fbpx
Wikipedia

Baruch Spinoza

Baruch (de) Spinoza[b] (24 November 1632 – 21 February 1677), also known under his Latinized pen name Benedictus de Spinoza, was a Dutch philosopher of Portuguese-Jewish origin. As a forerunner of the Age of Reason, Spinoza significantly influenced modern biblical criticism, 17th-century rationalism, and Dutch intellectual culture, establishing himself as one of the most important and radical philosophers of the early modern period.[15] He was influenced by Stoicism, Maimonides, Niccolò Machiavelli, René Descartes, Thomas Hobbes, and a variety of heterodox Christian thinkers of his day.[16]

Baruch Spinoza
Born
Baruch Espinosa[9] /
Bento de Spinosa[10]

(1632-11-24)24 November 1632
Died21 February 1677(1677-02-21) (aged 44)
The Hague, Dutch Republic
Other namesBenedictus de Spinoza
Education
Era
Region
School
Main interests
Signature

Spinoza was born in Amsterdam to a Marrano family that left Portugal for a more tolerant Dutch Republic. He had a traditional Jewish education, learning Hebrew and studying the sacred texts. He was part of the Portuguese Jewish community, where his father was a prominent merchant. As a young man, Spinoza was permanently expelled from the Jewish community for defying rabbinic authorities and disputing Jewish beliefs. After his expulsion in 1656, he did not affiliate with any religion, instead focusing on philosophical study and lens grinding. Spinoza established a dedicated following who met to discuss his writings and was devoted to pursuing truth philosophically.

Spinoza challenged the divine origin of the Hebrew Bible, the nature of God, and the earthly power wielded by religious authorities, Jewish and Christian alike. He was frequently called an atheist by contemporaries, although nowhere in his work does Spinoza argue against the existence of God.[17][18] This can be explained by the fact that, unlike contemporary 21st-century scholars, “when seventeenth-century readers accused Spinoza of atheism, they usually meant that he challenged doctrinal orthodoxy, particularly on moral issues, and not that he denied God's existence."[19] His theological studies were inseparable from his thinking on politics; he is grouped with Hobbes, John Locke, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and Immanuel Kant, who established the genre of political writing called secular theology.[20]

Spinoza's philosophy encompasses nearly every area of philosophical discourse, including metaphysics, epistemology, political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science. With an enduring reputation as one of the most original and influential thinkers of the seventeenth century, Rebecca Goldstein dubbed him "the renegade Jew who gave us modernity."[21]

Biography edit

 
The Moses and Aaron Church now stands at the site of Spinoza's childhood home.[22]

Family background edit

Spinoza's ancestors, adherents of Crypto-Judaism, faced persecution during the Portuguese Inquisition, enduring torture and public displays of humiliation.[23] In 1597, his paternal grandfather's family left Vidigueira for Nantes and lived as New Christians, eventually transferring to Holland for an unknown reason.[24] His maternal ancestors were a leading Oporto commercial family,[25] and his maternal grandfather was a foremost merchant who drifted between Judaism and Christianity.[26] Spinoza was raised by his grandmother from ages six to nine and probably learned much about his family history from her.[27]

Spinoza's father Michael was a prominent and wealthy merchant in Amsterdam with a business that had wide geographical reach.[28] In 1649, he was elected to serve as an administrative officer of the recently united congregation Talmud Torah.[29] He married his cousin Rachael d’Espinosa, daughter of his uncle Abraham d’Espinosa, who was also a community leader and Michael's business partner.[30] Marrying cousins was common in the Portuguese Jewish community then, giving Michael access to his father-in-law's commercial network and capital.[31] Rachel's children died in infancy, and she died in 1627.[32][31]

After the death of Rachel, Michael married Hannah Deborah, with whom he had five children. His second wife brought a dowry to the marriage that was absorbed into Michael's business capital instead of being set aside for her children, which may have caused a grudge between Spinoza and his father.[33] The family lived on the artificial island on the south side of the River Amstel, known as the Vlooienburg, at the fifth house along the Houtgracht canal.[22] The Jewish quarter was not formally divided. The family lived close to the Bet Ya'acov synagogue, and nearby were Christians, including the artist Rembrandt.[34] Miriam was their first child, followed by Isaac who was expected to take over as head of the family and the commercial enterprise but died in 1649.[33] Baruch Espinosa, the third child, was born on 24 November 1632 and named as per tradition for his maternal grandfather.[9]

Spinoza's younger brother Gabriel was born in 1634, followed by another sister Rebecca. Miriam married Samuel de Caceres but died shortly after childbirth. According to Jewish practice, Samuel had to marry his former sister-in-law Rebecca.[35] Following his brother's death, Spinoza's place as head of the family and its business meant scholarly ambitions were pushed aside.[28] Spinoza's mother, Hannah Deborah, died when Spinoza was six years old. Michael's third wife, Esther, raised Spinoza from age nine; she lacked formal Jewish knowledge due to growing up a New Christian and only spoke Portuguese at home. The marriage was childless.[36] Spinoza's sister Rebecca, brother Gabriel, and nephew eventually migrated to Curaçao, and the remaining family joined them after Spinoza's death.[35]

Uriel da Costa's early influence edit

 
Samuel Hirszenberg's imagined scene of Uriel da Costa instructing Spinoza (1901)

Through his mother, Spinoza was related to the philosopher Uriel da Costa, who stirred controversy in Amsterdam's Portuguese Jewish community.[37] Da Costa questioned traditional Christian and Jewish beliefs, asserting that, for example, their origins were based on human inventions instead of God's revelation. His clashes with the religious establishment led to his excommunication twice by rabbinic authorities, who imposed humiliation and social exclusion.[38] In 1639, as part of an agreement to be readmitted, da Costa had to prostrate himself for worshippers to step over him. He died in 1640, reportedly committing suicide.[39]

During his childhood, Spinoza was likely unaware of his family connection with Uriel da Costa; still, as a teenager, he certainly heard discussions about him.[40] Steven Nadler explains that, although da Costa died when Spinoza was eight, his ideas shaped Spinoza's intellectual development. Amsterdam's Jewish communities long remembered and discussed da Costa's skepticism about organized religion, denial of the soul's immortality, and the idea that Moses didn't write the Torah, influencing Spinoza's intellectual journey.[41]

School days and the family business edit

 
Spinoza's name crossed out on the list of pupils of Talmud Torah (Ets Haim in Hebrew)

Spinoza attended the Talmud Torah school adjoining the Bet Ya'acov synagogue, a few doors down from his home, headed by the senior Rabbi Saul Levi Morteira.[42][43] Instructed in Spanish, the language of learning and literature, students in the elementary school learned to read the prayerbook and the Torah in Hebrew, translate the weekly section into Spanish, and study Rashi's commentary.[44] Spinoza's name does not appear on the registry after age fourteen, and, likely, he never studied with rabbis such as Manasseh ben Israel and Morteira. Spinoza possibly went to work around fourteen and almost certainly was needed in his father's business after his brother died in 1649.[45]

During the First Anglo-Dutch War, much of the Spinoza firm's ships and cargo were captured by English ships, severely affecting the firm's financial viability. The firm was saddled with debt by the war's end in 1654 due to its merchant voyages being intercepted by the English, leading to its decline.[46][47] Spinoza's father died in 1654, making him the head of the family, responsible for organizing and leading the Jewish mourning rituals, and in a business partnership with his brother of their inherited firm.[48] As Spinoza's father had poor health for some years before his death, he was significantly involved in the business, putting his intellectual curiosity on hold.[49] Until 1656, he continued financially supporting the synagogue and attending services in compliance with synagogue conventions and practice.[50] By 1655, the family's wealth had evaporated and the business effectively ended.[49]

In March 1656, Spinoza went to the city authorities for protection against debts in the Portuguese Jewish community. To free himself from the responsibility of paying debts owed to his late father, Spinoza appealed to the city to declare him an orphan;[51] since he was a legal minor, not understanding his father's indebtedness would remove the obligation to repay his debts and retrospectively renounce his inheritance.[52] Though he was released of all debts and legally in the right, his reputation as a merchant was permanently damaged in addition to violating a synagogue regulation that business matters are to be arbitrated within the community.[53][51]

Expulsion from the Jewish community edit

 
Excommunicated Spinoza by Samuel Hirszenberg (1907), the second of his two modern paintings imagining scenes of Spinoza's life.

Amsterdam was tolerant of religious diversity so long as it was practiced discreetly, and Jews were not legally confined to a ghetto. The community was concerned with protecting its reputation and not associating with Spinoza lest his controversial views provide the basis for possible persecution or expulsion.[54] Spinoza did not openly break with Jewish authorities until his father died in 1654 when he became public and defiant, resulting from lengthy and stressful religious, financial, and legal clashes involving his business and synagogue, such as when Spinoza violated synagogue regulations by going to city authorities rather than resolving his disputes within the community to free himself from paying his father's debt.[51]

On 27 July 1656, the Talmud Torah community leaders, which included Aboab de Fonseca,[55] issued a writ of herem against the 23-year-old Spinoza.[56][57] Spinoza's censure was the harshest ever pronounced in the community, carrying tremendous emotional and spiritual impact.[58] The exact reason for expelling Spinoza is not stated, only referring to his "abominable heresies", "monstrous deeds", and the testimony of witnesses "in the presence of the said Espinoza".[59] Even though the Amsterdam municipal authorities were not directly involved in Spinoza's censure itself, the town council expressly ordered the Portuguese-Jewish community to regulate their conduct and ensure that the community kept a strict observance of Jewish law.[60] Other evidence shows that the danger of upsetting the civil authorities was not far from mind, such as bans adopted by the synagogue on public weddings or funeral processions and on discussing religious matters with Christians, lest such activity might "disturb the liberty we enjoy".[61]

 
Ban in Portuguese of Baruch Spinoza by the leaders of the community on 6 Av 5416 (27 July 1656)

Before the expulsion, Spinoza had not published anything or written a treatise; Steven Nadler states that if Spinoza was voicing his criticism of Judaism that later appeared through his philosophical works, such as Part I of Ethics, then there can be no wonder that he was severely punished.[62][63] He might already have been voicing the view expressed later in his Theological-Political Treatise that the civil authorities should suppress Judaism as harmful to the Jews themselves. He had effectively stopped contributing to the synagogue by March 1656 because of his bleak financial situation.[64] Unlike most censures issued by the Amsterdam congregation, it was never rescinded since the censure did not lead to repentance. After the censure, Spinoza is said to have written an Apologia in Spanish to the community leaders, defending his views and condemning the rabbis, but it is now lost.[65]

Spinoza's expulsion from the Jewish community did not lead him to convert to Christianity, remaining an apostate Jew for the rest of his life.[66] From 1656-61, Spinoza found lodgings elsewhere in Amsterdam and Leiden, supporting himself with teaching while learning lens grinding and constructing microscopes and telescopes.[67] Spinoza did not maintain a sense of Jewish identity; he argued that without adherence to Jewish law, the Jewish people lack a sustaining source of difference and identity, rendering the notion of a secular Jew incoherent.[68]

Education and study group edit

Sometime between 1654 and 1657, Spinoza started studying Latin with political radical Franciscus van den Enden, a former Jesuit and atheist, who likely introduced Spinoza to scholastic and modern philosophy, including Descartes, who had a dominant influence on Spinoza's philosophy.[69] While boarding with Van den Enden, Spinoza studied in his school, where he learned the arts and sciences and likely taught others.[70][66] Many of his friends were either secularized freethinkers or belonged to dissident Christian groups that rejected the authority of established churches and traditional dogmas.[71][72] Spinoza was acquainted with members of the Collegiants, a group of disaffected Mennonites and other dissenting Reformed sects that shunned official theology and must have played some role in Spinoza's developing views on religion and directed him to Van Enden.[73] Jonathan Israel conjectures that another possible influential figure was atheist translator Jan Hendriksz Glazemaker, a collaborator of Spinoza's friend and publisher Rieuwertsz, who could not have mentored Spinoza but was in a unique position to introduce Spinoza to Cartesian philosophy, mathematics, and lens grinding.[74]

After learning Latin with Van Enden, Spinoza studied at Leiden University around 1658,[75] where he audited classes in Cartesian philosophy.[c] From 1656-61, Spinoza's main discussion partners who formed his circle and played a formative part in Spinoza's life were Van den Enden, Pieter Balling, Jarig Jelles, Lodewijk Meyer, Johannes Bouwmeester and Adriaan Koerbagh.[77] Spinoza's following, or philosophical sect,[78] scrutinized the propositions of the Ethics while it was in draft and Spinoza's second text, Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being.[79] Though a few prominent people in Amsterdam discussed the teachings of the secretive but marginal group, it was mainly a testing ground for Spinoza's philosophy to extend his challenge to the status quo.[80] Their public reputation in Amsterdam was negative, with Ole Borch disparaging them as "atheists".[81] Throughout his life, Spinoza's general approach was to avoid intellectual battles, clashes, and public controversies, viewing them as a waste of energy that served no real purpose.[82]

Career as a philosopher edit

Rijnsburg edit

 
Spinoza's lodging in Rijnsburg, now a museum

In 1660 or 1661, Spinoza moved from Amsterdam to Rijnsburg, allowing for a quiet retreat in the country and access to the university town, Leiden, where he still had many friends.[83] Around this time, he wrote his Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being, which he never published in his lifetime, thinking it would enrage the theologians, synods, and city magistrates.[84][85] Two Dutch translations were discovered around 1810.[86] While lodging with Herman Homan in Rijnsburg, Spinoza produced lenses and instruments to support himself and out of scientific interest.[87] He began working on his Ethics and Descartes' Principles of Philosophy, which he completed in two weeks, communicating and interpreting Descartes' arguments and testing the water for his metaphysical and ethical ideas. Spinoza's explanations of essential elements of the Cartesian system helped many interested people study the system, enhancing his philosophical reputation. This work was published in 1663 and was one of the two works published in his lifetime under his name.[88]

Voorburg edit

In Voorburg, Spinoza continued work on his magnum opus, titled posthumously Ethics, and corresponded with scientists, philosophers, and theologians throughout Europe. He published in Latin, anonymously, and with false printer information Theological-Political Treatise (TTP) in 1670, in defense of secular and constitutional government, and in support of Johan de Witt, the Dutch Republic's grand pensionary, against the Stadtholder, the Prince of Orange.

Spinoza deliberately wrote in Latin, restricting his message to those who knew the scholarly language. Dutch philosopher and physician, Adriaan Koerbagh attempted to publish a work in Dutch questioning the Trinity as a concept, asserted that Jesus was a human being, and that the scripture was not divinely inspired, was proposing ideas that also appear in Spinoza writings in Latin. Koerbagh's "A Flower Garden of All Sorts of Delights" in Dutch came to the attention of the authorities, who incarcerated him to be followed by exile, but he died while in prison. Spinoza did not wish to die a martyr to his ideas and exercised caution by publishing his 1670 TTP anonymously in Latin and refraining from publishing any further works. Unlike Koerbagh, Spinoza died at home in his own bed.[89]

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz visited Spinoza and claimed that Spinoza's life was in danger when supporters of the Prince of Orange murdered de Witt in 1672.[90] While the TTP was published anonymously, the work did not long remain so, and de Witt's enemies characterized it as "forged in Hell by a renegade Jew and the Devil, and issued with the knowledge of Jan de Witt". It was placed on the Catholic Church's Index of Prohibited Works in 1679.[91]

The Hague edit

 
Spinoza's house in The Hague, where he died

In 1670, Spinoza moved to The Hague, where he lived on a small pension from Jan de Witt and a small annuity from the brother of his dead friend, Simon de Vries.[92] He worked on the manuscript of what was later called Ethics, wrote an unfinished Hebrew grammar, began his Political Treatise (TP), left unfinished at his death, wrote two scientific essays ("On the Rainbow" and "On the Calculation of Chances"), and began a Dutch translation of the Bible (which he later destroyed).[92] Spinoza was offered the chair of philosophy at the University of Heidelberg. He refused it, perhaps because of the possibility that it might in some way curb his freedom of thought.[93]

Spinoza also corresponded with Peter Serrarius, a radical Protestant and millenarian merchant. Serrarius was a patron to Spinoza after Spinoza was expelled from the Jewish community. He acted as an intermediary for Spinoza's correspondence, sending and receiving letters of the philosopher to and from third parties. Spinoza and Serrarius maintained their relationship until Serrarius died in 1669.[94]

By the beginning of the 1660s, Spinoza's name became more widely known. The Secretary of the British Royal Society Henry Oldenburg paid him visits and became a correspondent with Spinoza for the rest of his life.[95] In 1676, Leibniz wanted to examine a manuscript copy of the Ethics and traveled to the Hague to meet Spinoza, conversing with him at great length.[96]

Lens-grinding and optics edit

Spinoza earned a modest living from lens-grinding and instrument making, yet he was involved in important optical investigations of the day while living in Voorburg, through correspondence and friendships with scientist Christiaan Huygens and mathematician Johannes Hudde, including debate over microscope design with Huygens, favoring small objectives[97] and collaborating on calculations for a prospective 40-foot (12 m) focal length telescope which would have been one of the largest in Europe at the time.[98] He was known for making not just lenses but also telescopes and microscopes.[99] The quality of Spinoza's lenses was praised by Christiaan Huygens and others.[100] In fact, his technique and instruments were so esteemed that Constantijn Huygens ground a "clear and bright" telescope lens with focal length of 42 feet (13 m) in 1687 from one of Spinoza's grinding dishes, ten years after his death.[101] He was said by anatomist Theodor Kerckring to have produced an "excellent" microscope, the quality of which was the foundation of Kerckring's anatomy claims.[102] During his time as a lens and instrument maker, he was also supported by small but regular donations from close friends.[103]

Death and rescue of his unpublished writings edit

 
Burial monument of Spinoza at the churchyard of the Nieuwe Kerk (The Hague)

Spinoza's health began to fail in 1676, and he died in The Hague on 21 February 1677 at age 44, attended by a physician friend, Georg Herman Schuller. Although he had been ill with some form of lung affliction, described as "ex phthisi [from consumption]", possibly complicated by silicosis brought on by grinding glass lenses,[104] he and everyone he lived with did not expect him to die that day, and he died without leaving a will.[105][106] There were assertions that he had repented his philosophical stances on his deathbed, but all credible evidence points to his dying unrepentant and in tranquility. Lutheran preacher Johannes Colerus wrote the first biography of Spinoza for the original reason of researching his final days.[107]

Spinoza was buried in the Nieuwe Kerk (New Church) on the Spui four days after his death, on 25 February, inside the church, with six others in the same vault. At the time there was no memorial plaque for Spinoza. In the 18th century, the vault was emptied and the "remnants scattered over the earth of the churchyard." The memorial plaque visitors now see is outside, where some of his remains are part of the churchyard's soil.[108]

When he died, friends rescued his personal belongings and papers, most importantly his unpublished manuscripts. These were stored in a cabinet attached to his writing desk. His supporters swiftly took them away for safekeeping from seizure by those wishing to suppress his writings. They do not appear in the inventory of his possessions at death. Within a year of his death, his supporters translated his manuscripts written in Latin into Dutch, and subsequently into other vernacular languages. His works were banned by Dutch authorities and later the Roman Catholic Church.[109][110]

Writings edit

Spinoza published little in his lifetime and most of his formal writings were in Latin, which would have reached only a small number of readers. He actively told supporters not to translate his works, but following his death, his supporters published his works posthumously, in Latin and Dutch. A descriptive bibliography has been published that contextualizes all aspects of the publication history of Spinoza's writings from manuscript to print.[111]

The reaction to the anonymously published work, Theologico-Political Treatise (TTP)(1670), was extremely unfavorable. Spinoza abstained from publishing further, but his writings circulated among his supporters in manuscript form during his lifetime. Wary and independent, he wore a signet ring which he used to mark his letters and which was engraved with the word caute (Latin for "cautiously") underneath a rose, itself a symbol of secrecy.[112]

The Ethics and all other works, apart from the Descartes' Principles of Philosophy, which was published under his own name, and the Theologico-Political Treatise, published anonymously, appeared in print after his 1677 death. The Opera Posthuma was edited by his friends in secrecy to prevent confiscation and destruction of manuscripts. The Ethics contains many still-unresolved obscurities and is written with a forbidding mathematical structure modeled on Euclid's geometry and has been described as a "superbly cryptic masterwork".[113]

Correspondence edit

 
Letter from Spinoza to Leibniz, with his BdS seal

Few letters are extant for such an important intellectual figure and none before 1661. Practically all of them are of philosophical, technical nature, since "the political and ecclesiastical persecution of the time led the original editors of the Opera Posthuma his friends Lodewijk Meyer, Georg Hermann Schuller, and Johannes Bouwmeester—to delete personal matters and to disregard letters of a personal nature".[114] Spinoza engaged in correspondence from December 1664 to June 1665 with Willem van Blijenbergh, an amateur Calvinist theologian, who questioned Spinoza on the definition of evil. Later in 1665, Spinoza notified Oldenburg that he had started to work on a new book, the Theologico-Political Treatise, published in 1670. Leibniz disagreed harshly with Spinoza in his own manuscript "Refutation of Spinoza",[115] but he is also known to have met with Spinoza on at least one occasion[95][96] and his work bears some striking resemblances to some parts of Spinoza's philosophy, like in Monadology. Leibniz was concerned when his name was not redacted from a letter to Spinoza that was printed in the Opera Posthuma.[116]

In a letter, written in December 1675 and sent to Albert Burgh, who wanted to defend Catholicism, Spinoza clearly explained his view of both Catholicism and Islam. He stated that both religions are made "to deceive the people and to constrain the minds of men". He also states that Islam far surpasses Catholicism in doing so.[117][118] The Tractatus de Deo, Homine, ejusque Felicitate (Treatise on God, man and his happiness) was one of the last of Spinoza's works to be published, between 1851[119] and 1862.[120]

Philosophy edit

Spinoza's philosophy is explicated in his two major publications originally written in Latin, the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (TTP) (1670) and Ethics, published posthumously in Latin and Dutch. His incomplete Tractatus Politicus was also published posthumously.

Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (TTP) edit

 

Despite its being published in Latin rather than a vernacular language, this 1670 treatise published in Spinoza's lifetime caused a huge reaction, described as "one of the most significant events in European intellectual history."[121][122]

Ethics edit

The Ethics has been associated with that of Leibniz and René Descartes as part of the rationalist school of thought,[123] which includes the assumption that ideas correspond to reality perfectly, in the same way that mathematics is supposed to be an exact representation of the world. The writings of René Descartes have been described as "Spinoza's starting point".[113] Spinoza's first publication was his 1663 geometric exposition of proofs using Euclid's model with definitions and axioms of Descartes' Principles of Philosophy. Following Descartes, Spinoza aimed to understand truth through logical deductions from 'clear and distinct ideas', a process which always begins from the 'self-evident truths' of axioms.[124] However, his actual project does not end there: from his first work to his last one, there runs a thread of "attending to the highest good" (which also is the highest truth) and thereby achieving a state of peace and harmony, either in the metaphysical or political manner. In this light, the Principles of Philosophy might be viewed as an "exercise in geometric method and philosophy", paving the way for numerous concepts and conclusions that would define his philosophy (see Cogitata Metaphysica).[125]

Metaphysics edit

Spinoza's metaphysics consists of one thing, substance, and its modifications (modes). Early in The Ethics Spinoza argues that there is only one substance, which is absolutely infinite, self-caused, and eternal. He calls this substance "God", or "Nature". In fact, he takes these two terms to be synonymous (in the Latin the phrase he uses is "Deus sive Natura"). For Spinoza the whole of the natural universe consists of one substance, God, or, what is the same, Nature, and its modifications (modes).

It cannot be overemphasized how the rest of Spinoza's philosophy—his philosophy of mind, his epistemology, his psychology, his moral philosophy, his political philosophy, and his philosophy of religion—flows more or less directly from the metaphysical underpinnings in Part I of the Ethics.[126]

Substance, attributes, and modes edit

Spinoza sets forth a vision of Being, illuminated by his awareness of God. They may seem strange at first sight. To the question "What is?" he replies: "Substance, its attributes, and modes".

Following Maimonides, Spinoza defined substance as "that which is in itself and is conceived through itself", meaning that it can be understood without any reference to anything external.[128] Being conceptually independent also means that the same thing is ontologically independent, depending on nothing else for its existence and being the 'cause of itself' (causa sui).[128] A mode is something which cannot exist independently but rather must do so as part of something else on which it depends, including properties (for example colour), relations (such as size) and individual things.[129] Modes can be further divided into 'finite' and 'infinite' ones, with the latter being evident in every finite mode (he gives the examples of "motion" and "rest").[130] The traditional understanding of an attribute in philosophy is similar to Spinoza's modes, though he uses that word differently.[129] To him, an attribute is "that which the intellect perceives as constituting the essence of substance", and there are possibly an infinite number of them.[131] It is the essential nature which is "attributed" to reality by intellect.[132]

 
Probable portrait of Spinoza, by Barend Graat, 1666

Spinoza defined God as "a substance consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence", and since "no cause or reason" can prevent such a being from existing, it therefore must exist.[132] This is a form of the ontological argument, which is claimed to prove the existence of God, but Spinoza went further in stating that it showed that only God exists.[133] Accordingly, he stated that "Whatever is, is in God, and nothing can exist or be conceived without God".[133][134] This means that God is identical with the universe, an idea which he encapsulated in the phrase "Deus sive Natura" ('God or Nature'), which has been interpreted by some as atheism or pantheism.[135] Though there are many more of them, God can be known by humans either through the attribute of extension or the attribute of thought.[136] Thought and extension represent giving complete accounts of the world in mental or physical terms.[137] To this end, he says that "the mind and the body are one and the same thing, which is conceived now under the attribute of thought, now under the attribute of extension".[138]

After stating his proof for God's existence, Spinoza addresses who "God" is. Spinoza believed that God is "the sum of the natural and physical laws of the universe and certainly not an individual entity or creator".[139] Spinoza attempts to prove that God is just the substance of the universe by first stating that substances do not share attributes or essences and then demonstrating that God is a "substance" with an infinite number of attributes, thus the attributes possessed by any other substances must also be possessed by God. Therefore, God is just the sum of all the substances of the universe. God is the only substance in the universe, and everything is a part of God. This view was described by Charles Hartshorne as Classical Pantheism.[140]

Spinoza argues that "things could not have been produced by God in any other way or in any other order than is the case".[141] Therefore, concepts such as 'freedom' and 'chance' have little meaning.[135] This picture of Spinoza's determinism is illuminated in Ethics: "the infant believes that it is by free will that it seeks the breast; the angry boy believes that by free will he wishes vengeance; the timid man thinks it is with free will he seeks flight; the drunkard believes that by a free command of his mind he speaks the things which when sober he wishes he had left unsaid. … All believe that they speak by a free command of the mind, whilst, in truth, they have no power to restrain the impulse which they have to speak."[142] In his letter to G. H. Schuller (Letter 58), he wrote: "men are conscious of their desire and unaware of the causes by which [their desires] are determined."[143] He also held that knowledge of true causes of passive emotion can transform it into an active emotion, thus anticipating one of the key ideas of Sigmund Freud's psychoanalysis.[144]

According to Eric Schliesser, Spinoza was skeptical regarding the possibility of knowledge of nature and as a consequence at odds with scientists such as Galileo and Huygens.[145]

Causality edit

Although the principle of sufficient reason is commonly associated with Gottfried Leibniz, Spinoza employs it in a more systematic manner. In Spinoza's philosophical framework, questions concerning why a particular phenomenon exists are always answerable, and these answers are provided in terms of the relevant cause. Spinoza's approach involves first providing an account of a phenomenon, such as goodness or consciousness, to explain it, and then further explaining the phenomenon in terms of itself. For instance, he might argue that consciousness is the degree of power of a mental state.[146]

Spinoza has also been described as an "Epicurean materialist",[113] specifically in reference to his opposition to Cartesian mind-body dualism. This view was held by Epicureans before him, as they believed that atoms with their probabilistic paths were the only substance that existed fundamentally.[147][148] Spinoza, however, deviated significantly from Epicureans by adhering to strict determinism, much like the Stoics before him, in contrast to the Epicurean belief in the probabilistic path of atoms, which is more in line with contemporary thought on quantum mechanics.[147][149]

The emotions edit

One thing which seems, on the surface, to distinguish Spinoza's view of the emotions from both Descartes' and Hume's pictures of them is that he takes the emotions to be cognitive in some important respect. Jonathan Bennett claims that "Spinoza mainly saw emotions as caused by cognitions. [However] he did not say this clearly enough and sometimes lost sight of it entirely."[150] Spinoza provides several demonstrations which purport to show truths about how human emotions work. The picture presented is, according to Bennett, "unflattering, coloured as it is by universal egoism".[151]

Ethical philosophy edit

 
Engraving of Spinoza, captioned in Latin, "A Jew and an atheist"; he vehemently denied being an atheist.

Spinoza's notion of blessedness figures centrally in his ethical philosophy. Spinoza writes that blessedness (or salvation or freedom), "consists, namely, in a constant and eternal love of God, or in God's love for men.[152] Philosopher Jonathan Bennett interprets this as Spinoza wanting "'blessedness' to stand for the most elevated and desirable state one could possibly be in."[153] Understanding what is meant by "most elevated and desirable state" requires understanding Spinoza's notion of conatus (striving, but not necessarily with any teleological baggage)[citation needed] and that "perfection" refers not to (moral) value, but to completeness. Given that individuals are identified as mere modifications of the infinite Substance, it follows that no individual can ever be fully complete, i.e., perfect, or blessed. Absolute perfection, is, in Spinoza's thought, reserved solely for Substance. Nevertheless, modes can attain a lesser form of blessedness, namely, that of pure understanding of oneself as one really is, i.e., as a definite modification of Substance in a certain set of relationships with everything else in the universe. That this is what Spinoza has in mind can be seen at the end of the Ethics, in E5P24 and E5P25, where Spinoza makes two final key moves, unifying the metaphysical, epistemological, and ethical propositions he has developed over the course of the work. In E5P24, he links the understanding of particular things to the understanding of God, or Substance; in E5P25, the conatus of the mind is linked to the third kind of knowledge (Intuition). From here, it is a short step to the connection of Blessedness with the amor dei intellectualis ("intellectual love of God").[citation needed]

Tractatus Politicus (Political Treatise) (TP) edit

 
The title page of the Tractatus politicus in the Opera Posthuma.

This unfinished treatise in Latin expounds Spinoza's ideas about forms of government. As with the Ethics, this work was published posthumously by his circle of supporters in Latin and in Dutch. The subtitle is "In quo demonstratur, quomodo Societas, ubi Imperium Monarchicum locum habet, sicut et ea, ubi Optimi imperant, debet institui, ne in Tyrannidem labatur, et ut Pax, Libertasque civium inviolata maneat." ("In which it is demonstrated how a society, may it be a monarchy or an aristocracy, can be best governed, so as not to fall into tyranny, and so that the peace and liberty of the citizens remain unviolated").

Although Spinoza's political and theological thought was radical on many ways, he held traditional views on the place of women. In the TP, he writes briefly on the last page of the TP that women were “naturally” subordinate to men, stating bluntly his women are “by nature” not by “institutional practice” subordinate to men. Both his major biographers in English remark on his view of women. Biographer Steven Nadler is clearly disappointed by Spinoza's only statement on women. “It is unfortunate that the very last words we have by him, at the end of the extant chapters of the Political Treatise, are a short digression … on the unsuitability of women to hold political power.”[154] Likewise Jonathan I. Israel says that Spinoza's views are “hugely disappointing to the modern reader” and that most that can be said in his defense is that “in his age rampant tyrannizing over women was indeed universal.” He goes on to say, "one may legitimately wonder why did Spinoza, if he was to be consistent, not apply his highly sceptical and innovative, for his time uniquely subversive, de-legtimizing general principle likewise to men's tyrannizing over women."[155] One scholar has attempted to rationalize Spinoza's views excluding women from full citizenship.[156] But the topic has not attracted major consideration in Spinoza studies.

Pantheism edit

Spinoza was considered to be an atheist because he used the word "God" [Deus] to signify a concept that was different from that of traditional Judeo–Christian monotheism. "Spinoza expressly denies personality and consciousness to God; he has neither intelligence, feeling, nor will; he does not act according to purpose, but everything follows necessarily from his nature, according to law...."[157] Thus, Spinoza's cool, indifferent God differs from the concept of an anthropomorphic, fatherly God who cares about humanity.[158]

In 1785, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi published a condemnation of Spinoza's pantheism, after Gotthold Lessing was thought to have confessed on his deathbed to being a "Spinozist", which was the equivalent in his time of being called an atheist. Jacobi claimed that Spinoza's doctrine was pure materialism, because all Nature and God are said to be nothing but extended substance. This, for Jacobi, was the result of Enlightenment rationalism and it would finally end in absolute atheism. Moses Mendelssohn disagreed with Jacobi, saying that there is no actual difference between theism and pantheism. The issue became a major intellectual and religious concern for European civilization at the time.

The attraction of Spinoza's philosophy to late 18th-century Europeans was that it provided an alternative to materialism, atheism, and deism. Three of Spinoza's ideas strongly appealed to them:

  • the unity of all that exists;
  • the regularity of all that happens;
  • the identity of spirit and nature.[159]

By 1879, Spinoza's pantheism was praised by many, but was considered by some to be alarming and dangerously inimical.[160]

Spinoza's "God or Nature" (Deus sive Natura) provided a living, natural God, in contrast to Isaac Newton's first cause argument and the dead mechanism of Julien Offray de La Mettrie's (1709–1751) work, Man a Machine (L'homme machine). Coleridge and Shelley saw in Spinoza's philosophy a religion of nature.[103] Novalis called him the "God-intoxicated man".[113][161] Spinoza inspired the poet Shelley to write his essay "The Necessity of Atheism".[113]

It is a widespread belief that Spinoza equated God with the material universe. He has therefore been called the "prophet"[162] and "prince"[163] and most eminent expounder of pantheism. More specifically, in a letter to Henry Oldenburg he states, "as to the view of certain people that I identify God with Nature (taken as a kind of mass or corporeal matter), they are quite mistaken".[164] For Spinoza, the universe (cosmos) is a mode under two attributes of Thought and Extension. God has infinitely many other attributes which are not present in the world.

According to German philosopher Karl Jaspers (1883–1969), when Spinoza wrote Deus sive Natura (Latin for 'God or Nature'), Spinoza meant God was natura naturans (nature doing what nature does; literally, 'nature naturing'), not natura naturata (nature already created; literally, 'nature natured'). Jaspers believed that Spinoza, in his philosophical system, did not mean to say that God and Nature are interchangeable terms, but rather that God's transcendence was attested by his infinitely many attributes, and that two attributes known by humans, namely Thought and Extension, signified God's immanence.[165] Even God under the attributes of thought and extension cannot be identified strictly with our world. That world is of course "divisible"; it has parts. But Spinoza said, "no attribute of a substance can be truly conceived from which it follows that the substance can be divided", meaning that one cannot conceive an attribute in a way that leads to division of substance. He also said, "a substance which is absolutely infinite is indivisible" (Ethics, Part I, Propositions 12 and 13).[166] Following this logic, our world should be considered as a mode under two attributes of thought and extension. Therefore, according to Jaspers, the pantheist formula "One and All" would apply to Spinoza only if the "One" preserves its transcendence and the "All" were not interpreted as the totality of finite things.[165]

Martial Guéroult (1891–1976) suggested the term panentheism, rather than pantheism to describe Spinoza's view of the relation between God and the world. The world is not God, but in a strong sense, "in" God. Not only do finite things have God as their cause; they cannot be conceived without God.[166] However, American panentheist philosopher Charles Hartshorne (1897–2000) insisted on the term Classical Pantheism to describe Spinoza's view.[140]

According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spinoza's God is an "infinite intellect" (Ethics 2p11c) — all-knowing (2p3), and capable of loving both himself—and us, insofar as we are part of his perfection (5p35c). And if the mark of a personal being is that it is one towards which we can entertain personal attitudes, then we should note too that Spinoza recommends amor intellectualis dei (the intellectual love of God) as the supreme good for man (5p33). However, the matter is complex. Spinoza's God does not have free will (1p32c1), he does not have purposes or intentions (1 appendix), and Spinoza insists that "neither intellect nor will pertain to the nature of God" (1p17s1). Moreover, while we may love God, we need to remember that God is not a being who could ever love us back. "He who loves God cannot strive that God should love him in return", says Spinoza (5p19).[167]

Steven Nadler suggests that settling the question of Spinoza's atheism or pantheism depends on an analysis of attitudes. If pantheism is associated with religiosity, then Spinoza is not a pantheist, since Spinoza believes that the proper stance to take towards God is not one of reverence or religious awe, but instead one of objective study and reason, since taking the religious stance would leave one open to the possibility of error and superstition.[168]

Other philosophical connections edit

Many authors have discussed similarities between Spinoza's philosophy and Eastern philosophical traditions. Few decades after the philosopher's death, Pierre Bayle, in his famous Historical and Critical Dictionary (1697) pointed out a link between Spinoza's alleged atheism with "the theology of a Chinese sect", supposedly called "Foe Kiao",[169] of which had learned thanks to the testimonies of the Jesuit missions in Eastern Asia. A century later, Kant also established a parallel between the philosophy of Spinoza and the think of Laozi (a "monstrous system" in his words), grouping both under the name of pantheists, criticizing what he described as mystical tendencies in them.[170]

The 19th-century German Sanskritist Theodor Goldstücker was one of the early figures to notice the similarities between Spinoza's religious conceptions and the Vedanta tradition of India, writing that Spinoza's thought was "... so exact a representation of the ideas of the Vedanta, that we might have suspected its founder to have borrowed the fundamental principles of his system from the Hindus, did his biography not satisfy us that he was wholly unacquainted with their doctrines..."[171][172] Max Müller also noted the striking similarities between Vedanta and the system of Spinoza, equating the Brahman in Vedanta to Spinoza's 'Substantia.'[173]

Legacy edit

 
A Dutch commemorative coin issued on the 250th death anniversary of Spinoza, 1927

