscious thought or what the person is averse to knowing consciously In a sense this view places the self in relationship to their unconscious as an adversary warring with itself to keep what is unconscious hidden If a person feels pain all he can think of is alleviating the pain Any of his desires to get rid of pain or enjoy something command the mind what to do For Freud the unconscious was a repository for socially unacceptable ideas wishes or desires traumatic memories and painful emotions put out of mind by the mechanism of psychological repression However the contents did not necessarily have to be solely negative In the psychoanalytic view the unconscious is a force that can only be recognized by its effects it expresses itself in the symptom 124 The collective unconscious sometimes known as collective subconscious is a term of analytical psychology coined by Carl Jung It is a part of the unconscious mind shared by a society a people or all humanity in an interconnected system that is the product of all common experiences and contains such concepts as science religion and morality While Freud did not distinguish between individual psychology and collective psychology Jung distinguished the collective unconscious from the personal subconscious particular to each human being The collective unconscious is also known as a reservoir of the experiences of our species 125 In the Definitions chapter of Jung s seminal work Psychological Types under the definition of collective Jung references representations collectives a term coined by Lucien Levy Bruhl in his 1910 book How Natives Think Jung says this is what he describes as the collective unconscious Freud on the other hand did not accept the idea of a collective unconscious Related concepts and theories editLaws of thought edit Traditionally the term laws of thought refers to three fundamental laws of logic the law of contradiction the law of excluded middle and the principle of identity 126 127 These laws by themselves are not sufficient as axioms of logic but they can be seen as important precursors to the modern axiomatization of logic The law of contradiction states that for any proposition it is impossible that both it and its negation are true p p displaystyle lnot p land lnot p nbsp According to the law of excluded middle for any proposition either it or its opposite is true p p displaystyle p lor lnot p nbsp The principle of identity asserts that any object is identical to itself x x x displaystyle forall x x x nbsp 126 127 There are different conceptions of how the laws of thought are to be understood The interpretations most relevant to thinking are to understand them as prescriptive laws of how one should think or as formal laws of propositions that are true only because of their form and independent of their content or context 127 Metaphysical interpretations on the other hand see them as expressing the nature of being as such 127 While there is a very wide acceptance of these three laws among logicians they are not universally accepted 126 127 Aristotle for example held that there are some cases in which the law of excluded middle is false This concerns primarily uncertain future events On his view it is currently not either true or false that there will be a naval battle tomorrow 126 127 Modern intuitionist logic also rejects the law of excluded middle This rejection is based on the idea that mathematical truth depends on verification through a proof The law fails for cases where no such proof is possible which exist in every sufficiently strong formal system according to Godel s incompleteness theorems 128 129 126 127 Dialetheists on the other hand reject the law of contradiction by holding that some propositions are both true and false One motivation of this position is to avoid certain paradoxes in classical logic and set theory like the liar s paradox and Russell s paradox One of its problems is to find a formulation that circumvents the principle of explosion i e that anything follows from a contradiction 130 131 132 Some formulations of the laws of thought include a fourth law the principle of sufficient reason 127 It states that everything has a sufficient reason ground or cause It is closely connected to the idea that everything is intelligible or can be explained in reference to its sufficient reason 133 134 According to this idea there should always be a full explanation at least in principle to questions like why the sky is blue or why World War II happened One problem for including this principle among the laws of thought is that it is a metaphysical principle unlike the other three laws which pertain primarily to logic 134 127 133 Counterfactual thinking edit Counterfactual thinking involves mental representations of non actual situations and events i e of what is contrary to the facts 135 136 It is usually conditional it aims at assessing what would be the case if a certain condition had obtained 137 138 In this sense it tries to answer What if questions For example thinking after an accident that one would be dead if one had not used the seatbelt is a form of counterfactual thinking it assumes