fbpx
Wikipedia

Meta-ethics

In metaphilosophy and ethics, meta-ethics is the study of the nature, scope, and meaning of moral judgment. It is one of the three branches of ethics generally studied by philosophers, the others being normative ethics (questions of how one ought to be and act) and applied ethics (practical questions of right behavior in given, usually contentious, situations).

While normative ethics addresses such questions as "What should I do?", evaluating specific practices and principles of action, meta-ethics addresses questions such as "What is goodness?" and "How can we tell what is good from what is bad?", seeking to understand the assumptions underlying normative theories. Another distinction often made is that normative ethics involves first-order or substantive questions; meta-ethics involves second-order or formal questions.

Some theorists argue that a metaphysical account of morality is necessary for the proper evaluation of actual moral theories and for making practical moral decisions; others reason from opposite premises and suggest that studying moral judgments about proper actions can guide us to a true account of the nature of morality.

Meta-ethical questions

According to Richard Garner and Bernard Rosen, there are three kinds of meta-ethical problems, or three general questions:[1]

  1. What is the meaning of moral terms or judgments ? (moral semantics)
    • Asks about the meanings of such words as 'good', 'bad', 'right' and 'wrong' (see value theory)
  2. What is the nature of moral judgments ? (moral ontology)
  3. How may moral judgments be supported or defended ? (moral epistemology)
    • Asks such questions as how we can know if something is right or wrong, if at all.

Garner and Rosen say that answers to the three basic questions "are not unrelated, and sometimes an answer to one will strongly suggest, or perhaps even entail, an answer to another."[1] A meta-ethical theory, unlike a normative ethical theory, does not attempt to evaluate specific choices as being better, worse, good, bad, or evil; although it may have profound implications as to the validity and meaning of normative ethical claims. An answer to any of the three example questions above would not itself be a normative ethical statement.

Moral semantics

Moral semantics attempts to answer the question, "What is the meaning of moral terms or judgments?" Answers may have implications for answers to the other two questions as well.

Cognitivist theories

Cognitivist theories hold that evaluative moral sentences express propositions (i.e., they are 'truth-apt' or 'truth bearers', capable of being true or false), as opposed to non-cognitivism. Most forms of cognitivism hold that some such propositions are true (including moral realism and ethical subjectivism), as opposed to error theory, which asserts that all are erroneous.

Moral realism

Moral realism (in the robust sense; cf. moral universalism for the minimalist sense) holds that such propositions are about robust or mind-independent facts, that is, not facts about any person or group's subjective opinion, but about objective features of the world. Meta-ethical theories are commonly categorized as either a form of realism or as one of three forms of "anti-realism" regarding moral facts: ethical subjectivism, error theory, or non-cognitivism. Realism comes in two main varieties:

  1. Ethical naturalism holds that there are objective moral properties and that these properties are reducible or stand in some metaphysical relation (such as supervenience) to entirely non-ethical properties. Most ethical naturalists hold that we have empirical knowledge of moral truths. Ethical naturalism was implicitly assumed by many modern ethical theorists, particularly utilitarians.
  2. Ethical non-naturalism, as put forward by G. E. Moore, holds that there are objective and irreducible moral properties (such as the property of 'goodness'), and that we sometimes have intuitive or otherwise a priori awareness of moral properties or of moral truths. Moore's open question argument against what he considered the naturalistic fallacy was largely responsible for the birth of meta-ethical research in contemporary analytic philosophy.

Ethical subjectivism

Ethical subjectivism is one form of moral anti-realism. It holds that moral statements are made true or false by the attitudes and/or conventions of people, either those of each society, those of each individual, or those of some particular individual. Most forms of ethical subjectivism are relativist, but there are notable forms that are universalist:

  • Ideal observer theory holds that what is right is determined by the attitudes that a hypothetical ideal observer would have. An ideal observer is usually characterized as a being who is perfectly rational, imaginative, and informed, among other things. Though a subjectivist theory due to its reference to a particular (albeit hypothetical) subject, Ideal Observer Theory still purports to provide universal answers to moral questions.
  • Divine command theory holds that for a thing to be right is for a unique being, God, to approve of it, and that what is right for non-God beings is obedience to the divine will. This view was criticized by Plato in the Euthyphro (see the Euthyphro problem) but retains some modern defenders (Robert Adams, Philip Quinn, and others). Like ideal observer theory, divine command theory purports to be universalist despite its subjectivism.

