fbpx
Wikipedia

Transformational grammar

In linguistics, transformational grammar (TG) or transformational-generative grammar (TGG) is part of the theory of generative grammar, especially of natural languages. It considers grammar to be a system of rules that generate exactly those combinations of words that form grammatical sentences in a given language and involves the use of defined operations (called transformations) to produce new sentences from existing ones. The method is commonly associated with American linguist Noam Chomsky.

Generative algebra was first introduced to general linguistics by the structural linguist Louis Hjelmslev[1] although the method was described before him by Albert Sechehaye in 1908.[2] Chomsky adopted the concept of transformations from his teacher Zellig Harris, who followed the American descriptivist separation of semantics from syntax. Hjelmslev's structuralist conception including semantics and pragmatics is incorporated into functional grammar.[3]

Historical context

Transformational analysis is a part of the classical Western grammatical tradition based on the metaphysics of Plato and Aristotle and on the grammar of Apollonius Dyscolus. These were joined to establish linguistics as a natural science in the Middle Ages. Transformational analysis was later developed by humanistic grammarians such as Thomas Linacre (1524), Julius Caesar Scaliger (1540), and Sanctius (Francisco Sánchez de las Brozas, 1587). The core observation is that grammatical rules alone do not constitute elegance, so learning to use a language correctly requires certain additional effects such as ellipsis. It is more desirable, for example, to say "Maggie and Alex went to the market" than to express the full underlying idea "Maggie went to the market and Alex went to the market". Such phenomena were described in terms of understood elements. In modern terminology, the first expression is the surface structure of the second, and the second expression is the deep structure of the first. The notions of ellipsis and restoration are complementary: the deep structure is converted into the surface structure and restored from it by what were later known as transformational rules.[4]

It was generally agreed that a degree of simplicity improves the quality of speech and writing, but closer inspection of the deep structures of different types of sentences led to many further insights, such as the concept of agent and patient in active and passive sentences. Transformations were given an explanatory role. Sanctius, among others, argued that surface structures pertaining to the choice of grammatical case in certain Latin expressions could not be understood without the restoration of the deep structure. His full transformational system included

  1. ellipsis, the deletion of understood semantic or syntactic elements;
  2. pleonasm, the occurrence of syntactically superfluous elements;
  3. syllepsis, the violation of a rule of agreement;
  4. hyperbaton, the violation of normal word order.[5]

Transformational analysis fell out of favor with the rise of historical-comparative linguistics in the 19th century, and the historical linguist Ferdinand de Saussure argued for limiting linguistic analysis to the surface structure.[6] By contrast, Edmund Husserl, in his 1921 elaboration of the 17th-century Port-Royal Grammar, based his version of generative grammar on classical transformations (Modifikationen).[7] Husserl's concept influenced Roman Jakobson, who advocated it in the Prague linguistic circle, which was likewise influenced by Saussure.[8] Based on opposition theory, Jakobson developed his theory of markedness and, having moved to the United States, influenced Noam Chomsky, especially through Morris Halle. Chomsky and his colleagues, including Jerrold Katz and Jerry Fodor, developed what they called transformational generative grammar in the 1960s.[9][10]

The transformational grammar of the 1960s differs from the Renaissance linguistics in its relation to the theory of language. While the humanistic grammarians considered language manmade, Chomsky and his colleagues exploited markedness and transformation theory in their attempt to uncover innate grammar.[11] It would be later clarified that such grammar arises from a brain structure caused by a mutation in humans.[12] In particular, generative linguists tried to reconstruct the underlying innate structure based on deep structure and unmarked forms. Thus, a modern notion of universal grammar, in contrast to the humanistic classics, suggested that the basic word order of biological grammar is unmarked, and unmodified in transformational terms.[13][14]

Transformational generative grammar included two kinds of rules: phrase-structure rules and transformational rules. But scholars abandoned the project in the 1970s. Based on Chomsky's concept of I-language as the proper subject of linguistics as a cognitive science, Katz and Fodor had conducted their research on English grammar employing introspection. These findings could not be generalized cross-linguistically whereby they could not belong to an innate universal grammar.[15]