contrary to the facts that one had not used the seatbelt and tries to assess the result of this state of affairs 136 In this sense counterfactual thinking is normally counterfactual only to a small degree since just a few facts are changed like concerning the seatbelt while most other facts are kept in place like that one was driving one s gender the laws of physics etc 135 When understood in the widest sense there are forms of counterfactual thinking that do not involve anything contrary to the facts at all 138 This is the case for example when one tries to anticipate what might happen in the future if an uncertain event occurs and this event actually occurs later and brings with it the anticipated consequences 137 In this wider sense the term subjunctive conditional is sometimes used instead of counterfactual conditional 138 But the paradigmatic cases of counterfactual thinking involve alternatives to past events 135 Counterfactual thinking plays an important role since we evaluate the world around us not only by what actually happened but also by what could have happened 136 Humans have a greater tendency to engage in counterfactual thinking after something bad happened because of some kind of action the agent performed 137 135 In this sense many regrets are associated with counterfactual thinking in which the agent contemplates how a better outcome could have been obtained if only they had acted differently 136 These cases are known as upward counterfactuals in contrast to downward counterfactuals in which the counterfactual scenario is worse than actuality 137 135 Upward counterfactual thinking is usually experienced as unpleasant since it presents the actual circumstances in a bad light This contrasts with the positive emotions associated with downward counterfactual thinking 136 But both forms are important since it is possible to learn from them and to adjust one s behavior accordingly to get better results in the future 136 135 Thought experiments edit Thought experiments involve thinking about imaginary situations often with the aim of investigating the possible consequences of a change to the actual sequence of events 139 140 141 It is a controversial issue to what extent thought experiments should be understood as actual experiments 142 143 144 They are experiments in the sense that a certain situation is set up and one tries to learn from this situation by understanding what follows from it 145 142 They differ from regular experiments in that imagination is used to set up the situation and counterfactual reasoning is employed to evaluate what follows from it instead of setting it up physically and observing the consequences through perception 146 140 142 141 Counterfactual thinking therefore plays a central role in thought experiments 147 The Chinese room argument is a famous thought experiment proposed by John Searle 148 149 It involves a person sitting inside a closed off room tasked with responding to messages written in Chinese This person does not know Chinese but has a giant rule book that specifies exactly how to reply to any possible message similar to how a computer would react to messages The core idea of this thought experiment is that neither the person nor the computer understands Chinese This way Searle aims to show that computers lack a mind capable of deeper forms of understanding despite acting intelligently 148 149 Thought experiments are employed for various purposes for example for entertainment education or as arguments for or against theories Most discussions focus on their use as arguments This use is found in fields like philosophy the natural sciences and history 140 144 143 142 It is controversial since there is a lot of disagreement concerning the epistemic status of thought experiments i e how reliable they are as evidence supporting or refuting a theory 140 144 143 142 Central to the rejection of this usage is the fact that they pretend to be a source of knowledge without the need to leave one s armchair in search of any new empirical data Defenders of thought experiments usually contend that the intuitions underlying and guiding the thought experiments are at least in some cases reliable 140 142 But thought experiments can also fail if they are not properly supported by intuitions or if they go beyond what the intuitions support 140 141 In the latter sense sometimes counter thought experiments are proposed that modify the original scenario in slight ways in order to show that initial intuitions cannot survive this change 140 Various taxonomies of thought experiments have been suggested They can be distinguished for example by whether they are successful or not by the discipline that uses them by their role in a theory or by whether they accept or modify the actual laws of physics 141 140 Critical thinking edit Critical thinking is a form of thinking that is reasonable reflective and focused on determining what to believe or how to act 150 151 152 It holds itself to various standards like clarity and rationality In this sense it involves not just cognitive processes trying to solve the issue at hand but at the same time meta cognitive