Error theory

Error theory, another form of moral anti-realism, holds that although ethical claims do express propositions, all such propositions are false. Thus, both the statement "Murder is morally wrong" and the statement "Murder is morally permissible" are false, according to error theory. J. L. Mackie is probably the best-known proponent of this view. Since error theory denies that there are moral truths, error theory entails moral nihilism and, thus, moral skepticism; however, neither moral nihilism nor moral skepticism conversely entail error theory.

Non-cognitivist theories

Non-cognitivist theories hold that ethical sentences are neither true nor false because they do not express genuine propositions. Non-cognitivism is another form of moral anti-realism. Most forms of non-cognitivism are also forms of expressivism, however some such as Mark Timmons and Terrence Horgan distinguish the two and allow the possibility of cognitivist forms of expressivism. Non-cognitivism includes:

  • Emotivism, defended by A. J. Ayer and Charles Stevenson, holds that ethical sentences serve merely to express emotions. Ayer argues that ethical sentences are expressions of approval or disapproval, not assertions. So "Killing is wrong" means something like "Boo on killing!".
  • Quasi-realism, defended by Simon Blackburn, holds that ethical statements behave linguistically like factual claims and can be appropriately called "true" or "false", even though there are no ethical facts for them to correspond to. Projectivism and moral fictionalism are related theories.
  • Universal prescriptivism, defended by R. M. Hare, holds that moral statements function like universalized imperative sentences. So "Killing is wrong" means something like "Don't kill!" Hare's version of prescriptivism requires that moral prescriptions be universalizable, and hence actually have objective values, in spite of failing to be indicative statements with truth-values per se.

Centralism and non-centralism

Yet another way of categorizing meta-ethical theories is to distinguish between centralist and non-centralist moral theories. The debate between centralism and non-centralism revolves around the relationship between the so-called "thin" and "thick" concepts of morality: thin moral concepts are those such as good, bad, right, and wrong; thick moral concepts are those such as courageous, inequitable, just, or dishonest.[2] While both sides agree that the thin concepts are more general and the thick more specific, centralists hold that the thin concepts are antecedent to the thick ones and that the latter are therefore dependent on the former. That is, centralists argue that one must understand words like "right" and "ought" before understanding words like "just" and "unkind." Non-centralism rejects this view, holding that thin and thick concepts are on par with one another and even that the thick concepts are a sufficient starting point for understanding the thin ones.[3][4]

Non-centralism has been of particular importance to ethical naturalists in the late 20th and early 21st centuries as part of their argument that normativity is a non-excisable aspect of language and that there is no way of analyzing thick moral concepts into a purely descriptive element attached to a thin moral evaluation, thus undermining any fundamental division between facts and norms. Allan Gibbard, R. M. Hare, and Simon Blackburn have argued in favor of the fact/norm distinction, meanwhile, with Gibbard going so far as to argue that, even if conventional English has only mixed normative terms (that is, terms that are neither purely descriptive nor purely normative), we could develop a nominally English metalanguage that still allowed us to maintain the division between factual descriptions and normative evaluations.[5][6]

Moral ontology

Moral ontology attempts to answer the question, "What is the nature of moral judgments?"

Amongst those who believe there to be some standard(s) of morality (as opposed to moral nihilists), there are two divisions:

  1. universalists, who hold that the same moral facts or principles apply to everyone everywhere; and
  2. relativists, who hold that different moral facts or principles apply to different people or societies.

Moral universalism

Moral universalism (or universal morality) is the meta-ethical position that some system of ethics, or a universal ethic, applies universally, that is to all intelligent beings regardless of culture, race, sex, religion, nationality, sexuality, or other distinguishing feature. The source or justification of this system may be thought to be, for instance, human nature, shared vulnerability to suffering, the demands of universal reason, what is common among existing moral codes, or the common mandates of religion (although it can be argued that the latter is not in fact moral universalism because it may distinguish between Gods and mortals). Moral universalism is the opposing position to various forms of moral relativism.