Spinoza's ideas have had a major impact on intellectual debates from the seventeenth century to the current era. How Spinoza is viewed has gone from the atheistic author of treatises that undermine Judaism and organized religion, to a cultural hero, the first secular Jew.[174] One writer contends that what draws readers to Spinoza today and "makes him perhaps the most beloved philosopher since Socrates, is his confident equanimity". He is not a despairing nihilist, but rather Spinoza says that "blessedness is nothing else but the contentment of spirit, which arises from the intuitive knowledge of God."[175] One of his biographers, Jonathan I. Israel, argues that "No leading figure of the post-1750 later Enlightenment, for example, or the nineteenth century, was engaged with the philosophy of Descartes, Hobbes, Bayle, Locke, or Leibniz, to the degree leading figures such as Lessing, Goethe, Kant, Hegel, Fichte, Schelling, Heine, George Eliot, and Nietzsche, remained preoccupied throughout their creative lives with Spinoza."[176] Hegel (1770-1831) asserts that "The fact is that Spinoza is made a testing-point in modern philosophy, so that it may really be said: You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all."[177]

His expulsion from the Portuguese synagogue in 1656 has stirred debate over the years on whether he is the "first modern Jew". Spinoza influenced discussions of the so-called Jewish question, the examination of the idea of Judaism and the modern, secular Jew. Moses Mendelsohn, Lessing, Heine, and Kant, as well as subsequent thinkers, including Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud were influenced by Spinoza.[178] The changing conception of Spinoza as "the First Modern Jew" has been explicitly explored by various authors.[179][180][181] His expulsion has been revisited in the 21st century, with Jewish writers such Berthold Auerbach; Salomon Rubin, who translated Spinoza's Ethics into Hebrew and saw Spinoza as a new Maimonides, penning "a new guide to the perplexed"; Zionist Yosef Klausner, and fiction-writer Isaac Bashevis Singer shaping his image.[181]

In 1886, the young George Santayana published "The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza", in The Harvard Monthly.[182] Much later, he wrote an introduction to Spinoza's Ethics and "De Intellectus Emendatione".[183] In 1932, Santayana was invited to present an essay (published as "Ultimate Religion")[184] at a meeting at The Hague celebrating the tricentennial of Spinoza's birth. In Santayana's autobiography, he characterized Spinoza as his "master and model" in understanding the naturalistic basis of morality.[185]

Philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein evoked Spinoza with the title (suggested to him by G. E. Moore) of the English translation of his first definitive philosophical work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, an allusion to Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. Elsewhere, Wittgenstein deliberately borrowed the expression sub specie aeternitatis from Spinoza (Notebooks, 1914–16, p. 83). The structure of his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus does have some structural affinities with Spinoza's Ethics (though, admittedly, not with the Spinoza's Tractatus) in erecting complex philosophical arguments upon basic logical propositions and principles. In propositions 6.4311 and 6.45 he alludes to a Spinozian understanding of eternity and interpretation of the religious concept of eternal life, contending, "If by eternity is understood not eternal temporal duration, but timelessness, then he lives eternally who lives in the present." (6.4311) "The contemplation of the world sub specie aeterni is its contemplation as a limited whole." (6.45)

Spinoza's philosophy played an important role in the development of post-war French philosophy. Many of these philosophers "used Spinoza to erect a bulwark against the nominally irrationalist tendencies of phenomenology", which was associated with the dominance of Hegel, Martin Heidegger, and Edmund Husserl in France at that time.[186] Louis Althusser, as well as his colleagues such as Étienne Balibar, saw in Spinoza a philosophy which could lead Marxism out of what they considered to be flaws in its original formulation, particularly its reliance upon Hegel's conception of the dialectic, as well as Spinoza's concept of immanent causality. Antonio Negri, in exile in France for much of this period, also wrote a number of books on Spinoza, most notably The Savage Anomaly (1981) in his own reconfiguration of Italian Autonomia Operaia. Other notable French scholars of Spinoza in this period included Alexandre Matheron, Martial Gueroult, André Tosel, and Pierre Macherey, the last of whom published a widely read and influential five-volume commentary on Spinoza's Ethics, which has been described as "a monument of Spinoza commentary".[187] His philosophical accomplishments and moral character prompted Gilles Deleuze in his doctoral thesis (1968) to name him "the prince of philosophers".[188][189] Deleuze's interpretation of Spinoza's philosophy was highly influential among French philosophers, especially in restoring to prominence the political dimension of Spinoza's thought.[190] Deleuze published two books on Spinoza and gave numerous lectures on Spinoza in his capacity as a professor at the University of Paris VIII. His own work was deeply influenced by Spinoza's philosophy, particularly the concepts of immanence and univocity. Marilena de Souza Chaui described Deleuze's Expressionism in Philosophy (1968) as a "revolutionary work for its discovery of expression as a central concept in Spinoza's philosophy."[190][clarification needed]

 
Einstein 1921

Albert Einstein named Spinoza as the philosopher who exerted the most influence on his world view (Weltanschauung). Spinoza equated God (infinite substance) with Nature, consistent with Einstein's belief in an impersonal deity. In 1929, Einstein was asked in a telegram by Rabbi Herbert S. Goldstein whether he believed in God. Einstein responded by telegram: "I believe in Spinoza's God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists, not in a God who concerns himself with the fates and actions of human beings."[191][192] Einstein wrote the preface to a biography of Spinoza, published in 1946.[193]

Leo Strauss dedicated his first book, Spinoza's Critique of Religion, to an examination of his ideas. Strauss identified Spinoza as part of the tradition of Enlightenment rationalism that eventually produced Modernity. Moreover, he identifies Spinoza and his works as the beginning of Jewish Modernity.[113] More recently Jonathan Israel argued that, from 1650 to 1750, Spinoza was "the chief challenger of the fundamentals of revealed religion, received ideas, tradition, morality, and what was everywhere regarded, in absolutist and non-absolutist states alike, as divinely constituted political authority."[194]

Spinoza is an important historical figure in the Netherlands, where his portrait was featured prominently on the Dutch 1000-guilder banknote, legal tender until the euro was introduced in 2002. The highest and most prestigious scientific award of the Netherlands is named the Spinozaprijs (Spinoza prize). Spinoza was included in a 50 theme canon that attempts to summarise the history of the Netherlands.[195] In 2014 a copy of Spinoza's Tractatus Theologico-Politicus was presented to the Chair of the Dutch Parliament, and shares a shelf with the Bible and the Quran.[196]

Modern era edit

Reconsideration of Spinoza's expulsion edit

There has been a renewed debate in modern times about Spinoza's excommunication among Israeli politicians, rabbis and Jewish press, with many calling for the cherem to be reversed.[197] A conference was organized at the YIVO Institute for Jewish Research in New York entitled "From Heretic to Hero: A Symposium on the Impact of Baruch Spinoza on the 350th Anniversary of His Excommunication, 1656-2006". Presenters included Steven Nadler, Jonathan I. Israel, Steven B. Smith, and Daniel B. Schwartz.[198] There have been calls for Spinoza's cherem to be rescinded, but it can only be done by the congregation that issued it, and the chief rabbi of that community,[d] Haham Pinchas Toledano, declined to do so, citing Spinoza's "preposterous ideas, where he was tearing apart the very fundamentals of our religion",[199] the Amsterdam Jewish community organised a symposium in December 2015 to discuss lifting the cherem, inviting scholars from around the world to form an advisory committee at the meeting. However, the rabbi of the congregation ruled that it should hold, on the basis that he had no greater wisdom than his predecessors, and that Spinoza's views had not become less problematic over time.[197]

Memory and memorials edit

 
Statue (2008) of Spinoza by Nicolas Dings, Amsterdam, Zwanenburgwal, with inscription "The objective of the state is freedom" (translation, quote from Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, 1677)
  • Spinoza Lyceum, a high school in Amsterdam South was named after Spinoza. There is also a 3 metre tall marble statue of him on the grounds of the school carved by Hildo Krop.[200]
  • The Spinoza Havurah (a Humanistic Jewish community) was named in Spinoza's honor.[201]
  • The Spinoza Foundation Monument has a statute of Spinoza located in front of the Amsterdam City Hall (at Zwanenburgwal) [202] It was created by Dutch sculptor Nicolas Dings and was erected in 2008.[203][204]

Depictions and influence in literature edit

Spinoza's life and work have been subject of interest for several writers. For example, this influence was considerably early in German literature, where Goethe makes a glowing mention of the philosopher in his memoirs, highlighting a positive influence by the Ethics in his personal life.[205] The same thing happened in the case of his compatriot, the poet Heine, who is also lavish in praise for Spinoza on his On the History of Religion and Philosophy in Germany (1834).[206]

In the following century, the Argentinian Jorge Luis Borges famously wrote two sonnets in his honor ("Spinoza" in El otro, el mismo, 1964; and "Baruch Spinoza" in La moneda de hierro, 1976), and several direct references to Spinoza's philosophy can be found in this writer's work.[207] Also in Argentina and previously to Borges, the Ukrainian-born Jewish intellectual Alberto Gerchunoff wrote a novella about philosopher's early sentimental life, Los amores de Baruj [sic] Spinoza (lit. "The loves of Baruj Spinoza", 1932), recreating a supposed affair or romantic interest with Clara Maria van den Enden, daughter of his latin teacher and philosophical preceptor, Franciscus.[208]

That is not the only fiction work where the philosopher appears as the main character. In 1837 the German writer Berthold Auerbach dedicated to him the first novel in his series on Jewish history, translated into English in 1882 (Spinoza: a Novel).[209] Some other novels of biographical nature have appeared more recently, as The Spinoza Problem (2012; a parallel story between the philosopher's formative years, and the fascination that his work had on the Nazi leader Alfred Rosenberg) by psychiatrist Irvin D. Yalom, or O Segredo de Espinosa (lit. "The Secret of Spinoza", 2023) by Portuguese journalist José Rodrigues dos Santos. Spinoza also appear in the first novel of the Argentinian activist Andres Spokoiny, El impío (lit. "The Impious", 2021), about the marrano phicicyst and philosopher Juan de Prado, a key influence in his biography. [210]

Not directly his person, but his influence or legacy are themes present both in "The Spinoza of Market Street", a short story by the Polish-born Jewish-American Nobel Prize winner Isaac Bashevis Singer (originally written in yiddish in 1961), and also in the recent novel by Mexican Ezra Béjar Un Baruch para Spinoza (lit. "A Baruch for Spinoza", 2023).[211]

In another sense, Spinoza's philosophy is an important part of the series of satirical punk post-apocalyptic fiction novels by the French writer Jean-Bernard Pouy, begun with Spinoza encule Hegel (lit. "Spinoza fucks Hegel", 1983), where the protagonist take the nickname of "Spinoza" or "Spino" and projects a violent application of his thinking in a lawless world. The series continued with two more novels, subsequently issued in 1998 and 2006.

Finally, the British art critic John Berger published some prose poems and drawings under the title of Bento's Sketchbook (2011), inspired by the Philosopher's work (from which he takes literal quotes), and in the anecdote about the existence of a drawing notebook among his belongings that disappeared after his death.

Works edit

Original Editions edit

  • c. 1660. Korte Verhandeling van God, de mensch en deszelvs welstand (unpublished until the 19th century; A Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being; translated by A. Wolf. London, Adam and Charles Black Eds., 1910).
  • 1662. Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione (On the Improvement of the Understanding) (unfinished).
  • 1663. Principia philosophiae cartesianae (The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, also contains Metaphysical Thoughts/Cogitata Metaphisica; translated by Samuel Shirley, with an Introduction and Notes by Steven Barbone and Lee Rice, Indianapolis, 1998).
  • 1670. Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (A Theologico-Political Treatise), TTP, published anonymously in his lifetime with a false place of publication.
  • 1675–76. Tractatus Politicus (), TP (unfinished at his death), published posthumously.
  • 1677. Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata (The Ethics, finished 1674, but published posthumously, title added posthumously).
  • 1677. Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae (Hebrew Grammar, unfinished; translated with introduction by M. J. Bloom, London, 1963).[212]
  • 1677. Epistolae (The Letters, translated by Samuel Shirley, with an Introduction and Notes by S. Barbone, L. Rice and J. Adler, Indianapolis, 1995).
  • Last four were originally collected and published by Spinoza's friends briefly later his death, in: B. d. S. Opera Posthuma, Quorum series post Praefationem exhibetur.  (Amsterdam: Jan Rieuwertsz, 1677; both publisher and place were purposely omitted). Simultaneously, Rieuwertsz also published a Dutch translation by Jan Hendriksz Glazemaker (who some years later translated the TTP): De Nagelate Schriften van B. d. S., without the Hebrew Grammar.

Contemporary Editions edit

  • Morgan, Michael L. (ed.), 2002. Spinoza: Complete Works, with the Translation of Samuel Shirley, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-87220-620-5.
  • Edwin Curley (ed.), 1985, 2016. The Collected Works of Spinoza (two volumes), Princeton: Princeton University Press.(Excludes the Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae).
  • Spruit, Leen and Pina Totaro, 2011. The Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza's Ethica, Leiden: Brill. This is the only known surviving manuscript of Spinoza's Ethics, discovered in the Vatican archive and published in a bilingual Latin-English edition.

See also edit

References edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Spinoza has also been interpreted as a defender of the coherence theory of truth.[3]
  2. ^ /bəˈrk spɪˈnzə/;[12] Dutch: [baːˈrux spɪˈnoːzaː]; Portuguese: [ðɨ ʃpiˈnɔzɐ]; Hebrew: ברוך שפינוזה. His boyhood and early adult business name was "Bento", and his synagogue name was "Baruch", the Hebrew translation of "Bento", which means "blessed".[13] As a correspondent, he primarily signed his name as "Benedictus".[14]
  3. ^ Steven Nadler speculates that Spinoza Latinized his name at Leiden because all instruction was in Latin.[76]
  4. ^ Portugees-Israëlietische Gemeente te Amsterdam (Portuguese-Israelite commune of Amsterdam)