The concept of transformation was nevertheless not fully rejected. In Chomsky's 1990s Minimalist Program, transformations pertain to the lexicon and the move operation.[15] This more lenient approach offers more prospects of universalizability. It is, for example, argued that the English SVO word-order (subject, verb, object) represents the initial state of the cognitive language faculty. However, in languages like Classical Arabic, which has a basic VSO order, sentences are automatically transformed by the move operation from the underlying SVO order on which the matrix of all sentences in all languages is reconstructed. Therefore, there is no longer a need for a separate surface and deep matrix and additional rules of conversion between the two levels. According to Chomsky, this solution allows sufficient descriptive and explanatory adequacy—descriptive because all languages are analyzed on the same matrix, and explanatory because the analysis shows in which particular way the sentence is derived from the (hypothesized) initial cognitive state.[16][15]

Basic mechanisms

Deep structure and surface structure

While Chomsky's 1957 book Syntactic Structures followed Harris's distributionalistic practice of excluding semantics from structural analysis, his 1965 book Aspects of the Theory of Syntax developed the idea that each sentence in a language has two levels of representation: a deep structure and a surface structure.[17][18] But these are not quite identical to Hjelmslev's content plane and expression plane.[1] The deep structure represents the core semantic relations of a sentence and is mapped onto the surface structure, which follows the phonological form of the sentence very closely, via transformations. The concept of transformations had been proposed before the development of deep structure to increase the mathematical and descriptive power of context-free grammars. Deep structure was developed largely for technical reasons related to early semantic theory. Chomsky emphasized the importance of modern formal mathematical devices in the development of grammatical theory:

But the fundamental reason for [the] inadequacy of traditional grammars is a more technical one. Although it was well understood that linguistic processes are in some sense "creative," the technical devices for expressing a system of recursive processes were simply not available until much more recently. In fact, a real understanding of how a language can (in Humboldt's words) "make infinite use of finite means" has developed only within the last thirty years, in the course of studies in the foundations of mathematics.

— Aspects of the Theory of Syntax

Transformations

The usual usage of the term "transformation" in linguistics refers to a rule that takes an input, typically called the deep structure (in the Standard Theory) or D-structure (in the extended standard theory or government and binding theory), and changes it in some restricted way to result in a surface structure (or S-structure). In TG, phrase structure rules generate deep structures. For example, a typical transformation in TG is subject-auxiliary inversion (SAI). That rule takes as its input a declarative sentence with an auxiliary, such as "John has eaten all the heirloom tomatoes", and transforms it into "Has John eaten all the heirloom tomatoes?" In the original formulation (Chomsky 1957), those rules were stated as rules that held over strings of terminals, constituent symbols or both.

X NP AUX Y   X AUX NP Y

(NP = Noun Phrase and AUX = Auxiliary)

In the 1970s, by the time of the Extended Standard Theory, following Joseph Emonds's work on structure preservation, transformations came to be viewed as holding over trees. By the end of government and binding theory, in the late 1980s, transformations were no longer structure-changing operations at all; instead, they add information to already existing trees by copying constituents.

The earliest conceptions of transformations were that they were construction-specific devices. For example, there was a transformation that turned active sentences into passive ones. A different transformation raised embedded subjects into main clause subject position in sentences such as "John seems to have gone", and a third reordered arguments in the dative alternation. With the shift from rules to principles and constraints in the 1970s, those construction-specific transformations morphed into general rules (all the examples just mentioned are instances of NP movement), which eventually changed into the single general rule move alpha or Move.

Transformations actually come in two types: the post-deep structure kind mentioned above, which are string- or structure-changing, and generalized transformations (GTs). GTs were originally proposed in the earliest forms of generative grammar (such as in Chomsky 1957). They take small structures, either atomic or generated by other rules, and combine them. For example, the generalized transformation of embedding would take the kernel "Dave said X" and the kernel "Dan likes smoking" and combine them into "Dave said Dan likes smoking." GTs are thus structure-building rather than structure-changing. In the Extended Standard Theory and government and binding theory, GTs were abandoned in favor of recursive phrase structure rules, but they are still present in tree-adjoining grammar as the Substitution and Adjunction operations, and have recently reemerged in mainstream generative grammar in Minimalism, as the operations Merge and Move.