processes ensuring that it lives up to its own standards 151 This includes assessing both that the reasoning itself is sound and that the evidence it rests on is reliable 151 This means that logic plays an important role in critical thinking It concerns not just formal logic but also informal logic specifically to avoid various informal fallacies due to vague or ambiguous expressions in natural language 151 74 73 No generally accepted standard definition of critical thinking exists but there is significant overlap between the proposed definitions in their characterization of critical thinking as careful and goal directed 152 According to some versions only the thinker s own observations and experiments are accepted as evidence in critical thinking Some restrict it to the formation of judgments but exclude action as its goal 152 A concrete everyday example of critical thinking due to John Dewey involves observing foam bubbles moving in a direction that is contrary to one s initial expectations The critical thinker tries to come up with various possible explanations of this behavior and then slightly modifies the original situation in order to determine which one is the right explanation 152 153 But not all forms of cognitively valuable processes involve critical thinking Arriving at the correct solution to a problem by blindly following the steps of an algorithm does not qualify as critical thinking The same is true if the solution is presented to the thinker in a sudden flash of insight and accepted straight away 152 Critical thinking plays an important role in education fostering the student s ability to think critically is often seen as an important educational goal 152 151 154 In this sense it is important to convey not just a set of true beliefs to the student but also the ability to draw one s own conclusions and to question pre existing beliefs 154 The abilities and dispositions learned this way may profit not just the individual but also society at large 151 Critics of the emphasis on critical thinking in education have argued that there is no universal form of correct thinking Instead they contend that different subject matters rely on different standards and education should focus on imparting these subject specific skills instead of trying to teach universal methods of thinking 152 155 Other objections are based on the idea that critical thinking and the attitude underlying it involve various unjustified biases like egocentrism distanced objectivity indifference and an overemphasis of the theoretical in contrast to the practical 152 Positive thinking edit Positive thinking is an important topic in positive psychology 156 It involves focusing one s attention on the positive aspects of one s situation and thereby withdrawing one s attention from its negative sides 156 This is usually seen as a global outlook that applies especially to thinking but includes other mental processes like feeling as well 156 In this sense it is closely related to optimism It includes expecting positive things to happen in the future 157 156 This positive outlook makes it more likely for people to seek to attain new goals 156 It also increases the probability of continuing to strive towards pre existing goals that seem difficult to reach instead of just giving up 157 156 The effects of positive thinking are not yet thoroughly researched but some studies suggest that there is a correlation between positive thinking and well being 156 For example students and pregnant women with a positive outlook tend to be better at dealing with stressful situations 157 156 This is sometimes explained by pointing out that stress is not inherent in stressful situations but depends on the agent s interpretation of the situation Reduced stress may therefore be found in positive thinkers because they tend to see such situations in a more positive light 156 But the effects also include the practical domain in that positive thinkers tend to employ healthier coping strategies when faced with difficult situations 156 This effects for example the time needed to fully recover from surgeries and the tendency to resume physical exercise afterward 157 But it has been argued that whether positive thinking actually leads to positive outcomes depends on various other factors Without these factors it may lead to negative results For example the tendency of optimists to keep striving in difficult situations can backfire if the course of events is outside the agent s control 157 Another danger associated with positive thinking is that it may remain only on the level of unrealistic fantasies and thereby fail to make a positive practical contribution to the agent s life 158 Pessimism on the other hand may have positive effects since it can mitigate disappointments by anticipating failures 157 159 Positive thinking is a recurrent topic in the self help literature 160 Here often the claim is made that one can significantly improve one s life by trying to think positively even if this means fostering beliefs that are contrary to evidence 161 Such claims and the effectiveness of the suggested methods are controversial and have been