fbpx
Wikipedia

Atomism

Atomism (from Greek ἄτομον, atomon, i.e. "uncuttable, indivisible")[1][2][3] is a natural philosophy proposing that the physical universe is composed of fundamental indivisible components known as atoms.

References to the concept of atomism and its atoms appeared in both ancient Greek and ancient Indian philosophical traditions. Leucippus is the earliest figure whose commitment to atomism is well attested and he is usually credited with inventing atomism.[4] He and other ancient Greek atomists theorized that nature consists of two fundamental principles: atom and void. Clusters of different shapes, arrangements, and positions give rise to the various macroscopic substances in the world.[5][4]

The particles of chemical matter for which chemists and other natural philosophers of the early 19th century found experimental evidence were thought to be indivisible, and therefore were given by John Dalton the name "atom", long used by the atomist philosophy. Although the connection to historical atomism is at best tenuous, elementary particles have become a modern analogue of philosophical atoms.

Reductionism

Philosophical atomism is a reductive argument, proposing not only that everything is composed of atoms and void, but that nothing they compose really exists: the only things that really exist are atoms ricocheting off each other mechanistically in an otherwise empty void. Atomism stands in contrast to a substance theory wherein a prime material continuum remains qualitatively invariant under division (for example, the ratio of the four classical elements would be the same in any portion of a homogeneous material).

Indian Buddhists, such as Dharmakirti (fl. c. 6th or 7th century) and others, developed distinctive theories of atomism, for example, involving momentary (instantaneous) atoms (kalapas) that flash in and out of existence.

History

Antiquity

Greek atomism

Democritus

In the 5th century BC, Leucippus and his pupil Democritus proposed that all matter was composed of small indivisible particles which they called "atoms".[6][7][8][9] Nothing whatsoever is known about Leucippus except that he was the teacher of Democritus.[9] Democritus, by contrast, wrote prolifically, producing over eighty known treatises, none of which have survived to the present day complete.[9] However, a massive number of fragments and quotations of his writings have survived.[9] These are the main source of information on his teachings about atoms.[9] Democritus's argument for the existence of atoms hinged on the idea that it is impossible to keep dividing matter infinitely - and that matter must therefore be made up of extremely tiny particles.[9] The atomistic theory aimed to remove the "distinction which the Eleatic school drew between the Absolute, or the only real existence, and the world of change around us."[10]

Democritus believed that atoms are too small for human senses to detect, that they are infinitely many, that they come in infinitely many varieties, and that they have always existed.[9] They float in a vacuum, which Democritus called the "void",[9] and they vary in form, order, and posture.[9] Some atoms, he maintained, are convex, others concave, some shaped like hooks, and others like eyes.[9] They are constantly moving and colliding into each other.[9] Democritus wrote that atoms and void are the only things that exist and that all other things are merely said to exist by social convention.[9] The objects humans see in everyday life are composed of many atoms united by random collisions and their forms and materials are determined by what kinds of atom make them up.[9] Likewise, human perceptions are caused by atoms as well.[9] Bitterness is caused by small, angular, jagged atoms passing across the tongue;[9] whereas sweetness is caused by larger, smoother, more rounded atoms passing across the tongue.[9]

Previously, Parmenides had denied the existence of motion, change and void. He believed all existence to be a single, all-encompassing and unchanging mass (a concept known as monism), and that change and motion were mere illusions. He explicitly rejected sensory experience as the path to an understanding of the universe and instead used purely abstract reasoning. He believed there is no such thing as void, equating it with non-being. This in turn meant that motion is impossible, because there is no void to move into.[11] Parmenides doesn't mention or explicitly deny the existence of the void, stating instead that what is not does not exist.[12][13][14] He also wrote all that is must be an indivisible unity, for if it were manifold, then there would have to be a void that could divide it. Finally, he stated that the all encompassing Unity is unchanging, for the Unity already encompasses all that is and can be.[11]

Democritus accepted most of Parmenides' arguments, except for the idea that change is an illusion. He believed change was real, and if it was not then at least the illusion had to be explained. He thus supported the concept of void, and stated that the universe is made up of many Parmenidean entities that move around in the void.[11] The void is infinite and provides the space in which the atoms can pack or scatter differently. The different possible packings and scatterings within the void make up the shifting outlines and bulk of the objects that organisms feel, see, eat, hear, smell, and taste. While organisms may feel hot or cold, hot and cold actually have no real existence. They are simply sensations produced in organisms by the different packings and scatterings of the atoms in the void that compose the object that organisms sense as being "hot" or "cold".

The work of Democritus survives only in secondhand reports, some of which are unreliable or conflicting. Much of the best evidence of Democritus' theory of atomism is reported by Aristotle (384–322 BCE) in his discussions of Democritus' and Plato's contrasting views on the types of indivisibles composing the natural world.[15]

Geometry and atoms
Element Polyhedron Number of Faces Number of Triangles
Fire Tetrahedron

(Animation)

  4 24
Air Octahedron

(Animation)

  8 48
Water Icosahedron

(Animation)

  20 120
Earth Cube

(Animation)

  6 24
Geometrical simple bodies according to Plato

Plato (c. 427c. 347 BCE), if he had been familiar with the atomism of Democritus, would have objected to its mechanistic materialism. He argued that atoms just crashing into other atoms could never produce the beauty and form of the world. In Plato's Timaeus (28b–29a) the character of Timeaus insisted that the cosmos was not eternal but was created, although its creator framed it after an eternal, unchanging model.[16]

One part of that creation were the four simple bodies of fire, air, water, and earth. But Plato did not consider these corpuscles to be the most basic level of reality, for in his view they were made up of an unchanging level of reality, which was mathematical. These simple bodies were geometric solids, the faces of which were, in turn, made up of triangles. The square faces of the cube were each made up of four isosceles right-angled triangles and the triangular faces of the tetrahedron, octahedron, and icosahedron were each made up of six right-angled triangles.

Plato postulated the geometric structure of the simple bodies of the four elements as summarized in the adjacent table. The cube, with its flat base and stability, was assigned to earth; the tetrahedron was assigned to fire because its penetrating points and sharp edges made it mobile. The points and edges of the octahedron and icosahedron were blunter and so these less mobile bodies were assigned to air and water. Since the simple bodies could be decomposed into triangles, and the triangles reassembled into atoms of different elements, Plato's model offered a plausible account of changes among the primary substances.[17][18]

Rejection in Aristotelianism

Sometime before 330 BC Aristotle asserted that the elements of fire, air, earth, and water were not made of atoms, but were continuous. Aristotle considered the existence of a void, which was required by atomic theories, to violate physical principles. Change took place not by the rearrangement of atoms to make new structures, but by transformation of matter from what it was in potential to a new actuality. A piece of wet clay, when acted upon by a potter, takes on its potential to be an actual drinking mug. Aristotle has often been criticized for rejecting atomism, but in ancient Greece the atomic theories of Democritus remained "pure speculations, incapable of being put to any experimental test".[19][need quotation to verify][20][21][unbalanced opinion?]

Aristotle theorized minima naturalia as the smallest parts into which a homogeneous natural substance (e.g., flesh, bone, or wood) could be divided and still retain its essential character. Unlike the atomism of Democritus, these Aristotelian "natural minima" were not conceptualized as physically indivisible. Instead, Aristotle's concept was rooted in his hylomorphic worldview, which held that every physical thing is a compound of matter (Greek hyle) and of an immaterial substantial form (Greek morphe) that imparts its essential nature and structure. For instance, a rubber ball - for a hylomorphist like Aristotle - would be rubber (matter) structured by spherical shape (form). Aristotle's intuition was that there is some smallest size beyond which matter could no longer be structured as flesh, or bone, or wood, or some other such organic substance that for Aristotle (living before the invention of the microscope) could be considered homogeneous. For instance, if flesh were divided beyond its natural minimum, what would be left might be a large amount of the element water, and smaller amounts of the other elements. But whatever water or other elements were left, they would no longer have the "nature" of flesh: in hylomorphic terms, they would no longer be matter structured by the form of flesh; instead the remaining water, e.g., would be matter structured by the form of water, not by the form of flesh.

Later ancient atomism

Epicurus (341–270 BCE) studied atomism with Nausiphanes who had been a student of Democritus. Although Epicurus was certain of the existence of atoms and the void, he was less sure we could adequately explain specific natural phenomena such as earthquakes, lightning, comets, or the phases of the Moon. [22] Few of Epicurus' writings survive, and those that do reflect his interest in applying Democritus' theories to assist people in taking responsibility for themselves and for their own happiness—since he held there are no gods around that can help them. (Epicurus regarded the role of gods as exemplifying moral ideals.)

Epicurus' ideas re-appear in the works of his Roman follower Lucretius (c. 99 BC – c. 55 BC), who wrote On the Nature of Things. This Classical Latin scientific work in poetic form illustrates several segments of Epicurean theory on how the universe came into its current stage; it shows that the phenomena we perceive are actually composite forms. The atoms and the void are eternal and in constant motion. Atomic collisions create objects, which are still composed of the same eternal atoms whose motion for a while is incorporated into the created entity. Lucretius also explains human sensations and meteorological phenomena in terms of atomic motion.