Citations edit

  1. ^ Garber 2015, p. 121.
  2. ^ Newlands 2017, p. 64.
  3. ^ Young, James O. (26 June 2018). "The Coherence Theory of Truth". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  4. ^ David, Marian (28 May 2015). "The Correspondence Theory of Truth". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  5. ^ Koistinen 2018, p. 288.
  6. ^ Kreines 2015, p. 25.
  7. ^ LeBuffe, Michael (26 May 2020). "Spinoza's Psychological Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. ^ Yovel 1989b, p. 3.
  9. ^ a b Nadler 1999, p. 45.
  10. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 119.
  11. ^ Adler 2014, p. 27.
  12. ^ "Spinoza". Collins English Dictionary. HarperCollins. Retrieved 27 April 2019.
  13. ^ Nadler 1999, p. 42.
  14. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 353–54.
  15. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. xiii–xiv.
  16. ^ Dutton, Blake D. "Benedict De Spinoza (1632–1677)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 7 July 2019.
  17. ^ Stewart 2006, p. 352.
  18. ^ Simkins 2014.
  19. ^ Carlisle 2021, p. 10.
  20. ^ Smith 1997, p. 2.
  21. ^ Goldstein 2006, p. i.
  22. ^ a b Israel 2023, p. 115.
  23. ^ Israel 2023, p. 85.
  24. ^ Israel 2023, p. 134.
  25. ^ Israel 2023, p. 88.
  26. ^ Israel 2023, p. 299.
  27. ^ Israel 2023, p. 124.
  28. ^ a b Israel 2023, p. 158.
  29. ^ Israel 2023, p. 144.
  30. ^ Israel 2023, p. 140.
  31. ^ a b Israel 2023, p. 140-41.
  32. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 38.
  33. ^ a b Israel 2023, p. 183.
  34. ^ Israel 2023, p. 117.
  35. ^ a b Israel 2023, p. 185.
  36. ^ Israel 2023, p. 145-46.
  37. ^ Israel 2023, p. 159.
  38. ^ Israel 2023, p. 160.
  39. ^ Israel 2023, p. 161.
  40. ^ Israel 2023, p. 90.
  41. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 84.
  42. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 148–49.
  43. ^ Nadler 1999, pp. 65–66.
  44. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. 72–75.
  45. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 93.
  46. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. 100–101.
  47. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 206.
  48. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 204–05.
  49. ^ a b Israel 2023, pp. 205–06.
  50. ^ Israel 2023, p. 210.
  51. ^ a b c Nadler 2001, p. 25.
  52. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 220–22.
  53. ^ Israel 2023, p. 222.
  54. ^ Nadler 2001, pp. 17–22.
  55. ^ Israel 2023, p. 74.
  56. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 21.
  57. ^ Touber 2018, p. 45.
  58. ^ Nadler 2001, pp. 2–7.
  59. ^ Smith 2003, p. xx.
  60. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 19.
  61. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 20.
  62. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 16.
  63. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 160.
  64. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 28.
  65. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 22.
  66. ^ a b Israel 2023, pp. 229–30.
  67. ^ Israel 2023, p. 243.
  68. ^ Nadler 2011, p. 167.
  69. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. 129–30.
  70. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. 125–26.
  71. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 342.
  72. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 164.
  73. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 168.
  74. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 338–39.
  75. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 184.
  76. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 193.
  77. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 333–38.
  78. ^ Israel 2023, p. 322.
  79. ^ Israel 2023, p. 330.
  80. ^ Israel 2023, p. 350.
  81. ^ Israel 2023, p. 344.
  82. ^ Israel 2023, p. 343.
  83. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 214.
  84. ^ Israel 2023, p. 456.
  85. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 225.
  86. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 12.
  87. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. 215–16.
  88. ^ Nadler 2018, pp. 243–45.
  89. ^ Kirsch, Adam, "The Reticent Radical: Baruch Spinoza's quiet revolution". The New Yorker, February 12 & 19, 2024, 89-92
  90. ^ "he [Spinoza] told me [Leibniz] he had a strong desire, on the day of the massacre of Mess. De Witt, to sally forth at night, and put up somewhere, near the place of the massacre, a paper with the words Ultimi barbarorum [ultimate barbarians]. But his host had shut the house to prevent his going out, for he would have run the risk of being torn to pieces." (A Refutation Recently Discovered of Spinoza by Leibnitz, "Remarks on the Unpublished Refutation of Spinoza by Leibnitz", Edinburg: Thomas Constable and Company, 1855. p. 70.
  91. ^ Nadler 2011, p. 239.
  92. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 26.
  93. ^ Chauí 2001, pp. 30–31: "A commentary on Descartes' work, Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, only work published under his own name, brought him on an invitation to teach philosophy at the University of Heidelberg. Spinoza, however, refused, thinking that it might demand the renunciation of his freedom of thought, for the invite stipulated that all care should be taken to 'not insult the principles of the established religion'."
  94. ^ Popkin, Richard H., "Benedict de Spinoza" in The Columbia History of Western Philosophy (Columbia University Press, 1999), p. 381.
  95. ^ a b Lucas 1960.
  96. ^ a b Stewart 2006, pp. 12–14.
  97. ^ Christiaan Huygens, Oeuvres complètes, Letter No. 1638, 11 May 1668
  98. ^ Christiaan Huygens, Oeuvres complètes, letter to his brother 23 September 1667
  99. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 215.
  100. ^ Nadler 2001, p. 183.
  101. ^ Christiaan Huygens, Oeuvres complètes, vol. XXII, p. 732, footnote
  102. ^ Theodore Kerckring, "Spicilegium Anatomicum" Observatio XCIII (1670)
  103. ^ a b Gottlieb, Anthony. "God Exists, Philosophically". archive.nytimes.com. Retrieved 18 March 2024.
  104. ^ Gullan-Whur 1998, pp. 317–18.
  105. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 1150–1151.
  106. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 406.
  107. ^ Israel 2023, p. 1155.
  108. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 1158.
  109. ^ Jonathan Israel, "The Banning of Spinoza's Works in the Dutch Republic (1670–1678)", in: Wiep van Bunge and Wim Klever (eds.) Disguised and Overt Spinozism around 1700 (Leiden, 1996), pp. 3–14 (online 28 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine).
  110. ^ Totaro 2015, pp. 321–22.
  111. ^ Ven, Jeroen van de. Printing Spinoza: A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century. Leiden; Brill, 2022.
  112. ^ Stewart 2006, p. 106.
  113. ^ a b c d e f Bloom, Harold (16 June 2006). "Deciphering Spinoza, the Great Original – Book review of Betraying Spinoza. The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity by Rebecca Goldstein". The New York Times. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  114. ^ Morgan, Michael L. (2002). Spinoza: Complete Works, with the Translation of Samuel Shirley. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. p. 755. ISBN 978-0-87220-620-5.
  115. ^ see Refutation of Spinoza
  116. ^ Buruma 2024, pp. 166–67.
  117. ^ "Spinoza on Islam". 13 February 2012.
  118. ^ Spinoza, Baruch (2003). Correspondence of Spinoza. Translated by A. Wolf. Kessinger Publishing, LLC. p. 354.
  119. ^ Coyle, Patrick A. (1938). Some aspects of the philosophy of Spinoza and his ontological proof of the existence of God (PDF). University of Western Ontario, CA. p. 2. OCLC 1067012129. Retrieved 9 June 2021 – via University of Windsor, Electronic Theses and Dissertations.
  120. ^ Soley 1880.
  121. ^ Nadler 2011, p. xi.
  122. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 776.
  123. ^ Montanarelli, Lisa. "Spinoza stymies 'God's attorney' / Stewart argues the secular world was at stake in Leibniz face off". SFGate. Retrieved 20 March 2024.
  124. ^ Scruton 2002, pp. 31–32.
  125. ^ Morgan, Michael L. (2002). Spinoza: Complete Works, with the Translation of Samuel Shirley. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. p. 109. ISBN 978-0-87220-620-5.
  126. ^ Della Rocca 2008, p. 33.
  127. ^ Jaspers 1974, p. 9.
  128. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 41
  129. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 42
  130. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 43.
  131. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 44.
  132. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 45.
  133. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 38
  134. ^ Lin, Martin (2007). "Spinoza's Arguments for the Existence of God". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 75 (2): 269–297. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2007.00076.x.
  135. ^ a b Scruton 2002, p. 51.
  136. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 57.
  137. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 59.
  138. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 60.
  139. ^ Cannon, J. A. (2009, May 17). World in time of upheaval: Sources of enlightenment. Deseret News.
  140. ^ a b Charles Hartshorne and William Reese, "Philosophers Speak of God", Humanity Books, 1953 ch. 4
  141. ^ Baruch Spinoza. Ethics, in Spinoza: Complete Works, trans. by Samuel Shirley and ed. by Michael L. Morgan (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2002), see Part I, Proposition 33.
  142. ^ Curley 1996, p. 73.
  143. ^ Ethics, Pt. I, Prop. XXXVI, Appendix: "[M]en think themselves free inasmuch as they are conscious of their volitions and desires, and never even dream, in their ignorance, of the causes which have disposed of them so to wish and desire."
  144. ^ Scruton 2002, p. 86.
  145. ^ ""Spinoza and the Philosophy of Science: Mathematics, Motion, and Being"". PhilSci-Archive. 9 July 2012.
  146. ^ Della Rocca 2008, p. 30.
  147. ^ a b Konstan, David (8 July 2022). "Epicurus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  148. ^ Curley 1996, p. 118.
  149. ^ "Baruch Spinoza, "Human Beings are Determined"". Lander.edu. Retrieved 21 February 2017.
  150. ^ Bennett 1984, p. 276.
  151. ^ Bennett 1984, p. 277.
  152. ^ Spinoza, Benedictus de (1996). Ethics. Penguin Books. p. 176. ISBN 9780140435719.
  153. ^ Bennett 1984, p. 371.
  154. ^ Nadler 2018, p. 495.
  155. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 895–96.
  156. ^ Matheron, Alexandre, “Femmes et serviteurs dans lad démocratie spinoziste.” Revue philosophique de la la France et de l’étranger 2 (1977) 181-200
  157. ^ Frank Thilly, A History of Philosophy, § 47, Holt & Co., New York, 1914
  158. ^ "I believe in Spinoza's God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists, not in a God who concerns himself with fates and actions of human beings." These words were spoken by Albert Einstein, upon being asked if he believed in God by Rabbi Herbert Goldstein of the Institutional Synagogue, New York, April 24, 1921, published in the New York Times, April 25, 1929; from Einstein: The Life and Times Ronald W. Clark, New York: World Publishing Co., 1971, p. 413; also cited as a telegram to a Jewish newspaper, 1929, Einstein Archive 33–272, from Alice Calaprice, ed., The Expanded Quotable Einstein, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
  159. ^ Lange, Frederick Albert (1880). History of Materialism and Criticism of its Present Importance, Vol. II. Boston: Houghton, Osgood, & Co. p. 147. Retrieved 11 November 2015.
  160. ^ "The Pantheism of Spinoza Dr. Smith regarded as the most dangerous enemy of Christianity, and as he announced his conviction that it had gained the control of the schools, press and pulpit of the Old World [Europe], and was rapidly gaining the same control of the New [United States], his alarm and indignation sometimes rose to the eloquence of genuine passion." Memorial of the Rev. Henry Smith, D.D., LL D., Professor of Sacred Rhetoric and Pastoral Theology in Lane Theological Seminary, Consisting of Addresses on Occasion of the Anniversary of the Seminary, 8 May 1879, Together with Commemorative Resolutions, p. 26.
  161. ^ Hutchison, Percy (20 November 1932). "Spinoza, "God-Intoxicated Man"; Three Books Which Mark the Three Hundredth Anniversary of the Philosopher's Birth". The New York Times. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  162. ^ Picton, J. Allanson, "Pantheism: Its Story and Significance", 1905.
  163. ^ Fraser, Alexander Campbell "Philosophy of Theism", William Blackwood and Sons, 1895, p. 163.
  164. ^ Correspondence of Benedict de Spinoza, Wilder Publications (26 March 2009), ISBN 978-1-60459-156-9, letter 73.
  165. ^ a b Jaspers 1974, pp. 14, 95
  166. ^ a b Genevieve Lloyd, Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to Spinoza and The Ethics (Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks), Routledge; 1 edition (2 October 1996), ISBN 978-0-415-10782-2, p. 40
  167. ^ Mander, William (17 August 2023). "Pantheism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  168. ^ Nadler, Steven (8 November 2023). "Baruch Spinoza". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  169. ^ Pierre Bayle. Dictionnaire Historique et Critique, vol. 13 (in French). Libraire Desoer, Paris, 1820, p. 416
  170. ^ Immanuel Kant. "The end of all things", in: Religion and Rational Theology. Transl. and edited by Allen W. Wood and George Di Giovanni. Cambridge University Press, p.228
  171. ^ Literary Remains of the Late Professor Theodore Goldstucker, W. H. Allen, 1879. p. 32.
  172. ^ The Westminster Review 1862, pp. 256–257.
  173. ^ Three Lectures on the Vedanta Philosophy. F. Max Muller. Kessinger Publishing, 2003. p. 123
  174. ^ "Ralph Dumain: "The Autodidact Project": "Spinoza, the First Secular Jew?" by Yirmiyahu Yovel".
  175. ^ Kirsch, "The Reticent Radical", p.92
  176. ^ Israel 2023, pp. 1205.
  177. ^ Hegel Society of America. Meeting (2003). Duquette, David A. (ed.). Hegel's History of Philosophy: New Interpretations. SUNY Series in Hegelian Studies. SUNY Press. ISBN 9780791455432. from the original on 13 May 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  178. ^ Smith 1997, p. 168-69.
  179. ^ Yovel, Yirmiyahu. "Spinoza, the First Secular Jew?" Tikkun, vol. 5, no.1, pp. 40-42, 94-96.
  180. ^ Goetschel, Willi, Spinoza's Modernity: Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press 2004
  181. ^ a b Schwartz, Daniel B. The First Modern Jew: Spinoza and the History of an Image. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2012
  182. ^ George Santayana, "The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza", The Harvard Monthly, 2 (June 1886: 144–52).
  183. ^ George Santayana, "Introduction", in Spinoza's Ethics and "De intellectus emendatione"(London: Dent, 1910, vii–xxii)
  184. ^ George Santayana, "Ultimate Religion", in Obiter Scripta, eds. Justus Buchler and Benjamin Schwartz (New York and London: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1936) 280–97.
  185. ^ George Santayana, Persons and Places (Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press, 1986), pp. 233–36.
  186. ^ Peden, Knox (2014). Spinoza contra phenomenology : French rationalism from Cavaillès to Deleuze. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press. ISBN 978-0-8047-9136-6. OCLC 880877889.
  187. ^ Baugh, Bruce (28 March 2015). "Spinoza Contra Phenomenology: French Rationalism from Cavaillès to Deleuze". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved 19 May 2022.
  188. ^ Deleuze, 1968.
  189. ^ Quoted in the translator's preface of Deleuze's Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (1990).
  190. ^ a b Rocha, Mauricio (2021), "Spinozist Moments in Deleuze: Materialism as Immanence", Materialism and Politics, Berlin: ICI Berlin Press, pp. 73–90, doi:10.37050/ci-20_04, S2CID 234131869, retrieved 19 May 2022.
  191. ^ "Einstein believes in "Spinoza's God"; Scientist Defines His Faith in Reply, to Cablegram From Rabbi Here. Sees a Divine Order But Says Its Ruler Is Not Concerned "Wit [sic] Fates and Actions of Human Beings."". The New York Times. 25 April 1929. Retrieved 8 September 2009.
  192. ^ "Einstein's Third Paradise, by Gerald Holton". Aip.org. from the original on 22 May 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  193. ^ Kaiser, Rudolf, Spinoza: Portrait of a Spiritual Hero. New York: Philosophical Library 1946
  194. ^ Israel 2001, p. 159.
  195. ^ "Entoen.nu". Entoen.nu. from the original on 13 May 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  196. ^ "Van der Ham biedt Verbeet Spinoza aan". RTL Nieuws. 5 July 2012. Retrieved 30 November 2014.
  197. ^ a b Rutledge, David (3 October 2020). "The Jewish philosopher Spinoza was one of the great Enlightenment thinkers. So why was he 'cancelled'?". ABC News. ABC Radio National (The Philosopher's Zone). Australian Broadcasting Corporation. Retrieved 7 October 2020.
  198. ^ Schwartz. The First Modern Jew: Spinoza and the History of an Image. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2012, xi
  199. ^ Rocker, Simon (28 August 2014). "Why Baruch Spinoza is still excommunicated". The Jewish Chronicle Online.
  200. ^ "Mo 50 – Statue Spinoza – Amsterdam" (in Dutch). from the original on 22 January 2022. Retrieved 20 June 2023.
  201. ^ SpinozaHavurah.org 1 January 2023 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 202, 2022)
  202. ^ "Statute of Spinoza unveiled in Amsterdam centre" Simply Amsterdam (Nov. 25, 2008) 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 20, 2022)
  203. ^ "Who stands proud on a pedestal in Amsterdam" Unclogged in Amsterdam : An American Expat plumbs Holland (Aug. 22, 2020) 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 20, 2022)
  204. ^ "Spinoza Monument" CitySeeker.com 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine (Accessed Nov. 20, 2022)
  205. ^ Johan W. von Goethe. Autobiography, vol. 2. Transl. by John Oxenford. The Anthological Society. London-Chicago, 1901, Chapters 14-16, p.178-248
  206. ^ Heinrich Heine. On the History of Religion and Philosophy in Germany. Edited by Paul L. Rose. James Cook University of North Queensland, 1982, p. 56-57
  207. ^ Marcelo Abadi: "Spinoza in Borges' looking-glass".  Borges Studies Online. J. L. Borges Center for Studies & Documentation. Internet: 14/04/01
  208. ^ Diego Sztulwark: "Spinoza y la cultura judía argentina" (in Spanish). El Cohete a la Luna, 2/6/2022
  209. ^ See complete text on Wikisource.
  210. ^ El Impío de Andrés Spokoiny (In Spanish). 05/27/2022.
  211. ^ Baruch Spinoza, un pensador que cimbró su tiempo (in Spanish). 8/14/2022
  212. ^ See G. Licata, "Spinoza e la cognitio universalis dell'ebraico. Demistificazione e speculazione grammaticale nel Compendio di grammatica ebraica", Giornale di Metafisica, 3 (2009), pp. 625–61.

Sources edit

Books
Articles and online
  • Nadler, Steven (2001b). "The Excommunication of Spinoza: Trouble and Toleration in the "Dutch Jerusalem"". Shofar. 19 (4): 40–52. ISSN 0882-8539. JSTOR 42943396.
  • Simkins, James (2014). "On the Development of Spinoza's Account of Human Religion". Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies. 5 (1): 52–72. ISSN 2155-1723.
  • Soley, W.R. (1 July 1880). "Jewish Mediaeval Philosophy in Spinoza". Mind. os–V (19). Oxford University Press: 362–384. doi:10.1093/mind/os-V.19.362. ISSN 0026-4423. JSTOR 2246395. OCLC 5545819846. other hand, the discovery and publication in 1862 of a lost treatise of Spinoza's—the Tractatus brtvia de Deo et homine ejusque felicitate
  • "The Religious Difficulties of India". The Westminster Review. 78 (American ed.). New York: Leonard Scott & Co.: 245–263 1862. hdl:2027/mdp.39015013165819.

Other works edit

  • Damásio, António, 2003. Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain, Harvest Books, ISBN 978-0-15-602871-4
  • Della Rocca, Michael. 1996. Representation and the Mind-Body Problem in Spinoza. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509562-3
  • Garrett, Don, ed., 1995. The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza. Cambridge Uni. Press.
  • Deleuze, Gilles, 1968. Spinoza et le problème de l'expression. Trans. "Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza" Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books).
  • _____, 1970. Spinoza: Philosophie pratique. Transl. "Spinoza: Practical Philosophy".
  • _____, 1990. Negotiations trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press).
  • Gatens, Moira, and Lloyd, Genevieve, 1999. Collective imaginings: Spinoza, past and present. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-16570-9, 978-0-415-16571-6
  • Koistinen, Olli, (ed.). 2009. The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza's Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Goode, Francis, 2012. Life of Spinoza. Smashwords edition. ISBN 978-1-4661-3399-0
  • Hampshire, Stuart, 1951. Spinoza and Spinozism, OUP, 2005 ISBN 978-0-19-927954-8
  • Hardt, Michael, trans., University of Minnesota Press. Preface, in French, by Gilles Deleuze, available here: . Multitudes.samizdat.net. Archived from the original on 11 June 2011. Retrieved 2 May 2011.
  • _____, 2006. Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752, (ISBN 978-0-19-927922-7)
  • _____. 2002. “Philosophy, Commerce and the Synagogue: Spinoza's Expulsion from the Amsterdam Portuguese Jewish Community in 1656.” In Dutch Jewry: Its History and Secular Culture (1500-2000). Edited by Jonathan Israel and Reinier Salverda, pp. 125–140. Leiden: Brill.
  • Ives, David (2009). New Jerusalem; The Interrogation of Baruch de Spinoza at Talmud Torah Congregation: Amsterdam, 27 July 1656. New York: Dramatists Play Service. ISBN 978-0-8222-2385-6.)
  • Kayser, Rudolf, 1946, with an introduction by Albert Einstein. Spinoza: Portrait of a Spiritual Hero. New York: The Philosophical Library.
  • Kisner, Matthew J. 2011. Spinoza on human freedom: Reason, autonomy and the good life. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lloyd, Genevieve. 1994. Part of Nature: Self-Knowledge in Spinoza's 'Ethics'. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Lloyd, Genevieve. 2018. Reclaiming wonder. After the sublime. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-1-4744-3311-2
  • LeBuffe, Michael. 2010. Spinoza and Human Freedom. Oxford University Press.
  • Lovejoy, Arthur O., 1936. "Plenitude and Sufficient Reason in Leibniz and Spinoza" in his The Great Chain of Being. Harvard University Press: 144–82 (ISBN 978-0-674-36153-9). Reprinted in Frankfurt, H. G., ed., 1972. Leibniz: A Collection of Critical Essays. Anchor Books.
  • Macherey, Pierre, 1977. Hegel ou Spinoza, Maspéro (2nd ed. La Découverte, 2004).
  • _____, 1994–98. Introduction à l'Ethique de Spinoza. Paris: PUF.
  • Magnusson 1990: Magnusson, M (ed.), Spinoza, Baruch, Chambers Biographical Dictionary, Chambers 1990, ISBN 978-0-550-16041-6.
  • Matheron, Alexandre, 1969. Individu et communauté chez Spinoza, Paris: Minuit.
  • Millner, Simon L., The Face of Benedictus Spinoza (New York: Machmadim Art Editions, Inc., 1946).
  • Montag, Warren, Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and his Contemporaries. (London: Verso, 2002).
  • Moreau, Pierre-François, 2003, Spinoza et le spinozisme, PUF (Presses Universitaires de France)
  • Nadler, Steven, Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die, 2020 (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, ISBN 978-0691183848).
  • Negri, Antonio, 1991. The Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza's Metaphysics and Politics.
  • _____, 2004. Subversive Spinoza: (Un)Contemporary Variations.
  • Prokhovnik, Raia (2004). Spinoza and republicanism. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire New York: Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-0333733905.
  • Ratner, Joseph, 1927. The Philosophy of Spinoza (The Modern Library: Random House)
  • Stolze, Ted and Warren Montag (eds.), The New Spinoza, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.
  • Strauss, Leo. Persecution and the Art of Writing. Glencoe, Illinois: Free Press, 1952. Reprint. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.
  • _____ch. 5, "How to Study Spinoza's Tractus Theologico-Politicus;" reprinted in Strauss, Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, ed. Kenneth Hart Green (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1997), 181–233.
  • ____Spinoza's Critique of Religion. New York: Schocken Books, 1965. Reprint. University of Chicago Press, 1996.
  • _____ "Preface to the English Translation" reprinted as "Preface to Spinoza's Critique of Religion", in Strauss, Liberalism Ancient and Modern (New York: Basic Books, 1968, 224–59; also in Strauss, Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity, 137–77).
  • Valentiner, W.R., 1957. Rembrandt and Spinoza: A Study of the Spiritual Conflicts in Seventeenth-Century Holland, London: Phaidon Press.
  • Spinoza in French Philosophy Today. Philosophy Today 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine, Vol. 53, No. 4, Winter 2009 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine.
  • Van den Ven, Jeroen. Printing Spinoza: A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century. Leiden 2022.
  • _____. Documenting Spinoza: A Biographical History of his Life and Time. (forthcoming)
  • Williams, David Lay. 2010. "Spinoza and the General Will", The Journal of Politics, vol. 72 (April): 341–356.
  • Wolfson, Henry A. "The Philosophy of Spinoza". 2 vols. Harvard University Press.