criticized due to their lack of scientific evidence 161 162 In the New Thought movement positive thinking figures in the law of attraction the pseudoscientific claim that positive thoughts can directly influence the external world by attracting positive outcomes 163 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Psychology portalAnimal cognition Freethought Outline of human intelligence topic tree presenting the traits capacities models and research fields of human intelligence and more Outline of thought topic tree that identifies many types of thoughts types of thinking aspects of thought related fields and more RethinkingReferences edit a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x Thought Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 14 October 2021 Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary 2nd ed 2001 Published by Random House Inc ISBN 978 0 375 42599 8 p 1975 Webster s II New College Dictionary Webster Staff Webster Houghton Mifflin Company 2nd ed illustrated revised Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt 1999 ISBN 978 0 395 96214 5 p 1147 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Breyer Thiemo Gutland Christopher 2015 Introduction Phenomenology of Thinking Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences pp 1 24 a b c Nida rumelin Martine 2010 Thinking Without Language A Phenomenological Argument for Its Possibility and Existence Grazer Philosophische Studien 81 1 55 75 doi 10 1163 9789042030190 005 a b c d e f g h i j Crowell Steven 2015 What Is It to Think Phenomenology of Thinking Routledge pp 189 212 doi 10 4324 9781315697734 14 ISBN 978 1 315 69773 4 a b Mole Christopher 2021 Attention 2 3 Coherence Theories The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 21 October 2021 Katsafanas Paul 2015 Nietzsche on the Nature of the Unconscious Inquiry An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 58 3 327 352 doi 10 1080 0020174X 2013 855658 S2CID 38776513 a b c d e Garrison Katie E Handley Ian M 2017 Not Merely Experiential Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational Frontiers in Psychology 8 1096 doi 10 3389 fpsyg 2017 01096 ISSN 1664 1078 PMC 5498519 PMID 28729844 a b c d e f g h Dijksterhuis Ap Nordgren Loran F 1 June 2006 A Theory of Unconscious Thought Perspectives on Psychological Science 1 2 95 109 doi 10 1111 j 1745 6916 2006 00007 x ISSN 1745 6916 PMID 26151465 S2CID 7875280 Skirry Justin Descartes Rene Mind Body Distinction Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 17 October 2021 Smith Kurt 2021 Descartes Theory of Ideas 1 Ideas Understood as Modes of Thinking The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 21 October 2021 a b Baum Eric B 2004 1 Introduction What Is Thought Cambridge MA Bradford Book MIT Press Block Ned 1981 Psychologism and Behaviorism Philosophical Review 90 1 5 43 doi 10 2307 2184371 JSTOR 2184371 Romer Paul M May 2000 Thinking and Feeling American Economic Review 90 2 439 443 doi 10 1257 aer 90 2 439 ISSN 0002 8282 Planalp Sally Fitness Julie 1 December 1999 Thinking Feeling about Social and Personal Relationships Journal of Social and Personal Relationships 16 6 731 750 doi 10 1177 0265407599166004 ISSN 0265 4075 S2CID 145750153 Phelan Mark Arico Adam Nichols Shaun 2013 Thinking Things and Feeling Things On an Alleged Discontinuity in Folk Metaphysics of Mind Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 4 703 725 doi 10 1007 s11097 012 9278 7 S2CID 15856600 The American Heritage Dictionary entry thought www ahdictionary com Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Retrieved 23 October 2021 a b Mandelbaum Eric 2014 Thinking is Believing Inquiry An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57 1 55 96 doi 10 1080 0020174X 2014 858417 S2CID 52968342 a b The American Heritage Dictionary entry think www ahdictionary com Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Retrieved 23 October 2021 Harper Douglas Etymology of Thought Online Etymology Dictionary Retrieved 2009 05 22 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Borchert Donald 2006 Thinking Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan a b c d Woolf Raphael 1 January 2013 Plato and the Norms of Thought Mind 122 485 171 216 doi 10 1093 mind fzt012 ISSN 0026 4423 a b c Langland Hassan Peter Vicente Agustin 2018 Introduction Inner Speech New Voices Oxford Oxford University Press Kraut Richard 2017 Plato The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 24 April 2021 Brickhouse Thomas Smith Nicholas D Plato 6b The Theory of Forms Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 24 April 2021 Nehamas Alexander 1975 Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World American Philosophical Quarterly 12 2 105 117 ISSN 0003 0481 JSTOR 20009565 a b Sellars Wilfrid 1949 Aristotelian Philosophies of Mind Philosophy for The Future The Quest of Modern Materialism Klima Gyula 2017 The Medieval Problem of Universals 1 Introduction The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 21 October 2021 a b c d Harman Gilbert 1973 4 Thought and meaning Thought Princeton University Press Roessler Johannes 2016 