fbpx
Wikipedia

Political freedom

Political freedom (also known as political autonomy or political agency) is a central concept in history and political thought and one of the most important features of democratic societies.[1] Political freedom was described as freedom from oppression[2] or coercion,[3] the absence of disabling conditions for an individual and the fulfillment of enabling conditions,[4] or the absence of life conditions of compulsion, e.g. economic compulsion, in a society.[5] Although political freedom is often interpreted negatively as the freedom from unreasonable external constraints on action,[6] it can also refer to the positive exercise of rights, capacities and possibilities for action and the exercise of social or group rights.[7] The concept can also include freedom from internal constraints on political action or speech (e.g. social conformity, consistency, or inauthentic behaviour).[8] The concept of political freedom is closely connected with the concepts of civil liberties and human rights, which in democratic societies are usually afforded legal protection from the state.

Views edit

Various groups along the political spectrum hold different views about what they believe constitutes political freedom.

Left-wing political philosophy generally couples the notion of freedom with that of positive liberty or the enabling of a group or individual to determine their own life or realize their own potential. In this sense, freedom may include freedom from poverty, starvation, treatable disease, and oppression as well as freedom from force and coercion, from whomever they may issue.[citation needed]

According to neoliberal philosopher and economist Friedrich Hayek, the "socialist argument" defined "individual liberty" as " 'freedom from' obstacles". He argued that this definition only "confused" and obscured the aim of "securing individual freedom", because it permitted a possible "identification of freedom with power." The subsequent "collective power over circumstances" misappropriated "the physical 'ability to do what I want', the power to satisfy our wishes, or the extent of the choice of alternatives open to us." Hayek maintained that once any possible "identification of freedom with power is admitted," a "totalitarian state" coalesced where "liberty has been suppressed in the name of liberty."[9]

Social anarchists see negative and positive liberty as complementary concepts of freedom. Such a view of rights may require utilitarian trade-offs, such as sacrificing the right to the product of one's labor or freedom of association for less racial discrimination or more subsidies for housing. Social anarchists describe the negative liberty-centric view endorsed by capitalism as "selfish freedom".[10]

Anarcho-capitalists see negative rights as a consistent system. Ayn Rand described it as "a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man's freedom of action in a social context". To such libertarians, positive liberty is contradictory since so-called rights must be traded off against each other, debasing legitimate rights which by definition trump other moral considerations. Any alleged right which calls for an end result (e.g. housing, education, medical services and so on) produced by people is in effect a purported right to enslave others.[citation needed]

Political philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre theorized freedom in terms of our social interdependence with other people.[11]

Economist Milton Friedman argues in his book Capitalism and Freedom that there are two types of freedom, namely political freedom and economic freedom, and that without economic freedom there cannot be political freedom.[12]

In his article "Why the Market Subverts Democracy", Robin Hahnel takes issue with Friedman's concept of economic freedom, asserting that there will be infringements on the freedom of others whenever anyone exercises their own economic freedom. He argues that such infringements produce conflicts that are resolved through property rights systems, and therefore it is essential to decide what is a better or a worse property rights system, yet Friedman simply takes for granted the existing property rights and does not question them.[13]

Political philosopher Nikolas Kompridis posits that the pursuit of freedom in the modern era can be broadly divided into two motivating ideals, namely freedom as autonomy or independence and freedom as the ability to cooperatively initiate a new beginning.[14]

Political freedom has also been theorized in its opposition to and a condition of power relations, or the power of action upon actions, by Michel Foucault.[15] It has also been closely identified with certain kinds of artistic and cultural practice by Cornelius Castoriadis, Antonio Gramsci, Herbert Marcuse, Jacques Rancière and Theodor Adorno.

Environmentalists often argue that political freedoms should include some constraint on use of ecosystems. They maintain there is no such thing, for instance, as freedom to pollute or freedom to deforest given that such activities create negative externalities, which violates other groups' liberty to not be exposed to pollution. The popularity of SUVs, golf and urban sprawl has been used as evidence that some ideas of freedom and ecological conservation can clash. This leads at times to serious confrontations and clashes of values reflected in advertising campaigns, e.g. that of PETA regarding fur.[16]

John Dalberg-Acton stated: "The most certain test by which we judge whether a country is really free is the amount of security enjoyed by minorities."[17]

