fbpx
Wikipedia

Peano axioms

In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (/piˈɑːn/,[1] [peˈaːno]), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly unchanged in a number of metamathematical investigations, including research into fundamental questions of whether number theory is consistent and complete.

The need to formalize arithmetic was not well appreciated until the work of Hermann Grassmann, who showed in the 1860s that many facts in arithmetic could be derived from more basic facts about the successor operation and induction.[2][3] In 1881, Charles Sanders Peirce provided an axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic.[4][5] In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic, and in 1889, Peano published a simplified version of them as a collection of axioms in his book The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method (Latin: Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita).

The nine Peano axioms contain three types of statements. The first axiom asserts the existence of at least one member of the set of natural numbers. The next four are general statements about equality; in modern treatments these are often not taken as part of the Peano axioms, but rather as axioms of the "underlying logic".[6] The next three axioms are first-order statements about natural numbers expressing the fundamental properties of the successor operation. The ninth, final axiom is a second-order statement of the principle of mathematical induction over the natural numbers, which makes this formulation close to second-order arithmetic. A weaker first-order system called Peano arithmetic is obtained by explicitly adding the addition and multiplication operation symbols and replacing the second-order induction axiom with a first-order axiom schema.

Historical second-order formulation Edit

When Peano formulated his axioms, the language of mathematical logic was in its infancy. The system of logical notation he created to present the axioms did not prove to be popular, although it was the genesis of the modern notation for set membership (∈, which comes from Peano's ε) and implication (⊃, which comes from Peano's reversed 'C'.) Peano maintained a clear distinction between mathematical and logical symbols, which was not yet common in mathematics; such a separation had first been introduced in the Begriffsschrift by Gottlob Frege, published in 1879.[7] Peano was unaware of Frege's work and independently recreated his logical apparatus based on the work of Boole and Schröder.[8]

The Peano axioms define the arithmetical properties of natural numbers, usually represented as a set N or   The non-logical symbols for the axioms consist of a constant symbol 0 and a unary function symbol S.

The first axiom states that the constant 0 is a natural number:

  1. 0 is a natural number.

Peano's original formulation of the axioms used 1 instead of 0 as the "first" natural number,[9] while the axioms in Formulario mathematico include zero.[10]

The next four axioms describe the equality relation. Since they are logically valid in first-order logic with equality, they are not considered to be part of "the Peano axioms" in modern treatments.[8]

  1. For every natural number x, x = x. That is, equality is reflexive.
  2. For all natural numbers x and y, if x = y, then y = x. That is, equality is symmetric.
  3. For all natural numbers x, y and z, if x = y and y = z, then x = z. That is, equality is transitive.
  4. For all a and b, if b is a natural number and a = b, then a is also a natural number. That is, the natural numbers are closed under equality.

The remaining axioms define the arithmetical properties of the natural numbers. The naturals are assumed to be closed under a single-valued "successor" function S.

  1. For every natural number n, S(n) is a natural number. That is, the natural numbers are closed under S.
  2. For all natural numbers m and n, if S(m) = S(n), then m = n. That is, S is an injection.
  3. For every natural number n, S(n) = 0 is false. That is, there is no natural number whose successor is 0.
 
The chain of light dominoes, starting with the nearest, can represent N,[11][12] however, axioms 1–8 are also satisfied by the set of all light and dark dominoes.[note 1] The 9th axiom (induction) limits N to the chain of light pieces ("no junk") as only light dominoes will fall when the nearest is toppled. [13]

Axioms 1, 6, 7, 8 define a unary representation of the intuitive notion of natural numbers: the number 1 can be defined as S(0), 2 as S(S(0)), etc. However, considering the notion of natural numbers as being defined by these axioms, axioms 1, 6, 7, 8 do not imply that the successor function generates all the natural numbers different from 0.

The intuitive notion that each natural number can be obtained by applying successor sufficiently often to zero requires an additional axiom, which is sometimes called the axiom of induction.

  1. If K is a set such that:
    • 0 is in K, and
    • for every natural number n, n being in K implies that S(n) is in K,
    then K contains every natural number.

The induction axiom is sometimes stated in the following form:

  1. If φ is a unary predicate such that:
    • φ(0) is true, and
    • for every natural number n, φ(n) being true implies that φ(S(n)) is true,
    then φ(n) is true for every natural number n.

In Peano's original formulation, the induction axiom is a second-order axiom. It is now common to replace this second-order principle with a weaker first-order induction scheme. There are important differences between the second-order and first-order formulations, as discussed in the section § Peano arithmetic as first-order theory below.

Defining arithmetic operations and relations Edit

If we use the second-order induction axiom, it is possible to define addition, multiplication, and total (linear) ordering on N directly using the axioms. However, with first-order induction, this is not possible[citation needed] and addition and multiplication are often added as axioms. The respective functions and relations are constructed in set theory or second-order logic, and can be shown to be unique using the Peano axioms.

Addition Edit

Addition is a function that maps two natural numbers (two elements of N) to another one. It is defined recursively as:

 

For example:

 

The structure (N, +) is a commutative monoid with identity element 0. (N, +) is also a cancellative magma, and thus embeddable in a group. The smallest group embedding N is the integers.

Multiplication Edit

Similarly, multiplication is a function mapping two natural numbers to another one. Given addition, it is defined recursively as:

 

It is easy to see that   (or "1", in the familiar language of decimal representation) is the multiplicative right identity:

 

To show that   is also the multiplicative left identity requires the induction axiom due to the way multiplication is defined:

  •   is the left identity of 0:  .
  • If   is the left identity of   (that is  ), then   is also the left identity of  :  .

Therefore, by the induction axiom   is the multiplicative left identity of all natural numbers. Moreover, it can be shown that multiplication is commutative and distributes over addition:

 .

Thus,   is a commutative semiring.

Inequalities Edit

The usual total order relation ≤ on natural numbers can be defined as follows, assuming 0 is a natural number:

For all a, bN, ab if and only if there exists some cN such that a + c = b.

This relation is stable under addition and multiplication: for  , if ab, then:

  • a + cb + c, and
  • a · cb · c.

Thus, the structure (N, +, ·, 1, 0, ≤) is an ordered semiring; because there is no natural number between 0 and 1, it is a discrete ordered semiring.

The axiom of induction is sometimes stated in the following form that uses a stronger hypothesis, making use of the order relation "≤":

For any predicate φ, if
  • φ(0) is true, and
  • for every nN, if φ(k) is true for every kN such that kn, then φ(S(n)) is true,
  • then for every nN, φ(n) is true.

This form of the induction axiom, called strong induction, is a consequence of the standard formulation, but is often better suited for reasoning about the ≤ order. For example, to show that the naturals are well-ordered—every nonempty subset of N has a least element—one can reason as follows. Let a nonempty XN be given and assume X has no least element.

  • Because 0 is the least element of N, it must be that 0 ∉ X.
  • For any nN, suppose for every kn, kX. Then S(n) ∉ X, for otherwise it would be the least element of X.

Thus, by the strong induction principle, for every nN, nX. Thus, XN = ∅, which contradicts X being a nonempty subset of N. Thus X has a least element.