In generative phonology, another form of transformation is the phonological rule, which describes a mapping between an underlying representation (the phoneme) and the surface form that is articulated during natural speech.[19]

Formal definition

Chomsky's advisor, Zellig Harris, took transformations to be relations between sentences such as "I finally met this talkshow host you always detested" and simpler (kernel) sentences "I finally met this talkshow host" and "You always detested this talkshow host."[need quotation to verify] A transformational-generative (or simply transformational) grammar thus involved two types of productive rules: phrase structure rules, such as "S → NP VP" (a sentence may consist of a noun phrase followed by a verb phrase) etc., which could be used to generate grammatical sentences with associated parse trees (phrase markers, or P markers); and transformational rules, such as rules for converting statements to questions or active to passive voice, which acted on the phrase markers to produce other grammatically correct sentences. Hjelmslev had called word-order conversion rules "permutations".[20]

In this context, transformational rules are not strictly necessary to generate the set of grammatical sentences in a language, since that can be done using phrase structure rules alone, but the use of transformations provides economy in some cases (the number of rules can be reduced), and it also provides a way of representing the grammatical relations between sentences, which would not be reflected in a system with phrase structure rules alone.[21]

This notion of transformation proved adequate for subsequent versions, including the "extended", "revised extended", and Government-Binding (GB) versions of generative grammar, but it may no longer be sufficient for minimalist grammar, as merge may require a formal definition that goes beyond the tree manipulation characteristic of Move α.

Mathematical representation

An important feature of all transformational grammars is that they are more powerful than context-free grammars.[22] Chomsky formalized this idea in the Chomsky hierarchy. He argued that it is impossible to describe the structure of natural languages with context-free grammars.[23] His general position on the non-context-freeness of natural language has held up since then, though his specific examples of the inadequacy of CFGs in terms of their weak generative capacity were disproved.[24][25]

Core concepts

Innate linguistic knowledge

Using a term such as "transformation" may give the impression that theories of transformational generative grammar are intended as a model of the processes by which the human mind constructs and understands sentences, but Chomsky clearly stated that a generative grammar models only the knowledge that underlies the human ability to speak and understand, arguing that because most of that knowledge is innate, a baby can have a large body of knowledge about the structure of language in general and so need to learn only the idiosyncratic features of the language(s) to which it is exposed.[citation needed]

Chomsky is not the first person to suggest that all languages have certain fundamental things in common. He quoted philosophers who posited the same basic idea several centuries ago. But Chomsky helped make the innateness theory respectable after a period dominated by more behaviorist attitudes towards language. He made concrete and technically sophisticated proposals about the structure of language as well as important proposals about how grammatical theories' success should be evaluated.[26]

Grammaticality

Chomsky argued that "grammatical" and "ungrammatical" can be meaningfully and usefully defined. In contrast, an extreme behaviorist linguist would argue that language can be studied only through recordings or transcriptions of actual speech and that the role of the linguist is to look for patterns in such observed speech, not to hypothesize about why such patterns might occur or to label particular utterances grammatical or ungrammatical. Few linguists in the 1950s actually took such an extreme position, but Chomsky was on the opposite extreme, defining grammaticality in an unusually mentalistic way for the time.[27] He argued that the intuition of a native speaker is enough to define the grammaticality of a sentence; that is, if a particular string of English words elicits a double-take or a feeling of wrongness in a native English speaker, with various extraneous factors affecting intuitions controlled for, it can be said that the string of words is ungrammatical. That, according to Chomsky, is entirely distinct from the question of whether a sentence is meaningful or can be understood. It is possible for a sentence to be both grammatical and meaningless, as in Chomsky's famous example, "colorless green ideas sleep furiously".[28] But such sentences manifest a linguistic problem that is distinct from that posed by meaningful but ungrammatical (non)-sentences such as "man the bit sandwich the", the meaning of which is fairly clear, but which no native speaker would accept as well-formed.

The use of such intuitive judgments permitted generative syntacticians to base their research on a methodology in which studying language through a corpus of observed speech became downplayed since the grammatical properties of constructed sentences were considered appropriate data on which to build a grammatical model.

Theory evaluation

In the 1960s, Chomsky introduced two central ideas relevant to the construction and evaluation of grammatical theories.