Universalist theories are generally forms of moral realism, though exceptions exists, such as the subjectivist ideal observer and divine command theories, and the non-cognitivist universal prescriptivism of R. M. Hare. Forms of moral universalism include:

  • Value monism is the common form of universalism, which holds that all goods are commensurable on a single value scale.
  • Value pluralism contends that there are two or more genuine scales of value, knowable as such, yet incommensurable, so that any prioritization of these values is either non-cognitive or subjective. A value pluralist might, for example, contend that both a life as a nun and a life as a mother realize genuine values (in a universalist sense), yet they are incompatible (nuns may not have children), and there is no purely rational way to measure which is preferable. A notable proponent of this view is Isaiah Berlin.

Moral relativism

Moral relativism maintains that all moral judgments have their origins either in societal or in individual standards, and that no single standard exists by which one can objectively assess the truth of a moral proposition. Meta-ethical relativists, in general, believe that the descriptive properties of terms such as "good", "bad", "right", and "wrong" do not stand subject to universal truth conditions, but only to societal convention and personal preference. Given the same set of verifiable facts, some societies or individuals will have a fundamental disagreement about what one ought to do based on societal or individual norms, and one cannot adjudicate these using some independent standard of evaluation. The latter standard will always be societal or personal and not universal, unlike, for example, the scientific standards for assessing temperature or for determining mathematical truths. Some philosophers maintain that moral relativism entails non-cognitivism, while others consider it a form of cognitivism. Some but not all relativist theories are forms of moral subjectivism, although not all subjectivist theories are relativistic.[clarify]

Moral nihilism

Moral nihilism, also known as ethical nihilism, is the meta-ethical view that nothing has intrinsic moral value. For example, a moral nihilist would say that killing someone, for whatever reason, is intrinsically neither morally right nor morally wrong. Moral nihilism must be distinguished from moral relativism, which does allow for moral statements to be intrinsically true or false in a non-universal sense, but does not assign any static truth-values to moral statements. Insofar as only true statements can be known, moral nihilists are moral skeptics. Most forms of moral nihilism are non-cognitivist and vice versa, though there are notable exceptions such as universal prescriptivism (which is semantically non-cognitive but substantially universal).

Moral epistemology

Moral epistemology is the study of moral knowledge. It attempts to answer such questions as, "How may moral judgments be supported or defended?" and "Is moral knowledge possible?"

If one presupposes a cognitivist interpretation of moral sentences, morality is justified by the moralist's knowledge of moral facts, and the theories to justify moral judgements are epistemological theories. Most moral epistemologies posit that moral knowledge is somehow possible (including empiricism and moral rationalism), as opposed to moral skepticism. Amongst them, there are those who hold that moral knowledge is gained inferentially on the basis of some sort of non-moral epistemic process, as opposed to ethical intuitionism.

Moral knowledge gained by inference

Empiricism

Empiricism is the doctrine that knowledge is gained primarily through observation and experience. Meta-ethical theories that imply an empirical epistemology include:

  • ethical naturalism, which holds moral facts to be reducible to non-moral facts and thus knowable in the same ways; and
  • most common forms of ethical subjectivism, which hold that moral facts reduce to facts about individual opinions or cultural conventions and thus are knowable by observation of those conventions.

There are exceptions within subjectivism however, such as ideal observer theory, which implies that moral facts may be known through a rational process, and individualist ethical subjectivism, which holds that moral facts are merely personal opinions and so may be known only through introspection. Empirical arguments for ethics run into the is-ought problem, which asserts that the way the world is cannot alone instruct people how they ought to act.

Moral rationalism

Moral rationalism, also called ethical rationalism, is the view according to which moral truths (or at least general moral principles) are knowable a priori, by reason alone. Plato and Immanuel Kant, prominent figures in the history of philosophy, defended moral rationalism. David Hume and Friedrich Nietzsche are two figures in the history of philosophy who have rejected moral rationalism.

Recent philosophers who defended moral rationalism include R. M. Hare, Christine Korsgaard, Alan Gewirth, and Michael Smith. A moral rationalist may adhere to any number of different semantic theories as well; moral realism is compatible with rationalism, and the subjectivist ideal observer theory and non-cognitivist universal prescriptivism both entail it.