Atomism and ethics

Some later philosophers attributed the idea that man created gods and that gods did not create man to Democritus. For example, Sextus Empiricus noted:

Some people think that we arrived at the idea of gods from the remarkable things that happen in the world. Democritus ... says that the people of ancient times were frightened by happenings in the heavens such as thunder, lightning, ..., and thought that they were caused by gods.[23]

Three hundred years after Epicurus, Lucretius in his epic poem On the Nature of Things would depict him as the hero who crushed the monster Religion through educating the people in what was possible in atoms and what was not possible in atoms. However, Epicurus expressed a non-aggressive attitude characterized by his statement: "The man who best knows how to meet external threats makes into one family all the creatures he can; and those he can not, he at any rate does not treat as aliens; and where he finds even this impossible, he avoids all dealings, and, so far as is advantageous, excludes them from his life."[24]

Indian atomism

In ancient Indian philosophy, preliminary instances of atomism are found in the works of Vedic sage Aruni, who lived in the 8th century BCE, especially his proposition that "particles too small to be seen mass together into the substances and objects of experience" known as kaṇa.[25] Although kana refers to "particles" not atoms (paramanu), Some scholars such as Hermann Jacobi and Randall Collins have compared Aruni to Thales of Miletus in their scientific methodology, calling them both as "primitive physicists" or "proto-materialist thinkers".[26] Later, the Charvaka,[27][28] and Ajivika schools of atomism originated as early as the 7th century BCE.[29][30][31] Bhattacharya posits that Charvaka may have been one of several atheistic, materialist schools that existed in ancient India.[32][33]Kanada founded the Vaisheshika school of Indian philosophy that also represents the earliest Indian natural philosophy. The Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools developed theories on how kaṇas combined into more complex objects.[34]

Several of these doctrines of atomism are, in some respects, "suggestively similar" to that of Democritus.[35] McEvilley (2002) assumes that such similarities are due to extensive cultural contact and diffusion, probably in both directions.[36]

The NyayaVaisesika school developed one of the earliest forms of atomism; scholars[who?] date the Nyaya and Vaisesika texts from the 9th to 4th centuries BCE. Vaisesika atomists posited the four elemental atom types, but in Vaisesika physics atoms had 25 different possible qualities, divided between general extensive properties and specific (intensive) properties. The Nyaya–Vaisesika atomists had elaborate theories of how atoms combine. In Vaisesika atomism, atoms first combine in pairs (dyads), and then group into trios of pairs (triads), which are the smallest visible units of matter.[37]

The Buddhist atomists had very qualitative, Aristotelian-style atomic theory. According to ancient Buddhist atomism, which probably began developing before the 4th century BCE, there are four kinds of atoms, corresponding to the standard elements. Each of these elements has a specific property, such as solidity or motion, and performs a specific function in mixtures, such as providing support or causing growth. Like the Hindus, the Buddhists were able to integrate a theory of atomism with their theological presuppositions. Later Indian Buddhist philosophers, such as Dharmakirti and Dignāga, considered atoms to be point-sized, durationless, and made of energy.

Some of the canonical texts make reference to matter and atoms (called paramāṇu, a term already used in Yajnavalkya, Lalitha Sahasranama and Yoga Sutra), including Pancastikayasara, Kalpasutra and Tattvarthasutra.[citation needed] The Jains envisioned the world as consisting wholly of atoms, except for souls. Atoms were considered as the basic building blocks of all matter. Each atom had "one kind of taste, one smell, one color, and two kinds of touch", though it is unclear what was meant by "kind of touch".[citation needed][clarification needed] Atoms can exist in one of two states: subtle, in which case they can fit in infinitesimally small spaces, and gross, in which case they have extension and occupy a finite space.[citation needed] The texts also give "detailed theories" of how atoms could combine, react, vibrate, move, and perform other actions, all of which were thoroughly deterministic.[citation needed]

Middle Ages

Medieval Hinduism

Ajivika is a "Nastika" school of thought whose metaphysics included a theory of atoms or atomism which was later adapted in the Vaiśeṣika school, which postulated that all objects in the physical universe are reducible to paramāṇu (atoms), and one's experiences are derived from the interplay of substance (a function of atoms, their number and their spatial arrangements), quality, activity, commonness, particularity and inherence.[38] Everything was composed of atoms, qualities emerged from aggregates of atoms, but the aggregation and nature of these atoms was predetermined by cosmic forces.[39] The school founder's traditional name Kanada means 'atom eater',[40] and he is known for developing the foundations of an atomistic approach to physics and philosophy in the Sanskrit text Vaiśeṣika Sūtra.[41] His text is also known as Kanada Sutras, or Aphorisms of Kanada.[42][43]

Medieval Buddhism

Medieval Buddhist atomism, flourishing in ca. the 7th century, was very different from the atomist doctrines taught in early Buddhism. Medieval Buddhist philosophers Dharmakirti and Dignāga considered atoms to be point-sized, durationless, and made of energy. In discussing the two systems, Fyodor Shcherbatskoy (1930) stresses their commonality, the postulate of "absolute qualities" (guna-dharma) underlying all empirical phenomena.[44]

Still later, the Abhidhammattha-sangaha, a text dated to the 11th or 12th century, postulates the existence of rupa-kalapa, imagined as the smallest units of the physical world, of varying elementary composition.[45] Invisible under normal circumstances, the rupa-kalapa are said to become visible as a result of meditative samadhi.[46]

Medieval Islam

Atomistic philosophies are found very early in Islamic philosophy and was influenced by earlier Greek and to some extent Indian philosophy.[47][48] Like both the Greek and Indian versions, Islamic atomism was a charged topic that had the potential for conflict with the prevalent religious orthodoxy,[citation needed] but it was instead more often favoured by orthodox Islamic theologians. It was such a fertile and flexible idea that, as in Greece and India, it flourished in some leading schools of Islamic thought.

The most successful form of Islamic atomism was in the Asharite school of Islamic theology, most notably in the work of the theologian al-Ghazali (1058–1111). In Asharite atomism, atoms are the only perpetual, material things in existence, and all else in the world is "accidental" meaning something that lasts for only an instant. Nothing accidental can be the cause of anything else, except perception, as it exists for a moment. Contingent events are not subject to natural physical causes, but are the direct result of God's constant intervention, without which nothing could happen. Thus nature is completely dependent on God, which meshes with other Asharite Islamic ideas on causation, or the lack thereof (Gardet 2001). Al-Ghazali also used the theory to support his theory of occasionalism. In a sense, the Asharite theory of atomism has far more in common with Indian atomism than it does with Greek atomism.[49]

Other traditions in Islam rejected the atomism of the Asharites and expounded on many Greek texts, especially those of Aristotle. An active school of philosophers in Al-Andalus, including the noted commentator Averroes (1126–1198 CE) explicitly rejected the thought of al-Ghazali and turned to an extensive evaluation of the thought of Aristotle. Averroes commented in detail on most of the works of Aristotle and his commentaries became very influential in Jewish and Christian scholastic thought.

Medieval Christendom

While Aristotelian philosophy eclipsed the importance of the atomists in late Roman and medieval Europe, their work was still preserved and exposited through commentaries on the works of Aristotle. In the 2nd century, Galen (AD 129–216) presented extensive discussions of the Greek atomists, especially Epicurus, in his Aristotle commentaries. According to historian of atomism Joshua Gregory, there was no serious work done with atomism from the time of Galen until Isaac Beeckman, Gassendi and Descartes resurrected it in the 17th century; "the gap between these two 'modern naturalists' and the ancient Atomists marked "the exile of the atom" and "it is universally admitted that the Middle Ages had abandoned Atomism, and virtually lost it."

However, although the ancient atomists' works were unavailable, Scholastic thinkers still had Aristotle's critiques of atomism. In medieval universities there were expressions of atomism. For example, in the 14th century Nicholas of Autrecourt considered that matter, space, and time were all made up of indivisible atoms, points, and instants and that all generation and corruption took place by the rearrangement of material atoms. The similarities of his ideas with those of al-Ghazali suggest that Nicholas may have been familiar with Ghazali's work, perhaps through Averroes' refutation of it (Marmara, 1973–74).

Although the atomism of Epicurus had fallen out of favor in the centuries of Scholasticism, the minima naturalia of Aristotelianism received extensive consideration. Speculation on minima naturalia provided philosophical background for the mechanistic philosophy of early modern thinkers such as Descartes, and for the alchemical works of Geber and Daniel Sennert, who in turn influenced the corpuscularian alchemist Robert Boyle, one of the founders of modern chemistry.[50][51]

A chief theme in late Roman and Scholastic commentary on this concept is reconciling minima naturalia with the general Aristotelian principle of infinite divisibility. Commentators like John Philoponus and Thomas Aquinas reconciled these aspects of Aristotle's thought by distinguishing between mathematical and "natural" divisibility. With few exceptions, much of the curriculum in the universities of Europe was based on such Aristotelianism for most of the Middle Ages.[52]

Atomist renaissance

In the 17th century, a renewed interest arose in Epicurean atomism and corpuscularianism as a hybrid or an alternative to Aristotelian physics. The main figures in the rebirth of atomism were Isaac Beeckman, René Descartes, Pierre Gassendi, and Robert Boyle, as well as other notable figures.

One of the first groups of atomists in England was a cadre of amateur scientists known as the Northumberland circle, led by Henry Percy, 9th Earl of Northumberland (1564–1632). Although they published little of account, they helped to disseminate atomistic ideas among the burgeoning scientific culture of England, and may have been particularly influential to Francis Bacon, who became an atomist around 1605, though he later rejected some of the claims of atomism. Though they revived the classical form of atomism, this group was among the scientific avant-garde: the Northumberland circle contained nearly half of the confirmed Copernicans prior to 1610 (the year of Galileo's The Starry Messenger). Other influential atomists of late 16th and early 17th centuries include Giordano Bruno, Thomas Hobbes (who also changed his stance on atomism late in his career), and Thomas Hariot. A number of different atomistic theories were blossoming in France at this time, as well (Clericuzio 2000).

