fbpx
Wikipedia

Mind–body problem

The mind–body problem is a philosophical problem concerning the relationship between thought and consciousness in the human mind, and the body.[1][2]

René Descartes' illustration of mind–body dualism. Descartes believed inputs were passed on by the sensory organs to the epiphysis in the brain and from there to the immaterial spirit.

It is not obvious how the concept of the mind and the concept of the body relate. For example, feelings of sadness (which are mental events) cause people to cry (which is a physical state of the body). Finding a joke funny (a mental event) causes one to laugh (another bodily state). Feelings of pain (in the mind) cause avoidance behaviours (in the body), and so on.

Similarly, changing the chemistry of the body (and the brain especially) via drugs (such as antipsychotics, SSRIs, or alcohol) can change one's state of mind in nontrivial ways. Alternatively, therapeutic interventions like cognitive behavioural therapy can change cognition in ways that have downstream effects on the bodily health.

In general, the existence of these mind–body connections seems unproblematic. Issues arise, however, once one considers what exactly we should make of these relations from a metaphysical or scientific perspective. Such reflections quickly raise a number of questions like:

  • Are the mind and body two distinct entities, or a single entity?
  • If the mind and body are two distinct entities, do the two of them causally interact?
  • Is it possible for these two distinct entities to causally interact?
  • What is the nature of this interaction?
  • Can this interaction ever be an object of empirical study?
  • If the mind and body are a single entity, then are mental events explicable in terms of physical events, or vice versa?
  • Is the relation between mental and physical events something that arises de novo at a certain point in development?

And so on. These and other questions that discuss the relation between mind and body are questions that all fall under the banner of the 'mind–body problem'.

Mind–body interaction and mental causation edit

Philosophers David L. Robb and John F. Heil introduce mental causation in terms of the mind–body problem of interaction:

Mind–body interaction has a central place in our pretheoretic conception of agency. Indeed, mental causation often figures explicitly in formulations of the mind–body problem. Some philosophers insist that the very notion of psychological explanation turns on the intelligibility of mental causation. If your mind and its states, such as your beliefs and desires, were causally isolated from your bodily behavior, then what goes on in your mind could not explain what you do. If psychological explanation goes, so do the closely related notions of agency and moral responsibility. Clearly, a good deal rides on a satisfactory solution to the problem of mental causation [and] there is more than one way in which puzzles about the mind's "causal relevance" to behavior (and to the physical world more generally) can arise.

[René Descartes] set the agenda for subsequent discussions of the mind–body relation. According to Descartes, minds and bodies are distinct kinds of "substance". Bodies, he held, are spatially extended substances, incapable of feeling or thought; minds, in contrast, are unextended, thinking, feeling substances. If minds and bodies are radically different kinds of substance, however, it is not easy to see how they "could" causally interact. Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia puts it forcefully to him in a 1643 letter:

how the human soul can determine the movement of the animal spirits in the body so as to perform voluntary acts—being as it is merely a conscious substance. For the determination of movement seems always to come about from the moving body's being propelled—to depend on the kind of impulse it gets from what sets it in motion, or again, on the nature and shape of this latter thing's surface. Now the first two conditions involve contact, and the third involves that the impelling thing has extension; but you utterly exclude extension from your notion of soul, and contact seems to me incompatible with a thing's being immaterial...

Elizabeth is expressing the prevailing mechanistic view as to how causation of bodies works. Causal relations countenanced by contemporary physics can take several forms, not all of which are of the push–pull variety.[3]

— David Robb and John Heil, "Mental Causation" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Contemporary neurophilosopher Georg Northoff suggests that mental causation is compatible with classical formal and final causality.[4]

Biologist, theoretical neuroscientist and philosopher, Walter J. Freeman, suggests that explaining mind–body interaction in terms of "circular causation" is more relevant than linear causation.[5]

In neuroscience, much has been learned about correlations between brain activity and subjective, conscious experiences. Many suggest that neuroscience will ultimately explain consciousness: "...consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells..."[6] However, this view has been criticized because consciousness has yet to be shown to be a process,[7] and the "hard problem" of relating consciousness directly to brain activity remains elusive.[8]

Cognitive science today gets increasingly interested in the embodiment of human perception, thinking, and action. Abstract information processing models are no longer accepted as satisfactory accounts of the human mind. Interest has shifted to interactions between the material human body and its surroundings and to the way in which such interactions shape the mind. Proponents of this approach have expressed the hope that it will ultimately dissolve the Cartesian divide between the immaterial mind and the material existence of human beings (Damasio, 1994; Gallagher, 2005). A topic that seems particularly promising for providing a bridge across the mind–body cleavage is the study of bodily actions, which are neither reflexive reactions to external stimuli nor indications of mental states, which have only arbitrary relationships to the motor features of the action (e.g., pressing a button for making a choice response). The shape, timing, and effects of such actions are inseparable from their meaning. One might say that they are loaded with mental content, which cannot be appreciated other than by studying their material features. Imitation, communicative gesturing, and tool use are examples of these kinds of actions.[9]

— Georg Goldenberg, "How the Mind Moves the Body: Lessons From Apraxia" in Oxford Handbook of Human Action

Since 1927, at the Solvay Conference in Austria, European physicists of the late 19th and early 20th centuries, realized that the interpretations of their experiments with light and electricity required a different theory to explain why light behaves both as a wave and particle. The implications were profound. The usual empirical model of explaining natural phenomena could not account for this duality of matter and non-matter. In a significant way, this has brought back the conversation on the mind–body duality.[10][page needed]

Neural correlates edit

 
The neuronal correlates of consciousness constitute the smallest set of neural events and structures sufficient for a given conscious percept or explicit memory. This case involves synchronized action potentials in neocortical pyramidal neurons.[11]

The neural correlates of consciousness "are the smallest set of brain mechanisms and events sufficient for some specific conscious feeling, as elemental as the color red or as complex as the sensual, mysterious, and primeval sensation evoked when looking at [a] jungle scene..."[12] Neuroscientists use empirical approaches to discover neural correlates of subjective phenomena.[13]

Neurobiology and neurophilosophy edit

A science of consciousness must explain the exact relationship between subjective conscious mental states and brain states formed by electrochemical interactions in the body, the so-called hard problem of consciousness.[14] Neurobiology studies the connection scientifically, as do neuropsychology and neuropsychiatry. Neurophilosophy is the interdisciplinary study of neuroscience and philosophy of mind. In this pursuit, neurophilosophers, such as Patricia Churchland,[15][16] Paul Churchland[17] and Daniel Dennett,[18][19] have focused primarily on the body rather than the mind. In this context, neuronal correlates may be viewed as causing consciousness, where consciousness can be thought of as an undefined property that depends upon this complex, adaptive, and highly interconnected biological system.[20] However, it's unknown if discovering and characterizing neural correlates may eventually provide a theory of consciousness that can explain the first-person experience of these "systems", and determine whether other systems of equal complexity lack such features.

The massive parallelism of neural networks allows redundant populations of neurons to mediate the same or similar percepts. Nonetheless, it is assumed that every subjective state will have associated neural correlates, which can be manipulated to artificially inhibit or induce the subject's experience of that conscious state. The growing ability of neuroscientists to manipulate neurons using methods from molecular biology in combination with optical tools[21] was achieved by the development of behavioral and organic models that are amenable to large-scale genomic analysis and manipulation. Non-human analysis such as this, in combination with imaging of the human brain, have contributed to a robust and increasingly predictive theoretical framework.

Arousal and content edit

 
Midline structures in the brainstem and thalamus necessary to regulate the level of brain arousal. Small, bilateral lesions in many of these nuclei cause a global loss of consciousness.[22]

There are two common but distinct dimensions of the term consciousness,[23] one involving arousal and states of consciousness and the other involving content of consciousness and conscious states. To be conscious of something, the brain must be in a relatively high state of arousal (sometimes called vigilance), whether awake or in REM sleep. Brain arousal level fluctuates in a circadian rhythm but these natural cycles may be influenced by lack of sleep, alcohol and other drugs, physical exertion, etc. Arousal can be measured behaviorally by the signal amplitude required to trigger a given reaction (for example, the sound level that causes a subject to turn and look toward the source). High arousal states involve conscious states that feature specific perceptual content, planning and recollection or even fantasy. Clinicians use scoring systems such as the Glasgow Coma Scale to assess the level of arousal in patients with impaired states of consciousness such as the comatose state, the persistent vegetative state, and the minimally conscious state. Here, "state" refers to different amounts of externalized, physical consciousness: ranging from a total absence in coma, persistent vegetative state and general anesthesia, to a fluctuating, minimally conscious state, such as sleep walking and epileptic seizure.[24]

Many nuclei with distinct chemical signatures in the thalamus, midbrain and pons must function for a subject to be in a sufficient state of brain arousal to experience anything at all. These nuclei therefore belong to the enabling factors for consciousness. Conversely it is likely that the specific content of any particular conscious sensation is mediated by particular neurons in the cortex and their associated satellite structures, including the amygdala, thalamus, claustrum and the basal ganglia.

Theoretical Frameworks edit

 
Different approaches toward resolving the mind–body problem

A variety of approaches have been proposed. Most are either dualist or monist. Dualism maintains a rigid distinction between the realms of mind and matter. Monism maintains that there is only one unifying reality as in neutral or substance or essence, in terms of which everything can be explained.