Ethical intuitionism

Ethical intuitionism is the view according to which some moral truths can be known without inference. That is, the view is at its core a foundationalism about moral beliefs. Such an epistemological view implies that there are moral beliefs with propositional contents; so it implies cognitivism. Ethical intuitionism commonly suggests moral realism, the view that there are objective facts of morality and, to be more specific, ethical non-naturalism, the view that these evaluative facts cannot be reduced to natural fact. However, neither moral realism nor ethical non-naturalism are essential to the view; most ethical intuitionists simply happen to hold those views as well. Ethical intuitionism comes in both a "rationalist" variety, and a more "empiricist" variety known as moral sense theory.

Moral skepticism

Moral skepticism is the class of meta-ethical theories all members of which entail that no one has any moral knowledge. Many moral skeptics also make the stronger, modal, claim that moral knowledge is impossible. Forms of moral skepticism include, but are not limited to, error theory and most but not all forms of non-cognitivism.

See also

References

  1. ^ a b Garner, Richard T.; Bernard Rosen (1967). Moral Philosophy: A Systematic Introduction to Normative Ethics and Meta-ethics. New York: Macmillan. p. 215. LOC card number 67-18887.
  2. ^ Jackson, Frank. 1992. "Critical Notice." Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70(4):475–88.
  3. ^ Hurley, S.L. (1989). Natural Reasons: Personality and Polity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  4. ^ Hurley, S.L. (1985). "Objectivity and Disagreement." in Morality and Objectivity, Ted Honderich (ed.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, pp. 54-97.
  5. ^ Couture, Jocelyne, and Kai Nielsen. 1995. "Introduction: The Ages of Metaethics." Pp. 1–30 in On the Relevance of Metaethics: New Essays in Metaethics, edited by J. Couture and K. Nielsen. Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
  6. ^ Gibbard, Allan (1993). E. Villanueva (ed.). "Reply to Railton". Naturalism and Normativity. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview: Ridgeview Publishing Company. 4: 52–59. doi:10.2307/1522826. JSTOR 1522826.