Gerald C. MacCallum Jr. spoke of a compromise between positive and negative freedoms, saying that an agent must have full autonomy over themselves. In this view, freedom is a triadic relationship because it is about three things, namely the agent, the constraints they need to be free from and the goal they are aspiring to.[18]

History edit

Hannah Arendt traces the conceptual origins of freedom to ancient Greek politics.[1] According to her study, the concept of freedom was historically inseparable from political action. Politics could only be practiced by those who had freed themselves from the necessities of life so that they could participate in the realm of political affairs. According to Arendt, the concept of freedom became associated with the Christian notion of freedom of the will, or inner freedom, around the 5th century CE and since then freedom as a form of political action has been neglected even though, as she says, freedom is "the raison d'être of politics".[19]

Arendt says that political freedom is historically opposed to sovereignty or will-power since in ancient Greece and Rome the concept of freedom was inseparable from performance and did not arise as a conflict between the will and the self. Similarly, the idea of freedom as freedom from politics is a notion that developed in modern times. This is opposed to the idea of freedom as the capacity to "begin anew", which Arendt sees as a corollary to the innate human condition of natality, or our nature as "new beginnings and hence beginners".[20]

In Arendt's view, political action is an interruption of automatic process, either natural or historical. The freedom to begin anew is thus an extension of "the freedom to call something into being which did not exist before, which was not given, not even as an object of cognition or imagination, and which therefore, strictly speaking, could not be known".[21]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b Hannah Arendt, "What is Freedom?", Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought, (New York: Penguin, 1993).
  2. ^ Iris Marion Young, "Five Faces of Oppression", Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton University press, 1990), 39–65.
  3. ^ Michael Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do? (Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2010).
  4. ^ Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (Anchor Books, 2000).
  5. ^ Karl Marx, "Alienated Labour" in Early Writings.
  6. ^ Isaiah Berlin, Liberty (Oxford 2004).
  7. ^ Charles Taylor, "What's Wrong With Negative Liberty?", Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers (Cambridge, 1985), 211–229.
  8. ^ Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Self-Reliance 2011-03-23 at the Wayback Machine"; Nikolas Kompridis, "Struggling Over the Meaning of Recognition: A Matter of Identity, Justice or Freedom?" in European Journal of Political Theory July 2007 vol. 6 no. 3 pp. 277–289.
  9. ^ Friedrich August von Hayek, "Freedom and Coercion" in David Miller (ed), Liberty (1991) pp. 80, 85–86.
  10. ^ "Anarchism FAQ" 2019-10-06 at the Wayback Machine.
  11. ^ Alasdair MacIntyre, "The Virtues of Acknowledged Dependence", Rational Dependent Animals: Why Humans Need the Virtues (Open Court, 2001).
  12. ^ Friedman, Milton (1962). Capitalism and Freedom. University of Chicago Press.
  13. ^ Hahnel, R. (2009-03-01). "Why the Market Subverts Democracy". American Behavioral Scientist. 52 (7): 1006–1022. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.563.8688. doi:10.1177/0002764208327672. S2CID 56576412.
  14. ^ Nikolas Kompridis, "The Idea of a New Beginning: A Romantic Source of Normativity and Freedom" in Philosophical Romanticism (New York: Routledge, 2007), 32–59.
  15. ^ Michel Foucault, "The Subject and Power" in Paul Rabinow and Nikolas S. Rose, eds., The Essential Foucault.
  16. ^ "Fur Challenge: Unzip That Collar and Expose Cruelty | Action". PETA.org. 2016-02-09. from the original on 2022-08-30. Retrieved 2022-08-31.
  17. ^ Acton, John D. (1907). The History of Freedom and Other Essays. London: Macmillan. p. 4.
  18. ^ MacCallum, Gerald (July 1967). "Negative and Positive Freedom" (PDF). The Philosophical Review. 73 (3). (PDF) from the original on 2011-01-25.
  19. ^ Hannah Arendt, "What is Freedom?", Between Past and Future: Eight exercises in political thought (New York: Penguin, 1993).
  20. ^ Hannah, Arendt (1965). On revolution (Reprinted ed.). London: Penguin Books. pp. 211. ISBN 9780140184211. OCLC 25458723.
  21. ^ Hannah Arendt, "What is Freedom?", p. 151.

