fbpx
Wikipedia

Metaphilosophy

Metaphilosophy, sometimes called the philosophy of philosophy, is "the investigation of the nature of philosophy".[1] Its subject matter includes the aims of philosophy, the boundaries of philosophy, and its methods.[2][3] Thus, while philosophy characteristically inquires into the nature of being, the reality of objects, the possibility of knowledge, the nature of truth, and so on, metaphilosophy is the self-reflective inquiry into the nature, aims, and methods of the activity that makes these kinds of inquiries, by asking what is philosophy itself, what sorts of questions it should ask, how it might pose and answer them, and what it can achieve in doing so. It is considered by some to be a subject prior and preparatory to philosophy,[4] while others see it as inherently a part of philosophy,[5] or automatically a part of philosophy[6] while others adopt some combination of these views.[2]

The interest in metaphilosophy led to the establishment of the journal Metaphilosophy in January 1970.[7]

Many sub-disciplines of philosophy have their own branch of 'metaphilosophy', examples being meta-aesthetics, meta-epistemology, meta-ethics, and metametaphysics (meta-ontology).[8]

Although the term metaphilosophy and explicit attention to metaphilosophy as a specific domain within philosophy arose in the 20th century, the topic is likely as old as philosophy itself, and can be traced back at least as far as the works of Ancient Greeks and Ancient Indian Nyaya.[9]

Relationship to philosophy edit

Some philosophers consider metaphilosophy to be a subject apart from philosophy, above or beyond it,[4] while others object to that idea.[5] Timothy Williamson argues that the philosophy of philosophy is "automatically part of philosophy", as is the philosophy of anything else.[6] Nicholas Bunnin and Jiyuan Yu write that the separation of first- from second-order study has lost popularity as philosophers find it hard to observe the distinction.[10] As evidenced by these contrasting opinions, debate persists as to whether the evaluation of the nature of philosophy is 'second-order philosophy' or simply 'plain philosophy'.

Many philosophers have expressed doubts over the value of metaphilosophy.[11] Among them is Gilbert Ryle: "preoccupation with questions about methods tends to distract us from prosecuting the methods themselves. We run as a rule, worse, not better, if we think a lot about our feet. So let us ... not speak of it all but just do it."[12]

Terminology edit

The designations metaphilosophy and philosophy of philosophy have a variety of meanings, sometimes taken to be synonyms, and sometimes seen as distinct.

Morris Lazerowitz claims to have coined the term 'metaphilosophy' around 1940 and used it in print in 1942.[1] Lazerowitz proposed that metaphilosophy is 'the investigation of the nature of philosophy'.[1] Earlier uses have been found in translations from French.[13] The term is derived from Greek word meta μετά ("after", "beyond", "with") and philosophía φιλοσοφία ("love of wisdom").

The term 'metaphilosophy' is used by Paul Moser[14] in the sense of a 'second-order' or more fundamental undertaking than philosophy itself, in the manner suggested by Charles Griswold:[4]

"The distinction between philosophy and metaphilosophy has an analogue in the familiar distinction between mathematics and metamathematics."[14]

— Paul K. Moser, Metaphilosophy, p. 562

Some other philosophers treat the prefix meta as simply meaning 'about...', rather than as referring to a metatheoretical 'second-order' form of philosophy, among them Rescher[15] and Double.[16] Others, such as Williamson, prefer the term 'philosophy of philosophy' instead of 'metaphilosophy' as it avoids the connotation of a 'second-order' discipline that looks down on philosophy, and instead denotes something that is a part of it.[17] Joll suggests that to take metaphilosophy as 'the application of the methods of philosophy to philosophy itself' is too vague, while the view that sees metaphilosophy as a 'second-order' or more abstract discipline, outside philosophy, "is narrow and tendentious".[18]

In the analytic tradition, the term "metaphilosophy" is mostly used to tag commenting and research on previous works as opposed to original contributions towards solving philosophical problems.[19]

Writings edit

Ludwig Wittgenstein wrote about the nature of philosophical puzzles and philosophical understanding. He suggested philosophical errors arose from confusions about the nature of philosophical inquiry.

C. D. Broad distinguished Critical from Speculative philosophy in his "The Subject-matter of Philosophy, and its Relations to the special Sciences", in Introduction to Scientific Thought, 1923. Curt Ducasse, in Philosophy as a Science, examines several views of the nature of philosophy, and concludes that philosophy has a distinct subject matter: appraisals. Ducasse's view has been among the first to be described as 'metaphilosophy'.[20]

Henri Lefebvre in Métaphilosophie (1965) argued, from a Marxian standpoint, in favor of an "ontological break", as a necessary methodological approach for critical social theory (whilst criticizing Louis Althusser's "epistemological break" with subjective Marxism, which represented a fundamental theoretical tool for the school of Marxist structuralism).