External links

meta, ethics, metaphilosophy, ethics, meta, ethics, study, nature, scope, meaning, moral, judgment, three, branches, ethics, generally, studied, philosophers, others, being, normative, ethics, questions, ought, applied, ethics, practical, questions, right, beh. In metaphilosophy and ethics meta ethics is the study of the nature scope and meaning of moral judgment It is one of the three branches of ethics generally studied by philosophers the others being normative ethics questions of how one ought to be and act and applied ethics practical questions of right behavior in given usually contentious situations While normative ethics addresses such questions as What should I do evaluating specific practices and principles of action meta ethics addresses questions such as What is goodness and How can we tell what is good from what is bad seeking to understand the assumptions underlying normative theories Another distinction often made is that normative ethics involves first order or substantive questions meta ethics involves second order or formal questions Some theorists argue that a metaphysical account of morality is necessary for the proper evaluation of actual moral theories and for making practical moral decisions others reason from opposite premises and suggest that studying moral judgments about proper actions can guide us to a true account of the nature of morality Contents 1 Meta ethical questions 2 Moral semantics 2 1 Cognitivist theories 2 1 1 Moral realism 2 1 2 Ethical subjectivism 2 1 3 Error theory 2 2 Non cognitivist theories 2 3 Centralism and non centralism 3 Moral ontology 3 1 Moral universalism 3 2 Moral relativism 3 3 Moral nihilism 4 Moral epistemology 4 1 Moral knowledge gained by inference 4 1 1 Empiricism 4 1 2 Moral rationalism 4 2 Ethical intuitionism 4 3 Moral skepticism 5 See also 6 References 7 External linksMeta ethical questions EditAccording to Richard Garner and Bernard Rosen there are three kinds of meta ethical problems or three general questions 1 What is the meaning of moral terms or judgments moral semantics Asks about the meanings of such words as good bad right and wrong see value theory What is the nature of moral judgments moral ontology Asks questions of whether moral judgments are absolute or relative of one kind or many kinds etc How may moral judgments be supported or defended moral epistemology Asks such questions as how we can know if something is right or wrong if at all Garner and Rosen say that answers to the three basic questions are not unrelated and sometimes an answer to one will strongly suggest or perhaps even entail an answer to another 1 A meta ethical theory unlike a normative ethical theory does not attempt to evaluate specific choices as being better worse good bad or evil although it may have profound implications as to the validity and meaning of normative ethical claims An answer to any of the three example questions above would not itself be a normative ethical statement Moral semantics EditMoral semantics attempts to answer the question What is the meaning of moral terms or judgments Answers may have implications for answers to the other two questions as well Cognitivist theories Edit Cognitivist theories hold that evaluative moral sentences express propositions i e they are truth apt or truth bearers capable of being true or false as opposed to non cognitivism Most forms of cognitivism hold that some such propositions are true including moral realism and ethical subjectivism as opposed to error theory which asserts that all are erroneous Moral realism Edit Moral realism in the robust sense cf moral universalism for the minimalist sense holds that such propositions are about robust or mind independent facts that is not facts about any person or group s subjective opinion but about objective features of the world Meta ethical theories are commonly categorized as either a form of realism or as one of three forms of anti realism regarding moral facts ethical subjectivism error theory or non cognitivism Realism comes in two main varieties Ethical naturalism holds that there are objective moral properties and that these properties are reducible or stand in some metaphysical relation such as supervenience to entirely non ethical properties Most ethical naturalists hold that we have empirical knowledge of moral truths Ethical naturalism was implicitly assumed by many modern ethical theorists particularly utilitarians Ethical non naturalism as put forward by G E Moore holds that there are objective and irreducible moral properties such as the property of goodness and that we sometimes have intuitive or otherwise a priori awareness of moral properties or of moral truths Moore s open question argument against what he considered the naturalistic fallacy was largely responsible for the birth of meta ethical research in contemporary analytic philosophy Ethical subjectivism Edit Ethical subjectivism is one form of moral anti realism It holds that moral statements are made true or false by the attitudes and or conventions of people either those of each society those of each individual or those of some particular individual Most forms of ethical subjectivism are relativist but there are notable forms that are universalist Ideal observer theory holds that what is right is determined by the attitudes that a hypothetical ideal observer would have An ideal observer is usually characterized as a being who is perfectly rational imaginative and informed among other things Though a subjectivist theory due to its reference to a particular albeit hypothetical subject Ideal Observer Theory still purports to provide universal answers to moral questions Divine command theory holds that for a thing to be right is for a unique being God to approve of it and that what is right for non God beings is obedience to the divine will This view was criticized by Plato in the Euthyphro see the Euthyphro problem but retains some modern defenders Robert Adams Philip Quinn and others Like ideal observer theory divine command theory purports to be universalist despite its subjectivism Error theory Edit Error theory another form of moral anti realism holds that although ethical claims do express propositions all such propositions are false Thus both the statement Murder is morally wrong and the statement Murder is morally