External links edit

  • Alberto Abadie (October 2004). (PDF). Harvard University and NBER.
  • "Brief review of trends in political change: freedom and conflict".
  • "Freedom: The Great Gift of the West".

political, freedom, freedoms, redirects, here, other, uses, freedom, also, known, political, autonomy, political, agency, central, concept, history, political, thought, most, important, features, democratic, societies, described, freedom, from, oppression, coe. Freedoms redirects here For other uses see Freedom Political freedom also known as political autonomy or political agency is a central concept in history and political thought and one of the most important features of democratic societies 1 Political freedom was described as freedom from oppression 2 or coercion 3 the absence of disabling conditions for an individual and the fulfillment of enabling conditions 4 or the absence of life conditions of compulsion e g economic compulsion in a society 5 Although political freedom is often interpreted negatively as the freedom from unreasonable external constraints on action 6 it can also refer to the positive exercise of rights capacities and possibilities for action and the exercise of social or group rights 7 The concept can also include freedom from internal constraints on political action or speech e g social conformity consistency or inauthentic behaviour 8 The concept of political freedom is closely connected with the concepts of civil liberties and human rights which in democratic societies are usually afforded legal protection from the state Contents 1 Views 2 History 3 See also 4 Notes 5 External linksViews editVarious groups along the political spectrum hold different views about what they believe constitutes political freedom Left wing political philosophy generally couples the notion of freedom with that of positive liberty or the enabling of a group or individual to determine their own life or realize their own potential In this sense freedom may include freedom from poverty starvation treatable disease and oppression as well as freedom from force and coercion from whomever they may issue citation needed According to neoliberal philosopher and economist Friedrich Hayek the socialist argument defined individual liberty as freedom from obstacles He argued that this definition only confused and obscured the aim of securing individual freedom because it permitted a possible identification of freedom with power The subsequent collective power over circumstances misappropriated the physical ability to do what I want the power to satisfy our wishes or the extent of the choice of alternatives open to us Hayek maintained that once any possible identification of freedom with power is admitted a totalitarian state coalesced where liberty has been suppressed in the name of liberty 9 Social anarchists see negative and positive liberty as complementary concepts of freedom Such a view of rights may require utilitarian trade offs such as sacrificing the right to the product of one s labor or freedom of association for less racial discrimination or more subsidies for housing Social anarchists describe the negative liberty centric view endorsed by capitalism as selfish freedom 10 Anarcho capitalists see negative rights as a consistent system Ayn Rand described it as a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man s freedom of action in a social context To such libertarians positive liberty is contradictory since so called rights must be traded off against each other debasing legitimate rights which by definition trump other moral considerations Any alleged right which calls for an end result e g housing education medical services and so on produced by people is in effect a purported right to enslave others citation needed Political philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre theorized freedom in terms of our social interdependence with other people 11 Economist Milton Friedman argues in his book Capitalism and Freedom that there are two types of freedom namely political freedom and economic freedom and that without economic freedom there cannot be political freedom 12 In his article Why the Market Subverts Democracy Robin Hahnel takes issue with Friedman s concept of economic freedom asserting that there will be infringements on the freedom of others whenever anyone exercises their own economic freedom He argues that such infringements produce conflicts that are resolved through property rights systems and therefore it is essential to decide what is a better or a worse property rights system yet Friedman simply takes for granted the existing property rights and does not question them 13 Political philosopher Nikolas Kompridis posits that the pursuit of freedom in the modern era can be broadly divided into two motivating ideals namely freedom as autonomy or independence and freedom as the ability to cooperatively initiate a new beginning 14 Political freedom has also been theorized in its opposition to and a condition of power relations or the power of action upon actions by Michel Foucault 15 It has also been closely identified with certain kinds of artistic and cultural practice by Cornelius Castoriadis Antonio Gramsci Herbert Marcuse Jacques Ranciere and Theodor Adorno Environmentalists often argue that political freedoms should include some constraint on use of ecosystems They maintain there is no such thing for instance as freedom to pollute or freedom to deforest given that such activities create negative externalities which violates other groups