Paul Moser writes that typical metaphilosophical discussion includes determining the conditions under which a claim can be said to be a philosophical one. He regards meta-ethics, the study of ethics, to be a form of metaphilosophy, as well as meta-epistemology, the study of epistemology.[14]

Topics edit

Many sub-disciplines of philosophy have their own branch of 'metaphilosophy'.[8] However, some topics within 'metaphilosophy' cut across the various subdivisions of philosophy to consider fundamentals important to all its sub-disciplines.

Aims edit

Some philosophers (e.g. existentialists, pragmatists) think philosophy is ultimately a practical discipline that should help us lead meaningful lives by showing us who we are, how we relate to the world around us and what we should do. [citation needed] Others (e.g. analytic philosophers) see philosophy as a technical, formal, and entirely theoretical discipline, with goals such as "the disinterested pursuit of knowledge for its own sake".[21] Other proposed goals of philosophy include discovering the absolutely fundamental reason of everything it investigates, making explicit the nature and significance of ordinary and scientific beliefs,[22] and unifying and transcending the insights given by science and religion.[23] Others proposed that philosophy is a complex discipline because it has 4 or 6 different dimensions.[24][25]

Boundaries edit

Defining philosophy and its boundaries is itself problematic; Nigel Warburton has called it "notoriously difficult".[26] There is no straightforward definition,[23] and most interesting definitions are controversial.[27] As Bertrand Russell wrote:

"We may note one peculiar feature of philosophy. If someone asks the question what is mathematics, we can give him a dictionary definition, let us say the science of number, for the sake of argument. As far as it goes this is an uncontroversial statement... Definitions may be given in this way of any field where a body of definite knowledge exists. But philosophy cannot be so defined. Any definition is controversial and already embodies a philosophic attitude. The only way to find out what philosophy is, is to do philosophy."[28]

— Bertrand Russell, The Wisdom of the West, p. 7

While there is some agreement that philosophy involves general or fundamental topics,[21][29] there is no clear agreement about a series of demarcation issues, including:

  • that between first-order and second-order investigations. Some authors say that philosophical inquiry is second-order, having concepts, theories and presupposition as its subject matter; that it is "thinking about thinking", of a "generally second-order character";[30] that philosophers study, rather than use, the concepts that structure our thinking. However, the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy warns that "the borderline between such 'second-order' reflection, and ways of practicing the first-order discipline itself, is not always clear: philosophical problems may be tamed by the advance of a discipline, and the conduct of a discipline may be swayed by philosophical reflection".[29]
  • that between philosophy and empirical science. Some argue that philosophy is distinct from science in that its questions cannot be answered empirically, that is, by observation or experiment.[31][32] Some analytical philosophers argue that all meaningful empirical questions are to be answered by science, not philosophy. However, some schools of contemporary philosophy such as the pragmatists and naturalistic epistemologists argue that philosophy should be linked to science and should be scientific in the broad sense of that term, "preferring to see philosophical reflection as continuous with the best practice of any field of intellectual enquiry".[29]
  • that between philosophy and religion. Some argue that philosophy is distinct from religion in that it allows no place for faith or revelation:[21] that philosophy does not try to answer questions by appeal to revelation, myth or religious knowledge of any kind, but uses reason, without reference to sensible observation and experiments". However, philosophers and theologians such as Thomas Aquinas and Peter Damian have argued that philosophy is the "handmaiden of theology" (ancilla theologiae).[33]

Methods edit

Philosophical method (or philosophical methodology) is the study of how to do philosophy. A common view among philosophers is that philosophy is distinguished by the ways that philosophers follow in addressing philosophical questions. There is not just one method that philosophers use to answer philosophical questions.

C.D. Broad classifies philosophy into two methods, he distinguished between critical philosophy and speculative philosophy. He described critical philosophy as analysing "unanalysed concepts in daily life and in science" and then "expos[ing] them to every objection that we can think of". While speculative philosophy's role is to "take over all aspects of human experience, to reflect upon them, and to try to think out a view of Reality as a whole which shall do justice to all of them".[34]

Recently, some philosophers have cast doubt about intuition as a basic tool in philosophical inquiry, from Socrates up to contemporary philosophy of language. In Rethinking Intuition[35] various thinkers discard intuition as a valid source of knowledge and thereby call into question 'a priori' philosophy. Experimental philosophy is a form of philosophical inquiry that makes at least partial use of empirical research—especially opinion polling—in order to address persistent philosophical questions. This is in contrast with the methods found in analytic philosophy, whereby some say a philosopher will sometimes begin by appealing to his or her intuitions on an issue and then form an argument with those intuitions as premises. However, disagreement about what experimental philosophy can accomplish is widespread and several philosophers have offered criticisms. One claim is that the empirical data gathered by experimental philosophers can have an indirect effect on philosophical questions by allowing for a better understanding of the underlying psychological processes which lead to philosophical intuitions.[36] Some analytic philosophers like Timothy Williamson[37] have rejected such a move against 'armchair' philosophy–i.e., philosophical inquiry that is undergirded by intuition–by construing 'intuition' (which they believe to be a misnomer) as merely referring to common cognitive faculties: If one is calling into question 'intuition', one is, they would say, harboring a skeptical attitude towards common cognitive faculties–a consequence that seems philosophically unappealing. For Williamson, instances of intuition are instances of our cognitive faculties processing counterfactuals[38] (or subjunctive conditionals) that are specific to the thought experiment or example in question.