Thinking Inner Speech and Self Awareness Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7 3 541 557 doi 10 1007 s13164 015 0267 y S2CID 15028459 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Rescorla Michael 2019 The Language of Thought Hypothesis The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 October 2021 a b Bermudez Jose Luis 2003 Thinking Without Words Oxford University Press USA Lohmar Dieter 2012 Zahavi Dan ed Language and non linguistic thinking The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199594900 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 959490 0 Andrews Kristin Monso Susana 2021 Animal Cognition 3 4 Thought The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 25 October 2021 Premack David 28 August 2007 Human and animal cognition Continuity and discontinuity Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104 35 13861 13867 Bibcode 2007PNAS 10413861P doi 10 1073 pnas 0706147104 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 1955772 PMID 17717081 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Katz Matthew Language of Thought Hypothesis Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 27 October 2021 a b c d e Aydede Murat Oxford Bibliographies Language of Thought Retrieved 27 October 2021 Fodor Jerry A 2008 Lot 2 The Language of Thought Revisited Oxford University Press a b c Borchert Donald 2006 Language of thought Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan a b c d Milkowski Marcin Computational Theory of Mind Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 21 October 2021 a b Doorey Marie Conditioning The Gale Encyclopedia of Science a b Van der Veldt J H Associationism New Catholic Encyclopedia a b c d e Mandelbaum Eric 2020 Associationist Theories of Thought The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 23 October 2021 a b c d e f g h i j Rescorla Michael 2020 The Computational Theory of Mind The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 22 October 2021 Lazzeri Filipe 2019 08 16 O que e Behaviorismo sobre a mente Principia in Portuguese 23 2 249 277 doi 10 5007 1808 1711 2019v23n2p249 ISSN 1808 1711 S2CID 212888121 a b c Graham George 2019 Behaviorism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 31 May 2021 Audet Jean Nicolas Lefebvre Louis 18 February 2017 What s flexible in behavioral flexibility Behavioral Ecology 28 4 943 947 doi 10 1093 beheco arx007 ISSN 1045 2249 a b Reese Hayne W 2000 Thinking as the Behaviorist Views It Behavioral Development Bulletin 9 1 10 12 doi 10 1037 h0100531 Mele Alfred R 2003 Introduction Motivation and Agency Oxford University Press Mele Alfred R 1995 Motivation Essentially Motivation Constituting Attitudes Philosophical Review 104 3 387 423 doi 10 2307 2185634 JSTOR 2185634 Schwitzgebel Eric 2019 Belief The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 15 November 2019 Retrieved 22 June 2020 Borchert Donald 2006 Belief Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan Archived from the original on 12 January 2021 Retrieved 2 April 2021 a b c d Philosophy of mind The computational representational theory of thought CRTT Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 21 October 2021 a b Polger Thomas W Functionalism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 31 May 2021 Gulick Robert Van 2009 Beckermann Ansgar McLaughlin Brian P Walter Sven eds Functionalism The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199262618 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 926261 8 Honderich Ted 2005 Mind The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press Levin Janet 2021 Functionalism 2 2 Thinking Machines and the Turing Test The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 22 October 2021 Pitt David 2020 Mental Representation 1 The Representational Theory of Mind The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 22 October 2021 Schmidt R W Judgment New Catholic Encyclopedia Sgarbi Marco 2006 Theories of Judgment Historical and Theoretical Perspectives Quaestio 6 1 589 592 doi 10 1484 J QUAESTIO 2 302491 Robins E P 1898 Modern Theories of Judgment Philosophical Review 7 6 583 603 doi 10 2307 2176171 JSTOR 2176171 a b c d e Rojszczak Artur Smith Barry 2003 Theories of Judgment The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870 1945 Cambridge University Press 157 173 doi 10 1017 CHOL9780521591041 013 ISBN 978 0521591041 Hanna Robert 2018 Kant s Theory of Judgment The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 24 October 2021 a b c d Brandl Johannes L Textor Mark 2020 Brentano s Theory of Judgement The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 24 October 2021 a b Vinacke W Edgar Thought International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences Pollock John L 1987 Defeasible Reasoning Cognitive Science 11 4 481 518 doi 10 1207 s15516709cog1104 4 Koons Robert 2021 Defeasible Reasoning The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 16 October 2021 a b c Hansen Hans 2020 Fallacies The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 March 2021 Vleet Van Jacob E 2010 Introduction Informal Logical Fallacies A Brief