Each of these categories contains numerous variants. The two main forms of dualism are substance dualism, which holds that the mind is formed of a distinct type of substance not governed by the laws of physics, and property dualism, which holds that mental properties involving conscious experience are fundamental properties, alongside the fundamental properties identified by a completed physics. The three main forms of monism are physicalism, which holds that the mind consists of matter organized in a particular way; idealism, which holds that only thought truly exists and matter is merely a representation of mental processes; and neutral monism, which holds that both mind and matter are aspects of a distinct essence that is itself identical to neither of them. Psychophysical parallelism is a third possible alternative regarding the relation between mind and body, between interaction (dualism) and one-sided action (monism).[25]

Several philosophical perspectives that have sought to escape the problem by rejecting the mind–body dichotomy have been developed. The historical materialism of Karl Marx and subsequent writers, itself a form of physicalism, held that consciousness was engendered by the material contingencies of one's environment.[26] An explicit rejection of the dichotomy is found in French structuralism, and is a position that generally characterized post-war Continental philosophy.[27]

An ancient model of the mind known as the Five-Aggregate Model, described in the Buddhist teachings, explains the mind as continuously changing sense impressions and mental phenomena.[28] Considering this model, it is possible to understand that it is the constantly changing sense impressions and mental phenomena (i.e., the mind) that experience/analyze all external phenomena in the world as well as all internal phenomena including the body anatomy, the nervous system as well as the organ brain. This conceptualization leads to two levels of analyses: (i) analyses conducted from a third-person perspective on how the brain works, and (ii) analyzing the moment-to-moment manifestation of an individual's mind-stream (analyses conducted from a first-person perspective). Considering the latter, the manifestation of the mind-stream is described as happening in every person all the time, even in a scientist who analyzes various phenomena in the world, including analyzing and hypothesizing about the organ brain.[28]

Dualism edit

The following is a very brief account of some contributions to the mind–body problem.

Interactionism edit

The viewpoint of interactionism suggests that the mind and body are two separate substances, but that each can affect the other.[29] This interaction between the mind and body was first put forward by the philosopher René Descartes. Descartes believed that the mind was non-physical and permeated the entire body, but that the mind and body interacted via the pineal gland.[30][31] This theory has changed throughout the years, and in the 20th century its main adherents were the philosopher of science Karl Popper and the neurophysiologist John Carew Eccles.[32][33] A more recent and popular version of Interactionism is the viewpoint of emergentism.[29] This perspective states that mental states are a result of the brain states, and that the mental events can then influence the brain, resulting in a two way communication between the mind and body.[29]

The absence of an empirically identifiable meeting point between the non-physical mind (if there is such a thing) and its physical extension (if there is such a thing) has been raised as a criticism of interactionalist dualism. This criticism has lead many modern philosophers of mind to maintain that the mind is not something separate from the body.[34] These approaches have been particularly influential in the sciences, particularly in the fields of sociobiology, computer science, evolutionary psychology, and the neurosciences.[35][36][37][38]

Epiphenomenalism edit

The viewpoint of epiphenomenalism suggests that the physical brain can cause mental events in the mind, but that the mind cannot interact with the brain at all; stating that mental occurrences are simply a side effect of the brain's processes.[29] This viewpoint explains that while one's body may react to them feeling joy, fear, or sadness, that the emotion does not cause the physical response. Rather, it explains that joy, fear, sadness, and all bodily reactions are caused by chemicals and their interaction with the body.[39]

Psychophysical parallelism edit

The viewpoint of psychophysical parallelism suggests that the mind and body are entirely independent from one another. Furthermore, this viewpoint states that both mental and physical stimuli and reactions are experienced simultaneously by both the mind and body, however, there is no interaction nor communication between the two.[29][40]

Double aspectism edit

Double aspectism is an extension of psychophysical parallelism which also suggests that the mind and body cannot interact, nor can they be separated.[29] Baruch Spinoza and Gustav Fechner were two of the notable users of double aspectism, however, Fechner later expanded upon it to form the branch of psychophysics in an attempt to prove the relationship of the mind and body.[41]

Pre-established harmony edit

The viewpoint of pre-established harmony is another offshoot of psychophysical parallelism which suggests that mental events and bodily events are separate and distinct, but that they are both coordinated by an external agent, an example of such an agent could be God.[29] A notable adherent to the idea of pre-established harmony is Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz in his theory of Monadology.[42] His explanation of pre-established harmony relied heavily upon God as the external agent who coordinated the mental and bodily events of all things in the beginning.[43]

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz's theory of pre-established harmony (French: harmonie préétablie) is a philosophical theory about causation under which every "substance" affects only itself, but all the substances (both bodies and minds) in the world nevertheless seem to causally interact with each other because they have been programmed by God in advance to "harmonize" with each other. Leibniz's term for these substances was "monads", which he described in a popular work (Monadology §7) as "windowless".

The concept of pre-established harmony can be understood by considering an event with both seemingly mental and physical aspects. For example, consider saying 'ouch' after stubbing one's toe. There are two general ways to describe this event: in terms of mental events (where the conscious sensation of pain caused one to say 'ouch') and in terms of physical events (where neural firings in one's toe, carried to the brain, are what caused one to say 'ouch'). The main task of the mind–body problem is figuring out how these mental events (the feeling of pain) and physical events (the nerve firings) relate. Leibniz's pre-established harmony attempts to answer this puzzle, by saying that mental and physical events are not genuinely related in any causal sense, but only seem to interact due to psycho-physical fine-tuning.

Leibniz's theory is best known as a solution to the mind–body problem of how mind can interact with the body. Leibniz rejected the idea of physical bodies affecting each other, and explained all physical causation in this way.

Under pre-established harmony, the preprogramming of each mind must be extremely complex, since only it causes its own thoughts or actions, for as long as it exists. To appear to interact, each substance's "program" must contain a description of either the entire universe, or of how the object behaves at all times during all interactions that appear to occur.

An example:

An apple falls on Alice's head, apparently causing the experience of pain in her mind. In fact, the apple does not cause the pain—the pain is caused by some previous state of Alice's mind. If Alice then seems to shake her hand in anger, it is not actually her mind that causes this, but some previous state of her hand.

Note that if a mind behaves as a windowless monad, there is no need for any other object to exist to create that mind's sense perceptions, leading to a solipsistic universe that consists only of that mind. Leibniz seems to admit this in his Discourse on Metaphysics, section 14. However, he claims that his principle of harmony, according to which God creates the best and most harmonious world possible, dictates that the perceptions (internal states) of each monad "expresses" the world in its entirety, and the world expressed by the monad actually exists. Although Leibniz says that each monad is "windowless", he also claims that it functions as a "mirror" of the entire created universe.

On occasion, Leibniz styled himself as "the author of the system of pre-established harmony".[44]

Immanuel Kant's professor Martin Knutzen regarded pre-established harmony as "the pillow for the lazy mind".[45]

In his sixth Metaphysical Meditation, Descartes talked about a "coordinated disposition of created things set up by God", shortly after having identified "nature in its general aspect" with God himself. His conception of the relationship between God and his normative nature actualized in the existing world recalls both the pre-established harmony of Leibniz and the Deus sive Natura of Baruch Spinoza.[46]

Occasionalism edit

The viewpoint of Occasionalism is another offshoot of psychophysical parallelism, however, the major difference is that the mind and body have some indirect interaction. Occasionalism suggests that the mind and body are separate and distinct, but that they interact through divine intervention.[29] Nicolas Malebranche was one of the main contributors to this idea, using it as a way to address his disagreements with Descartes' view of the mind–body problem.[47] In Malebranche's occasionalism, he viewed thoughts as a wish for the body to move, which was then fulfilled by God causing the body to act.[47]

Historical background edit

The problem was popularized by René Descartes in the 17th century, which resulted in Cartesian dualism, also by pre-Aristotelian philosophers,[48][49] in Avicennian philosophy,[50] and in earlier Asian traditions.

The Buddha edit

The Buddha (480–400 B.C.E), founder of Buddhism, described the mind and the body as depending on each other in a way that two sheaves of reeds were to stand leaning against one another[51] and taught that the world consists of mind and matter which work together, interdependently. Buddhist teachings describe the mind as manifesting from moment to moment, one thought moment at a time as a fast flowing stream.[28] The components that make up the mind are known as the five aggregates (i.e., material form, feelings, perception, volition, and sensory consciousness), which arise and pass away continuously. The arising and passing of these aggregates in the present moment is described as being influenced by five causal laws: biological laws, psychological laws, physical laws, volitional laws, and universal laws.[28] The Buddhist practice of mindfulness involves attending to this constantly changing mind-stream.

Ultimately, the Buddha's philosophy is that both mind and forms are conditionally arising qualities of an ever-changing universe in which, when nirvāna is attained, all phenomenal experience ceases to exist.[52] According to the anattā doctrine of the Buddha, the conceptual self is a mere mental construct of an individual entity and is basically an impermanent illusion, sustained by form, sensation, perception, thought and consciousness.[53] The Buddha argued that mentally clinging to any views will result in delusion and stress,[54] since, according to the Buddha, a real self (conceptual self, being the basis of standpoints and views) cannot be found when the mind has clarity.

Plato edit

Plato (429–347 B.C.E.) believed that the material world is a shadow of a higher reality that consists of concepts he called Forms. According to Plato, objects in our everyday world "participate in" these Forms, which confer identity and meaning to material objects. For example, a circle drawn in the sand would be a circle only because it participates in the concept of an ideal circle that exists somewhere in the world of Forms. He argued that, as the body is from the material world, the soul is from the world of Forms and is thus immortal. He believed the soul was temporarily united with the body and would only be separated at death, when it, if pure, would return to the world of Forms; otherwise, reincarnation follows. Since the soul does not exist in time and space, as the body does, it can access universal truths. For Plato, ideas (or Forms) are the true reality, and are experienced by the soul. The body is for Plato empty in that it cannot access the abstract reality of the world; it can only experience shadows. This is determined by Plato's essentially rationalistic epistemology.[55]

Aristotle edit

For Aristotle (384–322 BC) mind is a faculty of the soul.[56][57] Regarding the soul, he said:

It is not necessary to ask whether soul and body are one, just as it is not necessary to ask whether the wax and its shape are one, nor generally whether the matter of each thing and that of which it is the matter are one. For even if one and being are spoken of in several ways, what is properly so spoken of is the actuality.