Models Edit

A model of the Peano axioms is a triple (N, 0, S), where N is a (necessarily infinite) set, 0 ∈ N and S: NN satisfies the axioms above. Dedekind proved in his 1888 book, The Nature and Meaning of Numbers (German: Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?, i.e., “What are the numbers and what are they good for?”) that any two models of the Peano axioms (including the second-order induction axiom) are isomorphic. In particular, given two models (NA, 0A, SA) and (NB, 0B, SB) of the Peano axioms, there is a unique homomorphism f : NANB satisfying

 

and it is a bijection. This means that the second-order Peano axioms are categorical. (This is not the case with any first-order reformulation of the Peano axioms, below.)

Set-theoretic models Edit

The Peano axioms can be derived from set theoretic constructions of the natural numbers and axioms of set theory such as ZF.[14] The standard construction of the naturals, due to John von Neumann, starts from a definition of 0 as the empty set, ∅, and an operator s on sets defined as:

 

The set of natural numbers N is defined as the intersection of all sets closed under s that contain the empty set. Each natural number is equal (as a set) to the set of natural numbers less than it:

 

and so on. The set N together with 0 and the successor function s : NN satisfies the Peano axioms.

Peano arithmetic is equiconsistent with several weak systems of set theory.[15] One such system is ZFC with the axiom of infinity replaced by its negation. Another such system consists of general set theory (extensionality, existence of the empty set, and the axiom of adjunction), augmented by an axiom schema stating that a property that holds for the empty set and holds of an adjunction whenever it holds of the adjunct must hold for all sets.

Interpretation in category theory Edit

The Peano axioms can also be understood using category theory. Let C be a category with terminal object 1C, and define the category of pointed unary systems, US1(C) as follows:

  • The objects of US1(C) are triples (X, 0X, SX) where X is an object of C, and 0X : 1CX and SX : XX are C-morphisms.
  • A morphism φ : (X, 0X, SX) → (Y, 0Y, SY) is a C-morphism φ : XY with φ 0X = 0Y and φ SX = SY φ.

Then C is said to satisfy the Dedekind–Peano axioms if US1(C) has an initial object; this initial object is known as a natural number object in C. If (N, 0, S) is this initial object, and (X, 0X, SX) is any other object, then the unique map u : (N, 0, S) → (X, 0X, SX) is such that

 

This is precisely the recursive definition of 0X and SX.

Consistency Edit

When the Peano axioms were first proposed, Bertrand Russell and others agreed that these axioms implicitly defined what we mean by a "natural number".[16] Henri Poincaré was more cautious, saying they only defined natural numbers if they were consistent; if there is a proof that starts from just these axioms and derives a contradiction such as 0 = 1, then the axioms are inconsistent, and don't define anything.[17] In 1900, David Hilbert posed the problem of proving their consistency using only finitistic methods as the second of his twenty-three problems.[18] In 1931, Kurt Gödel proved his second incompleteness theorem, which shows that such a consistency proof cannot be formalized within Peano arithmetic itself.[19]

Although it is widely claimed that Gödel's theorem rules out the possibility of a finitistic consistency proof for Peano arithmetic, this depends on exactly what one means by a finitistic proof. Gödel himself pointed out the possibility of giving a finitistic consistency proof of Peano arithmetic or stronger systems by using finitistic methods that are not formalizable in Peano arithmetic, and in 1958, Gödel published a method for proving the consistency of arithmetic using type theory.[20] In 1936, Gerhard Gentzen gave a proof of the consistency of Peano's axioms, using transfinite induction up to an ordinal called ε0.[21] Gentzen explained: "The aim of the present paper is to prove the consistency of elementary number theory or, rather, to reduce the question of consistency to certain fundamental principles". Gentzen's proof is arguably finitistic, since the transfinite ordinal ε0 can be encoded in terms of finite objects (for example, as a Turing machine describing a suitable order on the integers, or more abstractly as consisting of the finite trees, suitably linearly ordered). Whether or not Gentzen's proof meets the requirements Hilbert envisioned is unclear: there is no generally accepted definition of exactly what is meant by a finitistic proof, and Hilbert himself never gave a precise definition.

The vast majority of contemporary mathematicians believe that Peano's axioms are consistent, relying either on intuition or the acceptance of a consistency proof such as Gentzen's proof. A small number of philosophers and mathematicians, some of whom also advocate ultrafinitism, reject Peano's axioms because accepting the axioms amounts to accepting the infinite collection of natural numbers. In particular, addition (including the successor function) and multiplication are assumed to be total. Curiously, there are self-verifying theories that are similar to PA but have subtraction and division instead of addition and multiplication, which are axiomatized in such a way to avoid proving sentences that correspond to the totality of addition and multiplication, but which are still able to prove all true   theorems of PA, and yet can be extended to a consistent theory that proves its own consistency (stated as the non-existence of a Hilbert-style proof of "0=1").[22]

Peano arithmetic as first-order theory Edit

All of the Peano axioms except the ninth axiom (the induction axiom) are statements in first-order logic.[23] The arithmetical operations of addition and multiplication and the order relation can also be defined using first-order axioms. The axiom of induction above is second-order, since it quantifies over predicates (equivalently, sets of natural numbers rather than natural numbers). As an alternative one can consider a first-order axiom schema of induction. Such a schema includes one axiom per predicate definable in the first-order language of Peano arithmetic, making it weaker than the second-order axiom.[24] The reason that it is weaker is that the number of predicates in first-order language is countable, whereas the number of sets of natural numbers is uncountable. Thus, there exist sets that cannot be described in first-order language (in fact, most sets have this property).

First-order axiomatizations of Peano arithmetic have another technical limitation. In second-order logic, it is possible to define the addition and multiplication operations from the successor operation, but this cannot be done in the more restrictive setting of first-order logic. Therefore, the addition and multiplication operations are directly included in the signature of Peano arithmetic, and axioms are included that relate the three operations to each other.

The following list of axioms (along with the usual axioms of equality), which contains six of the seven axioms of Robinson arithmetic, is sufficient for this purpose:[25]

  •  
  •  
  •  
  •  
  •  
  •  

In addition to this list of numerical axioms, Peano arithmetic contains the induction schema, which consists of a recursively enumerable and even decidable set of axioms. For each formula φ(x, y1, ..., yk) in the language of Peano arithmetic, the first-order induction axiom for φ is the sentence

 

where   is an abbreviation for y1,...,yk. The first-order induction schema includes every instance of the first-order induction axiom; that is, it includes the induction axiom for every formula φ.

Equivalent axiomatizations Edit

The above axiomatization of Peano arithmetic uses a signature that only has symbols for zero as well as the successor, addition, and multiplications operations. There are many other different, but equivalent, axiomatizations. One such alternative[26] uses an order relation symbol instead of the successor operation and the language of discretely ordered semirings (axioms 1-7 for semirings, 8-10 on order, 11-13 regarding compatibility, and 14-15 for discreteness):

  1.  , i.e., addition is associative.
  2.  , i.e., addition is commutative.
  3.  , i.e., multiplication is associative.
  4.  , i.e., multiplication is commutative.
  5.  , i.e., multiplication distributes over addition.
  6.  , i.e., zero is an identity for addition, and an absorbing element for multiplication (actually superfluous[note 2]).
  7.  , i.e., one is an identity for multiplication.
  8.  , i.e., the '<' operator is transitive.
  9.  , i.e., the '<' operator is irreflexive.
  10.  , i.e., the ordering satisfies trichotomy.
  11.  , i.e. the ordering is preserved under addition of the same element.
  12.  , i.e. the ordering is preserved under multiplication by the same positive element.
  13.  , i.e. given any two distinct elements, the larger is the smaller plus another element.
  14.  , i.e. zero and one are distinct and there is no element between them. In other words, 0 is covered by 1, which suggests that these numbers are discrete.
  15.  , i.e. zero is the minimum element.