Guide Upa Stone Mark A 2012 Denying the Antecedent Its Effective Use in Argumentation Informal Logic 32 3 327 356 doi 10 22329 il v32i3 3681 Dowden Bradley Fallacies Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 19 March 2021 a b Walton Douglas N 1987 1 A new model of argument Informal Fallacies Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms John Benjamins a b Engel S Morris 1982 2 The medium of language With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies a b c Margolis Eric Laurence Stephen 2021 Concepts The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 28 September 2021 Philosophy of mind Thoughts and attitudes Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 16 October 2021 a b c Concept formation Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 16 October 2021 a b c d e f g h Kazdin Alan E ed 2000 Thinking An Overview Encyclopedia of Psychology American Psychological Association ISBN 978 1 55798 187 5 a b Fodor Jerry 2004 Having Concepts A Brief Refutation of the Twentieth Century Mind and Language 19 1 29 47 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0017 2004 00245 x Weiskopf Daniel A Bechtel William 2004 Remarks on Fodor on Having Concepts Mind and Language 19 1 48 56 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0017 2004 00246 x Learning theory Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 16 October 2021 Kim Kyung Hee Pierce Robert A 2013 Convergent Versus Divergent Thinking Encyclopedia of Creativity Invention Innovation and Entrepreneurship Springer pp 245 250 doi 10 1007 978 1 4614 3858 8 22 ISBN 978 1 4614 3857 1 Retrieved 24 October 2021 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a website ignored help Razumnikova Olga M 2013 Divergent Versus Convergent Thinking Encyclopedia of Creativity Invention Innovation and Entrepreneurship Springer pp 546 552 doi 10 1007 978 1 4614 3858 8 362 ISBN 978 1 4614 3857 1 Retrieved 24 October 2021 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a website ignored help a b Reed Stephen K 1 December 2016 The Structure of Ill Structured and Well Structured Problems Revisited Educational Psychology Review 28 4 691 716 doi 10 1007 s10648 015 9343 1 ISSN 1573 336X S2CID 146496245 Arpaly N Schroeder T 2012 Deliberation and Acting for Reasons Philosophical Review 121 2 209 239 doi 10 1215 00318108 1539089 a b c Steele Katie Stefansson H Orri 2020 Decision Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 24 October 2021 a b c Buchak Lara 2016 Decision Theory The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy Oxford University Press a b Perrin Denis Michaelian Kourken Sant Anna Andre 2020 The Phenomenology of Remembering Is an Epistemic Feeling Frontiers in Psychology 11 1531 doi 10 3389 fpsyg 2020 01531 ISSN 1664 1078 PMC 7350950 PMID 32719642 Gardiner J M 29 September 2001 Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness a first person approach Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B Biological Sciences 356 1413 1351 1361 doi 10 1098 rstb 2001 0955 ISSN 0962 8436 PMC 1088519 PMID 11571027 a b c Michaelian Kourken Sutton John 2017 Memory 3 Episodicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2 October 2021 Tulving Endel Learning and Memory Episodic Memory Michaelian Kourken Sutton John 2017 Memory 4 Mnemicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2 October 2021 a b Manser A R Encyclopedia of Philosophy Imagination Retrieved 3 October 2021 Russell Bertrand 1915 Sensation and Imagination The Monist 25 1 28 44 doi 10 5840 monist191525136 Abbott Alison 1 January 2015 Unconscious thought not so smart after all Nature 517 7536 537 538 Bibcode 2015Natur 517 537A doi 10 1038 517537a ISSN 1476 4687 PMID 25631423 Mealor Andy David Dienes Zoltan 2012 Conscious and Unconscious Thought in Artificial Grammar Learning Consciousness and Cognition 21 2 865 874 doi 10 1016 j concog 2012 03 001 PMID 22472202 S2CID 40114660 Fowles Christopher 2 January 2019 Nietzsche on conscious and unconscious thought Inquiry 62 1 1 22 doi 10 1080 0020174X 2019 1527537 ISSN 0020 174X S2CID 171812391 Smith David Woodruff 2018 Phenomenology 1 What is Phenomenology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 20 September 2021 Smith Joel Phenomenology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 10 October 2021 a b c d e f Hansen Mette Kristine Cognitive Phenomenology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 17 October 2021 a b c d e f Kriegel Uriah 2015 The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology Phenomenology of Thinking London and New York Routledge pp 25 43 a b Carruthers Peter Veillet Benedicte 2011 The Case Against Cognitive Phenomenology Cognitive Phenomenology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957993 8 a b c Prinz Jesse J 2011 The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1 Cognitive Phenomenology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957993 8 a b Levine Joseph 2011 On the Phenomenology of Thought Cognitive Phenomenology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957993 8 Siewert Charles 2011 Phenomenal Thought Cognitive