Galileo Galilei (1564–1642) was an advocate of atomism in his 1612, Discourse on Floating Bodies (Redondi 1969). In The Assayer, Galileo offered a more complete physical system based on a corpuscular theory of matter, in which all phenomena—with the exception of sound—are produced by "matter in motion". Galileo identified some basic problems with Aristotelian physics through his experiments. He utilized a theory of atomism as a partial replacement, but he was never unequivocally committed to it. For example, his experiments with falling bodies and inclined planes led him to the concepts of circular inertial motion and accelerating free-fall. The current Aristotelian theories of impetus and terrestrial motion were inadequate to explain these. While atomism did not explain the law of fall either, it was a more promising framework in which to develop an explanation because motion was conserved in ancient atomism (unlike Aristotelian physics).

René Descartes' (1596–1650) "mechanical" philosophy of corpuscularism had much in common with atomism, and is considered, in some senses, to be a different version of it. Descartes thought everything physical in the universe to be made of tiny vortices of matter. Like the ancient atomists, Descartes claimed that sensations, such as taste or temperature, are caused by the shape and size of tiny pieces of matter. The main difference between atomism and Descartes' concept was the existence of the void. For him, there could be no vacuum, and all matter was constantly swirling to prevent a void as corpuscles moved through other matter. Another key distinction between Descartes' view and classical atomism is the mind/body duality of Descartes, which allowed for an independent realm of existence for thought, soul, and most importantly, God. Gassendi's concept was closer to classical atomism, but with no atheistic overtone.

Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) was a Catholic priest from France who was also an avid natural philosopher. He was particularly intrigued by the Greek atomists, so he set out to "purify" atomism from its heretical and atheistic philosophical conclusions (Dijksterhius 1969). Gassendi formulated his atomistic conception of mechanical philosophy partly in response to Descartes; he particularly opposed Descartes' reductionist view that only purely mechanical explanations of physics are valid, as well as the application of geometry to the whole of physics (Clericuzio 2000).

Johann Chrysostom Magnenus (c. 1590c. 1679) published his Democritus reviviscens in 1646. Magnenus was the first to arrive at a scientific estimate of the size of an "atom" (i.e. of what would today be called a molecule). Measuring how much incense had to be burned before it could be smelled everywhere in a large church, he calculated the number of molecules in a grain of incense to be of the order 1018, only about one order of magnitude below the actual figure.[53]

Corpuscularianism

Corpuscularianism is similar to atomism, except that where atoms were supposed to be indivisible, corpuscles could in principle be divided. In this manner, for example, it was theorized that mercury could penetrate into metals and modify their inner structure, a step on the way towards transmutative production of gold. Corpuscularianism was associated by its leading proponents with the idea that some of the properties that objects appear to have are artifacts of the perceiving mind: 'secondary' qualities as distinguished from 'primary' qualities.[54] Not all corpuscularianism made use of the primary-secondary quality distinction, however. An influential tradition in medieval and early modern alchemy argued that chemical analysis revealed the existence of robust corpuscles that retained their identity in chemical compounds (to use the modern term). William R. Newman has dubbed this approach to matter theory "chymical atomism," and has argued for its significance to both the mechanical philosophy and to the chemical atomism that emerged in the early 19th century.[55] Corpuscularianism stayed a dominant theory over the next several hundred years and retained its links with alchemy in the work of scientists such as Robert Boyle and Isaac Newton in the 17th century.[56][57] It was used by Newton, for instance, in his development of the corpuscular theory of light. The form that came to be accepted by most English scientists after Robert Boyle (1627–1692) was an amalgam of the systems of Descartes and Gassendi. In The Sceptical Chymist (1661), Boyle demonstrates problems that arise from chemistry, and offers up atomism as a possible explanation. The unifying principle that would eventually lead to the acceptance of a hybrid corpuscular–atomism was mechanical philosophy, which became widely accepted by physical sciences.

Modern atomic theory

By the late 18th century, the useful practices of engineering and technology began to influence philosophical explanations for the composition of matter. Those who speculated on the ultimate nature of matter began to verify their "thought experiments" with some repeatable demonstrations, when they could.

Roger Boscovich provided the first general mathematical theory of atomism, based on the ideas of Newton and Leibniz but transforming them so as to provide a programme for atomic physics.[58]

In 1808, John Dalton assimilated the known experimental work of many people to summarize the empirical evidence on the composition of matter.[59] He noticed that distilled water everywhere analyzed to the same elements, hydrogen and oxygen. Similarly, other purified substances decomposed to the same elements in the same proportions by weight.

Therefore we may conclude that the ultimate particles of all homogeneous bodies are perfectly alike in weight, figure, etc. In other words, every particle of water is like every other particle of water; every particle of hydrogen is like every other particle of hydrogen, etc.

Furthermore, he concluded that there was a unique atom for each element, using Lavoisier's definition of an element as a substance that could not be analyzed into something simpler. Thus, Dalton concluded the following.

Chemical analysis and synthesis go no farther than to the separation of particles one from another, and to their reunion. No new creation or destruction of matter is within the reach of chemical agency. We might as well attempt to introduce a new planet into the solar system, or to annihilate one already in existence, as to create or destroy a particle of hydrogen. All the changes we can produce, consist in separating particles that are in a state of cohesion or combination, and joining those that were previously at a distance.

And then he proceeded to give a list of relative weights in the compositions of several common compounds, summarizing:[60]

1st. That water is a binary compound of hydrogen and oxygen, and the relative weights of the two elementary atoms are as 1:7, nearly;
2nd. That ammonia is a binary compound of hydrogen and azote nitrogen, and the relative weights of the two atoms are as 1:5, nearly...

Dalton concluded that the fixed proportions of elements by weight suggested that the atoms of one element combined with only a limited number of atoms of the other elements to form the substances that he listed.

Dalton's atomic theory remained controversial throughout the 19th century.[61] Whilst the Law of definite proportion was accepted, the hypothesis that this was due to atoms was not so widely accepted. For example, in 1826 when Sir Humphry Davy presented Dalton the Royal Medal from the Royal Society, Davy said that the theory only became useful when the atomic conjecture was ignored.[62]Sir Benjamin Collins Brodie in 1866 published the first part of his Calculus of Chemical Operations[63] as a non-atomic alternative to the Atomic Theory. He described atomic theory as a 'Thoroughly materialistic bit of joiners work'.[64] Alexander Williamson used his Presidential Address to the London Chemical Society in 1869[65] to defend the Atomic Theory against its critics and doubters. This in turn led to further meetings at which the positivists again attacked the supposition that there were atoms. The matter was finally resolved in Dalton's favour in the early 20th century with the rise of atomic physics.