The theory defined by these axioms is known as PA. It is also incomplete and one of its important properties is that any structure   satisfying this theory has an initial segment (ordered by  ) isomorphic to  . Elements in that segment are called standard elements, while other elements are called nonstandard elements.

Finally, Peano arithmetic PA is obtained by adding the first-order induction schema.

Undecidability and incompleteness Edit

According to Gödel's incompleteness theorems, the theory of PA (if consistent) is incomplete. Consequently, there are sentences of first-order logic (FOL) that are true in the standard model of PA but are not a consequence of the FOL axiomatization. Essential incompleteness already arises for theories with weaker axioms, such as Robinson arithmetic.

Closely related to the above incompleteness result (via Gödel's completeness theorem for FOL) it follows that there is no algorithm for deciding whether a given FOL sentence is a consequence of a first-order axiomatization of Peano arithmetic or not. Hence, PA is an example of an undecidable theory. Undecidability arises already for the existential sentences of PA, due to the negative answer to Hilbert's tenth problem, whose proof implies that all computably enumerable sets are diophantine sets, and thus definable by existentially quantified formulas (with free variables) of PA. Formulas of PA with higher quantifier rank (more quantifier alternations) than existential formulas are more expressive, and define sets in the higher levels of the arithmetical hierarchy.

Nonstandard models Edit

Although the usual natural numbers satisfy the axioms of PA, there are other models as well (called "non-standard models"); the compactness theorem implies that the existence of nonstandard elements cannot be excluded in first-order logic.[27] The upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem shows that there are nonstandard models of PA of all infinite cardinalities. This is not the case for the original (second-order) Peano axioms, which have only one model, up to isomorphism.[28] This illustrates one way the first-order system PA is weaker than the second-order Peano axioms.

When interpreted as a proof within a first-order set theory, such as ZFC, Dedekind's categoricity proof for PA shows that each model of set theory has a unique model of the Peano axioms, up to isomorphism, that embeds as an initial segment of all other models of PA contained within that model of set theory. In the standard model of set theory, this smallest model of PA is the standard model of PA; however, in a nonstandard model of set theory, it may be a nonstandard model of PA. This situation cannot be avoided with any first-order formalization of set theory.

It is natural to ask whether a countable nonstandard model can be explicitly constructed. The answer is affirmative as Skolem in 1933 provided an explicit construction of such a nonstandard model. On the other hand, Tennenbaum's theorem, proved in 1959, shows that there is no countable nonstandard model of PA in which either the addition or multiplication operation is computable.[29] This result shows it is difficult to be completely explicit in describing the addition and multiplication operations of a countable nonstandard model of PA. There is only one possible order type of a countable nonstandard model. Letting ω be the order type of the natural numbers, ζ be the order type of the integers, and η be the order type of the rationals, the order type of any countable nonstandard model of PA is ω + ζ·η, which can be visualized as a copy of the natural numbers followed by a dense linear ordering of copies of the integers.

Overspill Edit

A cut in a nonstandard model M is a nonempty subset C of M so that C is downward closed (x < y and yCxC) and C is closed under successor. A proper cut is a cut that is a proper subset of M. Each nonstandard model has many proper cuts, including one that corresponds to the standard natural numbers. However, the induction scheme in Peano arithmetic prevents any proper cut from being definable. The overspill lemma, first proved by Abraham Robinson, formalizes this fact.

Overspill lemma[30] — Let M be a nonstandard model of PA and let C be a proper cut of M. Suppose that   is a tuple of elements of M and   is a formula in the language of arithmetic so that

  for all bC.

Then there is a c in M that is greater than every element of C such that

 

See also Edit

Notes Edit

  1. ^ The non-contiguous set satisfies axiom 1 as it has a 0 element, 2–5 as it doesn't affect equality relations, 6 & 8 as all pieces have a successor, bar the zero element and axiom 7 as no two dominos topple, or are toppled by, the same piece.
  2. ^ " " can be proven from the other axioms (in first-order logic) as follows. Firstly,   by distributivity and additive identity. Secondly,   by Axiom 15. If   then   by addition of the same element and commutativity, and hence   by substitution, contradicting irreflexivity. Therefore it must be that  .

References Edit

Citations Edit

  1. ^ "Peano". Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary.
  2. ^ Grassmann 1861.
  3. ^ Wang 1957, pp. 145, 147, "It is rather well-known, through Peano's own acknowledgement, that Peano […] made extensive use of Grassmann's work in his development of the axioms. It is not so well-known that Grassmann had essentially the characterization of the set of all integers, now customary in texts of modern algebra, that it forms an ordered integral domain in wihich each set of positive elements has a least member. […] [Grassmann's book] was probably the first serious and rather successful attempt to put numbers on a more or less axiomatic basis.".
  4. ^ Peirce 1881.
  5. ^ Shields 1997.
  6. ^ Van Heijenoort 1967, p. 94.
  7. ^ Van Heijenoort 1967, p. 2.
  8. ^ a b Van Heijenoort 1967, p. 83.
  9. ^ Peano 1889, p. 1.
  10. ^ Peano 1908, p. 27.
  11. ^ Matt DeVos, Mathematical Induction, Simon Fraser University
  12. ^ Gerardo con Diaz, Mathematical Induction 2 May 2013 at the Wayback Machine, Harvard University
  13. ^ Meseguer & Goguen 1986, sections 2.3 (p. 464) and 4.1 (p. 471).
  14. ^ Suppes 1960, Hatcher 2014
  15. ^ Tarski & Givant 1987, Section 7.6.
  16. ^ Fritz 1952, p. 137
    An illustration of 'interpretation' is Russell's own definition of 'cardinal number'. The uninterpreted system in this case is Peano's axioms for the number system, whose three primitive ideas and five axioms, Peano believed, were sufficient to enable one to derive all the properties of the system of natural numbers. Actually, Russell maintains, Peano's axioms define any progression of the form   of which the series of the natural numbers is one instance.
  17. ^ Gray 2013, p. 133
    So Poincaré turned to see whether logicism could generate arithmetic, more precisely, the arithmetic of ordinals. Couturat, said Poincaré, had accepted the Peano axioms as a definition of a number. But this will not do. The axioms cannot be shown to be free of contradiction by finding examples of them, and any attempt to show that they were contradiction-free by examining the totality of their implications would require the very principle of mathematical induction Couturat believed they implied. For (in a further passage dropped from S&M) either one assumed the principle in order to prove it, which would only prove that if it is true it is not self-contradictory, which says nothing; or one used the principle in another form than the one stated, in which case one must show that the number of steps in one's reasoning was an integer according to the new definition, but this could not be done (1905c, 834).
  18. ^ Hilbert 1902.
  19. ^ Gödel 1931.
  20. ^ Gödel 1958
  21. ^ Gentzen 1936
  22. ^ Willard 2001.
  23. ^ Partee, Ter Meulen & Wall 2012, p. 215.
  24. ^ Harsanyi (1983).
  25. ^ Mendelson 1997, p. 155.
  26. ^ Kaye 1991, pp. 16–18.
  27. ^ Hermes 1973, VI.4.3, presenting a theorem of Thoralf Skolem
  28. ^ Hermes 1973, VI.3.1.
  29. ^ Kaye 1991, Section 11.3.
  30. ^ Kaye 1991, pp. 70ff..