External links edit

Works

  • Works by Benedictus de Spinoza at Project Gutenberg
  • Works by Baruch Spinoza at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  
  • Works by Baruch Spinoza at Open Library
  • – English Translation
  • Opera posthuma – Amsterdam 1677. Complete photographic reproduction, ed. by F. Mignini (Quodlibet publishing house website)
  • Spinoza Archive on the Digital collections of Younes and Soraya Nazarian Library, University of Haifa
  • Leprozengracht with a view on the houses at Houtgracht by Reinier Nooms, 1657 - 1662

baruch, spinoza, spinoza, redirects, here, other, uses, spinoza, disambiguation, baruch, spinoza, november, 1632, february, 1677, also, known, under, latinized, name, benedictus, spinoza, dutch, philosopher, portuguese, jewish, origin, forerunner, reason, spin. Spinoza redirects here For other uses see Spinoza disambiguation Baruch de Spinoza b 24 November 1632 21 February 1677 also known under his Latinized pen name Benedictus de Spinoza was a Dutch philosopher of Portuguese Jewish origin As a forerunner of the Age of Reason Spinoza significantly influenced modern biblical criticism 17th century rationalism and Dutch intellectual culture establishing himself as one of the most important and radical philosophers of the early modern period 15 He was influenced by Stoicism Maimonides Niccolo Machiavelli Rene Descartes Thomas Hobbes and a variety of heterodox Christian thinkers of his day 16 Baruch SpinozaBornBaruch Espinosa 9 Bento de Spinosa 10 1632 11 24 24 November 1632Amsterdam Dutch RepublicDied21 February 1677 1677 02 21 aged 44 The Hague Dutch RepublicOther namesBenedictus de SpinozaEducationTalmud Torah University of Leiden no degree 11 Era17th century philosophy Age of EnlightenmentRegionWestern philosophySchoolCartesianism 1 Conceptualism 2 Correspondence theory of truth a 4 Direct realism 5 Foundationalism according to Hegel 6 Rationalism Psychological Egoism 7 Main interestsEpistemologyethicsHebrew Bible 8 metaphysicsSignature Spinoza was born in Amsterdam to a Marrano family that left Portugal for a more tolerant Dutch Republic He had a traditional Jewish education learning Hebrew and studying the sacred texts He was part of the Portuguese Jewish community where his father was a prominent merchant As a young man Spinoza was permanently expelled from the Jewish community for defying rabbinic authorities and disputing Jewish beliefs After his expulsion in 1656 he did not affiliate with any religion instead focusing on philosophical study and lens grinding Spinoza established a dedicated following who met to discuss his writings and was devoted to pursuing truth philosophically Spinoza challenged the divine origin of the Hebrew Bible the nature of God and the earthly power wielded by religious authorities Jewish and Christian alike He was frequently called an atheist by contemporaries although nowhere in his work does Spinoza argue against the existence of God 17 18 This can be explained by the fact that unlike contemporary 21st century scholars when seventeenth century readers accused Spinoza of atheism they usually meant that he challenged doctrinal orthodoxy particularly on moral issues and not that he denied God s existence 19 His theological studies were inseparable from his thinking on politics he is grouped with Hobbes John Locke Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and Immanuel Kant who established the genre of political writing called secular theology 20 Spinoza s philosophy encompasses nearly every area of philosophical discourse including metaphysics epistemology political philosophy ethics philosophy of mind and philosophy of science With an enduring reputation as one of the most original and influential thinkers of the seventeenth century Rebecca Goldstein dubbed him the renegade Jew who gave us modernity 21 Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Family background 1 1 1 Uriel da Costa s early influence 1 2 School days and the family business 1 3 Expulsion from the Jewish community 1 4 Education and study group 1 5 Career as a philosopher 1 5 1 Rijnsburg 1 5 2 Voorburg 1 5 3 The Hague 1 5 4 Lens grinding and optics 1 5 5 Death and rescue of his unpublished writings 2 Writings 2 1 Correspondence 3 Philosophy 3 1 Tractatus Theologico Politicus TTP 3 2 Ethics 3 2 1 Metaphysics 3 2 1 1 Substance attributes and modes 3 2 1 2 Causality 3 2 1 3 The emotions 3 2 2 Ethical philosophy 3 3 Tractatus Politicus Political Treatise TP 4 Pantheism 5 Other philosophical connections 6 Legacy 7 Modern era 7 1 Reconsideration of Spinoza s expulsion 7 2 Memory and memorials 8 Depictions and influence in literature 9 Works 9 1 Original Editions 9 2 Contemporary Editions 10 See also 11 References 11 1 Notes 11 2 Citations 11 3 Sources 11 4 Other works 12 External linksBiography edit nbsp The Moses and Aaron Church now stands at the site of Spinoza s childhood home 22 Family background edit See also History of the Jews in Amsterdam Spinoza s ancestors adherents of Crypto Judaism faced persecution during the Portuguese Inquisition enduring torture and public displays of humiliation 23 In 1597 his paternal grandfather s family left Vidigueira for Nantes and lived as New Christians eventually transferring to Holland for an unknown reason 24 His maternal ancestors were a leading Oporto commercial family 25 and his maternal grandfather was a foremost merchant who drifted between Judaism and Christianity 26 Spinoza was raised by his grandmother from ages six to nine and probably learned much about his family history from her 27 Spinoza s father Michael was a prominent and wealthy merchant in Amsterdam with a business that had wide geographical reach 28 In 1649 he was elected to serve as an administrative officer of the recently united congregation Talmud Torah 29 He married his cousin Rachael d Espinosa daughter of his uncle Abraham d Espinosa who was also a community leader and Michael s business partner 30 Marrying cousins was common in the Portuguese Jewish community then giving Michael access to his father in law s commercial network and capital 31 Rachel s children died in infancy and she died in 1627 32 31 After the death of Rachel Michael married Hannah Deborah with whom he had five children His second wife brought a dowry to the marriage that was absorbed into Michael s business capital instead of being set aside for her children which may have caused a grudge between Spinoza and his father 33 The family lived on the artificial island on the south side of the River Amstel known as the Vlooienburg at the fifth house along the Houtgracht canal 22 The Jewish quarter was not formally divided The family lived close to the Bet Ya acov synagogue and nearby were Christians including the artist Rembrandt 34 Miriam was their first child followed by Isaac who was expected to take over as head of the family and the commercial enterprise but died in 1649 33 Baruch Espinosa the third child was born on 24 November 1632 and named as per tradition for his maternal grandfather 9 Spinoza s younger brother Gabriel was born in 1634 followed by another sister Rebecca Miriam married Samuel de Caceres but died shortly after childbirth According to Jewish practice Samuel had to marry his former sister in law Rebecca 35 Following his brother s death Spinoza s place as head of the family and its business meant scholarly ambitions were pushed aside 28 Spinoza s mother Hannah Deborah died when Spinoza was six years old Michael s third wife Esther raised Spinoza from age nine she lacked formal Jewish knowledge due to growing up a New Christian and only spoke Portuguese at home The marriage was childless 36 Spinoza s sister Rebecca brother Gabriel and nephew eventually migrated to Curacao and the remaining family joined them after Spinoza s death 35 Uriel da Costa s early influence edit nbsp Samuel Hirszenberg s imagined scene of Uriel da Costa instructing Spinoza 1901 Through his mother Spinoza was related to the philosopher Uriel da Costa who stirred controversy in Amsterdam s Portuguese Jewish community 37 Da Costa questioned traditional Christian and Jewish beliefs asserting that for example their origins were based on human inventions instead of God s revelation His clashes with the religious establishment led to his excommunication twice by rabbinic authorities who imposed humiliation and social exclusion 38 In 1639 as part of an agreement to be readmitted da Costa had to prostrate himself for worshippers to step over him He died in 1640 reportedly committing suicide 39 During his childhood Spinoza was likely unaware of his family connection with Uriel da Costa still as a teenager he certainly heard discussions about him 40 Steven Nadler explains that although da Costa died when Spinoza was eight his ideas shaped Spinoza s intellectual development Amsterdam s Jewish communities long remembered and discussed da Costa s skepticism about organized religion denial of the soul s immortality and the idea that Moses didn t write the Torah influencing Spinoza s intellectual journey 41 School days and the family business edit nbsp Spinoza s name crossed out on the list of pupils of Talmud Torah Ets Haim in Hebrew Spinoza attended the Talmud Torah school adjoining the Bet Ya acov synagogue a few doors down from his home headed by the senior Rabbi Saul Levi Morteira 42 43 Instructed in Spanish the language of learning and literature students in the elementary school learned to read the prayerbook and the Torah in Hebrew translate the weekly section into Spanish and study Rashi s commentary 44 Spinoza s name does not appear on the registry after age fourteen and likely he never studied with rabbis such as Manasseh ben Israel and Morteira Spinoza possibly went to work around fourteen and almost certainly was needed in his father s business after his brother died in 1649 45 During the First Anglo Dutch War much of the Spinoza firm s ships and cargo were captured by English ships severely affecting the firm s financial viability The firm was saddled with debt by the war s end in 1654 due to its merchant voyages being intercepted by the English leading to its decline 46 47 Spinoza s father died in 1654 making him the head of the family responsible for organizing and leading the Jewish mourning rituals and in a business partnership with his brother of their inherited firm 48 As Spinoza s father had poor health for some years before his death he was significantly involved in the business putting his intellectual curiosity on hold 49 Until 1656 he continued financially supporting the synagogue and attending services in compliance with synagogue conventions and practice 50 By 1655 the family s wealth had evaporated and the business effectively ended 49 In March 1656 Spinoza went to the city authorities for protection against debts in the Portuguese Jewish community To free himself from the responsibility of paying debts owed to his late father Spinoza appealed to the city to declare him an orphan 51 since he was a legal minor not understanding his father s indebtedness would remove the obligation to repay his debts and retrospectively renounce his inheritance 52 Though he was released of all debts and legally in the right his reputation as a merchant was permanently damaged in addition to violating a synagogue regulation that business matters are to be arbitrated within the community 53 51 Expulsion from the Jewish community edit nbsp Excommunicated Spinoza by Samuel Hirszenberg 1907 the second of his two modern paintings imagining scenes of Spinoza s life Amsterdam was tolerant of religious diversity so long as it was practiced discreetly and Jews were not legally confined to a ghetto The community was concerned with protecting its reputation and not associating with Spinoza lest his controversial views provide the basis for possible persecution or expulsion 54 Spinoza did not openly break with Jewish authorities until his father died in 1654 when he became public and defiant resulting from lengthy and stressful religious financial and legal clashes involving his business and synagogue such as when Spinoza violated synagogue regulations by going to city authorities rather than resolving his disputes within the community to free himself from paying his father s debt 51 On 27 July 1656 the Talmud Torah community leaders which included Aboab de Fonseca 55 issued a writ of herem against the 23 year old Spinoza 56 57 Spinoza s censure was the harshest ever pronounced in the community carrying tremendous emotional and spiritual impact 58 The exact reason for expelling Spinoza is not stated only referring to his abominable heresies monstrous deeds and the testimony of witnesses in the presence of the said Espinoza 59 Even though the Amsterdam municipal authorities were not directly involved in Spinoza s censure itself the town council expressly ordered the Portuguese Jewish community to regulate their conduct and ensure that the community kept a strict observance of Jewish law 60 Other evidence shows that the danger of upsetting the civil authorities was not far from mind such as bans adopted by the synagogue on public weddings or funeral processions and on discussing religious matters with Christians lest such activity might disturb the liberty we enjoy 61 nbsp Ban in Portuguese of Baruch Spinoza by the leaders of the community on 6 Av 5416 27 July 1656 Before the expulsion Spinoza had not published anything or written a treatise Steven Nadler states that if Spinoza was voicing his criticism of Judaism that later appeared through his philosophical works such as Part I of Ethics then there can be no wonder that he was severely punished 62 63 He might already have been voicing the view expressed later in his Theological Political Treatise that the civil authorities should suppress Judaism as harmful to the Jews themselves He had effectively stopped contributing to the synagogue by March 1656 because of his bleak financial situation 64 Unlike most censures issued by the Amsterdam congregation it was never rescinded since the censure did not lead to repentance After the censure Spinoza is said to have written an Apologia in Spanish to the community leaders defending his views and condemning the rabbis but it is now lost 65 Spinoza s expulsion from the Jewish community did not lead him to convert to Christianity remaining an apostate Jew for the rest of his life 66 From 1656 61 Spinoza found lodgings elsewhere in Amsterdam and Leiden supporting himself with teaching while learning lens grinding and constructing microscopes and telescopes 67 Spinoza did not maintain a sense of Jewish identity he argued that without adherence to Jewish law the Jewish people lack a sustaining source of difference and identity rendering the notion of a secular Jew incoherent 68 Education and study group edit Sometime between 1654 and 1657 Spinoza started studying Latin with political radical Franciscus van den Enden a former Jesuit and atheist who likely introduced Spinoza to scholastic and modern philosophy including Descartes who had a dominant influence on Spinoza s philosophy 69 While boarding with Van den Enden Spinoza studied in his school where he learned the arts and sciences and likely taught others 70 66 Many of his friends were either secularized freethinkers or belonged to dissident Christian groups that rejected the authority of established churches and traditional dogmas 71 72 Spinoza was acquainted with members of the Collegiants a group of disaffected Mennonites and other dissenting Reformed sects that shunned official theology and must have played some role in Spinoza s developing views on religion and directed him to Van Enden 73 Jonathan Israel conjectures that another possible influential figure was atheist translator Jan Hendriksz Glazemaker a collaborator of Spinoza s friend and publisher Rieuwertsz who could not have mentored Spinoza but was in a unique position to introduce Spinoza to Cartesian philosophy mathematics and lens grinding 74 After learning Latin with Van Enden Spinoza studied at Leiden University around 1658 75 where he audited classes in Cartesian philosophy c From 1656 61 Spinoza s main discussion partners who formed his circle and played a formative part in Spinoza s life were Van den Enden Pieter Balling Jarig Jelles Lodewijk Meyer Johannes Bouwmeester and Adriaan Koerbagh 77 Spinoza s following or philosophical sect 78 scrutinized the propositions of the Ethics while it was in draft and Spinoza s second text Short Treatise on God Man and His Well Being 79 Though a few prominent people in Amsterdam discussed the teachings of the secretive but marginal group it was mainly a testing ground for Spinoza s philosophy to extend his challenge to the status quo 80 Their public reputation in Amsterdam was negative with Ole Borch disparaging them as atheists 81 Throughout his life Spinoza s general approach was to avoid intellectual battles clashes and public controversies viewing them as a waste of energy that served no real purpose 82 Career as a philosopher edit Rijnsburg edit nbsp Spinoza s lodging in Rijnsburg now a museum In 1660 or 1661 Spinoza moved from Amsterdam to Rijnsburg allowing for a quiet retreat in the country and access to the university town Leiden where he still had many friends 83 Around this time he wrote his Short Treatise on God Man and His Well Being which he never published in his lifetime thinking it would enrage the theologians synods and city magistrates 84 85 Two Dutch translations were discovered around 1810 86 While lodging with Herman Homan in Rijnsburg Spinoza produced lenses and instruments to support himself and out of scientific interest 87 He began working on his Ethics and Descartes Principles of Philosophy which he completed in two weeks communicating and interpreting Descartes arguments and testing the water for his metaphysical and ethical ideas Spinoza s explanations of essential elements of the Cartesian system helped many interested people study the system enhancing his philosophical reputation This work was published in 1663 and was one of the two works published in his lifetime under his name 88 Voorburg edit In Voorburg Spinoza continued work on his magnum opus titled posthumously Ethics and corresponded with scientists philosophers and theologians throughout Europe He published in Latin anonymously and with false printer information Theological Political Treatise TTP in 1670 in defense of secular and constitutional government and in support of Johan de Witt the Dutch Republic s grand pensionary against the Stadtholder the Prince of Orange Spinoza deliberately wrote in Latin restricting his message to those who knew the scholarly language Dutch philosopher and physician Adriaan Koerbagh attempted to publish a work in Dutch questioning the Trinity as a concept asserted that Jesus was a human being and that the scripture was not divinely inspired was proposing ideas that also appear in Spinoza writings in Latin Koerbagh s A Flower Garden of All Sorts of Delights in Dutch came to the attention of the authorities who incarcerated him to be followed by exile but he died while in prison Spinoza did not wish to die a martyr to his ideas and exercised caution by publishing his 1670 TTP anonymously in Latin and refraining from publishing any further works Unlike Koerbagh Spinoza died at home in his own bed 89 Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz visited Spinoza and claimed that Spinoza s life was in danger when supporters of the Prince of Orange murdered de Witt in 1672 90 While the TTP was published anonymously the work did not long remain so and de Witt s enemies characterized it as forged in Hell by a renegade Jew and the Devil and issued with the knowledge of Jan de Witt It was placed on the Catholic Church s Index of Prohibited Works in 1679 91 The Hague edit nbsp Spinoza s house in The Hague where he died In 1670 Spinoza moved to The Hague where he lived on a small pension from Jan de Witt and a small annuity from the brother of his dead friend Simon de Vries 92 He worked on the manuscript of what was later called Ethics wrote an unfinished Hebrew grammar began his Political Treatise TP left unfinished at his death wrote two scientific essays On the Rainbow and On the Calculation of Chances and began a Dutch translation of the Bible which he later destroyed 92 Spinoza was offered the chair of philosophy at the University of Heidelberg He refused it perhaps because of the possibility that it might in some way curb his freedom of thought 93 Spinoza also corresponded with Peter Serrarius a radical Protestant and millenarian merchant Serrarius was a patron to Spinoza after Spinoza was expelled from the Jewish community He acted as an intermediary for Spinoza s correspondence sending and receiving letters of the philosopher to and from third parties Spinoza and Serrarius maintained their relationship until Serrarius died in 1669 94 By the beginning of the 1660s Spinoza s name became more widely known The Secretary of the British Royal Society Henry Oldenburg paid him visits and became a correspondent with Spinoza for the rest of his life 95 In 1676 Leibniz wanted to examine a manuscript copy of the Ethics and traveled to the Hague to meet Spinoza conversing with him at great length 96 Lens grinding and optics edit Spinoza earned a modest living from lens grinding and instrument making yet he was involved in important optical investigations of the day while living in Voorburg through correspondence and friendships with scientist Christiaan Huygens and mathematician Johannes Hudde including debate over microscope design with Huygens favoring small objectives 97 and collaborating on calculations for a prospective 40 foot 12 m focal length telescope which would have been one of the largest in Europe at the time 98 He was known for making not just lenses but also telescopes and microscopes 99 The quality of Spinoza s lenses was praised by Christiaan Huygens and others 100 In fact his technique and instruments were so esteemed that Constantijn Huygens ground a clear and bright telescope lens with