Phenomenology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957993 8 Pitt David 2004 The Phenomenology of Cognition Or What Is It Like to Think That P Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 1 1 36 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2004 tb00382 x Smith David Woodruff 2011 The Phenomenology of Consciously Thinking Cognitive Phenomenology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957993 8 a b Dastur Francoise Vallier Robert 2017 The Problem of Pre Predicative Experience Husserl Questions of Phenomenology Fordham University Press doi 10 5422 fordham 9780823233731 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 8232 3373 1 S2CID 148619048 a b Staiti Andrea 2018 Zahavi Dan ed Pre Predicative Experience and Life World doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780198755340 013 12 ISBN 978 0 19 875534 0 a b Diaz Emiliano 2020 Transcendental Anticipation A Reconsideration of Husserl s Type and Kant s Schemata Husserl Studies 36 1 1 23 doi 10 1007 s10743 019 09249 3 S2CID 203547989 a b Doyon Maxime 2015 The As Structure of Intentional Experience in Husserl and Heidegger Phenomenology of Thinking Routledge pp 122 139 doi 10 4324 9781315697734 10 ISBN 978 1 315 69773 4 a b c Hopp Walter 2015 Empty Intentions and Phenomenological Character A Defense of Inclusivism Phenomenology of Thinking Routledge pp 50 67 doi 10 4324 9781315697734 6 ISBN 978 1 315 69773 4 a b c d Spear Andrew D Husserl Edmund Intentionality and Intentional Content 2ai Act Character Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 26 October 2021 Kim J 1995 Honderich Ted ed Problems in the Philosophy of Mind Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 866132 0 Companion to Metaphysics By Jaegwon Kim Gary S Rosenkrantz Ernest Sosa Contributor Jaegwon Kim 2nd ed Wiley Blackwell 2009 ISBN 978 1 4051 5298 3 Varela Francisco J Thompson Evan T and Rosch Eleanor 1992 The Embodied Mind Cognitive Science and Human Experience Cambridge MA MIT Press ISBN 0 262 72021 3 Cowart Monica 2004 Embodied Cognition The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy ISSN 2161 0002 Retrieved 27 February 2012 Di Paolo Ezequiel 2009 Shallow and Deep Embodiment Video duration 1 11 38 University of Sussex Retrieved 27 February 2012 Gestalt Theory By Max Wertheimer Hayes Barton Press 1944 ISBN 978 1 59377 695 4 Piaget J 1951 Psychology of Intelligence London Routledge and Kegan Paul Demetriou A 1998 Cognitive development In A Demetriou W Doise K F M van Lieshout Eds Life span developmental psychology pp 179 269 London Wiley Schacter Daniel L 2011 Psychology Second Edition Positive Psychology New York a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link 584 pp Snowden Ruth 2006 Teach Yourself Freud illustrated ed McGraw Hill p 107 ISBN 978 0 07 147274 6 The Cambridge companion to Freud By Jerome Neu Cambridge University Press 1991 p 29 ISBN 978 0 521 37779 9 Jensen Peter S Mrazek David Knapp Penelope K Steinberg Laurence Pfeffer Cynthia Schowalter John amp Shapiro Theodore Dec 1997 Evolution and revolution in child psychiatry ADHD as a disorder of adaptation attention deficit hyperactivity syndrome Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry 36 p 1672 10 July 14 2007 a b c d e Laws of thought Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 28 October 2021 a b c d e f g h i Borchert Donald 2006 Laws of Thought Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan Moschovakis Joan 2021 Intuitionistic Logic 1 Rejection of Tertium Non Datur The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 28 October 2021 McKubre Jordens Maarten Constructive Mathematics 1b Constructivism as Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 28 October 2021 Priest Graham Berto Francesco Weber Zach 2018 Dialetheism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Horn Laurence R 2018 Contradiction The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Weber Zach Dialetheism Oxford Bibliographies Retrieved 28 October 2021 a b principle of sufficient reason Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 28 October 2021 a b Melamed Yitzhak Y Lin Martin 2021 Principle of Sufficient Reason The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 28 October 2021 a b c d e f Roese Neal J 1997 Counterfactual thinking Psychological Bulletin 121 1 133 148 doi 10 1037 0033 2909 121 1 133 PMID 9000895 a b c d e f Kazdin Alan E ed 2000 Counterfactual thought Encyclopedia of Psychology American Psychological Association ISBN 978 1 55798 187 5 a b c d Van Hoeck Nicole Watson Patrick D Barbey Aron K 2015 Cognitive neuroscience of human counterfactual reasoning Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9 420 doi 10 3389 fnhum 2015 00420 ISSN 1662 5161 PMC 4511878 PMID 26257633 a b c Starr William 2021 Counterfactuals 1 1 What are Counterfactuals The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 28 October 2021 The American Heritage Dictionary entry thought experiment www ahdictionary com Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Retrieved 30 October 2021 a b c d e f g h Brown James Robert Fehige Yiftach 2019 Thought Experiments