Sources Edit

  • Davis, Martin (1974). Computability. Notes by Barry Jacobs. Courant Institute of Mathematical Sciences, New York University.
  • Dedekind, Richard (1888). Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? [What are and what should the numbers be?] (PDF). Vieweg. Retrieved 4 July 2016.
  • Fritz, Charles A., Jr. (1952). Bertrand Russell's construction of the external world. New York, Humanities Press.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  • Gentzen, Gerhard (1936). Reprinted in English translation in his 1969 Collected works, M. E. Szabo, ed. "Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie". Mathematische Annalen. 112: 132–213. doi:10.1007/bf01565428. S2CID 122719892.
  • Harsanyi, John C. (1983). "Mathematics, the Empirical Facts, and Logical Necessity". In Hempel, Carl G.; Putnam, Hilary; Essler, Wilhelm K. (eds.). Methodology, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science. pp. 167–192. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-7676-5_8. ISBN 978-90-481-8389-0. S2CID 121297669.
  • Hermes, Hans (1973). Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Hochschultext. Springer. ISBN 3540058192. ISSN 1431-4657.
  • Hilbert, David (1902). Translated by Winton, Maby. "Mathematische Probleme" [Mathematical Problems]. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 8 (10): 437–479. doi:10.1090/s0002-9904-1902-00923-3.
  • Meseguer, José; Goguen, Joseph A. (Dec 1986). "Initiality, induction, and computability". In Maurice Nivat and John C. Reynolds (ed.). Algebraic Methods in Semantics (PDF). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 459–541. ISBN 9780521267939.
  • Peano, Giuseppe (1908). Formulario Mathematico (V ed.). Turin, Bocca frères, Ch. Clausen. p. 27.
  • Peirce, C. S. (1881). "On the Logic of Number". American Journal of Mathematics. 4 (1): 85–95. doi:10.2307/2369151. JSTOR 2369151. MR 1507856.
  • Shields, Paul (1997). "3. Peirce's Axiomatization of Arithmetic". In Houser, Nathan; Roberts, Don D.; Van Evra, James (eds.). Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Indiana University Press. pp. 43–52. ISBN 0-253-33020-3.
  • Van Heijenoort, Jean (1967). From Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press. ISBN 9780674324497.
    • Contains translations of the following two papers, with valuable commentary:
      • Dedekind, Richard (1890). Letter to Keferstein. On p. 100, he restates and defends his axioms of 1888. pp. 98–103.
      • Peano, Giuseppe (1889). Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita [The principles of arithmetic, presented by a new method]. An excerpt of the treatise where Peano first presented his axioms, and recursively defined arithmetical operations. Fratres Bocca. pp. 83–97.
  • Van Oosten, Jaap (June 1999). "Introduction to Peano Arithmetic (Gödel Incompleteness and Nonstandard Models)" (PDF). Utrecht University. Retrieved 2 September 2023.
  • Willard, Dan E. (2001). "Self-verifying axiom systems, the incompleteness theorem and related reflection principles" (PDF). The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 66 (2): 536–596. doi:10.2307/2695030. JSTOR 2695030. MR 1833464. S2CID 2822314.

Further reading Edit

  • Buss, Samuel R. (1998). "Chapter II: First-Order Proof Theory of Arithmetic". In Buss, Samuel R. (ed.). Handbook of Proof Theory. New York: Elsevier Science. ISBN 9780444898401.
  • Mendelson, Elliott (June 2015) [December 1979]. Introduction to Mathematical Logic (Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications) (6th ed.). Chapman and Hall/CRC. ISBN 9781482237726.

External links Edit

  • Murzi, Mauro. "Henri Poincaré". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Includes a discussion of Poincaré's critique of the Peano's axioms.
  • Podnieks, Karlis (2015-01-25). "3. First Order Arithmetic". What is Mathematics: Gödel's Theorem and Around. pp. 93–121.
  • "Peano axioms", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
  • Weisstein, Eric W. "Peano's Axioms". MathWorld.
  • Burris, Stanley N. (2001). "What are numbers, and what is their meaning?: Dedekind". Commentary on Dedekind's work.

This article incorporates material from PA on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.