focal length of 42 feet 13 m in 1687 from one of Spinoza s grinding dishes ten years after his death 101 He was said by anatomist Theodor Kerckring to have produced an excellent microscope the quality of which was the foundation of Kerckring s anatomy claims 102 During his time as a lens and instrument maker he was also supported by small but regular donations from close friends 103 Death and rescue of his unpublished writings edit nbsp Burial monument of Spinoza at the churchyard of the Nieuwe Kerk The Hague Spinoza s health began to fail in 1676 and he died in The Hague on 21 February 1677 at age 44 attended by a physician friend Georg Herman Schuller Although he had been ill with some form of lung affliction described as ex phthisi from consumption possibly complicated by silicosis brought on by grinding glass lenses 104 he and everyone he lived with did not expect him to die that day and he died without leaving a will 105 106 There were assertions that he had repented his philosophical stances on his deathbed but all credible evidence points to his dying unrepentant and in tranquility Lutheran preacher Johannes Colerus wrote the first biography of Spinoza for the original reason of researching his final days 107 Spinoza was buried in the Nieuwe Kerk New Church on the Spui four days after his death on 25 February inside the church with six others in the same vault At the time there was no memorial plaque for Spinoza In the 18th century the vault was emptied and the remnants scattered over the earth of the churchyard The memorial plaque visitors now see is outside where some of his remains are part of the churchyard s soil 108 When he died friends rescued his personal belongings and papers most importantly his unpublished manuscripts These were stored in a cabinet attached to his writing desk His supporters swiftly took them away for safekeeping from seizure by those wishing to suppress his writings They do not appear in the inventory of his possessions at death Within a year of his death his supporters translated his manuscripts written in Latin into Dutch and subsequently into other vernacular languages His works were banned by Dutch authorities and later the Roman Catholic Church 109 110 Writings editSpinoza published little in his lifetime and most of his formal writings were in Latin which would have reached only a small number of readers He actively told supporters not to translate his works but following his death his supporters published his works posthumously in Latin and Dutch A descriptive bibliography has been published that contextualizes all aspects of the publication history of Spinoza s writings from manuscript to print 111 The reaction to the anonymously published work Theologico Political Treatise TTP 1670 was extremely unfavorable Spinoza abstained from publishing further but his writings circulated among his supporters in manuscript form during his lifetime Wary and independent he wore a signet ring which he used to mark his letters and which was engraved with the word caute Latin for cautiously underneath a rose itself a symbol of secrecy 112 The Ethics and all other works apart from the Descartes Principles of Philosophy which was published under his own name and the Theologico Political Treatise published anonymously appeared in print after his 1677 death The Opera Posthuma was edited by his friends in secrecy to prevent confiscation and destruction of manuscripts The Ethics contains many still unresolved obscurities and is written with a forbidding mathematical structure modeled on Euclid s geometry and has been described as a superbly cryptic masterwork 113 Correspondence edit See also Epistolae Spinoza and List of Epistolae Letters of Spinoza nbsp Letter from Spinoza to Leibniz with his BdS seal Few letters are extant for such an important intellectual figure and none before 1661 Practically all of them are of philosophical technical nature since the political and ecclesiastical persecution of the time led the original editors of the Opera Posthuma his friends Lodewijk Meyer Georg Hermann Schuller and Johannes Bouwmeester to delete personal matters and to disregard letters of a personal nature 114 Spinoza engaged in correspondence from December 1664 to June 1665 with Willem van Blijenbergh an amateur Calvinist theologian who questioned Spinoza on the definition of evil Later in 1665 Spinoza notified Oldenburg that he had started to work on a new book the Theologico Political Treatise published in 1670 Leibniz disagreed harshly with Spinoza in his own manuscript Refutation of Spinoza 115 but he is also known to have met with Spinoza on at least one occasion 95 96 and his work bears some striking resemblances to some parts of Spinoza s philosophy like in Monadology Leibniz was concerned when his name was not redacted from a letter to Spinoza that was printed in the Opera Posthuma 116 In a letter written in December 1675 and sent to Albert Burgh who wanted to defend Catholicism Spinoza clearly explained his view of both Catholicism and Islam He stated that both religions are made to deceive the people and to constrain the minds of men He also states that Islam far surpasses Catholicism in doing so 117 118 The Tractatus de Deo Homine ejusque Felicitate Treatise on God man and his happiness was one of the last of Spinoza s works to be published between 1851 119 and 1862 120 Philosophy editSpinoza s philosophy is explicated in his two major publications originally written in Latin the Tractatus Theologico Politicus TTP 1670 and Ethics published posthumously in Latin and Dutch His incomplete Tractatus Politicus was also published posthumously Tractatus Theologico Politicus TTP edit nbsp Main article Tractatus Theologico PoliticusSee also Thomas Hobbes Despite its being published in Latin rather than a vernacular language this 1670 treatise published in Spinoza s lifetime caused a huge reaction described as one of the most significant events in European intellectual history 121 122 Ethics edit Main article Ethics Spinoza book The Ethics has been associated with that of Leibniz and Rene Descartes as part of the rationalist school of thought 123 which includes the assumption that ideas correspond to reality perfectly in the same way that mathematics is supposed to be an exact representation of the world The writings of Rene Descartes have been described as Spinoza s starting point 113 Spinoza s first publication was his 1663 geometric exposition of proofs using Euclid s model with definitions and axioms of Descartes Principles of Philosophy Following Descartes Spinoza aimed to understand truth through logical deductions from clear and distinct ideas a process which always begins from the self evident truths of axioms 124 However his actual project does not end there from his first work to his last one there runs a thread of attending to the highest good which also is the highest truth and thereby achieving a state of peace and harmony either in the metaphysical or political manner In this light the Principles of Philosophy might be viewed as an exercise in geometric method and philosophy paving the way for numerous concepts and conclusions that would define his philosophy see Cogitata Metaphysica 125 Metaphysics edit Spinoza s metaphysics consists of one thing substance and its modifications modes Early in The Ethics Spinoza argues that there is only one substance which is absolutely infinite self caused and eternal He calls this substance God or Nature In fact he takes these two terms to be synonymous in the Latin the phrase he uses is Deus sive Natura For Spinoza the whole of the natural universe consists of one substance God or what is the same Nature and its modifications modes It cannot be overemphasized how the rest of Spinoza s philosophy his philosophy of mind his epistemology his psychology his moral philosophy his political philosophy and his philosophy of religion flows more or less directly from the metaphysical underpinnings in Part I of the Ethics 126 Substance attributes and modes edit Spinoza sets forth a vision of Being illuminated by his awareness of God They may seem strange at first sight To the question What is he replies Substance its attributes and modes Karl Jaspers 127 Following Maimonides Spinoza defined substance as that which is in itself and is conceived through itself meaning that it can be understood without any reference to anything external 128 Being conceptually independent also means that the same thing is ontologically independent depending on nothing else for its existence and being the cause of itself causa sui 128 A mode is something which cannot exist independently but rather must do so as part of something else on which it depends including properties for example colour relations such as size and individual things 129 Modes can be further divided into finite and infinite ones with the latter being evident in every finite mode he gives the examples of motion and rest 130 The traditional understanding of an attribute in philosophy is similar to Spinoza s modes though he uses that word differently 129 To him an attribute is that which the intellect perceives as constituting the essence of substance and there are possibly an infinite number of them 131 It is the essential nature which is attributed to reality by intellect 132 nbsp Probable portrait of Spinoza by Barend Graat 1666 Spinoza defined God as a substance consisting of infinite attributes each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence and since no cause or reason can prevent such a being from existing it therefore must exist 132 This is a form of the ontological argument which is claimed to prove the existence of God but Spinoza went further in stating that it showed that only God exists 133 Accordingly he stated that Whatever is is in God and nothing can exist or be conceived without God 133 134 This means that God is identical with the universe an idea which he encapsulated in the phrase Deus sive Natura God or Nature which has been interpreted by some as atheism or pantheism 135 Though there are many more of them God can be known by humans either through the attribute of extension or the attribute of thought 136 Thought and extension represent giving complete accounts of the world in mental or physical terms 137 To this end he says that the mind and the body are one and the same thing which is conceived now under the attribute of thought now under the attribute of extension 138 After stating his proof for God s existence Spinoza addresses who God is Spinoza believed that God is the sum of the natural and physical laws of the universe and certainly not an individual entity or creator 139 Spinoza attempts to prove that God is just the substance of the universe by first stating that substances do not share attributes or essences and then demonstrating that God is a substance with an infinite number of attributes thus the attributes possessed by any other substances must also be possessed by God Therefore God is just the sum of all the substances of the universe God is the only substance in the universe and everything is a part of God This view was described by Charles Hartshorne as Classical Pantheism 140 Spinoza argues that things could not have been produced by God in any other way or in any other order than is the case 141 Therefore concepts such as freedom and chance have little meaning 135 This picture of Spinoza s determinism is illuminated in Ethics the infant believes that it is by free will that it seeks the breast the angry boy believes that by free will he wishes vengeance the timid man thinks it is with free will he seeks flight the drunkard believes that by a free command of his mind he speaks the things which when sober he wishes he had left unsaid All believe that they speak by a free command of the mind whilst in truth they have no power to restrain the impulse which they have to speak 142 In his letter to G H Schuller Letter 58 he wrote men are conscious of their desire and unaware of the causes by which their desires are determined 143 He also held that knowledge of true causes of passive emotion can transform it into an active emotion thus anticipating one of the key ideas of Sigmund Freud s psychoanalysis 144 According to Eric Schliesser Spinoza was skeptical regarding the possibility of knowledge of nature and as a consequence at odds with scientists such as Galileo and Huygens 145 Causality edit Although the principle of sufficient reason is commonly associated with Gottfried Leibniz Spinoza employs it in a more systematic manner In Spinoza s philosophical framework questions concerning why a particular phenomenon exists are always answerable and these answers are provided in terms of the relevant cause Spinoza s approach involves first providing an account of a phenomenon such as goodness or consciousness to explain it and then further explaining the phenomenon in terms of itself For instance he might argue that consciousness is the degree of power of a mental state 146 Spinoza has also been described as an Epicurean materialist 113 specifically in reference to his opposition to Cartesian mind body dualism This view was held by Epicureans before him as they believed that atoms with their probabilistic paths were the only substance that existed fundamentally 147 148 Spinoza however deviated significantly from Epicureans by adhering to strict determinism much like the Stoics before him in contrast to the Epicurean belief in the probabilistic path of atoms which is more in line with contemporary thought on quantum mechanics 147 149 The emotions edit One thing which seems on the surface to distinguish Spinoza s view of the emotions from both Descartes and Hume s pictures of them is that he takes the emotions to be cognitive in some important respect Jonathan Bennett claims that Spinoza mainly saw emotions as caused by cognitions However he did not say this clearly enough and sometimes lost sight of it entirely 150 Spinoza provides several demonstrations which purport to show truths about how human emotions work The picture presented is according to Bennett unflattering coloured as it is by universal egoism 151 Ethical philosophy edit nbsp Engraving of Spinoza captioned in Latin A Jew and an atheist he vehemently denied being an atheist Spinoza s notion of blessedness figures centrally in his ethical philosophy Spinoza writes that blessedness or salvation or freedom consists namely in a constant and eternal love of God or in God s love for men 152 Philosopher Jonathan Bennett interprets this as Spinoza wanting blessedness to stand for the most elevated and desirable state one could possibly be in 153 Understanding what is meant by most elevated and desirable state requires understanding Spinoza s notion of conatus striving but not necessarily with any teleological baggage citation needed and that perfection refers not to moral value but to completeness Given that individuals are identified as mere modifications of the infinite Substance it follows that no individual can ever be fully complete i e perfect or blessed Absolute perfection is in Spinoza s thought reserved solely for Substance Nevertheless modes can attain a lesser form of blessedness namely that of pure understanding of oneself as one really is i e as a definite modification of Substance in a certain set of relationships with everything else in the universe That this is what Spinoza has in mind can be seen at the end of the Ethics in E5P24 and E5P25 where Spinoza makes two final key moves unifying the metaphysical epistemological and ethical propositions he has developed over the course of the work In E5P24 he links the understanding of particular things to the understanding of God or Substance in E5P25 the conatus of the mind is linked to the third kind of knowledge Intuition From here it is a short step to the connection of Blessedness with the amor dei intellectualis intellectual love of God citation needed Tractatus Politicus Political Treatise TP edit Main article Tractatus Politicus nbsp The title page of the Tractatus politicus in the Opera Posthuma This unfinished treatise in Latin expounds Spinoza s ideas about forms of government As with the Ethics this work was published posthumously by his circle of supporters in Latin and in Dutch The subtitle is In quo demonstratur quomodo Societas ubi Imperium Monarchicum locum habet sicut et ea ubi Optimi imperant debet institui ne in Tyrannidem labatur et ut Pax Libertasque civium inviolata maneat In which it is demonstrated how a society may it be a monarchy or an aristocracy can be best governed so as not to fall into tyranny and so that the peace and liberty of the citizens remain unviolated Although Spinoza s political and theological thought was radical on many ways he held traditional views on the place of women In the TP he writes briefly on the last page of the TP that women were naturally subordinate to men stating bluntly his women are by nature not by institutional practice subordinate to men Both his major biographers in English remark on his view of women Biographer Steven Nadler is clearly disappointed by Spinoza s only statement on women It is unfortunate that the very last words we have by him at the end of the extant chapters of the Political Treatise are a short digression on the unsuitability of women to hold political power 154 Likewise Jonathan I Israel says that Spinoza s views are hugely disappointing to the modern reader and that most that can be said in his defense is that in his age rampant tyrannizing over women was indeed universal He goes on to say one may legitimately wonder why did Spinoza if he was to be consistent not apply his highly sceptical and innovative for his time uniquely subversive de legtimizing general principle likewise to men s tyrannizing over women 155 One scholar has attempted to rationalize Spinoza s views excluding women from full citizenship 156 But the topic has not attracted major consideration in Spinoza studies Pantheism editSee also Pantheism controversy Spinoza was considered to be an atheist because he used the word God Deus to signify a concept that was different from that of traditional Judeo Christian monotheism Spinoza expressly denies personality and consciousness to God he has neither intelligence feeling nor will he does not act according to purpose but everything follows necessarily from his nature according to law 157 Thus Spinoza s cool indifferent God differs from the concept of an anthropomorphic fatherly God who cares about humanity 158 In 1785 Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi published a condemnation of Spinoza s pantheism after Gotthold Lessing was thought to have confessed on his deathbed to being a Spinozist which was the equivalent in his time of being called an atheist Jacobi claimed that Spinoza s doctrine was pure materialism because all Nature and God are said to be nothing but extended substance This for Jacobi was the result of Enlightenment rationalism and it would finally end in absolute atheism Moses Mendelssohn disagreed with Jacobi saying that there is no actual difference between theism and pantheism The issue became a major intellectual and religious concern for European civilization at the time The attraction of Spinoza s philosophy to late 18th century Europeans was that it provided an alternative to materialism atheism and deism Three of Spinoza s ideas strongly appealed to them the unity of all that exists the regularity of all that happens the identity of spirit and nature 159 By 1879 Spinoza s pantheism was praised by many but was considered by some to be alarming and dangerously inimical 160 Spinoza s God or Nature Deus sive Natura provided a living natural God in contrast to Isaac Newton s first cause argument and the dead mechanism of Julien Offray de La Mettrie s 1709 1751 work Man a Machine L homme machine Coleridge and Shelley saw in Spinoza s philosophy a religion of nature 103 Novalis called him the God intoxicated man 113 161 Spinoza inspired the poet Shelley to write his essay The Necessity of Atheism 113 It is a widespread belief that Spinoza equated God with the material universe He has therefore been called the prophet 162 and prince 163 and most eminent expounder of pantheism More specifically in a letter to Henry Oldenburg he states as to the view of certain people that I identify God with Nature taken as a kind of mass or corporeal matter they are quite mistaken 164 For Spinoza the universe cosmos is a mode under two attributes of Thought and Extension God has infinitely many other attributes which are not present in the world According to German philosopher Karl Jaspers 1883 1969 when Spinoza wrote Deus sive Natura Latin for God or Nature Spinoza meant God was natura naturans nature doing what nature does literally nature naturing not natura naturata nature already created literally nature natured Jaspers believed that Spinoza in his philosophical system did not mean to say that God and Nature are interchangeable terms but rather that God s transcendence was attested by his infinitely many attributes and that two attributes known by humans namely Thought and Extension signified God s immanence 165 Even God under the attributes of thought and extension cannot be identified strictly with our world That world is of course divisible it has parts But Spinoza said no attribute of a substance can be truly conceived from which it follows that the substance can be divided meaning that one cannot conceive an attribute in a way that leads to division of substance He also said a substance which is absolutely infinite is indivisible Ethics Part I Propositions 12 and 13 166 Following this logic our world should be considered as a mode under two attributes of thought and extension Therefore according to Jaspers the pantheist formula One and All would apply to Spinoza only if the One preserves its transcendence and the All were not interpreted as the totality of finite things 165 Martial Gueroult 1891 1976 suggested the term panentheism rather than pantheism to describe Spinoza s view of the relation between God and