Atoms and molecules had long been theorized as the constituents of matter, and Albert Einstein published a paper in 1905 that explained in precise detail how the motion that Brown had observed was a result of the pollen being moved by individual water molecules, making one of his first big contributions to science. This explanation of Brownian motion served as convincing evidence that atoms and molecules exist, and was further verified experimentally by Jean Perrin in 1908. Perrin was awarded the Nobel Prize in Physics in 1926 "for his work on the discontinuous structure of matter". The direction of the force of atomic bombardment is constantly changing, and at different times the particle is hit more on one side than another, leading to the seemingly random nature of the motion.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ ἄτομον. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project
  2. ^ "atom". Online Etymology Dictionary.
  3. ^ The term 'atomism' is recorded in English since 1670–80 (Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary, 2001, "atomism").
  4. ^ a b Berryman, Sylvia, "Ancient Atomism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), online
  5. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics I, 4, 985b 10–15.
  6. ^ The atomists, Leucippus and Democritus: fragments, a text and translation with a commentary by C.C.W. Taylor, University of Toronto Press Incorporated, 1999, ISBN 0-8020-4390-9, pp. 157-158.
  7. ^ Pullman, Bernard (1998). The Atom in the History of Human Thought. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 31–33. ISBN 978-0-19-515040-7.
  8. ^ Cohen, Henri; Lefebvre, Claire, eds. (2017). Handbook of Categorization in Cognitive Science (Second ed.). Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Elsevier. p. 427. ISBN 978-0-08-101107-2.
  9. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p Kenny, Anthony (2004). Ancient Philosophy. A New History of Western Philosophy. Vol. 1. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 26–28. ISBN 0-19-875273-3.
  10. ^ Frederic Harrison (1982). The new calendar of great men: biographies of the 558 worthies of all ages. Internet Archive. London and New York: Mac Millan & Co. p. 90. Archived from the original on June 11, 2021.
  11. ^ a b c Melsen (1952)
  12. ^ Poem of Parmenides : on nature
  13. ^ Parmenides' Poem[bare URL PDF]
  14. ^ Bertrand Russell (1946). History of Western Philosophy. London: Routledge. p. 75. ISBN 978-0415325059.
  15. ^ Berryman, Sylvia, Democritus, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  16. ^ "Plato, Timaeus, section 68b". www.perseus.tufts.edu. Retrieved 2022-07-27.
  17. ^ Lloyd, Geoffrey (1970). Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle. London; New York: Chatto and Windus; W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 74–77. ISBN 978-0-393-00583-7.
  18. ^ Cornford, Francis Macdonald (1957). Plato's Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato. New York: Liberal Arts Press. pp. 210–239. ISBN 978-0-87220-386-0.
  19. ^ Lloyd, Geoffrey (1968). Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 165. ISBN 978-0-521-09456-6.
  20. ^ Lloyd, Geoffrey (1970). Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle. London; New York: Chatto and Windus; W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 108–109. ISBN 978-0-393-00583-7.
  21. ^ Lloyd, G E R (30 September 2012). Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle. Random Hous (published 2012). ISBN 9781448156719. Retrieved 25 July 2022. [...] it hardly makes sense to talk of the Greeks failing to use the experimental method, since it was either impracticable or quite impossible to devise experiments that would resolve the issues in question.
  22. ^ Lloyd 1973, 25–6.
  23. ^ Taylor, C. C. W. (1999). The Atomists, Leucippus and Democritus: a text and translation with commentary by C. C. W. Taylor. Toronto; Buffalo: University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-0-8020-4390-0.
  24. ^ - Quotation #39.
  25. ^ Thomas, McEvilley (2002). The shape of ancient thought : comparative studies in Greek and Indian philosophies. New York: Allworth Press. ISBN 1581152035. OCLC 48013687.
  26. ^ Marxism : with and beyond Marx. Amiya Kumar Bagchi, Amita Chatterjee. London. 2014. ISBN 978-1-317-56176-7. OCLC 910847914.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  27. ^ Gangopadhyaya, Mrinalkanti (1981). Indian Atomism: History and Sources. Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press. ISBN 978-0-391-02177-8. OCLC 10916778.
  28. ^ Iannone, A. Pablo (2001). Dictionary of World Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 83, 356. ISBN 978-0-415-17995-9. OCLC 44541769.
  29. ^ (Radhakrishnan 1957, pp. 227–249)
  30. ^ John M. Koller (1977), Skepticism in Early Indian Thought, Philosophy East and West, 27(2): 155-164
  31. ^ Dale Riepe (1996), Naturalistic Tradition in Indian Thought, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120812932, pages 53-58
  32. ^ Ramkrishna Bhattacharya (2013), The base text and its commentaries: Problem of representing and understanding the Charvaka / Lokayata, Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal, Issue 1, Volume 3, pages 133-150
  33. ^ Thomas McEvilley, The Shape of Ancient Thought: Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies, Allwarth Press, 2002, pp. 317–321, ISBN 1-58115-203-5.
  34. ^ Richard King, Indian philosophy: an introduction to Hindu and Buddhist thought, Edinburgh University Press, 1999, ISBN 0-7486-0954-7, pp. 105-107.
  35. ^ Will Durant wrote in Our Oriental Heritage (2011): "Two systems of Indian thought propound physical theories suggestively similar to those of Greece. Kanada, founder of the Vaisheshika philosophy, held that the world was composed of atoms as many in kind as the various elements more nearly approximated to Democritus by teaching that all atoms were of the same kind, producing different effects by diverse modes of combinations. The Vaisheshika believed light and heat to be varieties of the same substance; Udayana taught that all heat comes from the sun; and Vachaspati, like Newton, interpreted light as composed of minute particles emitted by substances and striking the eye."[page needed]
  36. ^ Jeremy D. Popkin (ed.), The Legacies of Richard Popkin (2008), p. 53.
  37. ^ Teresi, Dick (2003). Lost Discoveries: The Ancient Roots of Modern Science. Simon & Schuster. pp. 213–214. ISBN 978-0-7432-4379-7.
  38. ^ Oliver Leaman, Key Concepts in Eastern Philosophy. Routledge, ISBN 978-0415173629, 1999, page 269.
  39. ^ Basham, A.L. (1951). History and Doctrines of the Ājīvikas (2nd ed.). Delhi, India: Moltilal Banarsidass (Reprint: 2002). pp. 262–270. ISBN 81-208-1204-2.
  40. ^ Jeaneane D. Fowler (2002). Perspectives of Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Hinduism. Sussex Academic Press. p. 99. ISBN 978-1-898723-93-6.
  41. ^ "The Vaisesika sutras of Kanada. Translated by Nandalal Sinha" Full Text at archive.org
  42. ^ Riepe, Dale Maurice (1961). Naturalistic Tradition in Indian Thought. Motilal Banarsidass (Reprint 1996). pp. 227–229. ISBN 978-81-208-1293-2.
  43. ^ Kak, S. 'Matter and Mind: The Vaisheshika Sutra of Kanada' (2016), Mount Meru Publishing, Mississauga, Ontario, ISBN 978-1-988207-13-1.
  44. ^ "The Buddhists denied the existence of substantial matter altogether. Movement consists for them of moments, it is a staccato movement, momentary flashes of a stream of energy... "Everything is evanescent," ... says the Buddhist, because there is no stuff ... Both systems [Sānkhya and later Indian Buddhism] share in common a tendency to push the analysis of Existence up to its minutest, last elements which are imagined as absolute qualities, or things possessing only one unique quality. They are called "qualities" (guna-dharma) in both systems in the sense of absolute qualities, a kind of atomic, or intra-atomic, energies of which the empirical things are composed. Both systems, therefore, agree in denying the objective reality of the categories of Substance and Quality, ... and of the relation of Inference uniting them. There is in Sānkhya philosophy no separate existence of qualities. What we call quality is but a particular manifestation of a subtle entity. To every new unit of quality corresponds a subtle quantum of matter which is called guna "quality", but represents a subtle substantive entity. The same applies to early Buddhism where all qualities are substantive ... or, more precisely, dynamic entities, although they are also called dharmas ("qualities")." Stcherbatsky (1962 [1930]). Vol. 1. p. 19.
  45. ^ Abhidhammattha-sangaha, Britannica Online (1998, 2005).
  46. ^ Shankman, Richard (2008), The Experience of Samadhi: An In-depth Exploration of Buddhist Meditation, Shambhala, p. 178
  47. ^ Saeed, Abdullah (2006). Islamic Thought: An Introduction. Routledge. p. 95. ISBN 978-0415364096.
  48. ^ Michael Marmura (1976). "God and his creation:Two medieval Islamic views". In R. M. Savory (ed.). Introduction to Islamic Civilization. Cambridge University Press. p. 49. Islamic atomism indian greek.
  49. ^ Shlomo Pines (1986). Studies in Arabic versions of Greek texts and in mediaeval science. Vol. 2. Brill Publishers. pp. 355–6. ISBN 978-965-223-626-5.
  50. ^ John Emery Murdoch; Christoph Herbert Lüthy; William Royall Newman (1 January 2001). "The Medieval and Renaissance Tradition of Minima Naturalia". Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories. BRILL. pp. 91–133. ISBN 978-90-04-11516-3.
  51. ^ Alan Chalmers (4 June 2009). The Scientist's Atom and the Philosopher's Stone: How Science Succeeded and Philosophy Failed to Gain Knowledge of Atoms. Springer. pp. 75–96. ISBN 978-90-481-2362-9.
  52. ^ Kargon 1966[page needed]
  53. ^ Three Klaus Ruedenberg, W. H. Eugen Schwarz, Millennia of Atoms and Molecules (2013), Chapter 1, pp. 1–45, DOI: 10.1021/bk-2013-1122.ch001.
  54. ^ The Mechanical Philosophy June 11, 2008, at the Wayback Machine - Early modern 'atomism' ("corpuscularianism" as it was known)
  55. ^ William R. Newman, “The Significance of ‘Chymical Atomism’,” in Edith Sylla and W. R. Newman, eds., Evidence and Interpretation: Studies on Early Science and Medicine in Honor of John E. Murdoch (Leiden: Brill, 2009), pp. 248-264 and Newman, Atoms and Alchemy: Chymistry and the Experimental Origins of the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006)
  56. ^ Levere, Trevor, H. (2001). Transforming Matter – A History of Chemistry for Alchemy to the Buckyball. The Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-6610-4.
  57. ^ Corpuscularianism - Philosophical Dictionary
  58. ^ Lancelot Law Whyte Essay on Atomism, 1961, p 54.
  59. ^ Dalton, John (1808). A new system of chemical philosophy. London. ISBN 978-1-153-05671-7. Retrieved 8 July 2008.
  60. ^ . Archived from the original on 2003-08-02. Retrieved 2003-07-28.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  61. ^ Brock, W.H., ed. (1967). The Atomic Debates. Leicester University Press. p. 1.
  62. ^ Davy, J. (ed.). Collected Works of Sir Humphry Davy. Bart. p. 93 vol 8.
  63. ^ Brodie, Sir Benjamin Collins (1866). Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society. pp. 781–859 vol I56.
  64. ^ Brock, W.H., ed. (1967). The Atomic Debates. Leicester University Press. p. 12.
  65. ^ Brock, W.H., ed. (1967). The Atomic Debates. Leicester University Press. p. 15.

References

  • Clericuzio, Antonio. Elements, Principles, and Corpuscles; a study of atomism and chemistry in the seventeenth century. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000.
  • Cornford, Francis MacDonald. Plato's Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato. New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1957.
  • Dijksterhuis, E. The Mechanization of the World Picture. Trans. by C. Dikshoorn. New York: Oxford University Press, 1969. ISBN 0-691-02396-4
  • Firth, Raymond. Religion: A Humanist Interpretation. Routledge, 1996. ISBN 0-415-12897-8.
  • Gangopadhyaya, Mrinalkanti. Indian Atomism: history and sources. Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1981. ISBN 0-391-02177-X
  • Gardet, L. "djuz'" in Encyclopaedia of Islam CD-ROM Edition, v. 1.1. Leiden: Brill, 2001.
  • Gregory, Joshua C. A Short History of Atomism. London: A. and C. Black, Ltd, 1981.
  • Kargon, Robert Hugh. Atomism in England from Hariot to Newton. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966.
  • Lloyd, G. E. R. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968. ISBN 0-521-09456-9
  • Lloyd, G. E. R. Greek Science After Aristotle. New York: W. W. Norton, 1973. ISBN 0-393-00780-4
  • Marmara, Michael E. "Causation in Islamic Thought." Dictionary of the History of Ideas. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1973–74. online at the .
  • McEvilley, Thomas (2002). The Shape of Ancient Thought: Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies. New York: Allworth Communications Inc. ISBN 1-58115-203-5.
  • Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli and Moore, Charles (1957). A Source Book in Indian Philosophy. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-01958-1.
  • Redondi, Pietro. Galileo Heretic. Translated by Raymond Rosenthal. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1987. ISBN 0-691-02426-X
  • Riepe, Dale (1964). The Naturalistic Tradition of Indian Thought (2nd ed.). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
  • Andrew G. van Melsen (2004) [First published 1952]. From Atomos to Atom: The History of the Concept Atom. Translated by Henry J. Koren. Dover Publications. ISBN 0-486-49584-1.