— De Anima ii 1, 412b6–9

In the end, Aristotle saw the relation between soul and body as uncomplicated, in the same way that it is uncomplicated that a cubical shape is a property of a toy building block. The soul is a property exhibited by the body, one among many. Moreover, Aristotle proposed that when the body perishes, so does the soul, just as the shape of a building block disappears with destruction of the block.[58]

Medieval Aristotelianism edit

Working in the Aristotelian-influenced tradition of Thomism, Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274), like Aristotle, believed that the mind and the body are one, like a seal and wax; therefore, it is pointless to ask whether or not they are one. However, (referring to "mind" as "the soul") he asserted that the soul persists after the death of the body in spite of their unity, calling the soul "this particular thing". Since his view was primarily theological rather than philosophical, it is impossible to fit it neatly within either the category of physicalism or dualism.[59]

Influences of Eastern monotheistic religions edit

In religious philosophy of Eastern monotheism, dualism denotes a binary opposition of an idea that contains two essential parts. The first formal concept of a "mind–body" split may be found in the divinitysecularity dualism of the ancient Persian religion of Zoroastrianism around the mid-fifth century BC. Gnosticism is a modern name for a variety of ancient dualistic ideas inspired by Judaism popular in the first and second century AD. These ideas later seem to have been incorporated into Galen's "tripartite soul"[60] that led into both the Christian sentiments[61] expressed in the later Augustinian theodicy and Avicenna's Platonism in Islamic Philosophy.

Descartes edit

René Descartes (1596–1650) believed that mind exerted control over the brain via the pineal gland:

My view is that this gland is the principal seat of the soul, and the place in which all our thoughts are formed.[62]

— René Descartes, Treatise of Man

[The] mechanism of our body is so constructed that simply by this gland's being moved in any way by the soul or by any other cause, it drives the surrounding spirits towards the pores of the brain, which direct them through the nerves to the muscles; and in this way the gland makes the spirits move the limbs.[63]

— René Descartes, Passions of the Soul

His posited relation between mind and body is called Cartesian dualism or substance dualism. He held that mind was distinct from matter, but could influence matter. How such an interaction could be exerted remains a contentious issue.

Kant edit

For Kant (1724–1804) beyond mind and matter there exists a world of a priori forms, which are seen as necessary preconditions for understanding. Some of these forms, space and time being examples, today seem to be pre-programmed in the brain.

...whatever it is that impinges on us from the mind-independent world does not come located in a spatial or a temporal matrix,...The mind has two pure forms of intuition built into it to allow it to... organize this 'manifold of raw intuition'.[64]

— Andrew Brook, Kant's view of the mind and consciousness of self: Transcendental aesthetic

Kant views the mind–body interaction as taking place through forces that may be of different kinds for mind and body.[65]

Huxley edit

For Huxley (1825–1895) the conscious mind was a by-product of the brain that has no influence upon the brain, a so-called epiphenomenon.

On the epiphenomenalist view, mental events play no causal role. Huxley, who held the view, compared mental events to a steam whistle that contributes nothing to the work of a locomotive.[66]

— William Robinson, Epiphenomenalism

Whitehead edit

A. N. Whitehead advocated a sophisticated form of panpsychism that has been called by David Ray Griffin panexperientialism.[67]

Popper edit

For Popper (1902–1994) there are three aspects of the mind–body problem: the worlds of matter, mind, and of the creations of the mind, such as mathematics. In his view, the third-world creations of the mind could be interpreted by the second-world mind and used to affect the first-world of matter. An example might be radio, an example of the interpretation of the third-world (Maxwell's electromagnetic theory) by the second-world mind to suggest modifications of the external first world.

The body–mind problem is the question of whether and how our thought processes in World 2 are bound up with brain events in World 1. ...I would argue that the first and oldest of these attempted solutions is the only one that deserves to be taken seriously [namely]: World 2 and World 1 interact, so that when someone reads a book or listens to a lecture, brain events occur that act upon the World 2 of the reader's or listener's thoughts; and conversely, when a mathematician follows a proof, his World 2 acts upon his brain and thus upon World 1. This, then, is the thesis of body–mind interaction.[68]

— Karl Popper, Notes of a realist on the body–mind problem

Ryle edit

With his 1949 book, The Concept of Mind, Gilbert Ryle "was seen to have put the final nail in the coffin of Cartesian dualism".[69]

In the chapter "Descartes' Myth," Ryle introduces "the dogma of the Ghost in the machine" to describe the philosophical concept of the mind as an entity separate from the body:

I hope to prove that it is entirely false, and false not in detail but in principle. It is not merely an assemblage of particular mistakes. It is one big mistake and a mistake of a special kind. It is, namely, a category mistake.

Searle edit

For Searle (b. 1932) the mind–body problem is a false dichotomy; that is, mind is a perfectly ordinary aspect of the brain. Searle proposed Biological naturalism in 1980.

According to Searle then, there is no more a mind–body problem than there is a macro–micro economics problem. They are different levels of description of the same set of phenomena. [...] But Searle is careful to maintain that the mental – the domain of qualitative experience and understanding – is autonomous and has no counterpart on the microlevel; any redescription of these macroscopic features amounts to a kind of evisceration, ...[70]