Progress edit

A prominent question in metaphilosophy is that of whether or not philosophical progress occurs and more so, whether such progress in philosophy is even possible.[39]

David Chalmers divides inquiry into philosophical progress in metaphilosophy into three questions.

  1. The Existence Question: is there progress in philosophy?
  2. The Comparison Question: is there as much progress in philosophy as in science?
  3. The Explanation Question: why isn't there more progress in philosophy?[40]

Ludwig Wittgenstein, in Culture and Value remarked, "Philosophy hasn't made any progress? - If somebody scratches the spot where he has an itch, do we have to see some progress?...And can't this reaction to an irritation continue in the same way for a long time before the cure for an itching is discovered?".[41]

According to Hilary Putnam philosophy is more adept at showing people that specific ideas or arguments are wrong than that specific ideas or arguments are right.[42]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c Lazerowitz, M. (1970). "A note on "metaphilosophy"". Metaphilosophy. 1 (1): 91. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1970.tb00792.x. see also the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy article by Nicholas Joll: Contemporary Metaphilosophy
  2. ^ a b Nicholas Joll (November 18, 2010). "Contemporary Metaphilosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (IEP).
  3. ^ Armen T Marsoobian (2004). "Metaphilosophy". In John Lachs; Robert Talisse (eds.). American Philosophy: An Encyclopedia. pp. 500–501. ISBN 978-0203492796. Its primary question is "What is philosophy?"
  4. ^ a b c See for example, Charles L. Griswold Jr. (2010). Platonic Writings/Platonic Readings. Penn State Press. pp. 144–146. ISBN 978-0271044811.
  5. ^ a b Martin Heidegger (1956). Was Ist Das – die Philosophie?. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 21. ISBN 978-0808403197.
  6. ^ a b Timothy Williamson (2008). "Preface". The Philosophy of Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. p. ix. ISBN 978-0470695913. The philosophy of philosophy is automatically part of philosophy, just as the philosophy of anything else is...
  7. ^ The journal describes its scope as: "Particular areas of interest include: the foundation, scope, function and direction of philosophy; justification of philosophical methods and arguments; the interrelations among schools or fields of philosophy (for example, the relation of logic to problems in ethics or epistemology); aspects of philosophical systems; presuppositions of philosophical schools; the relation of philosophy to other disciplines (for example, artificial intelligence, linguistics or literature); sociology of philosophy; the relevance of philosophy to social and political action; issues in the teaching of philosophy."
  8. ^ a b Robert S Hartman (1995). "Axiology as a science". In Rem B. Edwards (ed.). Formal Axiology and Its Critics. Rodopi. p. 21. ISBN 978-9051839104.
  9. ^ Nicholas Joll, Metaphilosophy, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  10. ^ Nicholas Bunnin & Jiyuan Yu (2009). "Metaphilosophy". The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 426–427. ISBN 978-1405191128.
  11. ^ Søren Overgaard; Paul Gilbert; Stephen Burwood (2013). "Introduction: What good is metaphilosophy?". An introduction to metaphilosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 6. ISBN 978-0521193412.
  12. ^ Gilbert Ryle (2009). "Chapter 23: Ordinary language". Collected Essays 1929-1968: Collected Papers Volume 2 (Reprint of Hutchinson 1971 ed.). Routledge. p. 331. ISBN 978-0415485494. Quoted by Søren Overgaard; Paul Gilbert; Stephen Burwood (2013). "Introduction: What good is metaphilosophy?". An introduction to metaphilosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 6. ISBN 978-0521193412.
  13. ^ e.g. Clemenceau G., In the evening of my thought (Au soir de la pensée, Paris: Plon, 1927), Houghton Mifflin company, 1929, Vol. 2, p. 498: "this teratological product of metaphilosophy"; Gilson E., Christianity and philosophy, Pub. for the Institute of Mediaeval Studies by Sheed & Ward, 1939, p. 88
  14. ^ a b c Paul K. Moser (2008). "Metaphilosophy". In Robert Audi (ed.). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (Paperback reprint of 2nd ed.). Paw Prints 2008-06-26. pp. 561–562. ISBN 978-1439503508.
  15. ^ Rescher N. (2007). "Chapter 1: Philosophical principles". Philosophical Dialectics, an Essay on Metaphilosophy. State University of New York Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0791467466.
  16. ^ Richard Double (1996). Metaphilosophy and Free Will. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0195355413.
  17. ^ Williamson, Timothy (2007). "Preface". The Philosophy of Philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1405133968.
  18. ^ Nicholas Joll (November 18, 2010). "Contemporary Metaphysics: Defining metaphilosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  19. ^ e.g. PhilPapers
  20. ^ Dommeyer F., (1961), A Critical Examination of C. J. Ducasse's Metaphilosophy, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 21, (Jun., 1961), No. 4 pp. 439-455
  21. ^ a b c Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy (2005)