External links

  •   The dictionary definition of atomism at Wiktionary
  • Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Atomism: Antiquity to the Seventeenth Century
  • Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Atomism in the Seventeenth Century
  • Jonathan Schaffer, "Is There a Fundamental Level?" Nous 37 (2003): 498–517. Article by a philosopher who opposes atomism
  • Article on traditional Greek atomism
  • Atomism from the 17th to the 20th Century at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

atomism, this, article, about, natural, philosophy, regarding, fundamental, composition, physical, world, other, uses, disambiguation, from, greek, ἄτομον, atomon, uncuttable, indivisible, natural, philosophy, proposing, that, physical, universe, composed, fun. This article is about the natural philosophy regarding the fundamental composition of the physical world For other uses see Atomism disambiguation Atomism from Greek ἄtomon atomon i e uncuttable indivisible 1 2 3 is a natural philosophy proposing that the physical universe is composed of fundamental indivisible components known as atoms References to the concept of atomism and its atoms appeared in both ancient Greek and ancient Indian philosophical traditions Leucippus is the earliest figure whose commitment to atomism is well attested and he is usually credited with inventing atomism 4 He and other ancient Greek atomists theorized that nature consists of two fundamental principles atom and void Clusters of different shapes arrangements and positions give rise to the various macroscopic substances in the world 5 4 The particles of chemical matter for which chemists and other natural philosophers of the early 19th century found experimental evidence were thought to be indivisible and therefore were given by John Dalton the name atom long used by the atomist philosophy Although the connection to historical atomism is at best tenuous elementary particles have become a modern analogue of philosophical atoms Contents 1 Reductionism 2 History 2 1 Antiquity 2 1 1 Greek atomism 2 1 1 1 Democritus 2 1 1 2 Geometry and atoms 2 1 1 3 Rejection in Aristotelianism 2 1 1 4 Later ancient atomism 2 1 1 5 Atomism and ethics 2 1 2 Indian atomism 2 2 Middle Ages 2 2 1 Medieval Hinduism 2 2 2 Medieval Buddhism 2 2 3 Medieval Islam 2 2 4 Medieval Christendom 2 3 Atomist renaissance 2 3 1 Corpuscularianism 2 4 Modern atomic theory 3 See also 4 Notes 5 References 6 External linksReductionism EditPhilosophical atomism is a reductive argument proposing not only that everything is composed of atoms and void but that nothing they compose really exists the only things that really exist are atoms ricocheting off each other mechanistically in an otherwise empty void Atomism stands in contrast to a substance theory wherein a prime material continuum remains qualitatively invariant under division for example the ratio of the four classical elements would be the same in any portion of a homogeneous material Indian Buddhists such as Dharmakirti fl c 6th or 7th century and others developed distinctive theories of atomism for example involving momentary instantaneous atoms kalapas that flash in and out of existence History EditAntiquity Edit Greek atomism Edit Democritus Edit In the 5th century BC Leucippus and his pupil Democritus proposed that all matter was composed of small indivisible particles which they called atoms 6 7 8 9 Nothing whatsoever is known about Leucippus except that he was the teacher of Democritus 9 Democritus by contrast wrote prolifically producing over eighty known treatises none of which have survived to the present day complete 9 However a massive number of fragments and quotations of his writings have survived 9 These are the main source of information on his teachings about atoms 9 Democritus s argument for the existence of atoms hinged on the idea that it is impossible to keep dividing matter infinitely and that matter must therefore be made up of extremely tiny particles 9 The atomistic theory aimed to remove the distinction which the Eleatic school drew between the Absolute or the only real existence and the world of change around us 10 Democritus believed that atoms are too small for human senses to detect that they are infinitely many that they come in infinitely many varieties and that they have always existed 9 They float in a vacuum which Democritus called the void 9 and they vary in form order and posture 9 Some atoms he maintained are convex others concave some shaped like hooks and others like eyes 9 They are constantly moving and colliding into each other 9 Democritus wrote that atoms and void are the only things that exist and that all other things are merely said to exist by social convention 9 The objects humans see in everyday life are composed of many atoms united by random collisions and their forms and materials are determined by what kinds of atom make them up 9 Likewise human perceptions are caused by atoms as well 9 Bitterness is caused by small angular jagged atoms passing across the tongue 9 whereas sweetness is caused by larger smoother more rounded atoms passing across the tongue 9 Previously Parmenides had denied the existence of motion change and void He believed all existence to be a single all encompassing and unchanging mass a concept known as monism and that change and motion were mere illusions He explicitly rejected sensory experience as the path to an understanding of the universe and instead used purely abstract reasoning He believed there is no such thing as void equating it with non being This in turn meant that motion is impossible because there is no void to move into 11 Parmenides doesn t mention or explicitly deny the existence of the void stating instead that what is not does not exist 12 13 14 He also wrote all that is must be an indivisible unity for if it were manifold then there would have to be a void that could divide it Finally he stated that the all encompassing Unity is unchanging for the Unity already encompasses all that is and can be 11 Democritus accepted most of Parmenides arguments except for the idea that change is an illusion He believed change was real and if it was not then at least the illusion had to be explained He thus supported the concept of void and stated that the universe is made up of many Parmenidean entities that move around in the void 11 The void is infinite and provides the space in which the atoms can pack or scatter differently The different possible packings and scatterings within the void make up the shifting outlines and bulk of the objects that organisms feel see eat hear smell and taste While organisms may feel hot or cold hot and cold actually have no real existence They are simply sensations produced in organisms by the different packings and scatterings of the atoms in the void that compose the object that organisms sense as being hot or cold The work of Democritus survives only in secondhand reports some of which are unreliable or conflicting Much of the best evidence of Democritus theory of atomism is reported by Aristotle 384 322 BCE in his discussions of Democritus and Plato s contrasting views on the types of indivisibles composing the natural world 15 Geometry and atoms Edit This section possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed June 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Element Polyhedron Number of Faces Number of TrianglesFire Tetrahedron Animation 4 24Air Octahedron Animation 8 48Water Icosahedron Animation 20 120Earth Cube Animation 6 24Geometrical simple bodies according to PlatoPlato c 427 c 347 BCE if he had been familiar with the atomism of Democritus would have objected to its mechanistic materialism He argued that atoms just crashing into other atoms could never produce the beauty and form of the world In Plato s Timaeus 28b 29a the character of Timeaus insisted that the cosmos was not eternal but was created although its creator framed it after an eternal unchanging model 16 One part of that creation were the four simple bodies of fire air water and earth But Plato did not consider these corpuscles to be the most basic level of reality for in his view they were made up of an unchanging level of reality which was mathematical These simple bodies were geometric solids the faces of which were in turn made up of triangles The square faces of the cube were each made up of four isosceles right angled triangles and the triangular faces of the tetrahedron octahedron and icosahedron were each made up of six right angled triangles Plato postulated the geometric structure of the simple bodies of the four elements as summarized in the adjacent table The cube with its flat base and stability was assigned to earth the tetrahedron was assigned to fire because its penetrating points and sharp edges made it mobile The points and edges of the octahedron and icosahedron were blunter and so these less mobile bodies were assigned to air and water Since the simple bodies could be decomposed into triangles and the triangles reassembled into atoms of different elements Plato s model offered a plausible account of changes among the primary substances 17 18 Rejection in Aristotelianism Edit Sometime before 330 BC Aristotle asserted that the elements of fire air earth and water were not made of atoms but were continuous Aristotle considered the existence of a void which was required by atomic theories to violate physical principles Change took place not by the rearrangement of atoms to make new structures but by transformation of matter from what it was in potential to a new actuality A piece of wet clay when acted upon by a potter takes on its potential to be an actual drinking mug Aristotle has often been criticized for rejecting atomism but in ancient Greece the atomic theories of Democritus remained pure speculations incapable of being put to any experimental test 19 need quotation to verify 20 21 unbalanced opinion Aristotle theorized minima naturalia as the smallest parts into which a homogeneous natural substance e g flesh bone or wood could be divided and still retain its essential character Unlike the atomism of Democritus these Aristotelian natural minima were not conceptualized as physically indivisible Instead Aristotle s concept was rooted in his hylomorphic worldview which held that every physical thing is a compound of matter Greek hyle and of an immaterial substantial form Greek morphe that imparts its essential nature and structure For instance a rubber ball for a hylomorphist like Aristotle would be rubber matter structured by spherical shape form Aristotle s intuition was that there is some smallest size beyond which matter could no longer be structured as flesh or bone or wood or some other such organic substance that for Aristotle living before the invention of the microscope could be considered homogeneous For instance if flesh were divided beyond its natural minimum what would be left might be a large amount of the element water and smaller amounts of the other elements But whatever water or other elements were left they would no longer have the nature of flesh in hylomorphic terms they would no longer be matter structured by the form of flesh instead the remaining water e g would be matter structured by the form of water not by the form of flesh Later ancient atomism