peano, axioms, mathematical, logic, ɑː, peˈaːno, also, known, dedekind, peano, postulates, axioms, natural, numbers, presented, 19th, century, italian, mathematician, giuseppe, peano, these, axioms, have, been, used, nearly, unchanged, number, metamathematical. In mathematical logic the Peano axioms p i ˈ ɑː n oʊ 1 peˈaːno also known as the Dedekind Peano axioms or the Peano postulates are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano These axioms have been used nearly unchanged in a number of metamathematical investigations including research into fundamental questions of whether number theory is consistent and complete The need to formalize arithmetic was not well appreciated until the work of Hermann Grassmann who showed in the 1860s that many facts in arithmetic could be derived from more basic facts about the successor operation and induction 2 3 In 1881 Charles Sanders Peirce provided an axiomatization of natural number arithmetic 4 5 In 1888 Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural number arithmetic and in 1889 Peano published a simplified version of them as a collection of axioms in his book The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method Latin Arithmetices principia nova methodo exposita The nine Peano axioms contain three types of statements The first axiom asserts the existence of at least one member of the set of natural numbers The next four are general statements about equality in modern treatments these are often not taken as part of the Peano axioms but rather as axioms of the underlying logic 6 The next three axioms are first order statements about natural numbers expressing the fundamental properties of the successor operation The ninth final axiom is a second order statement of the principle of mathematical induction over the natural numbers which makes this formulation close to second order arithmetic A weaker first order system called Peano arithmetic is obtained by explicitly adding the addition and multiplication operation symbols and replacing the second order induction axiom with a first order axiom schema Contents 1 Historical second order formulation 1 1 Defining arithmetic operations and relations 1 1 1 Addition 1 1 2 Multiplication 1 1 3 Inequalities 1 2 Models 1 2 1 Set theoretic models 1 2 2 Interpretation in category theory 1 3 Consistency 2 Peano arithmetic as first order theory 2 1 Equivalent axiomatizations 2 2 Undecidability and incompleteness 2 3 Nonstandard models 2 3 1 Overspill 3 See also 4 Notes 5 References 5 1 Citations 5 2 Sources 6 Further reading 7 External linksHistorical second order formulation EditWhen Peano formulated his axioms the language of mathematical logic was in its infancy The system of logical notation he created to present the axioms did not prove to be popular although it was the genesis of the modern notation for set membership which comes from Peano s e and implication which comes from Peano s reversed C Peano maintained a clear distinction between mathematical and logical symbols which was not yet common in mathematics such a separation had first been introduced in the Begriffsschrift by Gottlob Frege published in 1879 7 Peano was unaware of Frege s work and independently recreated his logical apparatus based on the work of Boole and Schroder 8 The Peano axioms define the arithmetical properties of natural numbers usually represented as a set N or N displaystyle mathbb N nbsp The non logical symbols for the axioms consist of a constant symbol 0 and a unary function symbol S The first axiom states that the constant 0 is a natural number 0 is a natural number Peano s original formulation of the axioms used 1 instead of 0 as the first natural number 9 while the axioms in Formulario mathematico include zero 10 The next four axioms describe the equality relation Since they are logically valid in first order logic with equality they are not considered to be part of the Peano axioms in modern treatments 8 For every natural number x x x That is equality is reflexive For all natural numbers x and y if x y then y x That is equality is symmetric For all natural numbers x y and z if x y and y z then x z That is equality is transitive For all a and b if b is a natural number and a b then a is also a natural number That is the natural numbers are closed under equality The remaining axioms define the arithmetical properties of the natural numbers The naturals are assumed to be closed under a single valued successor function S For every natural number n S n is a natural number That is the natural numbers are closed under S For all natural numbers m and n if S m S n then m n That is S is an injection For every natural number n S n 0 is false That is there is no natural number whose successor is 0 nbsp The chain of light dominoes starting with the nearest can represent N 11 12 however axioms 1 8 are also satisfied by the set of all light and dark dominoes note 1 The 9th axiom induction limits N to the chain of light pieces no junk as only light dominoes will fall when the nearest is toppled 13 Axioms 1 6 7 8 define a unary representation of the intuitive notion of natural numbers the number 1 can be defined as S 0 2 as S S 0 etc However considering the notion of natural numbers as being defined by these axioms axioms 1 6 7 8 do not imply that the successor function generates all the natural numbers different from 0 The intuitive notion that each natural number can be obtained by applying successor sufficiently often to zero requires an additional axiom which is sometimes called the axiom of induction If K is a set such that 0 is in K and for every natural number n n being in K implies that S n is in K then K contains every natural number The induction axiom is sometimes stated in the following form If f is a unary predicate such that f 0 is true and for every natural number n f n being true implies that f S n is true then f n is true for every natural number n In Peano s original formulation the induction axiom is a second order axiom It is now common to replace this second order principle with a weaker first order induction scheme There are important differences between the second order and first order formulations as discussed in the section Peano arithmetic as first order theory below Defining arithmetic operations and relations Edit If we use the second order induction axiom it is possible to define addition multiplication and total linear ordering on N directly using the axioms However with first order induction this is not possible citation needed and addition and multiplication are often added as axioms The respective functions and relations are constructed in set theory or second order logic and can be shown to be unique using the Peano axioms Addition Edit Addition is a function that maps two natural numbers two elements of N to another one It is defined recursively as a 0 a 1 a S b S a b 2 displaystyle begin aligned a 0 amp a amp textrm 1 a S b amp S a b amp textrm 2 end aligned nbsp For example a 1 a S 0 by definition S a 0 using 2 S a using 1 a 2 a S 1 by definition S a 1 using 2 S S a using a 1 S a a 3 a S 2 by definition S a 2 using 2 S S S a using a 2 S S a etc displaystyle begin aligned a 1 amp a S 0 amp mbox by definition amp S a 0 amp mbox using 2 amp S a amp mbox using 1 a 2 amp a S 1 amp mbox by definition amp S a 1 amp mbox using 2 amp S S a amp mbox using a 1 S a a 3 amp a S 2 amp mbox by definition amp S a 2 amp mbox using 2 amp S S S a amp mbox using a 2 S S a text etc amp end aligned nbsp The structure N is a commutative monoid with identity element 0 N is also a cancellative magma and thus embeddable in a group The smallest group embedding N is the integers Multiplication Edit Similarly multiplication is a function mapping two natural numbers to another one Given addition it is defined recursively as a 0 0 a S b a a b displaystyle begin aligned a cdot 0 amp 0 a cdot S b amp a a cdot b end aligned nbsp It is easy to see that S 0 displaystyle S 0 nbsp or 1 in the familiar language of decimal representation is the multiplicative right identity a S 0 a a 0 a 0 a displaystyle a cdot S 0 a a cdot 0 a 0 a nbsp To show that S 0 displaystyle S 0 nbsp is also the multiplicative left identity requires the induction axiom due to the way multiplication is defined S 0 displaystyle S 0 nbsp is the left identity of 0 S 0 0 0 displaystyle S 0 cdot 0 0 nbsp If S 0 displaystyle S 0 nbsp is the left identity of a displaystyle a nbsp that is S 0 a a displaystyle S 0 cdot a a nbsp then S 0 displaystyle S 0 nbsp is also the left identity of S a displaystyle S a nbsp S 0 S a S 0 S 0 a S 0 a a S 0 S a 0 S a displaystyle S 0 cdot S a S 0 S 0 cdot a S 0 a a S 0 S a 0 S a nbsp Therefore by the induction axiom S 0 displaystyle S 0 nbsp is the multiplicative left identity of all natural numbers Moreover it can be shown that multiplication is commutative and distributes over addition a b c a b a c displaystyle a cdot b c a cdot b a cdot c nbsp Thus N 0 S 0 displaystyle mathbb N 0 cdot S 0 nbsp is a commutative semiring Inequalities Edit The usual total order relation on natural numbers can be defined as follows assuming 0 is a natural number For