Competence versus performance

One was the distinction between competence and performance.[29] Chomsky noted the obvious fact that when people speak in the real world, they often make linguistic errors, such as starting a sentence and then abandoning it midway through. He argued that such errors in linguistic performance are irrelevant to the study of linguistic competence, the knowledge that allows people to construct and understand grammatical sentences. Consequently, the linguist can study an idealised version of language, which greatly simplifies linguistic analysis.

Descriptive versus explanatory adequacy

The other idea related directly to evaluation of theories of grammar. Chomsky distinguished between grammars that achieve descriptive adequacy and those that go further and achieve explanatory adequacy. A descriptively adequate grammar for a particular language defines the (infinite) set of grammatical sentences in that language; that is, it describes the language in its entirety. A grammar that achieves explanatory adequacy has the additional property that it gives insight into the mind's underlying linguistic structures. In other words, it does not merely describe the grammar of a language, but makes predictions about how linguistic knowledge is mentally represented. For Chomsky, such mental representations are largely innate and so if a grammatical theory has explanatory adequacy, it must be able to explain different languages' grammatical nuances as relatively minor variations in the universal pattern of human language.

Chomsky argued that even though linguists were still a long way from constructing descriptively adequate grammars, progress in descriptive adequacy would come only if linguists held explanatory adequacy as their goal: real insight into individual languages' structure can be gained only by comparative study of a wide range of languages, on the assumption that they are all cut from the same cloth.[citation needed]

Development of concepts

Though transformations continue to be important in Chomsky's theories, he has now abandoned the original notion of deep structure and surface structure. Initially, two additional levels of representation were introduced—logical form (LF) and phonetic form (PF), but in the 1990s, Chomsky sketched a new program of research known at first as Minimalism, in which deep structure and surface structure are no longer featured and PF and LF remain as the only levels of representation.[30]

To complicate the understanding of the development of Chomsky's theories, the precise meanings of deep structure and surface structure have changed over time. By the 1970s, Chomskyan linguists normally called them D-Structure and S-Structure. In particular, Chomskyan linguists dropped for good the idea that a sentence's deep structure determined its meaning (taken to its logical conclusions by generative semanticists during the same period) when LF took over this role (previously, Chomsky and Ray Jackendoff had begun to argue that both deep and surface structure determined meaning).[31][32]

"I-language" and "E-language"

In 1986, Chomsky proposed a distinction between I-language and E-language that is similar but not identical to the competence/performance distinction.[33] "I-language" is internal language; "E-language" is external language. I-language is taken to be the object of study in linguistic theory; it is the mentally represented linguistic knowledge a native speaker of a language has and thus a mental object. From that perspective, most of theoretical linguistics is a branch of psychology. E-language encompasses all other notions of what a language is, such as a body of knowledge or behavioural habits shared by a community. Thus E-language is not a coherent concept by itself,[34] and Chomsky argues that such notions of language are not useful in the study of innate linguistic knowledge or competence even though they may seem sensible and intuitive and useful in other areas of study. Competence, he argues, can be studied only if languages are treated as mental objects.

Minimalist program

From the mid-1990s onward, much research in transformational grammar has been inspired by Chomsky's minimalist program.[35] It aims to further develop ideas involving "economy of derivation" and "economy of representation", which had started to become significant in the early 1990s but were still rather peripheral aspects of transformational-generative grammar theory:

  • Economy of derivation is the principle that movements, or transformations, occur only to match interpretable features with uninterpretable features. An example of an interpretable feature is the plural inflection on regular English nouns, e.g., dogs. The word dogs can be used to refer only to several dogs, not a single dog, and so the inflection contributes to meaning by making it interpretable. English verbs are inflected according to the number of their subject ("Dogs bite" v. "A dog bites"), but in most sentences, that inflection just duplicates the information about number that the subject noun already has, and the inflection is therefore uninterpretable.
  • Economy of representation is the principle that grammatical structures must exist for a purpose: the structure of a sentence should be no larger or more complex than required to satisfy constraints on grammaticality.

Both notions, as described here, are somewhat vague, and their precise formulation is controversial.[36][37] An additional aspect of minimalist thought is the idea that the derivation of syntactic structures should be uniform: rules should not be stipulated as applying at arbitrary points in a derivation but instead apply throughout derivations. Minimalist approaches to phrase structure have resulted in "Bare Phrase Structure", an attempt to eliminate X-bar theory. In 1998, Chomsky suggested that derivations proceed in phases. The distinction between deep structure and surface structure is absent in Minimalist theories of syntax, and the most recent phase-based theories also eliminate LF and PF as unitary levels of representation.