Edit Epicurus 341 270 BCE studied atomism with Nausiphanes who had been a student of Democritus Although Epicurus was certain of the existence of atoms and the void he was less sure we could adequately explain specific natural phenomena such as earthquakes lightning comets or the phases of the Moon 22 Few of Epicurus writings survive and those that do reflect his interest in applying Democritus theories to assist people in taking responsibility for themselves and for their own happiness since he held there are no gods around that can help them Epicurus regarded the role of gods as exemplifying moral ideals Epicurus ideas re appear in the works of his Roman follower Lucretius c 99 BC c 55 BC who wrote On the Nature of Things This Classical Latin scientific work in poetic form illustrates several segments of Epicurean theory on how the universe came into its current stage it shows that the phenomena we perceive are actually composite forms The atoms and the void are eternal and in constant motion Atomic collisions create objects which are still composed of the same eternal atoms whose motion for a while is incorporated into the created entity Lucretius also explains human sensations and meteorological phenomena in terms of atomic motion Atomism and ethics Edit Some later philosophers attributed the idea that man created gods and that gods did not create man to Democritus For example Sextus Empiricus noted Some people think that we arrived at the idea of gods from the remarkable things that happen in the world Democritus says that the people of ancient times were frightened by happenings in the heavens such as thunder lightning and thought that they were caused by gods 23 Three hundred years after Epicurus Lucretius in his epic poem On the Nature of Things would depict him as the hero who crushed the monster Religion through educating the people in what was possible in atoms and what was not possible in atoms However Epicurus expressed a non aggressive attitude characterized by his statement The man who best knows how to meet external threats makes into one family all the creatures he can and those he can not he at any rate does not treat as aliens and where he finds even this impossible he avoids all dealings and so far as is advantageous excludes them from his life 24 Indian atomism Edit In ancient Indian philosophy preliminary instances of atomism are found in the works of Vedic sage Aruni who lived in the 8th century BCE especially his proposition that particles too small to be seen mass together into the substances and objects of experience known as kaṇa 25 Although kana refers to particles not atoms paramanu Some scholars such as Hermann Jacobi and Randall Collins have compared Aruni to Thales of Miletus in their scientific methodology calling them both as primitive physicists or proto materialist thinkers 26 Later the Charvaka 27 28 and Ajivika schools of atomism originated as early as the 7th century BCE 29 30 31 Bhattacharya posits that Charvaka may have been one of several atheistic materialist schools that existed in ancient India 32 33 Kanada founded the Vaisheshika school of Indian philosophy that also represents the earliest Indian natural philosophy The Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools developed theories on how kaṇas combined into more complex objects 34 Several of these doctrines of atomism are in some respects suggestively similar to that of Democritus 35 McEvilley 2002 assumes that such similarities are due to extensive cultural contact and diffusion probably in both directions 36 The Nyaya Vaisesika school developed one of the earliest forms of atomism scholars who date the Nyaya and Vaisesika texts from the 9th to 4th centuries BCE Vaisesika atomists posited the four elemental atom types but in Vaisesika physics atoms had 25 different possible qualities divided between general extensive properties and specific intensive properties The Nyaya Vaisesika atomists had elaborate theories of how atoms combine In Vaisesika atomism atoms first combine in pairs dyads and then group into trios of pairs triads which are the smallest visible units of matter 37 The Buddhist atomists had very qualitative Aristotelian style atomic theory According to ancient Buddhist atomism which probably began developing before the 4th century BCE there are four kinds of atoms corresponding to the standard elements Each of these elements has a specific property such as solidity or motion and performs a specific function in mixtures such as providing support or causing growth Like the Hindus the Buddhists were able to integrate a theory of atomism with their theological presuppositions Later Indian Buddhist philosophers such as Dharmakirti and Dignaga considered atoms to be point sized durationless and made of energy Some of the canonical texts make reference to matter and atoms called paramaṇu a term already used in Yajnavalkya Lalitha Sahasranama and Yoga Sutra including Pancastikayasara Kalpasutra and Tattvarthasutra citation needed The Jains envisioned the world as consisting wholly of atoms except for souls Atoms were considered as the basic building blocks of all matter Each atom had one kind of taste one smell one color and two kinds of touch though it is unclear what was meant by kind of touch citation needed clarification needed Atoms can exist in one of two states subtle in which case they can fit in infinitesimally small spaces and gross in which case they have extension and occupy a finite space citation needed The texts also give detailed theories of how atoms could combine react vibrate move and perform other actions all of which were thoroughly deterministic citation needed Middle Ages Edit Medieval Hinduism Edit Ajivika is a Nastika school of thought whose metaphysics included a theory of atoms or atomism which was later adapted in the Vaiseṣika school which postulated that all objects in the physical universe are reducible to paramaṇu atoms and one s experiences are derived from the interplay of substance a function of atoms their number and their spatial arrangements quality activity commonness particularity and inherence 38 Everything was composed of atoms qualities emerged from aggregates of atoms but the aggregation and nature of these atoms was predetermined by cosmic forces 39 The school founder s traditional name Kanada means atom eater 40 and he is known for developing the foundations of an atomistic approach to physics and philosophy in the Sanskrit text Vaiseṣika Sutra 41 His text is also known as Kanada Sutras or Aphorisms of Kanada 42 43 Medieval Buddhism Edit Medieval Buddhist atomism flourishing in ca the 7th century was very different from the atomist doctrines taught in early Buddhism Medieval Buddhist philosophers Dharmakirti and Dignaga considered atoms to be point sized durationless and made of energy In discussing the two systems Fyodor Shcherbatskoy 1930 stresses their commonality the postulate of absolute qualities guna dharma underlying all empirical phenomena 44 Still later the Abhidhammattha sangaha a text dated to the 11th or 12th century postulates the existence of rupa kalapa imagined as the smallest units of the physical world of varying elementary composition 45 Invisible under normal circumstances the rupa kalapa are said to become visible as a result of meditative samadhi 46 Medieval Islam Edit See also Early Islamic philosophy Atomism and Alchemy and chemistry in medieval Islam Atomistic philosophies are found very early in Islamic philosophy and was influenced by earlier Greek and to some extent Indian philosophy 47 48 Like both the Greek and Indian versions Islamic atomism was a charged topic that had the potential for conflict with the prevalent religious orthodoxy citation needed but it was instead more often favoured by orthodox Islamic theologians It was such a fertile and flexible idea that as in Greece and India it flourished in some leading schools of Islamic thought The most successful form of Islamic atomism was in the Asharite school of Islamic theology most notably in the work of the theologian al Ghazali 1058 1111 In Asharite atomism atoms are the only perpetual material things in existence and all else in the world is accidental meaning something that lasts for only an instant Nothing accidental can be the cause of anything else except perception as it exists for a moment Contingent events are not subject to natural physical causes but are the direct result of God s constant intervention without which nothing could happen Thus nature is completely dependent on God which meshes with other Asharite Islamic ideas on causation or the lack thereof Gardet 2001 Al Ghazali also used the theory to support his theory of occasionalism In a sense the Asharite theory of atomism has far more in common with Indian atomism than it does with Greek atomism 49 Other traditions in Islam rejected the atomism of the Asharites and expounded on many Greek texts especially those of Aristotle An active school of philosophers in Al Andalus including the noted commentator Averroes 1126 1198 CE explicitly rejected the thought of al Ghazali and turned to an extensive evaluation of the thought of Aristotle Averroes commented in detail on most of the works of Aristotle and his commentaries became very influential in Jewish and Christian scholastic thought Medieval Christendom Edit While Aristotelian philosophy eclipsed the importance of the atomists in late Roman and medieval Europe their work was still preserved and exposited through commentaries on the works of Aristotle In the 2nd century Galen AD 129 216 presented extensive discussions of the Greek atomists especially Epicurus in his Aristotle commentaries According to historian of atomism Joshua Gregory there was no serious work done with atomism from the time of Galen until Isaac Beeckman Gassendi and Descartes resurrected it in the 17th century the gap between these two modern naturalists and the ancient Atomists marked the exile of the atom and it is universally admitted that the Middle Ages had abandoned Atomism and virtually lost it However although the ancient atomists works were unavailable Scholastic thinkers still had Aristotle s critiques of atomism In medieval universities there were expressions of atomism For example in the 14th century Nicholas of Autrecourt considered that matter space and time were all made up of indivisible atoms points and instants and that all generation and corruption took place by the rearrangement of material atoms The similarities of his ideas with those of al Ghazali suggest that Nicholas may have been familiar with Ghazali s work perhaps through Averroes refutation of it Marmara 1973 74 Although the atomism of Epicurus had fallen out of favor in the centuries of Scholasticism the minima naturalia of Aristotelianism received extensive consideration Speculation on minima naturalia provided philosophical background for the mechanistic philosophy of early modern thinkers such as Descartes and for the alchemical works of Geber and Daniel Sennert who in turn influenced the corpuscularian alchemist Robert Boyle one of the founders of modern chemistry 50 51 A chief theme in late Roman and Scholastic commentary on this concept is reconciling minima naturalia with the general Aristotelian principle of infinite divisibility Commentators like John