  22. ^ Collins English Dictionary
  23. ^ a b Mastering Philosophy by Anthony Harrison-Barbet (1990)[page needed]
  24. ^ Adler, Mortimer (1993), The Four Dimensions of Philosophy: Metaphysical-Moral-Objective-Categorical
  25. ^ Vidal, Clément (2012). "Metaphilosophical Criteria for Worldview Comparison" (PDF). Metaphilosophy. 43 (3): 306–347. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.508.631. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.2012.01749.x.
  26. ^ Nigel Warburton (2003). Philosophy: The Basics (3rd ed.). CRC Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0203202029.
  27. ^ The Rt. Hon. Lord Quinton (2005). "Philosophy". In Ted Honderich (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 702. ISBN 978-0199264797.
  28. ^ Bertrand Russell (1959). The Wisdom of the West: A Historical Survey of Western Philosophy in Its Social and Political Setting. Doubleday. p. 7.
  29. ^ a b c Simon Blackburn (2005). "Philosophy". Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (2nd ed.). pp. 276–7. ISBN 978-0198610137.
  30. ^ Ted Honderich, ed. (2005). "Conceptual analysis". Oxford Companion to Philosophy New Edition (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press USA. p. 154. ISBN 978-0199264797. "Insofar as conceptual analysis is the method of philosophy (as it was widely held to be for much of the twentieth century), philosophy is a second-order subject because it is about language not the world or what language is about.
  31. ^ Sara Heināmaa (2006). "Phenomenology: A foundational science". In Margaret A. Simons (ed.). The Philosophy of Simone De Beauvoir: Critical Essays. Indiana University Press. p. 22. ISBN 978-0253218407. The important difference between the scientist and the philosopher is in the radically critical nature of philosophy. Husserl characterizes this difference by saying that the task of philosophy is to ask the ultimate questions...The philosophical questions can not be answered in the same way that empirical questions can be answered.
  32. ^ Richard Tieszen (2008). "Science as a triumph of the human spirit and science in crisis: Husserl and the fortunes of reason". In Gary Gutting (ed.). Continental Philosophy of Science. John Wiley & Sons. p. 94. ISBN 978-1405137447. The sciences are in need of continual epistemological reflection and critique of a sort that only the philosopher can provide. ...Husserl pictures the work of the philosopher and the scientist as mutually complementary.
  33. ^ Gracia, J.G. and Noone, T.B., A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages, London: Blackwell, 2003, p. 35
  34. ^ Broad, C. D. (1953). "Critical and Speculative Philosophy". Contemporary British Philosophy Personal Statements · Volume 20. London, Allen & Unwin. pp. 87–100.
  35. ^ Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and its Role in Philosophical Inquiry ,(Studies in Epistemology and Cognitive Theory) by Michael DePaul, William Ramsey (Editors), Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. (1998) ISBN 0-8476-8796-1; ISBN 978-0-8476-8796-1
  36. ^ Knobe, J. and Nichols, S. (eds.) (2008) Experimental Philosophy, §2.1, OCLC 233792562
  37. ^ Williamson, Timothy (2016-04-29), "Philosophical Criticisms of Experimental Philosophy", A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, pp. 22–36, doi:10.1002/9781118661666.ch2, ISBN 9781118661666
  38. ^ Pust, Joel (2019), "Intuition", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-01-18
  39. ^ Dietrich, Eric (2011). There Is No Progress in Philosophy 2021-03-02 at the Wayback Machine. Essays in Philosophy 12 (2):9.
  40. ^ Chalmers, David (2015). "Why Isn't There More Progress in Philosophy?" (PDF). Philosophy. 90 (1): 3–31. doi:10.1017/S0031819114000436. hdl:1885/57201. S2CID 170974260. Retrieved 18 December 2017.
  41. ^ Hutto, D. (2003). Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy Neither Theory Nor Therapy. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 218.
  42. ^ Putnam, Hilary (1995). Renewing Philosophy. Harvard University Press. p. 134.

Further reading edit

  • Double R., (1996) Metaphilosophy and Free Will, Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-510762-4, ISBN 978-0-19-510762-3
  • Ducasse, C.J., (1941) Philosophy as a Science: Its Matter and Its Method
  • Lazerowitz M., (1964) Studies in Metaphilosphy, London: Routledge
  • Overgaard, S, Gilbert, P., Burwood, S. (2013) An Introduction to Metaphilosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
  • Rescher N., (2006), Philosophical Dialectics, an Essay on Metaphilosophy, Albany: State University of New York Press
  • Rescher, Nicholas (2001). Philosophical Reasoning. A Study in the Methodology of Philosophizing. Blackwell.
  • Williamson T., (2007) The Philosophy of Philosophy, London: Blackwell
  • Wittgenstein Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. David Pears and Brian McGuinness (1961), Routledge, hardcover: ISBN 0-7100-3004-5, 1974 paperback: ISBN 0-415-02825-6, 2001 hardcover: ISBN 0-415-25562-7, 2001 paperback: ISBN 0-415-25408-6;
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig (2001). Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 978-0-631-23127-1.