all a b N a b if and only if there exists some c N such that a c b This relation is stable under addition and multiplication for a b c N displaystyle a b c in mathbb N nbsp if a b then a c b c and a c b c Thus the structure N 1 0 is an ordered semiring because there is no natural number between 0 and 1 it is a discrete ordered semiring The axiom of induction is sometimes stated in the following form that uses a stronger hypothesis making use of the order relation For any predicate f if f 0 is true and for every n N if f k is true for every k N such that k n then f S n is true then for every n N f n is true This form of the induction axiom called strong induction is a consequence of the standard formulation but is often better suited for reasoning about the order For example to show that the naturals are well ordered every nonempty subset of N has a least element one can reason as follows Let a nonempty X N be given and assume X has no least element Because 0 is the least element of N it must be that 0 X For any n N suppose for every k n k X Then S n X for otherwise it would be the least element of X Thus by the strong induction principle for every n N n X Thus X N which contradicts X being a nonempty subset of N Thus X has a least element Models Edit A model of the Peano axioms is a triple N 0 S where N is a necessarily infinite set 0 N and S N N satisfies the axioms above Dedekind proved in his 1888 book The Nature and Meaning of Numbers German Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen i e What are the numbers and what are they good for that any two models of the Peano axioms including the second order induction axiom are isomorphic In particular given two models NA 0A SA and NB 0B SB of the Peano axioms there is a unique homomorphism f NA NB satisfying f 0 A 0 B f S A n S B f n displaystyle begin aligned f 0 A amp 0 B f S A n amp S B f n end aligned nbsp and it is a bijection This means that the second order Peano axioms are categorical This is not the case with any first order reformulation of the Peano axioms below Set theoretic models Edit Main article Set theoretic definition of natural numbers The Peano axioms can be derived from set theoretic constructions of the natural numbers and axioms of set theory such as ZF 14 The standard construction of the naturals due to John von Neumann starts from a definition of 0 as the empty set and an operator s on sets defined as s a a a displaystyle s a a cup a nbsp The set of natural numbers N is defined as the intersection of all sets closed under s that contain the empty set Each natural number is equal as a set to the set of natural numbers less than it 0 1 s 0 s 0 2 s 1 s 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 3 s 2 s 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 2 displaystyle begin aligned 0 amp emptyset 1 amp s 0 s emptyset emptyset cup emptyset emptyset 0 2 amp s 1 s 0 0 cup 0 0 0 0 1 3 amp s 2 s 0 1 0 1 cup 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 2 end aligned nbsp and so on The set N together with 0 and the successor function s N N satisfies the Peano axioms Peano arithmetic is equiconsistent with several weak systems of set theory 15 One such system is ZFC with the axiom of infinity replaced by its negation Another such system consists of general set theory extensionality existence of the empty set and the axiom of adjunction augmented by an axiom schema stating that a property that holds for the empty set and holds of an adjunction whenever it holds of the adjunct must hold for all sets Interpretation in category theory Edit The Peano axioms can also be understood using category theory Let C be a category with terminal object 1C and define the category of pointed unary systems US1 C as follows The objects of US1 C are triples X 0X SX where X is an object of C and 0X 1C X and SX X X are C morphisms A morphism f X 0X SX Y 0Y SY is a C morphism f X Y with f 0X 0Y and f SX SY f Then C is said to satisfy the Dedekind Peano axioms if US1 C has an initial object this initial object is known as a natural number object in C If N 0 S is this initial object and X 0X SX is any other object then the unique map u N 0 S X 0X SX is such that u 0 0 X u S x S X u x displaystyle begin aligned u 0 amp 0 X u Sx amp S X ux end aligned nbsp This is precisely the recursive definition of 0X and SX Consistency Edit Further information Hilbert s second problem and Consistency When the Peano axioms were first proposed Bertrand Russell and others agreed that these axioms implicitly defined what we mean by a natural number 16 Henri Poincare was more cautious saying they only defined natural numbers if they were consistent if there is a proof that starts from just these axioms and derives a contradiction such as 0 1 then the axioms are inconsistent and don t define anything 17 In 1900 David Hilbert posed the problem of proving their consistency using only finitistic methods as the second of his twenty three problems 18 In 1931 Kurt Godel proved his second incompleteness theorem which shows that such a consistency proof cannot be formalized within Peano arithmetic itself 19 Although it is widely claimed that Godel s theorem rules out the possibility of a finitistic consistency proof for Peano arithmetic this depends on exactly what one means by a finitistic proof Godel himself pointed out the possibility of giving a finitistic consistency proof of Peano arithmetic or stronger systems by using finitistic methods that are not formalizable in Peano arithmetic and in 1958 Godel published a method for proving the consistency of arithmetic using type theory 20 In 1936 Gerhard Gentzen gave a proof of the consistency of Peano s axioms using transfinite induction up to an ordinal called e0 21 Gentzen explained The aim of the present paper is to prove the consistency of elementary number theory or rather to reduce the question of consistency to certain fundamental principles Gentzen s proof is arguably finitistic since the transfinite ordinal e0 can be encoded in terms of finite objects for example as a Turing machine describing a suitable order on the integers or more abstractly as consisting of the finite trees suitably linearly ordered Whether or not Gentzen s proof meets the requirements Hilbert envisioned is unclear there is no generally accepted definition of exactly what is meant by a finitistic proof and Hilbert himself never gave a precise definition The vast majority of contemporary mathematicians believe that Peano s axioms are consistent relying either on intuition or the acceptance of a consistency proof such as Gentzen s proof A small number of philosophers and mathematicians some of whom also advocate ultrafinitism reject Peano s axioms because accepting the axioms amounts to accepting the infinite collection of natural numbers In particular addition including the successor function and multiplication are assumed to be total Curiously there are self verifying theories that are similar to PA but have subtraction and division instead of addition and multiplication which are axiomatized in such a way to avoid proving sentences that correspond to the totality of addition and multiplication but which are still able to prove all true P 1 displaystyle Pi 1 nbsp theorems of PA and yet can be extended to a consistent theory that proves its own consistency stated as the non existence of a Hilbert style proof of 0 1 22 Peano arithmetic as first order theory EditAll of the Peano axioms except the ninth axiom the induction axiom are statements in first order logic 23 The arithmetical operations of addition and multiplication and the order relation can also be defined using first order axioms The axiom of induction above is second order since it quantifies over predicates equivalently sets of natural numbers rather than natural numbers As an alternative one can consider a first order axiom schema of induction Such a schema includes one axiom per predicate definable in the first order language of Peano arithmetic making it weaker than the second order axiom 24 The reason that it is weaker is that the number of predicates in first order language is countable whereas the number of sets of natural numbers is uncountable Thus there exist sets that cannot be described in first order language in fact most sets have this property First order axiomatizations of Peano arithmetic have another technical limitation In second order logic it is possible to define the addition and multiplication operations from the successor operation but this cannot be done in the more restrictive setting of first order logic Therefore the addition and multiplication operations are directly included in the signature of Peano arithmetic and axioms are included that relate the three operations to each other The following list of axioms along with the usual axioms of equality which contains six of the seven axioms of Robinson arithmetic is sufficient for this purpose 25 x 0 S x displaystyle forall x 0 neq S x nbsp x y S x S y x y displaystyle forall x y S x S y Rightarrow x y nbsp x x 0 x displaystyle forall x x 0 x nbsp x y x S y S x y displaystyle forall x y x S y S x y nbsp x x 0 0 displaystyle