Philoponus and Thomas Aquinas reconciled these aspects of Aristotle s thought by distinguishing between mathematical and natural divisibility With few exceptions much of the curriculum in the universities of Europe was based on such Aristotelianism for most of the Middle Ages 52 Atomist renaissance Edit In the 17th century a renewed interest arose in Epicurean atomism and corpuscularianism as a hybrid or an alternative to Aristotelian physics The main figures in the rebirth of atomism were Isaac Beeckman Rene Descartes Pierre Gassendi and Robert Boyle as well as other notable figures One of the first groups of atomists in England was a cadre of amateur scientists known as the Northumberland circle led by Henry Percy 9th Earl of Northumberland 1564 1632 Although they published little of account they helped to disseminate atomistic ideas among the burgeoning scientific culture of England and may have been particularly influential to Francis Bacon who became an atomist around 1605 though he later rejected some of the claims of atomism Though they revived the classical form of atomism this group was among the scientific avant garde the Northumberland circle contained nearly half of the confirmed Copernicans prior to 1610 the year of Galileo s The Starry Messenger Other influential atomists of late 16th and early 17th centuries include Giordano Bruno Thomas Hobbes who also changed his stance on atomism late in his career and Thomas Hariot A number of different atomistic theories were blossoming in France at this time as well Clericuzio 2000 Galileo Galilei 1564 1642 was an advocate of atomism in his 1612 Discourse on Floating Bodies Redondi 1969 In The Assayer Galileo offered a more complete physical system based on a corpuscular theory of matter in which all phenomena with the exception of sound are produced by matter in motion Galileo identified some basic problems with Aristotelian physics through his experiments He utilized a theory of atomism as a partial replacement but he was never unequivocally committed to it For example his experiments with falling bodies and inclined planes led him to the concepts of circular inertial motion and accelerating free fall The current Aristotelian theories of impetus and terrestrial motion were inadequate to explain these While atomism did not explain the law of fall either it was a more promising framework in which to develop an explanation because motion was conserved in ancient atomism unlike Aristotelian physics Rene Descartes 1596 1650 mechanical philosophy of corpuscularism had much in common with atomism and is considered in some senses to be a different version of it Descartes thought everything physical in the universe to be made of tiny vortices of matter Like the ancient atomists Descartes claimed that sensations such as taste or temperature are caused by the shape and size of tiny pieces of matter The main difference between atomism and Descartes concept was the existence of the void For him there could be no vacuum and all matter was constantly swirling to prevent a void as corpuscles moved through other matter Another key distinction between Descartes view and classical atomism is the mind body duality of Descartes which allowed for an independent realm of existence for thought soul and most importantly God Gassendi s concept was closer to classical atomism but with no atheistic overtone Pierre Gassendi 1592 1655 was a Catholic priest from France who was also an avid natural philosopher He was particularly intrigued by the Greek atomists so he set out to purify atomism from its heretical and atheistic philosophical conclusions Dijksterhius 1969 Gassendi formulated his atomistic conception of mechanical philosophy partly in response to Descartes he particularly opposed Descartes reductionist view that only purely mechanical explanations of physics are valid as well as the application of geometry to the whole of physics Clericuzio 2000 Johann Chrysostom Magnenus c 1590 c 1679 published his Democritus reviviscens in 1646 Magnenus was the first to arrive at a scientific estimate of the size of an atom i e of what would today be called a molecule Measuring how much incense had to be burned before it could be smelled everywhere in a large church he calculated the number of molecules in a grain of incense to be of the order 1018 only about one order of magnitude below the actual figure 53 Corpuscularianism Edit Main article Corpuscularianism Corpuscularianism is similar to atomism except that where atoms were supposed to be indivisible corpuscles could in principle be divided In this manner for example it was theorized that mercury could penetrate into metals and modify their inner structure a step on the way towards transmutative production of gold Corpuscularianism was associated by its leading proponents with the idea that some of the properties that objects appear to have are artifacts of the perceiving mind secondary qualities as distinguished from primary qualities 54 Not all corpuscularianism made use of the primary secondary quality distinction however An influential tradition in medieval and early modern alchemy argued that chemical analysis revealed the existence of robust corpuscles that retained their identity in chemical compounds to use the modern term William R Newman has dubbed this approach to matter theory chymical atomism and has argued for its significance to both the mechanical philosophy and to the chemical atomism that emerged in the early 19th century 55 Corpuscularianism stayed a dominant theory over the next several hundred years and retained its links with alchemy in the work of scientists such as Robert Boyle and Isaac Newton in the 17th century 56 57 It was used by Newton for instance in his development of the corpuscular theory of light The form that came to be accepted by most English scientists after Robert Boyle 1627 1692 was an amalgam of the systems of Descartes and Gassendi In The Sceptical Chymist 1661 Boyle demonstrates problems that arise from chemistry and offers up atomism as a possible explanation The unifying principle that would eventually lead to the acceptance of a hybrid corpuscular atomism was mechanical philosophy which became widely accepted by physical sciences Modern atomic theory Edit Main article Atomic theory By the late 18th century the useful practices of engineering and technology began to influence philosophical explanations for the composition of matter Those who speculated on the ultimate nature of matter began to verify their thought experiments with some repeatable demonstrations when they could Roger Boscovich provided the first general mathematical theory of atomism based on the ideas of Newton and Leibniz but transforming them so as to provide a programme for atomic physics 58 In 1808 John Dalton assimilated the known experimental work of many people to summarize the empirical evidence on the composition of matter 59 He noticed that distilled water everywhere analyzed to the same elements hydrogen and oxygen Similarly other purified substances decomposed to the same elements in the same proportions by weight Therefore we may conclude that the ultimate particles of all homogeneous bodies are perfectly alike in weight figure etc In other words every particle of water is like every other particle of water every particle of hydrogen is like every other particle of hydrogen etc Furthermore he concluded that there was a unique atom for each element using Lavoisier s definition of an element as a substance that could not be analyzed into something simpler Thus Dalton concluded the following Chemical analysis and synthesis go no farther than to the separation of particles one from another and to their reunion No new creation or destruction of matter is within the reach of chemical agency We might as well attempt to introduce a new planet into the solar system or to annihilate one already in existence as to create or destroy a particle of hydrogen All the changes we can produce consist in separating particles that are in a state of cohesion or combination and joining those that were previously at a distance And then he proceeded to give a list of relative weights in the compositions of several common compounds summarizing 60 1st That water is a binary compound of hydrogen and oxygen and the relative weights of the two elementary atoms are as 1 7 nearly 2nd That ammonia is a binary compound of hydrogen and azote nitrogen and the relative weights of the two atoms are as 1 5 nearly Dalton concluded that the fixed proportions of elements by weight suggested that the atoms of one element combined with only a limited number of atoms of the other elements to form the substances that he listed Dalton s atomic theory remained controversial throughout the 19th century 61 Whilst the Law of definite proportion was accepted the hypothesis that this was due to atoms was not so widely accepted For example in 1826 when Sir Humphry Davy presented Dalton the Royal Medal from the Royal Society Davy said that the theory only became useful when the atomic conjecture was ignored 62 Sir Benjamin Collins Brodie in 1866 published the first part of his Calculus of Chemical Operations 63 as a non atomic alternative to the Atomic Theory He described atomic theory as a Thoroughly materialistic bit of joiners work 64 Alexander Williamson used his Presidential Address to the London Chemical Society in 1869 65 to defend the Atomic Theory against its critics and doubters This in turn led to further meetings at which the positivists again attacked the supposition that there were atoms The matter was finally resolved in Dalton s favour in the early 20th century with the rise of atomic physics Atoms and molecules had long been theorized as the constituents of matter and Albert Einstein published a paper in 1905 that explained in precise detail how the motion that Brown had observed was a result of the pollen being moved by individual water molecules making one of his first big contributions to science This explanation of Brownian motion served as convincing evidence that atoms and molecules exist and was further verified experimentally by Jean Perrin in 1908 Perrin was awarded the Nobel Prize in Physics in 1926 for his work on the discontinuous structure of matter The direction of the force of atomic bombardment is constantly changing and at different times the particle is hit more on one side than another leading to the seemingly random nature of the motion See also EditEliminative materialism Mereological nihilism Becoming philosophy First principle History of chemistry Infinite divisibility Ontological pluralism Physical ontology Prima materia Montonen Olive duality Philosophical implicationsNotes Edit ἄtomon Liddell Henry George Scott Robert A Greek English Lexicon at the Perseus Project atom Online Etymology Dictionary The term atomism is recorded in English since 1670 80 Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary 2001 atomism a b Berryman Sylvia Ancient Atomism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2008 Edition Edward N Zalta ed online Aristotle Metaphysics I 4 985b 10 15 The atomists Leucippus and Democritus fragments a text and translation with a commentary by C C W Taylor University of Toronto Press Incorporated 1999 ISBN 0 8020 4390 9 pp 157 158 Pullman Bernard 1998 The Atom