— Joshua Rust, John Searle

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ "Dualism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2020.
  2. ^ Georgiev, Danko D. (2020). "Quantum information theoretic approach to the mind–brain problem". Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology. 158: 16–32. arXiv:2012.07836. doi:10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2020.08.002. PMID 32822698. S2CID 221237249. The mind-brain problem is to explain how the unobservable conscious mind and the observable brain relate to each other: do they interact or does one unilaterally generate the other?
  3. ^ Robb, David; Heil, John (2009). "Mental Causation". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 ed.).
  4. ^ Georg Northoff (2004). Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem (Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research ed.). John Benjamins Publishing. pp. 137–139. ISBN 978-1588114174. The restriction of causality to 'efficient causality' lead to the neglect of 'goal-orientation' since it was no longer necessary within [that] framework. Not considering 'goal-orientation' resulted in the neglect of 'embedment' and the consequential presupposition of 'isolation' with separation between brain, body, and environment. Neglecting 'embedment' lead to the equation of perception/action with sensory impression/movement which could be well accounted for by 'efficient causality'. Accordingly, since dominated by 'efficient causality', qualia and intentionality, as related to perception/action rather than to sensory impression/movement, were excluded from science and consequently regarded [as] purely philosophical problems. Analogous to 'final causes', 'formal causes' were eliminated as well. 'Efficient causality' is not compatible with 'embedded coding' [which] is necessarily tied with 'formal causality' and 'final causality'... Finally, the possibility of mental causation remains incompatible with 'efficient causality'. It can, however, be properly described by 'formal and final causality'.
  5. ^ Walter J Freeman (2009). "Consciousness, intentionality and causality". In Susan Pockett; WP Banks; Shaun Gallagher (eds.). Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press. pp. 4–5, 88–90. ISBN 978-0262512572.
  6. ^ Eric R. Kandel (2007). In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. WW Norton. p. 9. ISBN 978-0393329377.
  7. ^ Oswald Hanfling (2002). Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life. Psychology Press. pp. 108–109. ISBN 978-0415256452.
  8. ^ A term attributed to David Chalmers by Eugene O Mills (1999). "Giving up on the hard problem of consciousness". In Jonathan Shear (ed.). Explaining Consciousness: The Hard Problem. MIT Press. p. 109. ISBN 978-0262692212.
  9. ^ Goldenberg, Georg (2008). "Chapter 7, How the Mind Moves the Body: Lessons From Apraxia". In Morsella, E.; Bargh, J.A.; Gollwitzer, P.M. (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Human Action. Social Cognition and Social Neuroscience. Oxford University Press, USA. p. 136. ISBN 9780195309980. LCCN 2008004997.
  10. ^ Gilder, L. (2009). The Age of Entanglement: When Quantum Physics was Reborn. Vintage Books. ISBN 978-1-4000-9526-1. Retrieved November 11, 2021.
  11. ^ Christof Koch (2004). "Figure 1.1: Neuronal correlates of consciousness". The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. Englewood, Colorado: Roberts & Company Publishers. p. 16. ISBN 978-0974707709.
  12. ^ Christof Koch (2004). "Chapter 5: What are the neuronal correlates of consciousness?". The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. Englewood, Colorado: Roberts & Company Publishers. pp. xvi, 97, 104. ISBN 978-0974707709.
  13. ^ See here 2013-03-13 at the Wayback Machine for a glossary of related terms.
  14. ^ Kandel, Eric R. (2007). In search of memory: The emergence of a new science of mind. W. W. Norton & Company. p. 382. ISBN 978-0393329377.
  15. ^ Churchland, Patricia Smith (2002). Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy. Bradford Books. MIT Press. ISBN 9780262532006. LCCN 2002066024.
  16. ^ Churchland, Patricia Smith (1989). Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind–Brain. Computational Models of Cognition and Perception. MIT Press. ISBN 9780262530859. LCCN 85023706.
  17. ^ Churchland, Paul (2007). Neurophilosophy at Work. Cambridge University Press. pp. viii–ix. ISBN 9780521864725. LCCN 2006014487.
  18. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (1986). Content and Consciousness. International Library of Philosophy. Taylor \& Francis. ISBN 9780415104319. LCCN 72436737.
  19. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (1997). Kinds of Minds: Toward an Understanding of Consciousness. Science Masters Series. Basic Books. ISBN 9780465073511. LCCN 96164655.
  20. ^ Squire, Larry R. (2008). Fundamental neuroscience (3rd ed.). Academic Press. p. 1223. ISBN 978-0-12-374019-9.
  21. ^ Adamantidis A.R.; Zhang F.; Aravanis A.M.; Deisseroth K.; de Lecea L. (2007). "Neural substrates of awakening probed with optogenetic control of hypocretin neurons". Nature. 450 (7168): 420–4. Bibcode:2007Natur.450..420A. doi:10.1038/nature06310. PMC 6744371. PMID 17943086.
  22. ^ Christof Koch (2004). "Figure 5.1 The Cholinergic Enabling System". The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. Englewood, Colorado: Roberts & Company Publishers. p. 91. ISBN 978-0974707709. Also see Chapter 5, available on line.
  23. ^ Zeman, A. (2001). "Consciousness". Brain. 124 (7): 1263–1289. doi:10.1093/brain/124.7.1263. PMID 11408323.
  24. ^ Schiff, Nicholas D. (November 2004), "The neurology of impaired consciousness: Challenges for cognitive neuroscience.", in Gazzaniga, Michael S. (ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences (3rd ed.), MIT Press, ISBN 978-0-262-07254-0
  25. ^ Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Parallelism, Psychophysical" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 20 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 762.
  26. ^ K. Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1977, with some notes by R. Rojas.
  27. ^ Bryan S. Turner (2008). The Body and Society: Explorations in Social Theory (3rd ed.). Sage Publications. p. 78. ISBN 978-1412929875. ...a rejection of any dualism between mind and body, and a consequent insistence on the argument that the body is never simply a physical object but always an embodiment of consciousness.
  28. ^ a b c d Karunamuni N.D. (May 2015). "The Five-Aggregate Model of the Mind". SAGE Open. 5 (2): 215824401558386. doi:10.1177/2158244015583860.
  29. ^ a b c d e f g h Hergenhahn, Baldwin R. (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology, Sixth Edition. Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning. p. 18. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8.
  30. ^ Hergenhahn, Baldwin, R (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology, Sixth Edition. Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning. pp. 121–122. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  31. ^ "Interactionism Philosophy". Encyclopaedia Britannica Online. Retrieved 17 July 2020.
  32. ^ Popper, Karl R. (1977). The self and its brain: an argument for interactionism. Springer International. ISBN 0-415-05898-8. OCLC 180195035.
  33. ^ Eccles, John C. (1994), "The Self and Its Brain: The Ultimate Synthesis", How the SELF Controls Its BRAIN, Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, pp. 167–183, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-49224-2_10, ISBN 978-3-642-49226-6
  34. ^ Kim, Jaegwan (1995). "Emergent properties". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 240. ISBN 9780198661320.
  35. ^ Pinel, J. (2009). Psychobiology (7th ed.). Pearson/Allyn and Bacon. ISBN 978-0205548927.
  36. ^ LeDoux, J. (2002). The Synaptic Self: How Our Brains Become Who We Are. Viking Penguin. ISBN 978-88-7078-795-5.
  37. ^ Russell, S. & Norvig, P. (2010). Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach (3rd ed.). Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0136042594.
  38. ^ Dawkins, R. (2006). The Selfish Gene (3rd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199291144.
  39. ^ Walter, Sven. "Epiphenomenalism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. University of Bielefeld. Retrieved 17 July 2020.
  40. ^ Broad, C.D. (2014-06-03). The Mind and its Place in Nature. doi:10.4324/9781315824147. ISBN 9781315824147.
  41. ^ Hergenhahn, Baldwin R. (2013). An Introduction to the History of Psychology, Seventh Edition. Cengage Learning. pp. 240–241. ISBN 978-1-133-95809-3.
  42. ^ Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. (2016). La Monadologie. BnF-P. ISBN 978-2-346-03192-4. OCLC 1041048644.
  43. ^ Hergenhahn, Baldwin R. (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology, Sixth Edition. Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning. pp. 186–188. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8.
  44. ^ Leibniz Philosophischen Schriften hrsg. C. Gerhardt, Bd VI 539, 546; and also the New Essays
  45. ^ Porter, Burton (2010). What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. p. 133.
  46. ^ Cuttingham, John (June 1, 2013). "II—John Cottingham: Descartes and Darwin: Reflections on the Sixth Meditation" (pdf). Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume. Oxford University Press. 87 (1): 268. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8349.2013.00229.x. ISSN 0309-7013. OCLC 5884450451. Retrieved April 30, 2021.
  47. ^ a b Hergenhahn, Baldwin R. (2009). An Introduction to the History of Psychology, Sixth Edition. Belmont, CA: Cengage Learning. p. 185. ISBN 978-0-495-50621-8.
  48. ^ Robert M. Young (1996). "The mind–body problem". In RC Olby; GN Cantor; JR Christie; MJS Hodges (eds.). Companion to the History of Modern Science (Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 ed.). Taylor and Francis. pp. 702–11. ISBN 978-0415145787. from the original on 2007-06-14.
  49. ^ Robinson, Howard (Nov 3, 2011). "Dualism". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition).
  50. ^ Henrik Lagerlund (2010). "Introduction". In Henrik Lagerlund (ed.). Forming the Mind: Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment (Paperback reprint of 2007 ed.). Springer Science+Business Media. p. 3. ISBN 978-9048175307.
  51. ^ Nalakalapiyo Sutta: Sheaves of Reeds 2016-05-03 at the Wayback Machine
  52. ^ Rohitassa Sutta: To Rohitassa 2011-05-12 at the Wayback Machine
  53. ^ The Five Aggregates: A Study Guide 2002-09-17 at the Wayback Machine
  54. ^ Sabbasava Sutta: All the Fermentations 2006-06-25 at the Wayback Machine
  55. ^ Nelson, Alan, ed. (2005). "A Companion to Rationalism". Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd. pp. xiv–xvi. doi:10.1111/b.9781405109093.2005.00003.x. ISBN 978-1-4051-0909-3. {{cite book}}: Missing or empty |title= (help)
  56. ^ Gendlin 2012b, p. 121–122
    432a1-2
    Hence the soul is as the hand is; for
    the hand is a tool of tools
    , and
    the nous is a form of forms
    (ὥστε ἡ ψυχὴ ὥσπερ ἡ χείρ ἐστιν· καὶ γὰρ η χεὶρ ὄργανόν
    ἐστιν ὀργάνων
    )

    Aristotle now lets this aspect of nous and hand define a new term which he does not use anywhere else, so far as I know. The hand is “a tool of tools.” The nous is a “form of forms.” The hand and the soul are unique in this respect. Let us see further what this means.

    Aristotle seems to say that the nous is a form, but on closer inspection we find that it is not, or at least not the usual kind. Nous is a maker of forms. A “form of forms” is like a tool of tools, like a living body's organ that makes tools. Nous is certainly not itself the sort of form that it makes. The hand is not a made tool (it would have to be made by yet another hand).
    In Greek “tool” and “organ” are the same word. So we see: ”In the phrase “tool of tools” the first use of the word stands for a living organ, the second for an artificially made tool. In II-4 he says “all natural bodies are tools (organs) of the soul's,” (both as food and as material from which to make tools). In English we would say that the hand is the organ of tools.

  57. ^ Hicks 1907, p. 542
    431b230–432a14. To sum up: the soul is in a manner the universe of things, which is made up of things sensible and things intelligible: and knowledge is in a manner identical with its object, the intelligible; sense with its object, the sensible. This statement calls for further explanation. Sense and knowledge, whether potential or actual, are distributed over things potential or actual, as the case may be. In the soul, again, the sensitive faculty and the cognitive faculty are potentially their respective objects. These objects must therefore exist in the soul, not indeed as concrete wholes, form and matter combined, which is impossible: it must be the forms of things which exist in the soul. Thus within the soul intellect is the form of forms, i.e. of intelligible forms, and sense the form of sensibles, precisely as in the body the hand is the instrument of instruments, i.e. the instrument by which other instruments are acquired.
  58. ^ Shields, Christopher. "Aristotle's Psychology". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition).
  59. ^ McInerny, Ralph; O'Callaghan, John (Summer 2018). "Saint Thomas Aquinas". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 7 November 2018.
  60. ^ Researchgate:Galen and the tripartite soul 2017-05-31 at the Wayback Machine
  61. ^ Early Christian writings:Galen 2017-05-31 at the Wayback Machine
  62. ^ Lokhorst, Gert-Jan (Nov 5, 2008). "Descartes and the Pineal Gland". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). Lokhorst quotes Descartes in his Treatise of Man
  63. ^ Lokhorst, Gert-Jan (Nov 5, 2008). "Descartes and the Pineal Gland". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). Lokhorst quotes Descartes in his Passions of the Soul
  64. ^ Brook, Andrew (October 20, 2008). "Kant's View of the Mind and Consciousness of Self". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition).
  65. ^ Eric Watkins (2004). "Causality in context". Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality. Cambridge University Press. p. 108. ISBN 978-0521543613.
  66. ^ Robinson, William (January 27, 2011). "Epiphenomenalism". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 Edition). Vol. 1. pp. 539–547. doi:10.1002/wcs.19. PMID 26271501. S2CID 239938469.
  67. ^ See, e.g., Ronny Desmet and Michel Weber (edited by), Whitehead. The Algebra of Metaphysics. Applied Process Metaphysics Summer Institute Memorandum 2017-07-27 at the Wayback Machine, Louvain-la-Neuve, Éditions Chromatika, 2010 (ISBN 978-2-930517-08-7).
  68. ^ Karl Raimund Popper (1999). "Notes of a realist on the body–mind problem". All Life is Problem Solving (A lecture given in Mannheim, 8 May 1972 ed.). Psychology Press. pp. 29 ff. ISBN 978-0415174862. The body–mind relationship...includes the problem of man's position in the physical world...'World 1'. The world of conscious human processes I shall call 'World 2', and the world of the objective creations of the human mind I shall call 'World 3'.
  69. ^ Tanney, Julia (December 18, 2007). "Gilbert Ryle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved May 2, 2021.
  70. ^ Joshua Rust (2009). John Searle. Continuum International Publishing Group. pp. 27–28. ISBN 978-0826497529.

Bibliography edit

  • Bunge, Mario (2014). The Mind–Body Problem: A Psychobiological Approach. Elsevier. ISBN 978-1-4831-5012-3.
  • Feigl, Herbert (1958). "The 'Mental' and the 'Physical'". In Feigl, Herbert; Scriven, Michael; Maxwell, Grover (eds.). Concepts, Theories, and the Mind–Body Problem. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 2. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 370–457.
  • Gendlin, E. T. (2012). "Line by Line translation on Aristotle's De Anima, Books I and II" (PDF).
  • Gendlin, E. T. (2012). "Line by Line translation on Aristotle's De Anima, Book III" (PDF).
  • Hicks, R. D. (1907). Aristotle, De Anima. Cambridge University Press.
  • Kim, J. (1995). "Mind–Body Problem", Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Ted Honderich (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Jaegwon Kim (2010). Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-162506-0.
  • Massimini, M.; Tononi, G. (2018). Sizing up Consciousness: Towards an Objective Measure of the Capacity for Experience. Oxford University Press.
  • Turner, Bryan S. (1996). The Body and Society: Exploration in Social Theory.