External links edit

metaphilosophy, this, article, about, philosophical, term, journal, journal, sometimes, called, philosophy, philosophy, investigation, nature, philosophy, subject, matter, includes, aims, philosophy, boundaries, philosophy, methods, thus, while, philosophy, ch. This article is about the philosophical term For the journal see Metaphilosophy journal Metaphilosophy sometimes called the philosophy of philosophy is the investigation of the nature of philosophy 1 Its subject matter includes the aims of philosophy the boundaries of philosophy and its methods 2 3 Thus while philosophy characteristically inquires into the nature of being the reality of objects the possibility of knowledge the nature of truth and so on metaphilosophy is the self reflective inquiry into the nature aims and methods of the activity that makes these kinds of inquiries by asking what is philosophy itself what sorts of questions it should ask how it might pose and answer them and what it can achieve in doing so It is considered by some to be a subject prior and preparatory to philosophy 4 while others see it as inherently a part of philosophy 5 or automatically a part of philosophy 6 while others adopt some combination of these views 2 The interest in metaphilosophy led to the establishment of the journal Metaphilosophy in January 1970 7 Many sub disciplines of philosophy have their own branch of metaphilosophy examples being meta aesthetics meta epistemology meta ethics and metametaphysics meta ontology 8 Although the term metaphilosophy and explicit attention to metaphilosophy as a specific domain within philosophy arose in the 20th century the topic is likely as old as philosophy itself and can be traced back at least as far as the works of Ancient Greeks and Ancient Indian Nyaya 9 Contents 1 Relationship to philosophy 2 Terminology 3 Writings 4 Topics 4 1 Aims 4 2 Boundaries 4 3 Methods 4 4 Progress 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksRelationship to philosophy editSome philosophers consider metaphilosophy to be a subject apart from philosophy above or beyond it 4 while others object to that idea 5 Timothy Williamson argues that the philosophy of philosophy is automatically part of philosophy as is the philosophy of anything else 6 Nicholas Bunnin and Jiyuan Yu write that the separation of first from second order study has lost popularity as philosophers find it hard to observe the distinction 10 As evidenced by these contrasting opinions debate persists as to whether the evaluation of the nature of philosophy is second order philosophy or simply plain philosophy Many philosophers have expressed doubts over the value of metaphilosophy 11 Among them is Gilbert Ryle preoccupation with questions about methods tends to distract us from prosecuting the methods themselves We run as a rule worse not better if we think a lot about our feet So let us not speak of it all but just do it 12 Terminology editThe designations metaphilosophy and philosophy of philosophy have a variety of meanings sometimes taken to be synonyms and sometimes seen as distinct Morris Lazerowitz claims to have coined the term metaphilosophy around 1940 and used it in print in 1942 1 Lazerowitz proposed that metaphilosophy is the investigation of the nature of philosophy 1 Earlier uses have been found in translations from French 13 The term is derived from Greek word meta meta after beyond with and philosophia filosofia love of wisdom The term metaphilosophy is used by Paul Moser 14 in the sense of a second order or more fundamental undertaking than philosophy itself in the manner suggested by Charles Griswold 4 The distinction between philosophy and metaphilosophy has an analogue in the familiar distinction between mathematics and metamathematics 14 Paul K Moser Metaphilosophy p 562 Some other philosophers treat the prefix meta as simply meaning about rather than as referring to a metatheoretical second order form of philosophy among them Rescher 15 and Double 16 Others such as Williamson prefer the term philosophy of philosophy instead of metaphilosophy as it avoids the connotation of a second order discipline that looks down on philosophy and instead denotes something that is a part of it 17 Joll suggests that to take metaphilosophy as the application of the methods of philosophy to philosophy itself is too vague while the view that sees metaphilosophy as a second order or more abstract discipline outside philosophy is narrow and tendentious 18 In the analytic tradition the term metaphilosophy is mostly used to tag commenting and research on previous works as opposed to original contributions towards solving philosophical problems 19 Writings editLudwig Wittgenstein wrote about the nature of philosophical puzzles and philosophical understanding He suggested philosophical errors arose from confusions about the nature of philosophical inquiry C D Broad distinguished Critical from Speculative philosophy in his The Subject matter of Philosophy and its Relations to the special Sciences in Introduction to Scientific Thought 1923 Curt Ducasse in Philosophy as a Science examines several views of the nature of philosophy and concludes that philosophy has a distinct subject matter appraisals Ducasse s view has been among the first to be described as metaphilosophy 20 Henri Lefebvre in Metaphilosophie 1965 argued from a Marxian standpoint in favor of an ontological break as a necessary methodological approach for critical social theory whilst criticizing Louis Althusser s epistemological break with subjective Marxism which represented a fundamental theoretical tool for the school of Marxist structuralism Paul Moser writes that