the world The world is not God but in a strong sense in God Not only do finite things have God as their cause they cannot be conceived without God 166 However American panentheist philosopher Charles Hartshorne 1897 2000 insisted on the term Classical Pantheism to describe Spinoza s view 140 According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spinoza s God is an infinite intellect Ethics 2p11c all knowing 2p3 and capable of loving both himself and us insofar as we are part of his perfection 5p35c And if the mark of a personal being is that it is one towards which we can entertain personal attitudes then we should note too that Spinoza recommends amor intellectualis dei the intellectual love of God as the supreme good for man 5p33 However the matter is complex Spinoza s God does not have free will 1p32c1 he does not have purposes or intentions 1 appendix and Spinoza insists that neither intellect nor will pertain to the nature of God 1p17s1 Moreover while we may love God we need to remember that God is not a being who could ever love us back He who loves God cannot strive that God should love him in return says Spinoza 5p19 167 Steven Nadler suggests that settling the question of Spinoza s atheism or pantheism depends on an analysis of attitudes If pantheism is associated with religiosity then Spinoza is not a pantheist since Spinoza believes that the proper stance to take towards God is not one of reverence or religious awe but instead one of objective study and reason since taking the religious stance would leave one open to the possibility of error and superstition 168 Other philosophical connections editMany authors have discussed similarities between Spinoza s philosophy and Eastern philosophical traditions Few decades after the philosopher s death Pierre Bayle in his famous Historical and Critical Dictionary 1697 pointed out a link between Spinoza s alleged atheism with the theology of a Chinese sect supposedly called Foe Kiao 169 of which had learned thanks to the testimonies of the Jesuit missions in Eastern Asia A century later Kant also established a parallel between the philosophy of Spinoza and the think of Laozi a monstrous system in his words grouping both under the name of pantheists criticizing what he described as mystical tendencies in them 170 The 19th century German Sanskritist Theodor Goldstucker was one of the early figures to notice the similarities between Spinoza s religious conceptions and the Vedanta tradition of India writing that Spinoza s thought was so exact a representation of the ideas of the Vedanta that we might have suspected its founder to have borrowed the fundamental principles of his system from the Hindus did his biography not satisfy us that he was wholly unacquainted with their doctrines 171 172 Max Muller also noted the striking similarities between Vedanta and the system of Spinoza equating the Brahman in Vedanta to Spinoza s Substantia 173 Legacy edit nbsp A Dutch commemorative coin issued on the 250th death anniversary of Spinoza 1927 Spinoza s ideas have had a major impact on intellectual debates from the seventeenth century to the current era How Spinoza is viewed has gone from the atheistic author of treatises that undermine Judaism and organized religion to a cultural hero the first secular Jew 174 One writer contends that what draws readers to Spinoza today and makes him perhaps the most beloved philosopher since Socrates is his confident equanimity He is not a despairing nihilist but rather Spinoza says that blessedness is nothing else but the contentment of spirit which arises from the intuitive knowledge of God 175 One of his biographers Jonathan I Israel argues that No leading figure of the post 1750 later Enlightenment for example or the nineteenth century was engaged with the philosophy of Descartes Hobbes Bayle Locke or Leibniz to the degree leading figures such as Lessing Goethe Kant Hegel Fichte Schelling Heine George Eliot and Nietzsche remained preoccupied throughout their creative lives with Spinoza 176 Hegel 1770 1831 asserts that The fact is that Spinoza is made a testing point in modern philosophy so that it may really be said You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all 177 His expulsion from the Portuguese synagogue in 1656 has stirred debate over the years on whether he is the first modern Jew Spinoza influenced discussions of the so called Jewish question the examination of the idea of Judaism and the modern secular Jew Moses Mendelsohn Lessing Heine and Kant as well as subsequent thinkers including Marx Nietzsche and Freud were influenced by Spinoza 178 The changing conception of Spinoza as the First Modern Jew has been explicitly explored by various authors 179 180 181 His expulsion has been revisited in the 21st century with Jewish writers such Berthold Auerbach Salomon Rubin who translated Spinoza s Ethics into Hebrew and saw Spinoza as a new Maimonides penning a new guide to the perplexed Zionist Yosef Klausner and fiction writer Isaac Bashevis Singer shaping his image 181 In 1886 the young George Santayana published The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza in The Harvard Monthly 182 Much later he wrote an introduction to Spinoza s Ethics and De Intellectus Emendatione 183 In 1932 Santayana was invited to present an essay published as Ultimate Religion 184 at a meeting at The Hague celebrating the tricentennial of Spinoza s birth In Santayana s autobiography he characterized Spinoza as his master and model in understanding the naturalistic basis of morality 185 Philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein evoked Spinoza with the title suggested to him by G E Moore of the English translation of his first definitive philosophical work Tractatus Logico Philosophicus an allusion to Spinoza s Tractatus Theologico Politicus Elsewhere Wittgenstein deliberately borrowed the expression sub specie aeternitatis from Spinoza Notebooks 1914 16 p 83 The structure of his Tractatus Logico Philosophicus does have some structural affinities with Spinoza s Ethics though admittedly not with the Spinoza s Tractatus in erecting complex philosophical arguments upon basic logical propositions and principles In propositions 6 4311 and 6 45 he alludes to a Spinozian understanding of eternity and interpretation of the religious concept of eternal life contending If by eternity is understood not eternal temporal duration but timelessness then he lives eternally who lives in the present 6 4311 The contemplation of the world sub specie aeterni is its contemplation as a limited whole 6 45 Spinoza s philosophy played an important role in the development of post war French philosophy Many of these philosophers used Spinoza to erect a bulwark against the nominally irrationalist tendencies of phenomenology which was associated with the dominance of Hegel Martin Heidegger and Edmund Husserl in France at that time 186 Louis Althusser as well as his colleagues such as Etienne Balibar saw in Spinoza a philosophy which could lead Marxism out of what they considered to be flaws in its original formulation particularly its reliance upon Hegel s conception of the dialectic as well as Spinoza s concept of immanent causality Antonio Negri in exile in France for much of this period also wrote a number of books on Spinoza most notably The Savage Anomaly 1981 in his own reconfiguration of Italian Autonomia Operaia Other notable French scholars of Spinoza in this period included Alexandre Matheron Martial Gueroult Andre Tosel and Pierre Macherey the last of whom published a widely read and influential five volume commentary on Spinoza s Ethics which has been described as a monument of Spinoza commentary 187 His philosophical accomplishments and moral character prompted Gilles Deleuze in his doctoral thesis 1968 to name him the prince of philosophers 188 189 Deleuze s interpretation of Spinoza s philosophy was highly influential among French philosophers especially in restoring to prominence the political dimension of Spinoza s thought 190 Deleuze published two books on Spinoza and gave numerous lectures on Spinoza in his capacity as a professor at the University of Paris VIII His own work was deeply influenced by Spinoza s philosophy particularly the concepts of immanence and univocity Marilena de Souza Chaui described Deleuze s Expressionism in Philosophy 1968 as a revolutionary work for its discovery of expression as a central concept in Spinoza s philosophy 190 clarification needed nbsp Einstein 1921 Albert Einstein named Spinoza as the philosopher who exerted the most influence on his world view Weltanschauung Spinoza equated God infinite substance with Nature consistent with Einstein s belief in an impersonal deity In 1929 Einstein was asked in a telegram by Rabbi Herbert S Goldstein whether he believed in God Einstein responded by telegram I believe in Spinoza s God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists not in a God who concerns himself with the fates and actions of human beings 191 192 Einstein wrote the preface to a biography of Spinoza published in 1946 193 Leo Strauss dedicated his first book Spinoza s Critique of Religion to an examination of his ideas Strauss identified Spinoza as part of the tradition of Enlightenment rationalism that eventually produced Modernity Moreover he identifies Spinoza and his works as the beginning of Jewish Modernity 113 More recently Jonathan Israel argued that from 1650 to 1750 Spinoza was the chief challenger of the fundamentals of revealed religion received ideas tradition morality and what was everywhere regarded in absolutist and non absolutist states alike as divinely constituted political authority 194 Spinoza is an important historical figure in the Netherlands where his portrait was featured prominently on the Dutch 1000 guilder banknote legal tender until the euro was introduced in 2002 The highest and most prestigious scientific award of the Netherlands is named the Spinozaprijs Spinoza prize Spinoza was included in a 50 theme canon that attempts to summarise the history of the Netherlands 195 In 2014 a copy of Spinoza s Tractatus Theologico Politicus was presented to the Chair of the Dutch Parliament and shares a shelf with the Bible and the Quran 196 Modern era editReconsideration of Spinoza s expulsion edit There has been a renewed debate in modern times about Spinoza s excommunication among Israeli politicians rabbis and Jewish press with many calling for the cherem to be reversed 197 A conference was organized at the YIVO Institute for Jewish Research in New York entitled From Heretic to Hero A Symposium on the Impact of Baruch Spinoza on the 350th Anniversary of His Excommunication 1656 2006 Presenters included Steven Nadler Jonathan I Israel Steven B Smith and Daniel B Schwartz 198 There have been calls for Spinoza s cherem to be rescinded but it can only be done by the congregation that issued it and the chief rabbi of that community d Haham Pinchas Toledano declined to do so citing Spinoza s preposterous ideas where he was tearing apart the very fundamentals of our religion 199 the Amsterdam Jewish community organised a symposium in December 2015 to discuss lifting the cherem inviting scholars from around the world to form an advisory committee at the meeting However the rabbi of the congregation ruled that it should hold on the basis that he had no greater wisdom than his predecessors and that Spinoza s views had not become less problematic over time 197 Memory and memorials edit nbsp Statue 2008 of Spinoza by Nicolas Dings Amsterdam Zwanenburgwal with inscription The objective of the state is freedom translation quote from Tractatus Theologico Politicus 1677 Spinoza Lyceum a high school in Amsterdam South was named after Spinoza There is also a 3 metre tall marble statue of him on the grounds of the school carved by Hildo Krop 200 The Spinoza Havurah a Humanistic Jewish community was named in Spinoza s honor 201 The Spinoza Foundation Monument has a statute of Spinoza located in front of the Amsterdam City Hall at Zwanenburgwal 202 It was created by Dutch sculptor Nicolas Dings and was erected in 2008 203 204 Depictions and influence in literature editSpinoza s life and work have been subject of interest for several writers For example this influence was considerably early in German literature where Goethe makes a glowing mention of the philosopher in his memoirs highlighting a positive influence by the Ethics in his personal life 205 The same thing happened in the case of his compatriot the poet Heine who is also lavish in praise for Spinoza on his On the History of Religion and Philosophy in Germany 1834 206 In the following century the Argentinian Jorge Luis Borges famously wrote two sonnets in his honor Spinoza in El otro el mismo 1964 and Baruch Spinoza in La moneda de hierro 1976 and several direct references to Spinoza s philosophy can be found in this writer s work 207 Also in Argentina and previously to Borges the Ukrainian born Jewish intellectual Alberto Gerchunoff wrote a novella about philosopher s early sentimental life Los amores de Baruj sic Spinoza lit The loves of Baruj Spinoza 1932 recreating a supposed affair or romantic interest with Clara Maria van den Enden daughter of his latin teacher and philosophical preceptor Franciscus 208 That is not the only fiction work where the philosopher appears as the main character In 1837 the German writer Berthold Auerbach dedicated to him the first novel in his series on Jewish history translated into English in 1882 Spinoza a Novel 209 Some other novels of biographical nature have appeared more recently as The Spinoza Problem 2012 a parallel story between the philosopher s formative years and the fascination that his work had on the Nazi leader Alfred Rosenberg by psychiatrist Irvin D Yalom or O Segredo de Espinosa lit The Secret of Spinoza 2023 by Portuguese journalist Jose Rodrigues dos Santos Spinoza also appear in the first novel of the Argentinian activist Andres Spokoiny El impio lit The Impious 2021 about the marrano phicicyst and philosopher Juan de Prado a key influence in his biography 210 Not directly his person but his influence or legacy are themes present both in The Spinoza of Market Street a short story by the Polish born Jewish American Nobel Prize winner Isaac Bashevis Singer originally written in yiddish in 1961 and also in the recent novel by Mexican Ezra Bejar Un Baruch para Spinoza lit A Baruch for Spinoza 2023 211 In another sense Spinoza s philosophy is an important part of the series of satirical punk post apocalyptic fiction novels by the French writer Jean Bernard Pouy begun with Spinoza encule Hegel lit Spinoza fucks Hegel 1983 where the protagonist take the nickname of Spinoza or Spino and projects a violent application of his thinking in a lawless world The series continued with two more novels subsequently issued in 1998 and 2006 Finally the British art critic John Berger published some prose poems and drawings under the title of Bento s Sketchbook 2011 inspired by the Philosopher s work from which he takes literal quotes and in the anecdote about the existence of a drawing notebook among his belongings that disappeared after his death Works editOriginal Editions edit c 1660 Korte Verhandeling van God de mensch en deszelvs welstand unpublished until the 19th century A Short Treatise on God Man and His Well Being translated by A Wolf London Adam and Charles Black Eds 1910 1662 Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione On the Improvement of the Understanding unfinished 1663 Principia philosophiae cartesianae The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy also contains Metaphysical Thoughts Cogitata Metaphisica translated by Samuel Shirley with an Introduction and Notes by Steven Barbone and Lee Rice Indianapolis 1998 1670 Tractatus Theologico Politicus A Theologico Political Treatise TTP published anonymously in his lifetime with a false place of publication 1675 76 Tractatus Politicus Political Treatise TP unfinished at his death published posthumously 1677 Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata The Ethics finished 1674 but published posthumously title added posthumously 1677 Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae Hebrew Grammar unfinished translated with introduction by M J Bloom London 1963 212 1677 Epistolae The Letters translated by Samuel Shirley with an Introduction and Notes by S Barbone L Rice and J Adler Indianapolis 1995 Last four were originally collected and published by Spinoza s friends briefly later his death in B d S Opera Posthuma Quorum series post Praefationem exhibetur Amsterdam Jan Rieuwertsz 1677 both publisher and place were purposely omitted Simultaneously Rieuwertsz also published a Dutch translation by Jan Hendriksz Glazemaker who some years later translated the TTP De Nagelate Schriften van B d S without the Hebrew Grammar Contemporary Editions edit Morgan Michael L ed 2002 Spinoza Complete Works with the Translation of Samuel Shirley Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 87220 620 5 Edwin Curley ed 1985 2016 The Collected Works of Spinoza two volumes Princeton Princeton University Press Excludes the Compendium grammatices linguae hebraeae Spruit Leen and Pina Totaro 2011 The Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza s Ethica Leiden Brill This is the only known surviving manuscript of Spinoza s Ethics discovered in the Vatican archive and published in a bilingual Latin English edition See also editList of works about Baruch Spinoza History of the Jews in the NetherlandsReferences editNotes edit Spinoza has also been interpreted as a defender of the coherence theory of truth 3 b e ˈ r uː k s p ɪ ˈ n oʊ z e 12 Dutch baːˈrux spɪˈnoːzaː Portuguese dɨ ʃpiˈnɔzɐ Hebrew ברוך שפינוזה His boyhood and early adult business name was Bento and his synagogue name was Baruch the Hebrew translation of Bento which means blessed 13 As a correspondent he primarily signed his name as Benedictus 14 Steven Nadler speculates that Spinoza Latinized his name at Leiden because all instruction was in Latin 76 Portugees Israelietische Gemeente te Amsterdam Portuguese Israelite commune of Amsterdam Citations edit Garber 2015 p 121 Newlands 2017 p 64 Young James O 26 June 2018 The Coherence Theory of Truth In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy David Marian 28 May 2015 The Correspondence Theory of Truth In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Koistinen 2018 p 288 Kreines 2015 p 25 LeBuffe Michael 26 May 2020 Spinoza s Psychological Theory In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Yovel 1989b p 3 a b Nadler 1999 p 45 Nadler 1999 p 119 Adler 2014 p 27 Spinoza Collins English Dictionary HarperCollins Retrieved 27 April 2019 Nadler 1999 p 42 Israel 2023 pp 353 54 Nadler 2018 pp xiii xiv Dutton Blake D Benedict De Spinoza 1632 1677 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 7 July 2019 Stewart 2006 p 352 Simkins 2014 Carlisle 2021 p 10 Smith 1997 p 2 Goldstein 2006 p i a b Israel 2023 p 115 Israel 2023 p 85 Israel 2023 p 134 Israel 2023 p 88 Israel 2023 p 299 Israel 2023 p 124 a b Israel 2023 p 158 Israel 2023 p 144 Israel 2023 p 140 a b Israel 2023 p 140 41 Nadler 2018 p 38 a b Israel 2023 p 183 Israel 2023 p 117 a b Israel 2023 p 185 Israel 2023 p 145 46 Israel 2023 p 159 Israel 2023 p 160 Israel 2023 p 161 Israel 2023 p 90 Nadler 2018 p 84 Israel 2023 pp 148 49 Nadler 1999 pp 65 66 Nadler 2018 pp 72 75 Nadler 2018 p 93 Nadler 2018 pp 100 101 Israel 2023 pp 206 Israel 2023 pp 204 05 a b Israel 2023 pp 205 06 Israel 2023 p 210 a b c Nadler 2001 p 25 Israel 2023 pp 220 22 Israel 2023 p 222 Nadler 2001 pp 17 22 Israel 2023 p 74 Scruton 2002 p 21 Touber 2018 p 45 Nadler 2001 pp 2 7 Smith 2003 p xx Nadler 2001 p 19 Nadler 2001 p 20 Nadler 2001 p 16 Nadler 2018 p 160 Nadler 2001 p 28 Scruton 2002 p 22 a b Israel 2023 pp 229 30 Israel 2023 p 243 Nadler 2011 p 167 Nadler 2018 pp 129 30 Nadler 2018 pp 125 26 Israel 2023 pp 342 Nadler 2018 p 164 Nadler 2018 p 168 Israel 2023 pp 338 39 Nadler 2018 p 184 Nadler 2018 p 193 Israel 2023 pp 333 38 Israel 2023 p 322 Israel 2023 p 330 Israel 2023 p 350 Israel 2023 p 344 Israel 2023 p 343 Nadler 2018 p 214 Israel 2023 p 456 Nadler 2018 p 225 Scruton 2002 p 12 Nadler 2018 pp 215 16 Nadler 2018 pp 243 45 Kirsch Adam The Reticent Radical Baruch Spinoza s quiet revolution The New Yorker February 12 amp 19 2024 89 92 he Spinoza told me Leibniz he had a strong desire on the day of the massacre of Mess De Witt to sally forth at night and put up somewhere near the place of the massacre a paper with the words Ultimi barbarorum ultimate barbarians But his host had shut the house to prevent his going out for he would have run the risk of being torn to pieces A Refutation Recently Discovered of Spinoza by Leibnitz Remarks on the Unpublished Refutation of Spinoza by Leibnitz Edinburg Thomas Constable and Company 1855 p 70 Nadler 2011 p 239 a b Scruton 2002 p 26 Chaui 2001 pp 30 31 A commentary on Descartes work Principles of Cartesian Philosophy only work published under his own name brought him on an invitation to teach philosophy at the University of Heidelberg Spinoza however refused thinking that it might demand the renunciation of his freedom of thought for the invite stipulated that all care should be taken to not insult the principles of the established religion Popkin Richard H Benedict de Spinoza in The Columbia History of Western Philosophy Columbia University Press 1999 p 381 a b Lucas 1960 a b Stewart 2006 pp 12 14 Christiaan Huygens Oeuvres completes Letter No 1638 11 May 1668 Christiaan Huygens Oeuvres completes letter to his brother 23 September 1667 Nadler 2018 p 215 Nadler 2001 p 183 Christiaan Huygens Oeuvres completes vol XXII p 732 footnote Theodore Kerckring Spicilegium Anatomicum Observatio XCIII 1670 a b Gottlieb Anthony God Exists Philosophically archive nytimes com Retrieved 18 March 2024 Gullan Whur 1998 pp 317 18 Israel 2023 pp 1150 1151 Nadler 2018 p 406 Israel 2023 p 1155 Israel 2023 pp 1158 Jonathan Israel The Banning of Spinoza s Works in the Dutch