External links edit

  •   Consciousness Studies at Wikibooks
  • Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology - The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Robert M. Young (1996). "The mind–body problem". In RC Olby; GN Cantor; JR Christie; MJS Hodges (eds.). Companion to the History of Modern Science (Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 ed.). Taylor and Francis. pp. 702–11. ISBN 978-0415145787.
  • The Mind/Body Problem, BBC Radio 4 discussion with Anthony Grayling, Julian Baggini & Sue James (In Our Time, Jan. 13, 2005)

mind, body, problem, mind, body, problem, philosophical, problem, concerning, relationship, between, thought, consciousness, human, mind, body, rené, descartes, illustration, mind, body, dualism, descartes, believed, inputs, were, passed, sensory, organs, epip. The mind body problem is a philosophical problem concerning the relationship between thought and consciousness in the human mind and the body 1 2 Rene Descartes illustration of mind body dualism Descartes believed inputs were passed on by the sensory organs to the epiphysis in the brain and from there to the immaterial spirit It is not obvious how the concept of the mind and the concept of the body relate For example feelings of sadness which are mental events cause people to cry which is a physical state of the body Finding a joke funny a mental event causes one to laugh another bodily state Feelings of pain in the mind cause avoidance behaviours in the body and so on Similarly changing the chemistry of the body and the brain especially via drugs such as antipsychotics SSRIs or alcohol can change one s state of mind in nontrivial ways Alternatively therapeutic interventions like cognitive behavioural therapy can change cognition in ways that have downstream effects on the bodily health In general the existence of these mind body connections seems unproblematic Issues arise however once one considers what exactly we should make of these relations from a metaphysical or scientific perspective Such reflections quickly raise a number of questions like Are the mind and body two distinct entities or a single entity If the mind and body are two distinct entities do the two of them causally interact Is it possible for these two distinct entities to causally interact What is the nature of this interaction Can this interaction ever be an object of empirical study If the mind and body are a single entity then are mental events explicable in terms of physical events or vice versa Is the relation between mental and physical events something that arises de novo at a certain point in development And so on These and other questions that discuss the relation between mind and body are questions that all fall under the banner of the mind body problem Contents 1 Mind body interaction and mental causation 2 Neural correlates 2 1 Neurobiology and neurophilosophy 2 2 Arousal and content 3 Theoretical Frameworks 3 1 Dualism 3 1 1 Interactionism 3 1 2 Epiphenomenalism 3 1 3 Psychophysical parallelism 3 1 3 1 Double aspectism 3 1 3 2 Pre established harmony 3 1 3 3 Occasionalism 4 Historical background 4 1 The Buddha 4 2 Plato 4 3 Aristotle 4 3 1 Medieval Aristotelianism 4 4 Influences of Eastern monotheistic religions 4 5 Descartes 4 6 Kant 4 7 Huxley 4 8 Whitehead 4 9 Popper 4 10 Ryle 4 11 Searle 5 See also 6 References 7 Bibliography 8 External linksMind body interaction and mental causation editPhilosophers David L Robb and John F Heil introduce mental causation in terms of the mind body problem of interaction Mind body interaction has a central place in our pretheoretic conception of agency Indeed mental causation often figures explicitly in formulations of the mind body problem Some philosophers insist that the very notion of psychological explanation turns on the intelligibility of mental causation If your mind and its states such as your beliefs and desires were causally isolated from your bodily behavior then what goes on in your mind could not explain what you do If psychological explanation goes so do the closely related notions of agency and moral responsibility Clearly a good deal rides on a satisfactory solution to the problem of mental causation and there is more than one way in which puzzles about the mind s causal relevance to behavior and to the physical world more generally can arise Rene Descartes set the agenda for subsequent discussions of the mind body relation According to Descartes minds and bodies are distinct kinds of substance Bodies he held are spatially extended substances incapable of feeling or thought minds in contrast are unextended thinking feeling substances If minds and bodies are radically different kinds of substance however it is not easy to see how they could causally interact Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia puts it forcefully to him in a 1643 letter how the human soul can determine the movement of the animal spirits in the body so as to perform voluntary acts being as it is merely a conscious substance For the determination of movement seems always to come about from the moving body s being propelled to depend on the kind of impulse it gets from what sets it in motion or again on the nature and shape of this latter thing s surface Now the first two conditions involve contact and the third involves that the impelling thing has extension but you utterly exclude extension from your notion of soul and contact seems to me incompatible with a thing s being immaterial Elizabeth is expressing the prevailing mechanistic view as to how causation of bodies works Causal relations countenanced by contemporary physics can take several forms not all of which are of the push pull variety 3 David Robb and John Heil Mental Causation in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Contemporary neurophilosopher Georg Northoff suggests that mental causation is compatible with classical formal and final causality 4 Biologist theoretical neuroscientist and philosopher Walter J Freeman suggests that explaining mind body interaction in terms of circular causation is more relevant than linear causation 5 In neuroscience much has been learned about correlations between brain activity and subjective conscious experiences Many suggest that neuroscience will ultimately explain consciousness consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells 6 However this view has been criticized because consciousness has yet to be shown to be a process 7 and the hard problem of relating consciousness directly to brain activity remains elusive 8 Cognitive science today gets increasingly interested in the embodiment of human perception thinking and action Abstract information processing models are no longer accepted as satisfactory accounts of the human mind Interest has shifted to interactions between the material human body and its surroundings and to the way in which such interactions shape the mind Proponents of this approach have expressed the hope that it will ultimately dissolve the Cartesian divide between the immaterial mind and the material existence of human beings Damasio 1994 Gallagher 2005 A topic that seems particularly promising for providing a bridge across the mind body cleavage is the study of bodily actions which are neither reflexive reactions to external stimuli nor indications of mental states which have only arbitrary relationships to the motor features of the action e g pressing a button for making a choice response The shape timing and effects of such actions are inseparable from their meaning One might say that they are loaded with mental content which cannot be appreciated other than by studying their material features Imitation communicative gesturing and tool use are examples of these kinds of actions 9 Georg Goldenberg How the Mind Moves the Body Lessons From Apraxia in Oxford Handbook of Human Action Since 1927 at the Solvay Conference in Austria European physicists of the late 19th and early 20th centuries realized that the interpretations of their experiments with light and electricity required a different theory to explain why light behaves both as a wave and particle The implications were profound The usual empirical model of explaining natural phenomena could not account for this duality of matter and non matter In a significant way this has brought back the conversation on the mind body duality 10 page needed Neural correlates editMain article Neural correlates of consciousness nbsp The neuronal correlates of consciousness constitute the smallest set of neural events and structures sufficient for a given conscious percept or explicit memory This case involves synchronized action potentials in neocortical pyramidal neurons 11 The neural correlates of consciousness are the smallest set of brain mechanisms and events sufficient for some specific conscious feeling as elemental as the color red or as complex as the sensual mysterious and primeval sensation evoked when looking at a jungle scene 12 Neuroscientists use empirical approaches to discover neural correlates of subjective phenomena 13 Neurobiology and neurophilosophy edit Main articles Neurobiology and Neurophilosophy A science of consciousness must explain the exact relationship between subjective conscious mental states and brain states formed by electrochemical interactions in the body the so called hard problem of consciousness 14 Neurobiology studies the connection scientifically as do neuropsychology and neuropsychiatry Neurophilosophy is the interdisciplinary study of neuroscience and philosophy of mind In this pursuit neurophilosophers such as Patricia Churchland 15 16 Paul Churchland 17 and Daniel Dennett 18 19 have focused primarily on the body rather than the mind In this context neuronal correlates may be viewed as causing consciousness where consciousness can be thought of as an undefined property that depends upon this complex adaptive and highly interconnected biological system 20 However it s unknown if discovering and characterizing neural correlates may eventually provide a theory of consciousness that can explain the first person experience of these systems and determine whether other systems of equal complexity lack such features The massive parallelism of neural networks allows redundant populations of neurons to mediate the same or similar percepts Nonetheless it is assumed that every subjective state will have associated neural correlates which can be manipulated to artificially inhibit or induce the subject s experience of that conscious state The growing ability of neuroscientists to manipulate neurons using methods from molecular biology in combination with optical tools 21 was achieved by the development of behavioral and organic models that are amenable to large scale genomic analysis and manipulation Non human analysis such as this in combination with imaging of the human brain have contributed to a robust and increasingly predictive theoretical framework Arousal and content edit nbsp Midline structures in the brainstem and thalamus necessary to regulate the level of brain arousal Small bilateral lesions in many of these nuclei cause a global loss of consciousness 22 There are two common but distinct dimensions of the term consciousness 23 one involving arousal and states of consciousness and the other involving content of consciousness and conscious states To be conscious of something the brain must be in a relatively high state of arousal sometimes called vigilance whether awake or in REM sleep Brain arousal level fluctuates in a circadian rhythm but these natural cycles may be influenced by lack of sleep alcohol and other drugs physical exertion etc Arousal can be measured behaviorally by the signal amplitude required to trigger a given reaction for example the sound level that causes a subject to turn and look toward the source High arousal states involve conscious states that feature specific perceptual content planning and recollection or even fantasy Clinicians use scoring systems such as the Glasgow Coma Scale to assess the level of arousal in patients with impaired states of consciousness such as the comatose state the persistent vegetative state and the minimally conscious state Here state refers to different amounts of externalized physical consciousness