typical metaphilosophical discussion includes determining the conditions under which a claim can be said to be a philosophical one He regards meta ethics the study of ethics to be a form of metaphilosophy as well as meta epistemology the study of epistemology 14 Topics editMany sub disciplines of philosophy have their own branch of metaphilosophy 8 However some topics within metaphilosophy cut across the various subdivisions of philosophy to consider fundamentals important to all its sub disciplines Aims edit Some philosophers e g existentialists pragmatists think philosophy is ultimately a practical discipline that should help us lead meaningful lives by showing us who we are how we relate to the world around us and what we should do citation needed Others e g analytic philosophers see philosophy as a technical formal and entirely theoretical discipline with goals such as the disinterested pursuit of knowledge for its own sake 21 Other proposed goals of philosophy include discovering the absolutely fundamental reason of everything it investigates making explicit the nature and significance of ordinary and scientific beliefs 22 and unifying and transcending the insights given by science and religion 23 Others proposed that philosophy is a complex discipline because it has 4 or 6 different dimensions 24 25 Boundaries edit Main article Definitions of philosophy Defining philosophy and its boundaries is itself problematic Nigel Warburton has called it notoriously difficult 26 There is no straightforward definition 23 and most interesting definitions are controversial 27 As Bertrand Russell wrote We may note one peculiar feature of philosophy If someone asks the question what is mathematics we can give him a dictionary definition let us say the science of number for the sake of argument As far as it goes this is an uncontroversial statement Definitions may be given in this way of any field where a body of definite knowledge exists But philosophy cannot be so defined Any definition is controversial and already embodies a philosophic attitude The only way to find out what philosophy is is to do philosophy 28 Bertrand Russell The Wisdom of the West p 7 While there is some agreement that philosophy involves general or fundamental topics 21 29 there is no clear agreement about a series of demarcation issues including that between first order and second order investigations Some authors say that philosophical inquiry is second order having concepts theories and presupposition as its subject matter that it is thinking about thinking of a generally second order character 30 that philosophers study rather than use the concepts that structure our thinking However the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy warns that the borderline between such second order reflection and ways of practicing the first order discipline itself is not always clear philosophical problems may be tamed by the advance of a discipline and the conduct of a discipline may be swayed by philosophical reflection 29 that between philosophy and empirical science Some argue that philosophy is distinct from science in that its questions cannot be answered empirically that is by observation or experiment 31 32 Some analytical philosophers argue that all meaningful empirical questions are to be answered by science not philosophy However some schools of contemporary philosophy such as the pragmatists and naturalistic epistemologists argue that philosophy should be linked to science and should be scientific in the broad sense of that term preferring to see philosophical reflection as continuous with the best practice of any field of intellectual enquiry 29 that between philosophy and religion Some argue that philosophy is distinct from religion in that it allows no place for faith or revelation 21 that philosophy does not try to answer questions by appeal to revelation myth or religious knowledge of any kind but uses reason without reference to sensible observation and experiments However philosophers and theologians such as Thomas Aquinas and Peter Damian have argued that philosophy is the handmaiden of theology ancilla theologiae 33 Methods edit Main article Philosophical method Philosophical method or philosophical methodology is the study of how to do philosophy A common view among philosophers is that philosophy is distinguished by the ways that philosophers follow in addressing philosophical questions There is not just one method that philosophers use to answer philosophical questions C D Broad classifies philosophy into two methods he distinguished between critical philosophy and speculative philosophy He described critical philosophy as analysing unanalysed concepts in daily life and in science and then expos ing them to every objection that we can think of While speculative philosophy s role is to take over all aspects of human experience to reflect upon them and to try to think out a view of Reality as a whole which shall do justice to all of them 34 Recently some philosophers have cast doubt about intuition as a basic tool in philosophical inquiry from Socrates up to contemporary philosophy of language In Rethinking Intuition 35 various thinkers discard intuition as a valid source of knowledge and thereby call into question a priori philosophy Experimental philosophy is a form of philosophical inquiry that makes at least partial use of empirical research especially opinion polling in order to address persistent philosophical questions This is in contrast with the methods found in analytic philosophy whereby some say a philosopher will sometimes begin by appealing to his or her intuitions on an issue and then form an