Republic 1670 1678 in Wiep van Bunge and Wim Klever eds Disguised and Overt Spinozism around 1700 Leiden 1996 pp 3 14 online Archived 28 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine Totaro 2015 pp 321 22 Ven Jeroen van de Printing Spinoza A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century Leiden Brill 2022 Stewart 2006 p 106 a b c d e f Bloom Harold 16 June 2006 Deciphering Spinoza the Great Original Book review of Betraying Spinoza The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity by Rebecca Goldstein The New York Times Retrieved 8 September 2009 Morgan Michael L 2002 Spinoza Complete Works with the Translation of Samuel Shirley Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company p 755 ISBN 978 0 87220 620 5 see Refutation of Spinoza Buruma 2024 pp 166 67 Spinoza on Islam 13 February 2012 Spinoza Baruch 2003 Correspondence of Spinoza Translated by A Wolf Kessinger Publishing LLC p 354 Coyle Patrick A 1938 Some aspects of the philosophy of Spinoza and his ontological proof of the existence of God PDF University of Western Ontario CA p 2 OCLC 1067012129 Retrieved 9 June 2021 via University of Windsor Electronic Theses and Dissertations Soley 1880 Nadler 2011 p xi Israel 2023 pp 776 Montanarelli Lisa Spinoza stymies God s attorney Stewart argues the secular world was at stake in Leibniz face off SFGate Retrieved 20 March 2024 Scruton 2002 pp 31 32 Morgan Michael L 2002 Spinoza Complete Works with the Translation of Samuel Shirley Indianapolis Cambridge Hackett Publishing Company p 109 ISBN 978 0 87220 620 5 Della Rocca 2008 p 33 Jaspers 1974 p 9 a b Scruton 2002 p 41 a b Scruton 2002 p 42 Scruton 2002 p 43 Scruton 2002 p 44 a b Scruton 2002 p 45 a b Scruton 2002 p 38 Lin Martin 2007 Spinoza s Arguments for the Existence of God Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 2 269 297 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2007 00076 x a b Scruton 2002 p 51 Scruton 2002 p 57 Scruton 2002 p 59 Scruton 2002 p 60 Cannon J A 2009 May 17 World in time of upheaval Sources of enlightenment Deseret News a b Charles Hartshorne and William Reese Philosophers Speak of God Humanity Books 1953 ch 4 Baruch Spinoza Ethics inSpinoza Complete Works trans by Samuel Shirley and ed by Michael L Morgan Indianapolis Hackett Publishing 2002 see Part I Proposition 33 Curley 1996 p 73 Ethics Pt I Prop XXXVI Appendix M en think themselves free inasmuch as they are conscious of their volitions and desires and never even dream in their ignorance of the causes which have disposed of them so to wish and desire Scruton 2002 p 86 Spinoza and the Philosophy of Science Mathematics Motion and Being PhilSci Archive 9 July 2012 Della Rocca 2008 p 30 a b Konstan David 8 July 2022 Epicurus In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Curley 1996 p 118 Baruch Spinoza Human Beings are Determined Lander edu Retrieved 21 February 2017 Bennett 1984 p 276 Bennett 1984 p 277 Spinoza Benedictus de 1996 Ethics Penguin Books p 176 ISBN 9780140435719 Bennett 1984 p 371 Nadler 2018 p 495 Israel 2023 pp 895 96 Matheron Alexandre Femmes et serviteurs dans lad democratie spinoziste Revue philosophique de la la France et de l etranger 2 1977 181 200 Frank Thilly A History of Philosophy 47 Holt amp Co New York 1914 I believe in Spinoza s God who reveals himself in the orderly harmony of what exists not in a God who concerns himself with fates and actions of human beings These words were spoken by Albert Einstein upon being asked if he believed in God by Rabbi Herbert Goldstein of the Institutional Synagogue New York April 24 1921 published in the New York Times April 25 1929 from Einstein The Life and Times Ronald W Clark New York World Publishing Co 1971 p 413 also cited as a telegram to a Jewish newspaper 1929 Einstein Archive 33 272 from Alice Calaprice ed The Expanded Quotable Einstein Princeton NJ Princeton University Lange Frederick Albert 1880 History of Materialism and Criticism of its Present Importance Vol II Boston Houghton Osgood amp Co p 147 Retrieved 11 November 2015 The Pantheism of Spinoza Dr Smith regarded as the most dangerous enemy of Christianity and as he announced his conviction that it had gained the control of the schools press and pulpit of the Old World Europe and was rapidly gaining the same control of the New United States his alarm and indignation sometimes rose to the eloquence of genuine passion Memorial of the Rev Henry Smith D D LL D Professor of Sacred Rhetoric and Pastoral Theology in Lane Theological Seminary Consisting of Addresses on Occasion of the Anniversary of the Seminary 8 May 1879 Together with Commemorative Resolutions p 26 Hutchison Percy 20 November 1932 Spinoza God Intoxicated Man Three Books Which Mark the Three Hundredth Anniversary of the Philosopher s Birth The New York Times Retrieved 8 September 2009 Picton J Allanson Pantheism Its Story and Significance 1905 Fraser Alexander Campbell Philosophy of Theism William Blackwood and Sons 1895 p 163 Correspondence of Benedict de Spinoza Wilder Publications 26 March 2009 ISBN 978 1 60459 156 9 letter 73 a b Jaspers 1974 pp 14 95 a b Genevieve Lloyd Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to Spinoza and The Ethics Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks Routledge 1 edition 2 October 1996 ISBN 978 0 415 10782 2 p 40 Mander William 17 August 2023 Pantheism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Nadler Steven 8 November 2023 Baruch Spinoza In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Pierre Bayle Dictionnaire Historique et Critique vol 13 in French Libraire Desoer Paris 1820 p 416 Immanuel Kant The end of all things in Religion and Rational Theology Transl and edited by Allen W Wood and George Di Giovanni Cambridge University Press p 228 Literary Remains of the Late Professor Theodore Goldstucker W H Allen 1879 p 32 The Westminster Review 1862 pp 256 257 Three Lectures on the Vedanta Philosophy F Max Muller Kessinger Publishing 2003 p 123 Ralph Dumain The Autodidact Project Spinoza the First Secular Jew by Yirmiyahu Yovel Kirsch The Reticent Radical p 92 Israel 2023 pp 1205 Hegel Society of America Meeting 2003 Duquette David A ed Hegel s History of Philosophy New Interpretations SUNY Series in Hegelian Studies SUNY Press ISBN 9780791455432 Archived from the original on 13 May 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Smith 1997 p 168 69 Yovel Yirmiyahu Spinoza the First Secular Jew Tikkun vol 5 no 1 pp 40 42 94 96 Goetschel Willi Spinoza s Modernity Mendelssohn Lessing and Heine Madison University of Wisconsin Press 2004 a b Schwartz Daniel B The First Modern Jew Spinoza and the History of an Image Princeton Princeton University Press 2012 George Santayana The Ethical Doctrine of Spinoza The Harvard Monthly 2 June 1886 144 52 George Santayana Introduction in Spinoza s Ethics and De intellectus emendatione London Dent 1910 vii xxii George Santayana Ultimate Religion in Obiter Scripta eds Justus Buchler and Benjamin Schwartz New York and London Charles Scribner s Sons 1936 280 97 George Santayana Persons and Places Cambridge MA and London MIT Press 1986 pp 233 36 Peden Knox 2014 Spinoza contra phenomenology French rationalism from Cavailles to Deleuze Stanford California Stanford University Press ISBN 978 0 8047 9136 6 OCLC 880877889 Baugh Bruce 28 March 2015 Spinoza Contra Phenomenology French Rationalism from Cavailles to Deleuze Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews Retrieved 19 May 2022 Deleuze 1968 Quoted in the translator s preface of Deleuze s Expressionism in Philosophy Spinoza 1990 a b Rocha Mauricio 2021 Spinozist Moments in Deleuze Materialism as Immanence Materialism and Politics Berlin ICI Berlin Press pp 73 90 doi 10 37050 ci 20 04 S2CID 234131869 retrieved 19 May 2022 Einstein believes in Spinoza s God Scientist Defines His Faith in Reply to Cablegram From Rabbi Here Sees a Divine Order But Says Its Ruler Is Not Concerned Wit sic Fates and Actions of Human Beings The New York Times 25 April 1929 Retrieved 8 September 2009 Einstein s Third Paradise by Gerald Holton Aip org Archived from the original on 22 May 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Kaiser Rudolf Spinoza Portrait of a Spiritual Hero New York Philosophical Library 1946 Israel 2001 p 159 Entoen nu Entoen nu Archived from the original on 13 May 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 Van der Ham biedt Verbeet Spinoza aan RTL Nieuws 5 July 2012 Retrieved 30 November 2014 a b Rutledge David 3 October 2020 The Jewish philosopher Spinoza was one of the great Enlightenment thinkers So why was he cancelled ABC News ABC Radio National The Philosopher s Zone Australian Broadcasting Corporation Retrieved 7 October 2020 Schwartz The First Modern Jew Spinoza and the History of an Image Princeton Princeton University Press 2012 xi Rocker Simon 28 August 2014 Why Baruch Spinoza is still excommunicated The Jewish Chronicle Online Mo 50 Statue Spinoza Amsterdam in Dutch Archived from the original on 22 January 2022 Retrieved 20 June 2023 SpinozaHavurah org Archived 1 January 2023 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 202 2022 Statute of Spinoza unveiled in Amsterdam centre Simply Amsterdam Nov 25 2008 Archived 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 20 2022 Who stands proud on a pedestal in Amsterdam Unclogged in Amsterdam An American Expat plumbs Holland Aug 22 2020 Archived 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 20 2022 Spinoza Monument CitySeeker com Archived 21 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine Accessed Nov 20 2022 Johan W von Goethe Autobiography vol 2 Transl by John Oxenford The Anthological Society London Chicago 1901 Chapters 14 16 p 178 248 Heinrich Heine On the History of Religion and Philosophy in Germany Edited by Paul L Rose James Cook University of North Queensland 1982 p 56 57 Marcelo Abadi Spinoza in Borges looking glass Borges Studies Online J L Borges Center for Studies amp Documentation Internet 14 04 01 Diego Sztulwark Spinoza y la cultura judia argentina in Spanish El Cohete a la Luna 2 6 2022 See complete text on Wikisource El Impio de Andres Spokoiny In Spanish 05 27 2022 Baruch Spinoza un pensador que cimbro su tiempo in Spanish 8 14 2022 See G Licata Spinoza e la cognitio universalis dell ebraico Demistificazione e speculazione grammaticale nel Compendio di grammatica ebraica Giornale di Metafisica 3 2009 pp 625 61 Sources edit Books Adler Jacob 2014 Mortality of the soul from Alexander of Aphrodisias to Spinoza In Nadler Steven ed Spinoza and Medieval Jewish Philosophy Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 13 35 doi 10 1017 CBO9781139795395 002 ISBN 978 1 139 79539 5 via Cambridge Core Bennett Jonathan 1984 A Study of Spinoza sEthics Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 0 915145 83 9 OCLC 1036958076 Buruma Ian 2024 Spinoza Freedom s Messiah Yale University Press ISBN 978 0 30 024892 0 Carlisle Clare 2021 Spinoza s Religion Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 17659 8 Chaui Marilena 2001 1995 Espinosa uma filosofia da liberdade Sao Paulo Editora Moderna Curley Edwin ed 1985 The Collected Works of Spinoza Volume 1 Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 07222 7 Curley Edwin ed 1996 Ethics Penguin classics 1st ed London Penguin Books ISBN 978 0 14 043571 9 Della Rocca Michael 2008 Spinoza New York Routledge ISBN 978 0 41 528330 4 Koistinen Olli 2018 Spinoza on Mind In Della Rocca Michael ed The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza Cambridge Oxford University Press pp 273 294 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780195335828 013 004 ISBN 978 0 195 33582 8 Gullan Whur Margaret 1998 Within Reason A Life of Spinoza Jonathan Cape ISBN 978 0 224 05046 3 Israel Jonathan 2023 Spinoza Life and Legacy Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 885748 8 Israel Jonathan 2001 Radical Enlightenment Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650 1750 Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 925456 9 Jaspers Karl 23 October 1974 Spinoza Great Philosophers Harvest Books ISBN 978 0 15 684730 8 Kreines James 2015 Reason in the World Hegel s Metaphysics and Its Philosophical Appeal Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 020430 3 Lucas P G 1960 Some Speculative and Critical Philosophers In I Levine ed Philosophy London Odhams Garber Daniel 2015 Spinoza s Cartesian Dualism in the Korte Verhandeling In Melamed Yitzhak Y ed The Young Spinoza A Metaphysician in the Making Oxford Oxford University Press pp 121 132 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199971657 003 0008 ISBN 978 0 19 997166 4 OCLC 900634238 Goldstein Rebecca 2006 Betraying Spinoza The Renegade Jew who Gave Us Modernity New York Schocken Books ISBN 978 0 8052 4209 6 OCLC 61859859 Totaro Pina 2015 The Young Spinoza and the Vatican Manuscript of Spinoza s Ethics In Melamed Yitzhak Y ed The Young Spinoza A Metaphysician in the Making Oxford Oxford University Press pp 319 332 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199971657 003 0021 ISBN 978 0 19 997166 4 OCLC 900634238 Nadler Steven M 1999 Spinoza A Life Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 55210 3 OCLC 185335604 Nadler Steven M 2018 Spinoza A Life 2nd ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 44246 6 Nadler Steven M 2001 Spinoza s Heresy Immortality and the Jewish Mind New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926887 0 Nadler Steven 2011 A Book Forged in Hell Spinoza s Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the Secular Age Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 13989 0 Newlands Samuel 2017 Spinoza on Universals In Di Bella Stefano Schmaltz Tad M eds The Problem of Universals in Early Modern Philosophy New York Oxford University Press pp 62 86 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780190608040 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 060806 4 Popkin R H 2004 Spinoza Oxford One World Publications Scruton Roger 2002 Spinoza A Very Short Introduction Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 280316 0 Smith Steven B 2003 Spinoza s Book of Life Freedom and Redemption in theEthics New Haven Yale University Press ISBN 0 300 10019 1 Smith Steven B 1997 Spinoza Liberalism and the Question of Jewish Identity New Haven Yale University Press ISBN 978 0 300 07665 3 Touber Jetze 2018 Spinoza and Biblical Philology in the Dutch Republic 1660 1710 New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 880500 7 OCLC 1042074357 Stewart Matthew 2006 The Courtier and the Heretic Leibniz Spinoza and the Fate of God in the Modern World New York W W Norton and Company ISBN 978 0 393 32917 9 OCLC 1064514238 Yovel Yirmiyahu 1989a Spinoza and Other Heretics The Marrano of Reason Vol 1 Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 07344 9 OCLC 24378397 Yovel Yirmiyahu 1989b Spinoza and other heretics The Adventures of Immanence Vol 2 Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 02079 5 OCLC 1273001409 Articles and online Nadler Steven 2001b The Excommunication of Spinoza Trouble and Toleration in the Dutch Jerusalem Shofar 19 4 40 52 ISSN 0882 8539 JSTOR 42943396 Simkins James 2014 On the Development of Spinoza s Account of Human Religion Intermountain West Journal of Religious Studies 5 1 52 72 ISSN 2155 1723 Soley W R 1 July 1880 Jewish Mediaeval Philosophy in Spinoza Mind os V 19 Oxford University Press 362 384 doi 10 1093 mind os V 19 362 ISSN 0026 4423 JSTOR 2246395 OCLC 5545819846 other hand the discovery and publication in 1862 of a lost treatise of Spinoza s the Tractatus brtvia de Deo et homine ejusque felicitate The Religious Difficulties of India The Westminster Review 78 American ed New York Leonard Scott amp Co 245 263 1862 hdl 2027 mdp 39015013165819 Other works edit Damasio Antonio 2003 Looking for Spinoza Joy Sorrow and the Feeling Brain Harvest Books ISBN 978 0 15 602871 4 Della Rocca Michael 1996 Representation and the Mind Body Problem in Spinoza Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 509562 3 Garrett Don ed 1995 The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza Cambridge Uni Press Deleuze Gilles 1968 Spinoza et le probleme de l expression Trans Expressionism in Philosophy Spinoza Martin Joughin New York Zone Books 1970 Spinoza Philosophie pratique Transl Spinoza Practical Philosophy 1990 Negotiations trans Martin Joughin New York Columbia University Press Gatens Moira and Lloyd Genevieve 1999 Collective imaginings Spinoza past and present Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 16570 9 978 0 415 16571 6 Koistinen Olli ed 2009 The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza s Ethics Cambridge Cambridge University Press Goode Francis 2012 Life of Spinoza Smashwords edition ISBN 978 1 4661 3399 0 Hampshire Stuart 1951 Spinoza and Spinozism OUP 2005 ISBN 978 0 19 927954 8 Hardt Michael trans University of Minnesota Press Preface in French by Gilles Deleuze available here 01 Preface a L Anomalie sauvage de Negri Multitudes samizdat net Archived from the original on 11 June 2011 Retrieved 2 May 2011 2006 Enlightenment Contested Philosophy Modernity and the Emancipation of Man 1670 1752 ISBN 978 0 19 927922 7 2002 Philosophy Commerce and the Synagogue Spinoza s Expulsion from the Amsterdam Portuguese Jewish Community in 1656 In Dutch Jewry Its History and Secular Culture 1500 2000 Edited by Jonathan Israel and Reinier Salverda pp 125 140 Leiden Brill Ives David 2009 New Jerusalem The Interrogation of Baruch de Spinoza at Talmud Torah Congregation Amsterdam 27 July 1656 New York Dramatists Play Service ISBN 978 0 8222 2385 6 Kayser Rudolf 1946 with an introduction by Albert Einstein Spinoza Portrait of a Spiritual Hero New York The Philosophical Library Kisner Matthew J 2011 Spinoza on human freedom Reason autonomy and the good life New York Cambridge University Press Lloyd Genevieve 1994 Part of Nature Self Knowledge in Spinoza s Ethics Ithaca Cornell University Press Lloyd Genevieve 2018 Reclaiming wonder After the sublime Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 1 4744 3311 2 LeBuffe Michael 2010 Spinoza and Human Freedom Oxford University Press Lovejoy Arthur O 1936 Plenitude and Sufficient Reason in Leibniz and Spinoza in his The Great Chain of Being Harvard University Press 144 82 ISBN 978 0 674 36153 9 Reprinted in Frankfurt H G ed 1972 Leibniz A Collection of Critical Essays Anchor Books Macherey Pierre 1977 Hegel ou Spinoza Maspero 2nd ed La Decouverte 2004 1994 98 Introduction a l Ethique de Spinoza Paris PUF Magnusson 1990 Magnusson M ed Spinoza Baruch Chambers Biographical Dictionary Chambers 1990 ISBN 978 0 550 16041 6 Matheron Alexandre 1969 Individu et communaute chez Spinoza Paris Minuit Millner Simon L The Face of Benedictus Spinoza New York Machmadim Art Editions Inc 1946 Montag Warren Bodies Masses Power Spinoza and his Contemporaries London Verso 2002 Moreau Pierre Francois 2003 Spinoza et le spinozisme PUF Presses Universitaires de France Nadler Steven Think Least of Death Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die 2020 Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0691183848 Negri Antonio 1991 The Savage Anomaly The Power of Spinoza s Metaphysics and Politics 2004 Subversive Spinoza Un Contemporary Variations Prokhovnik Raia 2004 Spinoza and republicanism Houndmills Basingstoke Hampshire New York Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 0333733905 Ratner Joseph 1927 The Philosophy of Spinoza The Modern Library Random House Stolze Ted and Warren Montag eds The New Spinoza Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press 1997 Strauss Leo Persecution and the Art of Writing Glencoe Illinois Free Press 1952 Reprint Chicago University of Chicago Press 1988 ch 5 How to Study Spinoza s Tractus Theologico Politicus reprinted in Strauss Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity ed Kenneth Hart Green Albany NY SUNY Press 1997 181 233 Spinoza s Critique of Religion New York Schocken Books 1965 Reprint University of Chicago Press 1996 Preface to the English Translation reprinted as Preface to Spinoza s Critique of Religion in Strauss Liberalism Ancient and Modern New York Basic Books 1968 224 59 also in Strauss Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity 137 77 Valentiner W R 1957 Rembrandt and Spinoza A Study of the Spiritual Conflicts in Seventeenth Century Holland London Phaidon Press Vinciguerra Lorenzo Spinoza in French Philosophy Today Philosophy Today Archived 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine Vol 53 No 4 Winter 2009 Archived 7 August 2020 at the Wayback Machine Van den Ven Jeroen Printing Spinoza A Descriptive Bibliography of the Works Published in the Seventeenth Century Leiden 2022 Documenting Spinoza A Biographical History of his Life and Time forthcoming Williams David Lay 2010 Spinoza and the General Will The Journal of Politics vol 72 April 341 356 Wolfson Henry A The Philosophy of Spinoza 2 vols Harvard University Press External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Baruch de Spinoza nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Baruch Spinoza nbsp Wikisource has original works by or about Benedictus de Spinoza Works Works by Benedictus de Spinoza at Project Gutenberg Works by Baruch Spinoza at LibriVox public domain audiobooks nbsp Works by Baruch Spinoza at Open Library A Theologico Political Treatise English Translation Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata et in quinque partes distincta in quibus agetur Opera posthuma Amsterdam 1677 Complete photographic reproduction ed by F Mignini Quodlibet publishing house website The Ethics of Benedict de Spinoza translated by George Eliot transcribed by Thomas Deegan Spinoza Archive on the Digital collections of Younes and Soraya Nazarian Library University of Haifa Leprozengracht with a view on the houses at Houtgracht by Reinier Nooms 1657 1662 Portals nbsp Biography nbsp Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Baruch Spinoza amp oldid 1224007037, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.