forall x x cdot 0 0 nbsp x y x S y x y x displaystyle forall x y x cdot S y x cdot y x nbsp In addition to this list of numerical axioms Peano arithmetic contains the induction schema which consists of a recursively enumerable and even decidable set of axioms For each formula f x y1 yk in the language of Peano arithmetic the first order induction axiom for f is the sentence y f 0 y x f x y f S x y x f x y displaystyle forall bar y Bigg bigg varphi 0 bar y land forall x Big varphi x bar y Rightarrow varphi S x bar y Big bigg Rightarrow forall x varphi x bar y Bigg nbsp where y displaystyle bar y nbsp is an abbreviation for y1 yk The first order induction schema includes every instance of the first order induction axiom that is it includes the induction axiom for every formula f Equivalent axiomatizations Edit The above axiomatization of Peano arithmetic uses a signature that only has symbols for zero as well as the successor addition and multiplications operations There are many other different but equivalent axiomatizations One such alternative 26 uses an order relation symbol instead of the successor operation and the language of discretely ordered semirings axioms 1 7 for semirings 8 10 on order 11 13 regarding compatibility and 14 15 for discreteness x y z x y z x y z displaystyle forall x y z x y z x y z nbsp i e addition is associative x y x y y x displaystyle forall x y x y y x nbsp i e addition is commutative x y z x y z x y z displaystyle forall x y z x cdot y cdot z x cdot y cdot z nbsp i e multiplication is associative x y x y y x displaystyle forall x y x cdot y y cdot x nbsp i e multiplication is commutative x y z x y z x y x z displaystyle forall x y z x cdot y z x cdot y x cdot z nbsp i e multiplication distributes over addition x x 0 x x 0 0 displaystyle forall x x 0 x land x cdot 0 0 nbsp i e zero is an identity for addition and an absorbing element for multiplication actually superfluous note 2 x x 1 x displaystyle forall x x cdot 1 x nbsp i e one is an identity for multiplication x y z x lt y y lt z x lt z displaystyle forall x y z x lt y land y lt z Rightarrow x lt z nbsp i e the lt operator is transitive x x lt x displaystyle forall x neg x lt x nbsp i e the lt operator is irreflexive x y x lt y x y y lt x displaystyle forall x y x lt y lor x y lor y lt x nbsp i e the ordering satisfies trichotomy x y z x lt y x z lt y z displaystyle forall x y z x lt y Rightarrow x z lt y z nbsp i e the ordering is preserved under addition of the same element x y z 0 lt z x lt y x z lt y z displaystyle forall x y z 0 lt z land x lt y Rightarrow x cdot z lt y cdot z nbsp i e the ordering is preserved under multiplication by the same positive element x y x lt y z x z y displaystyle forall x y x lt y Rightarrow exists z x z y nbsp i e given any two distinct elements the larger is the smaller plus another element 0 lt 1 x x gt 0 x 1 displaystyle 0 lt 1 land forall x x gt 0 Rightarrow x geq 1 nbsp i e zero and one are distinct and there is no element between them In other words 0 is covered by 1 which suggests that these numbers are discrete x x 0 displaystyle forall x x geq 0 nbsp i e zero is the minimum element The theory defined by these axioms is known as PA It is also incomplete and one of its important properties is that any structure M displaystyle M nbsp satisfying this theory has an initial segment ordered by displaystyle leq nbsp isomorphic to N displaystyle mathbb N nbsp Elements in that segment are called standard elements while other elements are called nonstandard elements Finally Peano arithmetic PA is obtained by adding the first order induction schema Undecidability and incompleteness Edit According to Godel s incompleteness theorems the theory of PA if consistent is incomplete Consequently there are sentences of first order logic FOL that are true in the standard model of PA but are not a consequence of the FOL axiomatization Essential incompleteness already arises for theories with weaker axioms such as Robinson arithmetic Closely related to the above incompleteness result via Godel s completeness theorem for FOL it follows that there is no algorithm for deciding whether a given FOL sentence is a consequence of a first order axiomatization of Peano arithmetic or not Hence PA is an example of an undecidable theory Undecidability arises already for the existential sentences of PA due to the negative answer to Hilbert s tenth problem whose proof implies that all computably enumerable sets are diophantine sets and thus definable by existentially quantified formulas with free variables of PA Formulas of PA with higher quantifier rank more quantifier alternations than existential formulas are more expressive and define sets in the higher levels of the arithmetical hierarchy Nonstandard models Edit Main article Non standard model of arithmetic Although the usual natural numbers satisfy the axioms of PA there are other models as well called non standard models the compactness theorem implies that the existence of nonstandard elements cannot be excluded in first order logic 27 The upward Lowenheim Skolem theorem shows that there are nonstandard models of PA of all infinite cardinalities This is not the case for the original second order Peano axioms which have only one model up to isomorphism 28 This illustrates one way the first order system PA is weaker than the second order Peano axioms When interpreted as a proof within a first order set theory such as ZFC Dedekind s categoricity proof for PA shows that each model of set theory has a unique model of the Peano axioms up to isomorphism that embeds as an initial segment of all other models of PA contained within that model of set theory In the standard model of set theory this smallest model of PA is the standard model of PA however in a nonstandard model of set theory it may be a nonstandard model of PA This situation cannot be avoided with any first order formalization of set theory It is natural to ask whether a countable nonstandard model can be explicitly constructed The answer is affirmative as Skolem in 1933 provided an explicit construction of such a nonstandard model On the other hand Tennenbaum s theorem proved in 1959 shows that there is no countable nonstandard model of PA in which either the addition or multiplication operation is computable 29 This result shows it is difficult to be completely explicit in describing the addition and multiplication operations of a countable nonstandard model of PA There is only one possible order type of a countable nonstandard model Letting w be the order type of the natural numbers z be the order type of the integers and h be the order type of the rationals the order type of any countable nonstandard model of PA is w z h which can be visualized as a copy of the natural numbers followed by a dense linear ordering of copies of the integers Overspill Edit A cut in a nonstandard model M is a nonempty subset C of M so that C is downward closed x lt y and y C x C and C is closed under successor A proper cut is a cut that is a proper subset of M Each nonstandard model has many proper cuts including one that corresponds to the standard natural numbers However the induction scheme in Peano arithmetic prevents any proper cut from being definable The overspill lemma first proved by Abraham Robinson formalizes this fact Overspill lemma 30 Let M be a nonstandard model of PA and let C be a proper cut of M Suppose that a displaystyle bar a nbsp is a tuple of elements of M and ϕ x a displaystyle phi x bar a nbsp is a formula in the language of arithmetic so that M ϕ b a displaystyle M vDash phi b bar a nbsp for all b C Then there is a c in M that is greater than every element of C such that M ϕ c a displaystyle M vDash phi c bar a nbsp See also Edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Mathematics portalFoundations of mathematics Frege s theorem Goodstein s theorem Neo logicism Non standard model of arithmetic Paris Harrington theorem Presburger arithmetic Robinson arithmetic Second order arithmetic Typographical Number TheoryNotes Edit The non contiguous set satisfies axiom 1 as it has a 0 element 2 5 as it doesn t affect equality relations 6 amp 8 as all pieces have a successor bar the zero element and axiom 7 as no two dominos topple or are toppled by the same piece x x 0 0 displaystyle forall x x cdot 0 0 nbsp can be proven from the other axioms in first order logic as follows Firstly x 0 x 0 x 0 0 x 0 x 0 0 displaystyle x cdot 0 x cdot 0 x cdot 0 0 x cdot 0 x cdot 0 0 nbsp by distributivity and additive identity Secondly x 0 0 x 0 gt 0 displaystyle x cdot 0 0 lor x cdot 0 gt 0 nbsp by Axiom 15 If x 0 gt 0 displaystyle x cdot 0 gt 0 nbsp then x 0 x 0 gt x 0 0 displaystyle x cdot 0 x cdot 0 gt x cdot 0 0 nbsp by addition of the same element and commutativity and hence x 0 0 gt x 0 0 displaystyle x cdot 0 0 gt x cdot 0 0 nbsp by substitution contradicting irreflexivity Therefore it must be that x 0 0 displaystyle x cdot 0 0 nbsp References EditCitations Edit Peano Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary Grassmann 1861 Wang 1957 pp 145 147 It is rather well known through Peano s own acknowledgement that Peano made