ranging from a total absence in coma persistent vegetative state and general anesthesia to a fluctuating minimally conscious state such as sleep walking and epileptic seizure 24 Many nuclei with distinct chemical signatures in the thalamus midbrain and pons must function for a subject to be in a sufficient state of brain arousal to experience anything at all These nuclei therefore belong to the enabling factors for consciousness Conversely it is likely that the specific content of any particular conscious sensation is mediated by particular neurons in the cortex and their associated satellite structures including the amygdala thalamus claustrum and the basal ganglia Theoretical Frameworks edit nbsp Different approaches toward resolving the mind body problemA variety of approaches have been proposed Most are either dualist or monist Dualism maintains a rigid distinction between the realms of mind and matter Monism maintains that there is only one unifying reality as in neutral or substance or essence in terms of which everything can be explained Each of these categories contains numerous variants The two main forms of dualism are substance dualism which holds that the mind is formed of a distinct type of substance not governed by the laws of physics and property dualism which holds that mental properties involving conscious experience are fundamental properties alongside the fundamental properties identified by a completed physics The three main forms of monism are physicalism which holds that the mind consists of matter organized in a particular way idealism which holds that only thought truly exists and matter is merely a representation of mental processes and neutral monism which holds that both mind and matter are aspects of a distinct essence that is itself identical to neither of them Psychophysical parallelism is a third possible alternative regarding the relation between mind and body between interaction dualism and one sided action monism 25 Several philosophical perspectives that have sought to escape the problem by rejecting the mind body dichotomy have been developed The historical materialism of Karl Marx and subsequent writers itself a form of physicalism held that consciousness was engendered by the material contingencies of one s environment 26 An explicit rejection of the dichotomy is found in French structuralism and is a position that generally characterized post war Continental philosophy 27 An ancient model of the mind known as the Five Aggregate Model described in the Buddhist teachings explains the mind as continuously changing sense impressions and mental phenomena 28 Considering this model it is possible to understand that it is the constantly changing sense impressions and mental phenomena i e the mind that experience analyze all external phenomena in the world as well as all internal phenomena including the body anatomy the nervous system as well as the organ brain This conceptualization leads to two levels of analyses i analyses conducted from a third person perspective on how the brain works and ii analyzing the moment to moment manifestation of an individual s mind stream analyses conducted from a first person perspective Considering the latter the manifestation of the mind stream is described as happening in every person all the time even in a scientist who analyzes various phenomena in the world including analyzing and hypothesizing about the organ brain 28 Dualism edit The following is a very brief account of some contributions to the mind body problem Interactionism edit Main article Interactionism philosophy of mind The viewpoint of interactionism suggests that the mind and body are two separate substances but that each can affect the other 29 This interaction between the mind and body was first put forward by the philosopher Rene Descartes Descartes believed that the mind was non physical and permeated the entire body but that the mind and body interacted via the pineal gland 30 31 This theory has changed throughout the years and in the 20th century its main adherents were the philosopher of science Karl Popper and the neurophysiologist John Carew Eccles 32 33 A more recent and popular version of Interactionism is the viewpoint of emergentism 29 This perspective states that mental states are a result of the brain states and that the mental events can then influence the brain resulting in a two way communication between the mind and body 29 The absence of an empirically identifiable meeting point between the non physical mind if there is such a thing and its physical extension if there is such a thing has been raised as a criticism of interactionalist dualism This criticism has lead many modern philosophers of mind to maintain that the mind is not something separate from the body 34 These approaches have been particularly influential in the sciences particularly in the fields of sociobiology computer science evolutionary psychology and the neurosciences 35 36 37 38 Epiphenomenalism edit Main article Epiphenomenalism The viewpoint of epiphenomenalism suggests that the physical brain can cause mental events in the mind but that the mind cannot interact with the brain at all stating that mental occurrences are simply a side effect of the brain s processes 29 This viewpoint explains that while one s body may react to them feeling joy fear or sadness that the emotion does not cause the physical response Rather it explains that joy fear sadness and all bodily reactions are caused by chemicals and their interaction with the body 39 Psychophysical parallelism edit Main article Psychophysical parallelism The viewpoint of psychophysical parallelism suggests that the mind and body are entirely independent from one another Furthermore this viewpoint states that both mental and physical stimuli and reactions are experienced simultaneously by both the mind and body however there is no interaction nor communication between the two 29 40 Double aspectism edit Main article Double aspectism Double aspectism is an extension of psychophysical parallelism which also suggests that the mind and body cannot interact nor can they be separated 29 Baruch Spinoza and Gustav Fechner were two of the notable users of double aspectism however Fechner later expanded upon it to form the branch of psychophysics in an attempt to prove the relationship of the mind and body 41 Pre established harmony edit The viewpoint of pre established harmony is another offshoot of psychophysical parallelism which suggests that mental events and bodily events are separate and distinct but that they are both coordinated by an external agent an example of such an agent could be God 29 A notable adherent to the idea of pre established harmony is Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz in his theory of Monadology 42 His explanation of pre established harmony relied heavily upon God as the external agent who coordinated the mental and bodily events of all things in the beginning 43 Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz s theory of pre established harmony French harmonie preetablie is a philosophical theory about causation under which every substance affects only itself but all the substances both bodies and minds in the world nevertheless seem to causally interact with each other because they have been programmed by God in advance to harmonize with each other Leibniz s term for these substances was monads which he described in a popular work Monadology 7 as windowless The concept of pre established harmony can be understood by considering an event with both seemingly mental and physical aspects For example consider saying ouch after stubbing one s toe There are two general ways to describe this event in terms of mental events where the conscious sensation of pain caused one to say ouch and in terms of physical events where neural firings in one s toe carried to the brain are what caused one to say ouch The main task of the mind body problem is figuring out how these mental events the feeling of pain and physical events the nerve firings relate Leibniz s pre established harmony attempts to answer this puzzle by saying that mental and physical events are not genuinely related in any causal sense but only seem to interact due to psycho physical fine tuning Leibniz s theory is best known as a solution to the mind body problem of how mind can interact with the body Leibniz rejected the idea of physical bodies affecting each other and explained all physical causation in this way Under pre established harmony the preprogramming of each mind must be extremely complex since only it causes its own thoughts or actions for as long as it exists To appear to interact each substance s program must contain a description of either the entire universe or of how the object behaves at all times during all interactions that appear to occur An example An apple falls on Alice s head apparently causing the experience of pain in her mind In fact the apple does not cause the pain the pain is caused by some previous state of Alice s mind If Alice then seems to shake her hand in anger it is not actually her mind that causes this but some previous state of her hand Note that if a mind behaves as a windowless monad there is no need for any other object to exist to create that mind s sense perceptions leading to a solipsistic universe that consists only of that mind Leibniz seems to admit this in his Discourse on Metaphysics section 14 However he claims that his principle of harmony according to which God creates the best and most harmonious world possible dictates that the perceptions internal states of each monad expresses the world in its entirety and the world expressed by the monad actually exists Although Leibniz says that each monad is windowless he also claims that it functions as a mirror of the entire created universe On occasion Leibniz styled himself as the author of the system of pre established harmony 44 Immanuel Kant s professor Martin Knutzen regarded pre established harmony as the pillow for the lazy mind 45 In his sixth Metaphysical Meditation Descartes talked about a coordinated disposition of created things set up by God shortly after having identified nature in its general aspect with God himself His conception of the relationship between God and his normative nature actualized in the existing world recalls both the pre established harmony of Leibniz and the Deus sive Natura of Baruch Spinoza 46 Occasionalism edit Main article Occasionalism The viewpoint of Occasionalism is another offshoot of psychophysical parallelism however the major difference is that the mind and body have some indirect interaction Occasionalism suggests that the mind and body are separate and distinct but that they interact through divine intervention 29 Nicolas Malebranche was one of the main contributors to this idea using it as a way to address his disagreements with Descartes view of the mind body problem 47 In Malebranche s occasionalism he viewed thoughts as a wish for the body to move which was then fulfilled by God causing the body to act 47 Historical background editThe problem was popularized by Rene Descartes in the 17th century which resulted in Cartesian dualism also by pre Aristotelian philosophers 48 49 in Avicennian philosophy 50 and in earlier Asian traditions The Buddha edit See also Gautama Buddha Buddhism and the body and Pratityasamutpada The Buddha 480 400 B C E founder of Buddhism described the mind and the body as depending on each other in a way that two sheaves of reeds were to stand leaning against one another 51 and taught that the world consists of mind and matter which work together interdependently Buddhist teachings describe the mind as manifesting from moment to moment one thought moment at a time as a fast flowing stream 28 The components that make up the mind are known as the five aggregates i e material form feelings perception volition and sensory consciousness which arise and pass away continuously The arising and passing of these aggregates in the present moment is described as being influenced by five causal laws biological laws psychological laws physical laws volitional laws and universal laws 28 The Buddhist practice of mindfulness involves attending to this constantly changing mind stream