liberty to not be exposed to pollution The popularity of SUVs golf and urban sprawl has been used as evidence that some ideas of freedom and ecological conservation can clash This leads at times to serious confrontations and clashes of values reflected in advertising campaigns e g that of PETA regarding fur 16 John Dalberg Acton stated The most certain test by which we judge whether a country is really free is the amount of security enjoyed by minorities 17 Gerald C MacCallum Jr spoke of a compromise between positive and negative freedoms saying that an agent must have full autonomy over themselves In this view freedom is a triadic relationship because it is about three things namely the agent the constraints they need to be free from and the goal they are aspiring to 18 History editHannah Arendt traces the conceptual origins of freedom to ancient Greek politics 1 According to her study the concept of freedom was historically inseparable from political action Politics could only be practiced by those who had freed themselves from the necessities of life so that they could participate in the realm of political affairs According to Arendt the concept of freedom became associated with the Christian notion of freedom of the will or inner freedom around the 5th century CE and since then freedom as a form of political action has been neglected even though as she says freedom is the raison d etre of politics 19 Arendt says that political freedom is historically opposed to sovereignty or will power since in ancient Greece and Rome the concept of freedom was inseparable from performance and did not arise as a conflict between the will and the self Similarly the idea of freedom as freedom from politics is a notion that developed in modern times This is opposed to the idea of freedom as the capacity to begin anew which Arendt sees as a corollary to the innate human condition of natality or our nature as new beginnings and hence beginners 20 In Arendt s view political action is an interruption of automatic process either natural or historical The freedom to begin anew is thus an extension of the freedom to call something into being which did not exist before which was not given not even as an object of cognition or imagination and which therefore strictly speaking could not be known 21 See also editAcademic freedom Civil and political rights Decentralization Dissident Economic freedom Freedom from unreasonable searches and seizures which is related to freedom of privacy Freedom House Freedom of assembly Freedom of association Freedom of movement Freedom of religion Freedom of speech Freedom of the press Freedom of thought Global Social Change Research Project Libertarianism disambiguation List of indices of freedom Negative and positive rights Political equality Political prisoner Political repression Right to arms Scientific freedom Suffrage Two Treatises of GovernmentNotes edit a b Hannah Arendt What is Freedom Between Past and Future Eight Exercises in Political Thought New York Penguin 1993 Iris Marion Young Five Faces of Oppression Justice and the Politics of Difference Princeton University press 1990 39 65 Michael Sandel Justice What s the Right Thing to Do Farrar Straus and Giroux 2010 Amartya Sen Development as Freedom Anchor Books 2000 Karl Marx Alienated Labour in Early Writings Isaiah Berlin Liberty Oxford 2004 Charles Taylor What s Wrong With Negative Liberty Philosophy and the Human Sciences Philosophical Papers Cambridge 1985 211 229 Ralph Waldo Emerson Self Reliance Archived 2011 03 23 at the Wayback Machine Nikolas Kompridis Struggling Over the Meaning of Recognition A Matter of Identity Justice or Freedom in European Journal of Political Theory July 2007 vol 6 no 3 pp 277 289 Friedrich August von Hayek Freedom and Coercion in David Miller ed Liberty 1991 pp 80 85 86 Anarchism FAQ Archived 2019 10 06 at the Wayback Machine Alasdair MacIntyre The Virtues of Acknowledged Dependence Rational Dependent Animals Why Humans Need the Virtues Open Court 2001 Friedman Milton 1962 Capitalism and Freedom University of Chicago Press Hahnel R 2009 03 01 Why the Market Subverts Democracy American Behavioral Scientist 52 7 1006 1022 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 563 8688 doi 10 1177 0002764208327672 S2CID 56576412 Nikolas Kompridis The Idea of a New Beginning A Romantic Source of Normativity and Freedom in Philosophical Romanticism New York Routledge 2007 32 59 Michel Foucault The Subject and Power in Paul Rabinow and Nikolas S Rose eds The Essential Foucault Fur Challenge Unzip That Collar and Expose Cruelty Action PETA org 2016 02 09 Archived from the original on 2022 08 30 Retrieved 2022 08 31 Acton John D 1907 The History of Freedom and Other Essays London Macmillan p 4 MacCallum Gerald July 1967 Negative and Positive Freedom PDF The Philosophical Review 73 3 Archived PDF from the original on 2011 01 25 Hannah Arendt What is Freedom Between Past and Future Eight exercises in political thought New York Penguin 1993 Hannah Arendt 1965 On revolution Reprinted ed London Penguin Books pp 211 ISBN 9780140184211 OCLC 25458723 Hannah Arendt What is Freedom p 151 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Freedom Alberto Abadie October 2004 Poverty Political Freedom and the Roots of Terrorism PDF Harvard University and NBER Brief review of trends in political change freedom and conflict Freedom The Great Gift of the West Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Political freedom amp oldid 1183517951, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.