argument with those intuitions as premises However disagreement about what experimental philosophy can accomplish is widespread and several philosophers have offered criticisms One claim is that the empirical data gathered by experimental philosophers can have an indirect effect on philosophical questions by allowing for a better understanding of the underlying psychological processes which lead to philosophical intuitions 36 Some analytic philosophers like Timothy Williamson 37 have rejected such a move against armchair philosophy i e philosophical inquiry that is undergirded by intuition by construing intuition which they believe to be a misnomer as merely referring to common cognitive faculties If one is calling into question intuition one is they would say harboring a skeptical attitude towards common cognitive faculties a consequence that seems philosophically unappealing For Williamson instances of intuition are instances of our cognitive faculties processing counterfactuals 38 or subjunctive conditionals that are specific to the thought experiment or example in question Progress edit A prominent question in metaphilosophy is that of whether or not philosophical progress occurs and more so whether such progress in philosophy is even possible 39 David Chalmers divides inquiry into philosophical progress in metaphilosophy into three questions The Existence Question is there progress in philosophy The Comparison Question is there as much progress in philosophy as in science The Explanation Question why isn t there more progress in philosophy 40 Ludwig Wittgenstein in Culture and Value remarked Philosophy hasn t made any progress If somebody scratches the spot where he has an itch do we have to see some progress And can t this reaction to an irritation continue in the same way for a long time before the cure for an itching is discovered 41 According to Hilary Putnam philosophy is more adept at showing people that specific ideas or arguments are wrong than that specific ideas or arguments are right 42 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Religion portal nbsp Science portal Antiphilosophy Metacognition Metatheory Meta knowledge Metaphysics Metapolitics Metasemantics Non philosophy Unsolved problems in philosophy Theory of everything philosophy References edit a b c Lazerowitz M 1970 A note on metaphilosophy Metaphilosophy 1 1 91 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9973 1970 tb00792 x see also the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy article by Nicholas Joll Contemporary Metaphilosophy a b Nicholas Joll November 18 2010 Contemporary Metaphilosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy IEP Armen T Marsoobian 2004 Metaphilosophy In John Lachs Robert Talisse eds American Philosophy An Encyclopedia pp 500 501 ISBN 978 0203492796 Its primary question is What is philosophy a b c See for example Charles L Griswold Jr 2010 Platonic Writings Platonic Readings Penn State Press pp 144 146 ISBN 978 0271044811 a b Martin Heidegger 1956 Was Ist Das die Philosophie Rowman amp Littlefield p 21 ISBN 978 0808403197 a b Timothy Williamson 2008 Preface The Philosophy of Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons p ix ISBN 978 0470695913 The philosophy of philosophy is automatically part of philosophy just as the philosophy of anything else is The journal describes its scope as Particular areas of interest include the foundation scope function and direction of philosophy justification of philosophical methods and arguments the interrelations among schools or fields of philosophy for example the relation of logic to problems in ethics or epistemology aspects of philosophical systems presuppositions of philosophical schools the relation of philosophy to other disciplines for example artificial intelligence linguistics or literature sociology of philosophy the relevance of philosophy to social and political action issues in the teaching of philosophy a b Robert S Hartman 1995 Axiology as a science In Rem B Edwards ed Formal Axiology and Its Critics Rodopi p 21 ISBN 978 9051839104 Nicholas Joll Metaphilosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Nicholas Bunnin amp Jiyuan Yu 2009 Metaphilosophy The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy Wiley Blackwell pp 426 427 ISBN 978 1405191128 Soren Overgaard Paul Gilbert Stephen Burwood 2013 Introduction What good is metaphilosophy An introduction to metaphilosophy Cambridge University Press p 6 ISBN 978 0521193412 Gilbert Ryle 2009 Chapter 23 Ordinary language Collected Essays 1929 1968 Collected Papers Volume 2 Reprint of Hutchinson 1971 ed Routledge p 331 ISBN 978 0415485494 Quoted by Soren Overgaard Paul Gilbert Stephen Burwood 2013 Introduction What good is metaphilosophy An introduction to metaphilosophy Cambridge University Press p 6 ISBN 978 0521193412 e g Clemenceau G In the evening of my thought Au soir de la pensee Paris Plon 1927 Houghton Mifflin company 1929 Vol 2 p 498 this teratological product of metaphilosophy Gilson E Christianity and philosophy Pub for the Institute of Mediaeval Studies by Sheed amp Ward 1939 p 88 a b c Paul K Moser 2008 Metaphilosophy In Robert Audi ed The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Paperback reprint of 2nd ed Paw Prints 2008 06 26 pp 561 562 ISBN 978 1439503508 Rescher N 2007 Chapter 1 Philosophical principles Philosophical Dialectics an Essay on Metaphilosophy State University of New York Press p 1 ISBN 978 0791467466 Richard Double 1996 Metaphilosophy and Free Will Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0195355413 Williamson Timothy 2007 Preface The Philosophy of Philosophy Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 