extensive use of Grassmann s work in his development of the axioms It is not so well known that Grassmann had essentially the characterization of the set of all integers now customary in texts of modern algebra that it forms an ordered integral domain in wihich each set of positive elements has a least member Grassmann s book was probably the first serious and rather successful attempt to put numbers on a more or less axiomatic basis Peirce 1881 Shields 1997 Van Heijenoort 1967 p 94 Van Heijenoort 1967 p 2 a b Van Heijenoort 1967 p 83 Peano 1889 p 1 Peano 1908 p 27 Matt DeVos Mathematical Induction Simon Fraser University Gerardo con Diaz Mathematical Induction Archived 2 May 2013 at the Wayback Machine Harvard University Meseguer amp Goguen 1986 sections 2 3 p 464 and 4 1 p 471 Suppes 1960 Hatcher 2014 Tarski amp Givant 1987 Section 7 6 Fritz 1952 p 137An illustration of interpretation is Russell s own definition of cardinal number The uninterpreted system in this case is Peano s axioms for the number system whose three primitive ideas and five axioms Peano believed were sufficient to enable one to derive all the properties of the system of natural numbers Actually Russell maintains Peano s axioms define any progression of the form x 0 x 1 x 2 x n displaystyle x 0 x 1 x 2 ldots x n ldots nbsp of which the series of the natural numbers is one instance Gray 2013 p 133So Poincare turned to see whether logicism could generate arithmetic more precisely the arithmetic of ordinals Couturat said Poincare had accepted the Peano axioms as a definition of a number But this will not do The axioms cannot be shown to be free of contradiction by finding examples of them and any attempt to show that they were contradiction free by examining the totality of their implications would require the very principle of mathematical induction Couturat believed they implied For in a further passage dropped from S amp M either one assumed the principle in order to prove it which would only prove that if it is true it is not self contradictory which says nothing or one used the principle in another form than the one stated in which case one must show that the number of steps in one s reasoning was an integer according to the new definition but this could not be done 1905c 834 Hilbert 1902 Godel 1931 Godel 1958 Gentzen 1936 Willard 2001 Partee Ter Meulen amp Wall 2012 p 215 Harsanyi 1983 Mendelson 1997 p 155 Kaye 1991 pp 16 18 Hermes 1973 VI 4 3 presenting a theorem of Thoralf Skolem Hermes 1973 VI 3 1 Kaye 1991 Section 11 3 Kaye 1991 pp 70ff Sources Edit Davis Martin 1974 Computability Notes by Barry Jacobs Courant Institute of Mathematical Sciences New York University Dedekind Richard 1888 Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen What are and what should the numbers be PDF Vieweg Retrieved 4 July 2016 Two English translations Beman Wooster Woodruff 1901 Essays on the Theory of Numbers PDF Dover Publications a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Ewald William B 1996 From Kant to Hilbert A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics Oxford University Press pp 787 832 ISBN 9780198532712 Fritz Charles A Jr 1952 Bertrand Russell s construction of the external world New York Humanities Press a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Gentzen Gerhard 1936 Reprinted in English translation in his 1969 Collected works M E Szabo ed Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie Mathematische Annalen 112 132 213 doi 10 1007 bf01565428 S2CID 122719892 Godel Kurt 1931 See On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems for details on English translations Uber formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I PDF Monatshefte fur Mathematik 38 173 198 doi 10 1007 bf01700692 S2CID 197663120 Archived from the original PDF on 2018 04 11 Retrieved 2013 10 31 Godel Kurt 1958 Reprinted in English translation in 1990 Godel s Collected Works Vol II Solomon Feferman et al eds Uber eine bisher noch nicht benutzte Erweiterung des finiten Standpunktes Dialectica Oxford University Press 12 3 4 280 287 doi 10 1111 j 1746 8361 1958 tb01464 x Grassmann Hermann Gunther 1861 Lehrbuch der Arithmetik fur hohere Lehranstalten Verlag von Theod Chr Fr Enslin Gray Jeremy 2013 The Essayist Henri Poincare A scientific biography Princeton University Press p 133 ISBN 978 0 691 15271 4 Harsanyi John C 1983 Mathematics the Empirical Facts and Logical Necessity In Hempel Carl G Putnam Hilary Essler Wilhelm K eds Methodology Epistemology and Philosophy of Science pp 167 192 doi 10 1007 978 94 015 7676 5 8 ISBN 978 90 481 8389 0 S2CID 121297669 Hatcher William S 2014 1982 The Logical Foundations of Mathematics Elsevier ISBN 978 1 4831 8963 5 Derives the Peano axioms called S from several axiomatic set theories and from category theory Hermes Hans 1973 Introduction to Mathematical Logic Hochschultext Springer ISBN 3540058192 ISSN 1431 4657 Hilbert David 1902 Translated by Winton Maby Mathematische Probleme Mathematical Problems Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 8 10 437 479 doi 10 1090 s0002 9904 1902 00923 3 Kaye Richard 1991 Models of Peano arithmetic Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 853213 X Landau Edmund 1965 Grundlagen Der Analysis Derives the basic number systems from the Peano axioms English German vocabulary included AMS Chelsea Publishing ISBN 978 0 8284 0141 8 Mendelson Elliott December 1997 December 1979 Introduction to Mathematical Logic Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications 4th ed Springer ISBN 9780412808302 Meseguer Jose Goguen Joseph A Dec 1986 Initiality induction and computability In Maurice Nivat and John C Reynolds ed Algebraic Methods in Semantics PDF Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 459 541 ISBN 9780521267939 Partee Barbara Ter Meulen Alice Wall Robert 2012 Mathematical Methods in Linguistics Springer ISBN 978 94 009 2213 6 Peano Giuseppe 1908 Formulario Mathematico V ed Turin Bocca freres Ch Clausen p 27 Peirce C S 1881 On the Logic of Number American Journal of Mathematics 4 1 85 95 doi 10 2307 2369151 JSTOR 2369151 MR 1507856 Shields Paul 1997 3 Peirce s Axiomatization of Arithmetic In Houser Nathan Roberts Don D Van Evra James eds Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce Indiana University Press pp 43 52 ISBN 0 253 33020 3 Suppes Patrick 1960 Axiomatic Set Theory Dover Publications ISBN 0 486 61630 4 Derives the Peano axioms from ZFCTarski Alfred Givant Steven 1987 A Formalization of Set Theory without Variables AMS Colloquium Publications Vol 41 American Mathematical Society ISBN 978 0 8218 1041 5 Van Heijenoort Jean 1967 From Frege to Godel A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674324497 Contains translations of the following two papers with valuable commentary Dedekind Richard 1890 Letter to Keferstein On p 100 he restates and defends his axioms of 1888 pp 98 103 Peano Giuseppe 1889 Arithmetices principia nova methodo exposita The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method An excerpt of the treatise where Peano first presented his axioms and recursively defined arithmetical operations Fratres Bocca pp 83 97 Van Oosten Jaap June 1999 Introduction to Peano Arithmetic Godel Incompleteness and Nonstandard Models PDF Utrecht University Retrieved 2 September 2023 Wang Hao June 1957 The Axiomatization of Arithmetic The Journal of Symbolic Logic Association for Symbolic Logic 22 2 145 158 doi 10 2307 2964176 JSTOR 2964176 S2CID 26896458 Willard Dan E 2001 Self verifying axiom systems the incompleteness theorem and related reflection principles PDF The Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 2 536 596 doi 10 2307 2695030 JSTOR 2695030 MR 1833464 S2CID 2822314 Further reading EditBuss Samuel R 1998 Chapter II First Order Proof Theory of Arithmetic In Buss Samuel R ed Handbook of Proof Theory New York Elsevier Science ISBN 9780444898401 Mendelson Elliott June 2015 December 1979 Introduction to Mathematical Logic Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications 6th ed Chapman and Hall CRC ISBN 9781482237726 Smullyan Raymond M December 2013 The Godelian Puzzle Book Puzzles Paradoxes and Proofs Dover Publications ISBN 978 0 486 49705 1 Takeuti Gaisi 2013 Proof theory Second ed Mineola New York ISBN 978 0486490731 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link External links EditMurzi Mauro Henri Poincare Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Includes a discussion of Poincare s critique of the Peano s axioms Podnieks Karlis 2015 01 25 3 First Order Arithmetic What is Mathematics Godel s Theorem and Around pp 93 121 Peano axioms Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Weisstein Eric W Peano s Axioms MathWorld Burris Stanley N 2001 What are numbers and what is their meaning Dedekind Commentary on Dedekind s work This article incorporates material from PA on PlanetMath which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution Share Alike License Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Peano axioms amp oldid 1176547436 Peano arithmetic as first order theory, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.