in the History of Human Thought Oxford England Oxford University Press pp 31 33 ISBN 978 0 19 515040 7 Cohen Henri Lefebvre Claire eds 2017 Handbook of Categorization in Cognitive Science Second ed Amsterdam The Netherlands Elsevier p 427 ISBN 978 0 08 101107 2 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p Kenny Anthony 2004 Ancient Philosophy A New History of Western Philosophy Vol 1 Oxford England Oxford University Press pp 26 28 ISBN 0 19 875273 3 Frederic Harrison 1982 The new calendar of great men biographies of the 558 worthies of all ages Internet Archive London and New York Mac Millan amp Co p 90 Archived from the original on June 11 2021 a b c Melsen 1952 Poem of Parmenides on nature Parmenides Poem bare URL PDF Bertrand Russell 1946 History of Western Philosophy London Routledge p 75 ISBN 978 0415325059 Berryman Sylvia Democritus The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2008 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Plato Timaeus section 68b www perseus tufts edu Retrieved 2022 07 27 Lloyd Geoffrey 1970 Early Greek Science Thales to Aristotle London New York Chatto and Windus W W Norton amp Company pp 74 77 ISBN 978 0 393 00583 7 Cornford Francis Macdonald 1957 Plato s Cosmology TheTimaeusof Plato New York Liberal Arts Press pp 210 239 ISBN 978 0 87220 386 0 Lloyd Geoffrey 1968 Aristotle The Growth and Structure of his Thought Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 165 ISBN 978 0 521 09456 6 Lloyd Geoffrey 1970 Early Greek Science Thales to Aristotle London New York Chatto and Windus W W Norton amp Company pp 108 109 ISBN 978 0 393 00583 7 Lloyd G E R 30 September 2012 Early Greek Science Thales to Aristotle Random Hous published 2012 ISBN 9781448156719 Retrieved 25 July 2022 it hardly makes sense to talk of the Greeks failing to use the experimental method since it was either impracticable or quite impossible to devise experiments that would resolve the issues in question Lloyd 1973 25 6 Taylor C C W 1999 The Atomists Leucippus and Democritus a text and translation with commentary by C C W Taylor Toronto Buffalo University of Toronto Press ISBN 978 0 8020 4390 0 Principal Doctrines Epicurus Quotation 39 Thomas McEvilley 2002 The shape of ancient thought comparative studies in Greek and Indian philosophies New York Allworth Press ISBN 1581152035 OCLC 48013687 Marxism with and beyond Marx Amiya Kumar Bagchi Amita Chatterjee London 2014 ISBN 978 1 317 56176 7 OCLC 910847914 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint others link Gangopadhyaya Mrinalkanti 1981 Indian Atomism History and Sources Atlantic Highlands New Jersey Humanities Press ISBN 978 0 391 02177 8 OCLC 10916778 Iannone A Pablo 2001 Dictionary of World Philosophy Routledge pp 83 356 ISBN 978 0 415 17995 9 OCLC 44541769 Radhakrishnan 1957 pp 227 249 John M Koller 1977 Skepticism in Early Indian Thought Philosophy East and West 27 2 155 164 Dale Riepe 1996 Naturalistic Tradition in Indian Thought Motilal Banarsidass ISBN 978 8120812932 pages 53 58 Ramkrishna Bhattacharya 2013 The base text and its commentaries Problem of representing and understanding the Charvaka Lokayata Argument Biannual Philosophical Journal Issue 1 Volume 3 pages 133 150 Thomas McEvilley The Shape of Ancient Thought Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies Allwarth Press 2002 pp 317 321 ISBN 1 58115 203 5 Richard King Indian philosophy an introduction to Hindu and Buddhist thought Edinburgh University Press 1999 ISBN 0 7486 0954 7 pp 105 107 Will Durant wrote in Our Oriental Heritage 2011 Two systems of Indian thought propound physical theories suggestively similar to those of Greece Kanada founder of the Vaisheshika philosophy held that the world was composed of atoms as many in kind as the various elements more nearly approximated to Democritus by teaching that all atoms were of the same kind producing different effects by diverse modes of combinations The Vaisheshika believed light and heat to be varieties of the same substance Udayana taught that all heat comes from the sun and Vachaspati like Newton interpreted light as composed of minute particles emitted by substances and striking the eye page needed Jeremy D Popkin ed The Legacies of Richard Popkin 2008 p 53 Teresi Dick 2003 Lost Discoveries The Ancient Roots of Modern Science Simon amp Schuster pp 213 214 ISBN 978 0 7432 4379 7 Oliver Leaman Key Concepts in Eastern Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0415173629 1999 page 269 Basham A L 1951 History and Doctrines of the Ajivikas 2nd ed Delhi India Moltilal Banarsidass Reprint 2002 pp 262 270 ISBN 81 208 1204 2 Jeaneane D Fowler 2002 Perspectives of Reality An Introduction to the Philosophy of Hinduism Sussex Academic Press p 99 ISBN 978 1 898723 93 6 The Vaisesika sutras of Kanada Translated by Nandalal Sinha Full Text at archive org Riepe Dale Maurice 1961 Naturalistic Tradition in Indian Thought Motilal Banarsidass Reprint 1996 pp 227 229 ISBN 978 81 208 1293 2 Kak S Matter and Mind The Vaisheshika Sutra of Kanada 2016 Mount Meru Publishing Mississauga Ontario ISBN 978 1 988207 13 1 The Buddhists denied the existence of substantial matter altogether Movement consists for them of moments it is a staccato movement momentary flashes of a stream of energy Everything is evanescent says the Buddhist because there is no stuff Both systems Sankhya and later Indian Buddhism share in common a tendency to push the analysis of Existence up to its minutest last elements which are imagined as absolute qualities or things possessing only one unique quality They are called qualities guna dharma in both systems in the sense of absolute qualities a kind of atomic or intra atomic energies of which the empirical things are composed Both systems therefore agree in denying the objective reality of the categories of Substance and Quality and of the relation of Inference uniting them There is in Sankhya philosophy no separate existence of qualities What we call quality is but a particular manifestation of a subtle entity To every new unit of quality corresponds a subtle quantum of matter which is called guna quality but represents a subtle substantive entity The same applies to early Buddhism where all qualities are substantive or more precisely dynamic entities although they are also called dharmas qualities Stcherbatsky 1962 1930 Vol 1 p 19 Abhidhammattha sangaha Britannica Online 1998 2005 Shankman Richard 2008 The Experience of Samadhi An In depth Exploration of Buddhist Meditation Shambhala p 178 Saeed Abdullah 2006 Islamic Thought An Introduction Routledge p 95 ISBN 978 0415364096 Michael Marmura 1976 God and his creation Two medieval Islamic views In R M Savory ed Introduction to Islamic Civilization Cambridge University Press p 49 Islamic atomism indian greek Shlomo Pines 1986 Studies in Arabic versions of Greek texts and in mediaeval science Vol 2 Brill Publishers pp 355 6 ISBN 978 965 223 626 5 John Emery Murdoch Christoph Herbert Luthy William Royall Newman 1 January 2001 The Medieval and Renaissance Tradition of Minima Naturalia Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories BRILL pp 91 133 ISBN 978 90 04 11516 3 Alan Chalmers 4 June 2009 The Scientist s Atom and the Philosopher s Stone How Science Succeeded and Philosophy Failed to Gain Knowledge of Atoms Springer pp 75 96 ISBN 978 90 481 2362 9 Kargon 1966 page needed Three Klaus Ruedenberg W H Eugen Schwarz Millennia of Atoms and Molecules 2013 Chapter 1 pp 1 45 DOI 10 1021 bk 2013 1122 ch001 The Mechanical Philosophy Archived June 11 2008 at the Wayback Machine Early modern atomism corpuscularianism as it was known William R Newman The Significance of Chymical Atomism in Edith Sylla and W R Newman eds Evidence and Interpretation Studies on Early Science and Medicine in Honor of John E Murdoch Leiden Brill 2009 pp 248 264 and Newman Atoms and Alchemy Chymistry and the Experimental Origins of the Scientific Revolution Chicago University of Chicago Press 2006 Levere Trevor H 2001 Transforming Matter A History of Chemistry for Alchemy to the Buckyball The Johns Hopkins University Press ISBN 978 0 8018 6610 4 Corpuscularianism Philosophical Dictionary Lancelot Law Whyte Essay on Atomism 1961 p 54 Dalton John 1808 A new system of chemical philosophy London ISBN 978 1 153 05671 7 Retrieved 8 July 2008 Archived copy Archived from the original on 2003 08 02 Retrieved 2003 07 28 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link Brock W H ed 1967 The Atomic Debates Leicester University Press p 1 Davy J ed Collected Works of Sir Humphry Davy Bart p 93 vol 8 Brodie Sir Benjamin Collins 1866 Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society pp 781 859 vol I56 Brock W H ed 1967 The Atomic Debates Leicester University Press p 12 Brock W H ed 1967 The Atomic Debates Leicester University Press p 15 References EditClericuzio Antonio Elements Principles and Corpuscles a study of atomism and chemistry in the seventeenth century Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers 2000 Cornford Francis MacDonald Plato s Cosmology TheTimaeusof Plato New York Liberal Arts Press 1957 Dijksterhuis E The Mechanization of the World Picture Trans by C Dikshoorn New York Oxford University Press 1969 ISBN 0 691 02396 4 Firth Raymond Religion A Humanist Interpretation Routledge 1996 ISBN 0 415 12897 8 Gangopadhyaya Mrinalkanti Indian Atomism history and sources Atlantic Highlands New Jersey Humanities Press 1981 ISBN 0 391 02177 X Gardet L djuz in Encyclopaedia of Islam CD ROM Edition v 1 1 Leiden Brill 2001 Gregory Joshua C A Short History of Atomism London A and C Black Ltd 1981 Kargon Robert Hugh Atomism in England from Hariot to Newton Oxford Clarendon Press 1966 Lloyd G E R Aristotle The Growth and Structure of his Thought Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1968 ISBN 0 521 09456 9 Lloyd G E R Greek Science After Aristotle New York W W Norton 1973 ISBN 0 393 00780 4 Marmara Michael E Causation in Islamic Thought Dictionary of the History of Ideas New York Charles Scribner s Sons 1973 74 online at the of Virginia Electronic Text Center McEvilley Thomas 2002 The Shape of Ancient Thought Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies New York Allworth Communications Inc ISBN 1 58115 203 5 Radhakrishnan Sarvepalli and Moore Charles 1957 A Source Book in Indian Philosophy Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 01958 1 Redondi Pietro Galileo Heretic Translated by Raymond Rosenthal Princeton NJ Princeton University Press 1987 ISBN 0 691 02426 X Riepe Dale 1964 The Naturalistic Tradition of Indian Thought 2nd ed Delhi Motilal Banarsidass Andrew G van Melsen 2004 First published 1952 From Atomos to Atom The History of the Concept Atom Translated by Henry J Koren Dover Publications ISBN 0 486 49584 1 External links Edit The dictionary definition of atomism at Wiktionary Dictionary of the History of Ideas Atomism Antiquity to the Seventeenth Century Dictionary of the History of Ideas Atomism in the Seventeenth Century Jonathan Schaffer Is There a Fundamental Level Nous 37 2003 498 517 1 Article by a philosopher who opposes atomism Article on traditional Greek atomism Atomism from the 17th to the 20th Century at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Atomism amp oldid 1129506888 Greek atomism, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.