The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 29 October 2021 a b c d Goffi Jean Yves Roux Sophie 2011 On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts Brill 165 191 doi 10 1163 ej 9789004201767 i 233 35 ISBN 978 9004201774 S2CID 260640180 a b c d e f Sorensen Roy A 1999 Are Thought Experiments Experiments Thought Experiments Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 019512913X 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 512913 7 a b c Bishop Michael A 1999 Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments Philosophy of Science 66 4 534 541 doi 10 1086 392753 S2CID 170519663 a b c Norton John D 1996 Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 3 333 366 doi 10 1080 00455091 1996 10717457 S2CID 143017404 Sorensen Roy 1 January 1995 Roy Sorensen s Thought Experiments Informal Logic 17 3 doi 10 22329 il v17i3 2425 ISSN 2293 734X Reiss Julian 1 December 2009 Counterfactuals Thought Experiments and Singular Causal Analysis in History Philosophy of Science 76 5 712 723 doi 10 1086 605826 ISSN 0031 8248 S2CID 43496954 Aligica Paul Dragos Evans Anthony J 1 September 2009 Thought experiments counterfactuals and comparative analysis The Review of Austrian Economics 22 3 225 239 doi 10 1007 s11138 009 0082 8 ISSN 1573 7128 S2CID 144831020 a b Cole David 2020 The Chinese Room Argument The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 29 October 2021 a b Hauser Larry Chinese Room Argument Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 29 October 2021 Ennis Robert H 2015 Critical Thinking A Streamlined Conception The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education Palgrave Macmillan US pp 31 47 doi 10 1057 9781137378057 2 ISBN 978 1 137 37805 7 a b c d e f Davies Martin Barnett Ronald 2015 Introduction The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education Palgrave Macmillan US pp 1 25 doi 10 1057 9781137378057 1 ISBN 978 1 137 37805 7 a b c d e f g h Hitchcock David 2020 Critical Thinking The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 1 November 2021 Dewey John 1910 6 The Analysis of a Complete Act of Thought How We Think a b Siegel Harvey 2006 Philosophy if Education Epistemological Issues In Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan Monteiro Sandra Sherbino Jonathan Sibbald Matthew Norman Geoff 2020 Critical thinking biases and dual processing The enduring myth of generalisable skills Medical Education 54 1 66 73 doi 10 1111 medu 13872 ISSN 1365 2923 PMID 31468581 S2CID 201674464 a b c d e f g h i j Khalid Ruhi June 2010 Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes Literature Review Journal of Research and Reflections in Education 4 1 42 61 a b c d e f Scheier Michael F Carver Charles S 1 February 1993 On the Power of Positive Thinking The Benefits of Being Optimistic Current Directions in Psychological Science 2 1 26 30 doi 10 1111 1467 8721 ep10770572 ISSN 0963 7214 S2CID 145393172 Oettingen Gabriele Cachia Julie Y A 2017 30 Problems with Positive Thinking and How to Overcome Them Handbook of Self Regulation Third Edition Research Theory and Applications Thomas Sandra P 2020 Defensive Pessimism Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences Springer International Publishing pp 1036 1038 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 24612 3 1061 ISBN 978 3 319 24612 3 S2CID 243736790 Peale Norman Vincent The Power of Positive Thinking Om Books International ISBN 978 93 85609 89 3 a b Seligman Martin E P 2002 6 Optimism about the Future Authentic Happiness Using the New Positive Psychology to Realize Your Potential for Lasting Fulfillment Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 0 7432 4788 7 Woodstock Louise 1 April 2007 Think About It The Misbegotten Promise of Positive Thinking Discourse Journal of Communication Inquiry 31 2 166 189 doi 10 1177 0196859906298177 ISSN 0196 8599 S2CID 145436993 Chabris Christopher F Simons Daniel J 24 September 2010 Fight The Power The New York Times Further reading editListen to this article 18 minutes source source nbsp This audio file was created from a revision of this article dated 4 December 2010 2010 12 04 and does not reflect subsequent edits Audio help More spoken articles Bayne Tim 21 September 2013 Thoughts New Scientist 7 page feature article on the topic Fields R Douglas The Brain Learns in Unexpected Ways Neuroscientists have discovered a set of unfamiliar cellular mechanisms for making fresh memories Scientific American vol 322 no 3 March 2020 pp 74 79 Myelin long considered inert insulation on axons is now seen as making a contribution to learning by controlling the speed at which signals travel along neural wiring p 79 Rajvanshi Anil K 2010 Nature of Human Thought ISBN 978 81 905781 2 7 Simon Herbert Models of Thought Vol I 1979 ISBN 0 300 02347 2 Vol II 1989 ISBN 0 300 04230 2 Yale University Press External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Thought nbsp The dictionary definition of think at Wiktionary nbsp Media related to Thinking at Wikimedia Commons Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Thought amp oldid 1206073514, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.