permissible are false according to error theory J L Mackie is probably the best known proponent of this view Since error theory denies that there are moral truths error theory entails moral nihilism and thus moral skepticism however neither moral nihilism nor moral skepticism conversely entail error theory Non cognitivist theories Edit Non cognitivist theories hold that ethical sentences are neither true nor false because they do not express genuine propositions Non cognitivism is another form of moral anti realism Most forms of non cognitivism are also forms of expressivism however some such as Mark Timmons and Terrence Horgan distinguish the two and allow the possibility of cognitivist forms of expressivism Non cognitivism includes Emotivism defended by A J Ayer and Charles Stevenson holds that ethical sentences serve merely to express emotions Ayer argues that ethical sentences are expressions of approval or disapproval not assertions So Killing is wrong means something like Boo on killing Quasi realism defended by Simon Blackburn holds that ethical statements behave linguistically like factual claims and can be appropriately called true or false even though there are no ethical facts for them to correspond to Projectivism and moral fictionalism are related theories Universal prescriptivism defended by R M Hare holds that moral statements function like universalized imperative sentences So Killing is wrong means something like Don t kill Hare s version of prescriptivism requires that moral prescriptions be universalizable and hence actually have objective values in spite of failing to be indicative statements with truth values per se Centralism and non centralism Edit Yet another way of categorizing meta ethical theories is to distinguish between centralist and non centralist moral theories The debate between centralism and non centralism revolves around the relationship between the so called thin and thick concepts of morality thin moral concepts are those such as good bad right and wrong thick moral concepts are those such as courageous inequitable just or dishonest 2 While both sides agree that the thin concepts are more general and the thick more specific centralists hold that the thin concepts are antecedent to the thick ones and that the latter are therefore dependent on the former That is centralists argue that one must understand words like right and ought before understanding words like just and unkind Non centralism rejects this view holding that thin and thick concepts are on par with one another and even that the thick concepts are a sufficient starting point for understanding the thin ones 3 4 Non centralism has been of particular importance to ethical naturalists in the late 20th and early 21st centuries as part of their argument that normativity is a non excisable aspect of language and that there is no way of analyzing thick moral concepts into a purely descriptive element attached to a thin moral evaluation thus undermining any fundamental division between facts and norms Allan Gibbard R M Hare and Simon Blackburn have argued in favor of the fact norm distinction meanwhile with Gibbard going so far as to argue that even if conventional English has only mixed normative terms that is terms that are neither purely descriptive nor purely normative we could develop a nominally English metalanguage that still allowed us to maintain the division between factual descriptions and normative evaluations 5 6 Moral ontology EditMoral ontology attempts to answer the question What is the nature of moral judgments Amongst those who believe there to be some standard s of morality as opposed to moral nihilists there are two divisions universalists who hold that the same moral facts or principles apply to everyone everywhere and relativists who hold that different moral facts or principles apply to different people or societies Moral universalism Edit Moral universalism or universal morality is the meta ethical position that some system of ethics or a universal ethic applies universally that is to all intelligent beings regardless of culture race sex religion nationality sexuality or other distinguishing feature The source or justification of this system may be thought to be for instance human nature shared vulnerability to suffering the demands of universal reason what is common among existing moral codes or the common mandates of religion although it can be argued that the latter is not in fact moral universalism because it may distinguish between Gods and mortals Moral universalism is the opposing position to various forms of moral relativism Universalist theories are generally forms of moral realism though exceptions exists such as the subjectivist ideal observer and divine command theories and the non cognitivist universal prescriptivism of R M Hare Forms of moral universalism include Value monism is the common form of universalism which holds that all goods are commensurable on a single value scale Value pluralism contends that there are two or more genuine scales of value knowable as such yet incommensurable so that any prioritization of these values is either non cognitive or subjective A value pluralist might for example contend that both a life as a nun and a life as a mother realize genuine values in a universalist sense yet they are incompatible nuns may not have children and there is no purely rational way to measure which is preferable A notable proponent of this view is Isaiah Berlin Moral relativism Edit Moral relativism maintains that all moral judgments have their origins either in societal or in individual standards and that no single standard exists by which one can objectively assess the truth of a moral proposition Meta ethical relativists in general believe that the descriptive properties of terms such as good bad right and wrong do not stand subject to universal truth conditions but only to societal convention and personal preference Given the same set of verifiable facts some societies or individuals will have a fundamental disagreement about what one ought to do based on societal or individual norms and one cannot adjudicate these using some independent standard of evaluation The latter standard will always be societal or personal and not universal unlike for example the scientific standards for assessing temperature or for