1405133968 Nicholas Joll November 18 2010 Contemporary Metaphysics Defining metaphilosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy e g PhilPapers Dommeyer F 1961 A Critical Examination of C J Ducasse s Metaphilosophy Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 21 Jun 1961 No 4 pp 439 455 a b c Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy 2005 Collins English Dictionary a b Mastering Philosophy by Anthony Harrison Barbet 1990 page needed Adler Mortimer 1993 The Four Dimensions of Philosophy Metaphysical Moral Objective Categorical Vidal Clement 2012 Metaphilosophical Criteria for Worldview Comparison PDF Metaphilosophy 43 3 306 347 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 508 631 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9973 2012 01749 x Nigel Warburton 2003 Philosophy The Basics 3rd ed CRC Press p 1 ISBN 978 0203202029 The Rt Hon Lord Quinton 2005 Philosophy In Ted Honderich ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy 2nd ed Oxford University Press p 702 ISBN 978 0199264797 Bertrand Russell 1959 The Wisdom of the West A Historical Survey of Western Philosophy in Its Social and Political Setting Doubleday p 7 a b c Simon Blackburn 2005 Philosophy Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy 2nd ed pp 276 7 ISBN 978 0198610137 Ted Honderich ed 2005 Conceptual analysis Oxford Companion to Philosophy New Edition 2nd ed Oxford University Press USA p 154 ISBN 978 0199264797 Insofar as conceptual analysis is the method of philosophy as it was widely held to be for much of the twentieth century philosophy is a second order subject because it is about language not the world or what language is about Sara Heinamaa 2006 Phenomenology A foundational science In Margaret A Simons ed The Philosophy of Simone De Beauvoir Critical Essays Indiana University Press p 22 ISBN 978 0253218407 The important difference between the scientist and the philosopher is in the radically critical nature of philosophy Husserl characterizes this difference by saying that the task of philosophy is to ask the ultimate questions The philosophical questions can not be answered in the same way that empirical questions can be answered Richard Tieszen 2008 Science as a triumph of the human spirit and science in crisis Husserl and the fortunes of reason In Gary Gutting ed Continental Philosophy of Science John Wiley amp Sons p 94 ISBN 978 1405137447 The sciences are in need of continual epistemological reflection and critique of a sort that only the philosopher can provide Husserl pictures the work of the philosopher and the scientist as mutually complementary Gracia J G and Noone T B A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages London Blackwell 2003 p 35 Broad C D 1953 Critical and Speculative Philosophy Contemporary British Philosophy Personal Statements Volume 20 London Allen amp Unwin pp 87 100 Rethinking Intuition The Psychology of Intuition and its Role in Philosophical Inquiry Studies in Epistemology and Cognitive Theory by Michael DePaul William Ramsey Editors Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers Inc 1998 ISBN 0 8476 8796 1 ISBN 978 0 8476 8796 1 Knobe J and Nichols S eds 2008 Experimental Philosophy 2 1 OCLC 233792562 Williamson Timothy 2016 04 29 Philosophical Criticisms of Experimental Philosophy A Companion to Experimental Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons Ltd pp 22 36 doi 10 1002 9781118661666 ch2 ISBN 9781118661666 Pust Joel 2019 Intuition in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2020 01 18 Dietrich Eric 2011 There Is No Progress in Philosophy Archived 2021 03 02 at the Wayback Machine Essays in Philosophy 12 2 9 Chalmers David 2015 Why Isn t There More Progress in Philosophy PDF Philosophy 90 1 3 31 doi 10 1017 S0031819114000436 hdl 1885 57201 S2CID 170974260 Retrieved 18 December 2017 Hutto D 2003 Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy Neither Theory Nor Therapy Palgrave Macmillan p 218 Putnam Hilary 1995 Renewing Philosophy Harvard University Press p 134 Further reading editDouble R 1996 Metaphilosophy and Free Will Oxford University Press USA ISBN 0 19 510762 4 ISBN 978 0 19 510762 3 Ducasse C J 1941 Philosophy as a Science Its Matter and Its Method Lazerowitz M 1964 Studies in Metaphilosphy London Routledge Overgaard S Gilbert P Burwood S 2013 An Introduction to Metaphilosophy Cambridge Cambridge University Press Rescher N 2006 Philosophical Dialectics an Essay on Metaphilosophy Albany State University of New York Press Rescher Nicholas 2001 Philosophical Reasoning A Study in the Methodology of Philosophizing Blackwell Williamson T 2007 The Philosophy of Philosophy London Blackwell Wittgenstein Ludwig Tractatus Logico Philosophicus trans David Pears and Brian McGuinness 1961 Routledge hardcover ISBN 0 7100 3004 5 1974 paperback ISBN 0 415 02825 6 2001 hardcover ISBN 0 415 25562 7 2001 paperback ISBN 0 415 25408 6 Philosophische Untersuchungen 1953 or Philosophical Investigations translated by G E M Anscombe 1953 Wittgenstein Ludwig 2001 Philosophical Investigations Blackwell Publishing ISBN 978 0 631 23127 1 External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Metaphilosophy Metaphilosophy at PhilPapers Joll Micholas Metaphilosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphilosophy journal published by Blackwell Metaphilosophy at Curlie Zalta Edward N ed Lvov Warsaw School Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Peter Suber Metaphilosophy Themes and Questions A Personal List Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Metaphilosophy amp oldid 1217571615, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.