Ultimately the Buddha s philosophy is that both mind and forms are conditionally arising qualities of an ever changing universe in which when nirvana is attained all phenomenal experience ceases to exist 52 According to the anatta doctrine of the Buddha the conceptual self is a mere mental construct of an individual entity and is basically an impermanent illusion sustained by form sensation perception thought and consciousness 53 The Buddha argued that mentally clinging to any views will result in delusion and stress 54 since according to the Buddha a real self conceptual self being the basis of standpoints and views cannot be found when the mind has clarity Plato edit See also Plato and Theory of forms Plato 429 347 B C E believed that the material world is a shadow of a higher reality that consists of concepts he called Forms According to Plato objects in our everyday world participate in these Forms which confer identity and meaning to material objects For example a circle drawn in the sand would be a circle only because it participates in the concept of an ideal circle that exists somewhere in the world of Forms He argued that as the body is from the material world the soul is from the world of Forms and is thus immortal He believed the soul was temporarily united with the body and would only be separated at death when it if pure would return to the world of Forms otherwise reincarnation follows Since the soul does not exist in time and space as the body does it can access universal truths For Plato ideas or Forms are the true reality and are experienced by the soul The body is for Plato empty in that it cannot access the abstract reality of the world it can only experience shadows This is determined by Plato s essentially rationalistic epistemology 55 Aristotle edit Main article Hylomorphism Body soul hylomorphism For Aristotle 384 322 BC mind is a faculty of the soul 56 57 Regarding the soul he said It is not necessary to ask whether soul and body are one just as it is not necessary to ask whether the wax and its shape are one nor generally whether the matter of each thing and that of which it is the matter are one For even if one and being are spoken of in several ways what is properly so spoken of is the actuality De Anima ii 1 412b6 9 In the end Aristotle saw the relation between soul and body as uncomplicated in the same way that it is uncomplicated that a cubical shape is a property of a toy building block The soul is a property exhibited by the body one among many Moreover Aristotle proposed that when the body perishes so does the soul just as the shape of a building block disappears with destruction of the block 58 Medieval Aristotelianism edit Working in the Aristotelian influenced tradition of Thomism Thomas Aquinas 1225 1274 like Aristotle believed that the mind and the body are one like a seal and wax therefore it is pointless to ask whether or not they are one However referring to mind as the soul he asserted that the soul persists after the death of the body in spite of their unity calling the soul this particular thing Since his view was primarily theological rather than philosophical it is impossible to fit it neatly within either the category of physicalism or dualism 59 Influences of Eastern monotheistic religions edit Main articles Dualistic cosmology and Gnosticism In religious philosophy of Eastern monotheism dualism denotes a binary opposition of an idea that contains two essential parts The first formal concept of a mind body split may be found in the divinity secularity dualism of the ancient Persian religion of Zoroastrianism around the mid fifth century BC Gnosticism is a modern name for a variety of ancient dualistic ideas inspired by Judaism popular in the first and second century AD These ideas later seem to have been incorporated into Galen s tripartite soul 60 that led into both the Christian sentiments 61 expressed in the later Augustinian theodicy and Avicenna s Platonism in Islamic Philosophy Descartes edit Main article Rene Descartes Rene Descartes 1596 1650 believed that mind exerted control over the brain via the pineal gland My view is that this gland is the principal seat of the soul and the place in which all our thoughts are formed 62 Rene Descartes Treatise of Man The mechanism of our body is so constructed that simply by this gland s being moved in any way by the soul or by any other cause it drives the surrounding spirits towards the pores of the brain which direct them through the nerves to the muscles and in this way the gland makes the spirits move the limbs 63 Rene Descartes Passions of the Soul His posited relation between mind and body is called Cartesian dualism or substance dualism He held that mind was distinct from matter but could influence matter How such an interaction could be exerted remains a contentious issue Kant edit Main article Immanuel Kant For Kant 1724 1804 beyond mind and matter there exists a world of a priori forms which are seen as necessary preconditions for understanding Some of these forms space and time being examples today seem to be pre programmed in the brain whatever it is that impinges on us from the mind independent world does not come located in a spatial or a temporal matrix The mind has two pure forms of intuition built into it to allow it to organize this manifold of raw intuition 64 Andrew Brook Kant s view of the mind and consciousness of self Transcendental aesthetic Kant views the mind body interaction as taking place through forces that may be of different kinds for mind and body 65 Huxley edit Main article Thomas Huxley For Huxley 1825 1895 the conscious mind was a by product of the brain that has no influence upon the brain a so called epiphenomenon On the epiphenomenalist view mental events play no causal role Huxley who held the view compared mental events to a steam whistle that contributes nothing to the work of a locomotive 66 William Robinson Epiphenomenalism Whitehead edit Main article Alfred North Whitehead A N Whitehead advocated a sophisticated form of panpsychism that has been called by David Ray Griffin panexperientialism 67 Popper edit Main article Karl Popper For Popper 1902 1994 there are three aspects of the mind body problem the worlds of matter mind and of the creations of the mind such as mathematics In his view the third world creations of the mind could be interpreted by the second world mind and used to affect the first world of matter An example might be radio an example of the interpretation of the third world Maxwell s electromagnetic theory by the second world mind to suggest modifications of the external first world The body mind problem is the question of whether and how our thought processes in World 2 are bound up with brain events in World 1 I would argue that the first and oldest of these attempted solutions is the only one that deserves to be taken seriously namely World 2 and World 1 interact so that when someone reads a book or listens to a lecture brain events occur that act upon the World 2 of the reader s or listener s thoughts and conversely when a mathematician follows a proof his World 2 acts upon his brain and thus upon World 1 This then is the thesis of body mind interaction 68 Karl Popper Notes of a realist on the body mind problem Ryle edit Main article Gilbert Ryle With his 1949 book The Concept of Mind Gilbert Ryle was seen to have put the final nail in the coffin of Cartesian dualism 69 In the chapter Descartes Myth Ryle introduces the dogma of the Ghost in the machine to describe the philosophical concept of the mind as an entity separate from the body I hope to prove that it is entirely false and false not in detail but in principle It is not merely an assemblage of particular mistakes It is one big mistake and a mistake of a special kind It is namely a category mistake Searle edit Main article John Searle For Searle b 1932 the mind body problem is a false dichotomy that is mind is a perfectly ordinary aspect of the brain Searle proposed Biological naturalism in 1980 According to Searle then there is no more a mind body problem than there is a macro micro economics problem They are different levels of description of the same set of phenomena But Searle is careful to maintain that the mental the domain of qualitative experience and understanding is autonomous and has no counterpart on the microlevel any redescription of these macroscopic features amounts to a kind of evisceration 70 Joshua Rust John SearleSee also editBodymind Chinese room Cognitive closure philosophy Cognitive neuroscience Connectionism Consciousness in animals Downward causation Descartes Error Embodied cognition Existentialism Explanatory gap Free will Ideasthesia Namarupa Buddhist concept Neuroscience of free will Philosophical zombie Philosophy of artificial intelligence Pluralism Problem of other minds Reductionism Sacred profane dichotomy Sentience Strange loop self reflective thoughts The Mind s I book on the subject Turing test Vertiginous question William H PoteatReferences edit Dualism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2020 Georgiev Danko D 2020 Quantum information theoretic approach to the mind brain problem Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 158 16 32 arXiv 2012 07836 doi 10 1016 j pbiomolbio 2020 08 002 PMID 32822698 S2CID 221237249 The mind brain problem is to explain how the unobservable conscious mind and the observable brain relate to each other do they interact or does one unilaterally generate the other Robb David Heil John 2009 Mental Causation In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2009 ed Georg Northoff 2004 Philosophy of the Brain The Brain Problem Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research ed John Benjamins Publishing pp 137 139 ISBN 978 1588114174 The restriction of causality to efficient causality lead to the neglect of goal orientation since it was no longer necessary within that framework Not considering goal orientation resulted in the neglect of embedment and the consequential presupposition of isolation with separation between brain body and environment Neglecting embedment lead to the equation of perception action with sensory impression movement which could be well accounted for by efficient causality Accordingly since dominated by efficient causality qualia and intentionality as related to perception action rather than to sensory impression movement were excluded from science and consequently regarded as purely philosophical problems Analogous to final causes formal causes were eliminated as well Efficient causality is not compatible with embedded coding which is necessarily tied with formal causality and final causality Finally the possibility of mental causation remains incompatible with efficient causality It can however be properly described by formal and final causality Walter J Freeman 2009 Consciousness intentionality and causality In Susan Pockett WP Banks Shaun Gallagher eds Does Consciousness Cause Behavior MIT Press pp 4 5 88 90 ISBN 978 0262512572 Eric R Kandel 2007 In Search of Memory The Emergence of a New Science of Mind WW Norton p 9 ISBN 978 0393329377 Oswald Hanfling 2002 Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life Psychology Press pp 108 109 ISBN 978 0415256452 A term attributed to David Chalmers by Eugene O Mills 1999 Giving up on the hard problem of consciousness In Jonathan Shear ed Explaining Consciousness The Hard Problem MIT Press p 109 ISBN 978 0262692212 Goldenberg Georg 2008 Chapter 7 How the Mind Moves the Body Lessons From Apraxia In Morsella E Bargh J A Gollwitzer P M eds Oxford Handbook of Human Action Social Cognition and Social Neuroscience Oxford University Press USA p 136 ISBN 9780195309980 LCCN 2008004997 Gilder L 2009 The Age of Entanglement When Quantum Physics was Reborn Vintage Books ISBN 978 1 4000 9526 1 Retrieved November 11 2021 Christof Koch 2004 Figure 1 1 Neuronal correlates of consciousness The Quest for Consciousness A Neurobiological Approach Englewood Colorado Roberts amp Company Publishers p 16 ISBN 978 0974707709 Christof Koch 2004 Chapter 5 What are the neuronal correlates of consciousness The Quest for Consciousness A Neurobiological Approach Englewood Colorado Roberts amp Company Publishers pp xvi 97 104 ISBN 978 0974707709 See