determining mathematical truths Some philosophers maintain that moral relativism entails non cognitivism while others consider it a form of cognitivism Some but not all relativist theories are forms of moral subjectivism although not all subjectivist theories are relativistic clarify Moral nihilism Edit Moral nihilism also known as ethical nihilism is the meta ethical view that nothing has intrinsic moral value For example a moral nihilist would say that killing someone for whatever reason is intrinsically neither morally right nor morally wrong Moral nihilism must be distinguished from moral relativism which does allow for moral statements to be intrinsically true or false in a non universal sense but does not assign any static truth values to moral statements Insofar as only true statements can be known moral nihilists are moral skeptics Most forms of moral nihilism are non cognitivist and vice versa though there are notable exceptions such as universal prescriptivism which is semantically non cognitive but substantially universal Moral epistemology Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Moral epistemology Moral epistemology is the study of moral knowledge It attempts to answer such questions as How may moral judgments be supported or defended and Is moral knowledge possible If one presupposes a cognitivist interpretation of moral sentences morality is justified by the moralist s knowledge of moral facts and the theories to justify moral judgements are epistemological theories Most moral epistemologies posit that moral knowledge is somehow possible including empiricism and moral rationalism as opposed to moral skepticism Amongst them there are those who hold that moral knowledge is gained inferentially on the basis of some sort of non moral epistemic process as opposed to ethical intuitionism Moral knowledge gained by inference Edit Empiricism Edit Empiricism is the doctrine that knowledge is gained primarily through observation and experience Meta ethical theories that imply an empirical epistemology include ethical naturalism which holds moral facts to be reducible to non moral facts and thus knowable in the same ways and most common forms of ethical subjectivism which hold that moral facts reduce to facts about individual opinions or cultural conventions and thus are knowable by observation of those conventions There are exceptions within subjectivism however such as ideal observer theory which implies that moral facts may be known through a rational process and individualist ethical subjectivism which holds that moral facts are merely personal opinions and so may be known only through introspection Empirical arguments for ethics run into the is ought problem which asserts that the way the world is cannot alone instruct people how they ought to act Moral rationalism Edit Moral rationalism also called ethical rationalism is the view according to which moral truths or at least general moral principles are knowable a priori by reason alone Plato and Immanuel Kant prominent figures in the history of philosophy defended moral rationalism David Hume and Friedrich Nietzsche are two figures in the history of philosophy who have rejected moral rationalism Recent philosophers who defended moral rationalism include R M Hare Christine Korsgaard Alan Gewirth and Michael Smith A moral rationalist may adhere to any number of different semantic theories as well moral realism is compatible with rationalism and the subjectivist ideal observer theory and non cognitivist universal prescriptivism both entail it Ethical intuitionism Edit Ethical intuitionism is the view according to which some moral truths can be known without inference That is the view is at its core a foundationalism about moral beliefs Such an epistemological view implies that there are moral beliefs with propositional contents so it implies cognitivism Ethical intuitionism commonly suggests moral realism the view that there are objective facts of morality and to be more specific ethical non naturalism the view that these evaluative facts cannot be reduced to natural fact However neither moral realism nor ethical non naturalism are essential to the view most ethical intuitionists simply happen to hold those views as well Ethical intuitionism comes in both a rationalist variety and a more empiricist variety known as moral sense theory Moral skepticism Edit Moral skepticism is the class of meta ethical theories all members of which entail that no one has any moral knowledge Many moral skeptics also make the stronger modal claim that moral knowledge is impossible Forms of moral skepticism include but are not limited to error theory and most but not all forms of non cognitivism See also EditAnthropic principle Axiology Deontic logic Ethical subjectivism Fact value distinction Is ought problem Meta rights Moral realism Normative ethics Principia Ethica The Right and the GoodReferences Edit a b Garner Richard T Bernard Rosen 1967 Moral Philosophy A Systematic Introduction to Normative Ethics and Meta ethics New York Macmillan p 215 LOC card number 67 18887 Jackson Frank 1992 Critical Notice Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 4 475 88 Hurley S L 1989 Natural Reasons Personality and Polity Oxford Oxford University Press Hurley S L 1985 Objectivity and Disagreement in Morality and Objectivity Ted Honderich ed London Routledge amp Kegan Paul pp 54 97 Couture Jocelyne and Kai Nielsen 1995 Introduction The Ages of Metaethics Pp 1 30 in On the Relevance of Metaethics New Essays in Metaethics edited by J Couture and K Nielsen Calgary University of Calgary Press Gibbard Allan 1993 E Villanueva ed Reply to Railton Naturalism and Normativity Atascadero CA Ridgeview Ridgeview Publishing Company 4 52 59 doi 10 2307 1522826 JSTOR 1522826 External links Edit Wikimedia Commons has media related to Meta ethics Sayre McCord Geoff Metaethics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaethics entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Language of Morals 1952 by R M Hare Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant Essays by philosopher Michael Huemer on meta ethics especially intuitionism Relativity theory of ethics by J J Mittler Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Meta ethics amp oldid 1137139324, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.