here Archived 2013 03 13 at the Wayback Machine for a glossary of related terms Kandel Eric R 2007 In search of memory The emergence of a new science of mind W W Norton amp Company p 382 ISBN 978 0393329377 Churchland Patricia Smith 2002 Brain Wise Studies in Neurophilosophy Bradford Books MIT Press ISBN 9780262532006 LCCN 2002066024 Churchland Patricia Smith 1989 Neurophilosophy Toward a Unified Science of the Mind Brain Computational Models of Cognition and Perception MIT Press ISBN 9780262530859 LCCN 85023706 Churchland Paul 2007 Neurophilosophy at Work Cambridge University Press pp viii ix ISBN 9780521864725 LCCN 2006014487 Dennett Daniel C 1986 Content and Consciousness International Library of Philosophy Taylor amp Francis ISBN 9780415104319 LCCN 72436737 Dennett Daniel C 1997 Kinds of Minds Toward an Understanding of Consciousness Science Masters Series Basic Books ISBN 9780465073511 LCCN 96164655 Squire Larry R 2008 Fundamental neuroscience 3rd ed Academic Press p 1223 ISBN 978 0 12 374019 9 Adamantidis A R Zhang F Aravanis A M Deisseroth K de Lecea L 2007 Neural substrates of awakening probed with optogenetic control of hypocretin neurons Nature 450 7168 420 4 Bibcode 2007Natur 450 420A doi 10 1038 nature06310 PMC 6744371 PMID 17943086 Christof Koch 2004 Figure 5 1 The Cholinergic Enabling System The Quest for Consciousness A Neurobiological Approach Englewood Colorado Roberts amp Company Publishers p 91 ISBN 978 0974707709 Also see Chapter 5 available on line Zeman A 2001 Consciousness Brain 124 7 1263 1289 doi 10 1093 brain 124 7 1263 PMID 11408323 Schiff Nicholas D November 2004 The neurology of impaired consciousness Challenges for cognitive neuroscience in Gazzaniga Michael S ed The Cognitive Neurosciences 3rd ed MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 07254 0 Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Parallelism Psychophysical Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 20 11th ed Cambridge University Press p 762 K Marx A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy Progress Publishers Moscow 1977 with some notes by R Rojas Bryan S Turner 2008 The Body and Society Explorations in Social Theory 3rd ed Sage Publications p 78 ISBN 978 1412929875 a rejection of any dualism between mind and body and a consequent insistence on the argument that the body is never simply a physical object but always an embodiment of consciousness a b c d Karunamuni N D May 2015 The Five Aggregate Model of the Mind SAGE Open 5 2 215824401558386 doi 10 1177 2158244015583860 a b c d e f g h Hergenhahn Baldwin R 2009 An Introduction to the History of Psychology Sixth Edition Belmont CA Cengage Learning p 18 ISBN 978 0 495 50621 8 Hergenhahn Baldwin R 2009 An Introduction to the History of Psychology Sixth Edition Belmont CA Cengage Learning pp 121 122 ISBN 978 0 495 50621 8 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Interactionism Philosophy Encyclopaedia Britannica Online Retrieved 17 July 2020 Popper Karl R 1977 The self and its brain an argument for interactionism Springer International ISBN 0 415 05898 8 OCLC 180195035 Eccles John C 1994 The Self and Its Brain The Ultimate Synthesis How the SELF Controls Its BRAIN Berlin Heidelberg Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 167 183 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 49224 2 10 ISBN 978 3 642 49226 6 Kim Jaegwan 1995 Emergent properties In Honderich Ted ed Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press p 240 ISBN 9780198661320 Pinel J 2009 Psychobiology 7th ed Pearson Allyn and Bacon ISBN 978 0205548927 LeDoux J 2002 The Synaptic Self How Our Brains Become Who We Are Viking Penguin ISBN 978 88 7078 795 5 Russell S amp Norvig P 2010 Artificial Intelligence A Modern Approach 3rd ed Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0136042594 Dawkins R 2006 The Selfish Gene 3rd ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0199291144 Walter Sven Epiphenomenalism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy University of Bielefeld Retrieved 17 July 2020 Broad C D 2014 06 03 The Mind and its Place in Nature doi 10 4324 9781315824147 ISBN 9781315824147 Hergenhahn Baldwin R 2013 An Introduction to the History of Psychology Seventh Edition Cengage Learning pp 240 241 ISBN 978 1 133 95809 3 Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm 2016 La Monadologie BnF P ISBN 978 2 346 03192 4 OCLC 1041048644 Hergenhahn Baldwin R 2009 An Introduction to the History of Psychology Sixth Edition Belmont CA Cengage Learning pp 186 188 ISBN 978 0 495 50621 8 Leibniz Philosophischen Schriften hrsg C Gerhardt Bd VI 539 546 and also the New Essays Porter Burton 2010 What the Tortoise Taught Us The Story of Philosophy Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers p 133 Cuttingham John June 1 2013 II John Cottingham Descartes and Darwin Reflections on the Sixth Meditation pdf Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume Oxford University Press 87 1 268 doi 10 1111 j 1467 8349 2013 00229 x ISSN 0309 7013 OCLC 5884450451 Retrieved April 30 2021 a b Hergenhahn Baldwin R 2009 An Introduction to the History of Psychology Sixth Edition Belmont CA Cengage Learning p 185 ISBN 978 0 495 50621 8 Robert M Young 1996 The mind body problem In RC Olby GN Cantor JR Christie MJS Hodges eds Companion to the History of Modern Science Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 ed Taylor and Francis pp 702 11 ISBN 978 0415145787 Archived from the original on 2007 06 14 Robinson Howard Nov 3 2011 Dualism In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2011 Edition Henrik Lagerlund 2010 Introduction In Henrik Lagerlund ed Forming the Mind Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment Paperback reprint of 2007 ed Springer Science Business Media p 3 ISBN 978 9048175307 Nalakalapiyo Sutta Sheaves of Reeds Archived 2016 05 03 at the Wayback Machine Rohitassa Sutta To Rohitassa Archived 2011 05 12 at the Wayback Machine The Five Aggregates A Study Guide Archived 2002 09 17 at the Wayback Machine Sabbasava Sutta All the Fermentations Archived 2006 06 25 at the Wayback Machine Nelson Alan ed 2005 A Companion to Rationalism Oxford UK Blackwell Publishing Ltd pp xiv xvi doi 10 1111 b 9781405109093 2005 00003 x ISBN 978 1 4051 0909 3 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a Missing or empty title help Gendlin 2012b p 121 122harvnb error no target CITEREFGendlin2012b help 432a1 2Hence the soul is as the hand is forthe hand is a tool of tools andthe nous is a form of forms ὥste ἡ psyxὴ ὥsper ἡ xeir ἐstin kaὶ gὰr h xeὶr ὄrganonἐstin ὀrganwn Aristotle now lets this aspect of nous and hand define a new term which he does not use anywhere else so far as I know The hand is a tool of tools The nous is a form of forms The hand and the soul are unique in this respect Let us see further what this means Aristotle seems to say that the nous is a form but on closer inspection we find that it is not or at least not the usual kind Nous is a maker of forms A form of forms is like a tool of tools like a living body s organ that makes tools Nous is certainly not itself the sort of form that it makes The hand is not a made tool it would have to be made by yet another hand In Greek tool and organ are the same word So we see In the phrase tool of tools the first use of the word stands for a living organ the second for an artificially made tool In II 4 he says all natural bodies are tools organs of the soul s both as food and as material from which to make tools In English we would say that the hand is the organ of tools Hicks 1907 p 542 431b230 432a14 To sum up the soul is in a manner the universe of things which is made up of things sensible and things intelligible and knowledge is in a manner identical with its object the intelligible sense with its object the sensible This statement calls for further explanation Sense and knowledge whether potential or actual are distributed over things potential or actual as the case may be In the soul again the sensitive faculty and the cognitive faculty are potentially their respective objects These objects must therefore exist in the soul not indeed as concrete wholes form and matter combined which is impossible it must be the forms of things which exist in the soul Thus within the soul intellect is the form of forms i e of intelligible forms and sense the form of sensibles precisely as in the body the hand is the instrument of instruments i e the instrument by which other instruments are acquired Shields Christopher Aristotle s Psychology In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2011 Edition McInerny Ralph O Callaghan John Summer 2018 Saint Thomas Aquinas The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 7 November 2018 Researchgate Galen and the tripartite soul Archived 2017 05 31 at the Wayback Machine Early Christian writings Galen Archived 2017 05 31 at the Wayback Machine Lokhorst Gert Jan Nov 5 2008 Descartes and the Pineal Gland In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition Lokhorst quotes Descartes in his Treatise of Man Lokhorst Gert Jan Nov 5 2008 Descartes and the Pineal Gland In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2011 Edition Lokhorst quotes Descartes in his Passions of the Soul Brook Andrew October 20 2008 Kant s View of the Mind and Consciousness of Self In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2011 Edition Eric Watkins 2004 Causality in context Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality Cambridge University Press p 108 ISBN 978 0521543613 Robinson William January 27 2011 Epiphenomenalism In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2012 Edition Vol 1 pp 539 547 doi 10 1002 wcs 19 PMID 26271501 S2CID 239938469 See e g Ronny Desmet and Michel Weber edited by Whitehead The Algebra of Metaphysics Applied Process Metaphysics Summer Institute Memorandum Archived 2017 07 27 at the Wayback Machine Louvain la Neuve Editions Chromatika 2010 ISBN 978 2 930517 08 7 Karl Raimund Popper 1999 Notes of a realist on the body mind problem All Life is Problem Solving A lecture given in Mannheim 8 May 1972 ed Psychology Press pp 29 ff ISBN 978 0415174862 The body mind relationship includes the problem of man s position in the physical world World 1 The world of conscious human processes I shall call World 2 and the world of the objective creations of the human mind I shall call World 3 Tanney Julia December 18 2007 Gilbert Ryle Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved May 2 2021 Joshua Rust 2009 John Searle Continuum International Publishing Group pp 27 28 ISBN 978 0826497529 Bibliography editBunge Mario 2014 The Mind Body Problem A Psychobiological Approach Elsevier ISBN 978 1 4831 5012 3 Feigl Herbert 1958 The Mental and the Physical In Feigl Herbert Scriven Michael Maxwell Grover eds Concepts Theories and the Mind Body Problem Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol 2 Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press pp 370 457 Gendlin E T 2012 Line by Line translation on Aristotle s De Anima Books I and II PDF Gendlin E T 2012 Line by Line translation on Aristotle s De Anima Book III PDF Hicks R D 1907 Aristotle De Anima Cambridge University Press Kim J 1995 Mind Body Problem Oxford Companion to Philosophy Ted Honderich ed Oxford Oxford University Press Jaegwon Kim 2010 Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 162506 0 Massimini M Tononi G 2018 Sizing up Consciousness Towards an Objective Measure of the Capacity for Experience Oxford University Press Turner Bryan S 1996 The Body and Society Exploration in Social Theory External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Mind body problem nbsp Consciousness Studies at Wikibooks Plato s Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Robert M Young 1996 The mind body problem In RC Olby GN Cantor JR Christie MJS Hodges eds Companion to the History of Modern Science Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 ed Taylor and Francis pp 702 11 ISBN 978 0415145787 The Mind Body Problem BBC Radio 4 discussion with Anthony Grayling Julian Baggini amp Sue James In Our Time Jan 13 2005 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Mind body problem amp oldid 1177800252, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.