Critical reception

In 1978, linguist and historian E. F. K. Koerner hailed transformational grammar as the third and last Kuhnian revolution in linguistics, arguing that it had brought about a shift from Ferdinand de Saussure's sociological approach to a Chomskyan conception of linguistics as analogous to chemistry and physics. Koerner also praised the philosophical and psychological value of Chomsky's theory.[38]

In 1983 Koerner retracted his earlier statement suggesting that transformational grammar was a 1960s fad that had spread across the U.S. at a time when the federal government had invested heavily in new linguistic departments. But he claims Chomsky's work is unoriginal when compared to other syntactic models of the time. According to Koerner, Chomsky's rise to fame was orchestrated by Bernard Bloch, editor of Language, the journal of the Linguistic Society of America, and Roman Jakobson, a personal friend of Chomsky's father. Koerner suggests that great sums of money were spent to fly foreign students to the 1962 International Congress at Harvard, where an exceptional opportunity was arranged for Chomsky to give a keynote speech making questionable claims of belonging to the rationalist tradition of Saussure, Humboldt and the Port-Royal Grammar, in order to win popularity among the Europeans. The transformational agenda was subsequently forced through at American conferences where students, instructed by Chomsky, regularly verbally attacked and ridiculed his potential opponents.[39]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b Seuren, Pieter A. M. (1998). Western linguistics: An historical introduction. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 0-631-20891-7.
  2. ^ Seuren, Pieter (2018). Saussure and Sechehaye: Myth and Genius. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-37815-5.
  3. ^ Butler, Christopher S. (2003). Structure and Function: A Guide to Three Major Structural-Functional Theories, part 1 (PDF). John Benjamins. ISBN 9781588113580. Retrieved 2020-01-19.
  4. ^ Percival, William Keith (1976). "Deep and surface structure concepts in renaissance and mediaeval syntactic theory". In Parret (ed.). History of Linguistic Thought and Contemporary Linguistics. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 238–253.
  5. ^ Percival, William Keith (1976). "Deep and surface structure concepts in renaissance and mediaeval syntactic theory". In Parret (ed.). History of Linguistic Thought and Contemporary Linguistics. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 238–253.
  6. ^ de Saussure, Ferdinand (1959) [First published 1916]. (PDF). New York: Philosophy Library. ISBN 9780231157278. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-04-14. Retrieved 2022-08-08.
  7. ^ Bianchin, Matteo (2018). "Husserl on Meaning, Grammar, and the Structure of Content" (PDF). Husserl Studies. 34 (2): 101–121. doi:10.1007/s10743-017-9223-2. S2CID 254553890. Retrieved 2022-08-08.
  8. ^ Holenstein, Elmar (2018). "Jakobson und Husserl: Ein beitrag zur genealogie Des strukturalismus" (PDF). Tijdschrift voor Filosofie. 35 (3): 560–607. JSTOR 40882437. Retrieved 2022-08-08.
  9. ^ Battistella, Edwin (2015). "Markedness in Linguistics". In Wright, James D. (ed.). International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences (2nd ed.). Elsevier. pp. 533–537. doi:10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.52037-6. ISBN 978-0-08-097087-5.
  10. ^ Partee, Barbara (2011). "Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact". The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication. Vol. 6. BIYCLC. pp. 1–52. doi:10.4148/biyclc.v6i0.1580.
  11. ^ Percival, William Keith (1976). "Deep and surface structure concepts in renaissance and mediaeval syntactic theory". In Parret (ed.). History of Linguistic Thought and Contemporary Linguistics. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 238–253.
  12. ^ de Boer, Bart; Thompson, Bill; Ravigniani, Andrea; Boeckx, Cedric (2020). "Evolutionary Dynamics Do Not Motivate a Single-Mutant Theory of Human Language". Scientific Reports. 10 (451). doi:10.1038/s41598-019-57235-8. S2CID 92035839. Retrieved 2022-08-10.
  13. ^ Battistella, Edwin (2015). "Markedness in Linguistics". In Wright, James D. (ed.). International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences (2nd ed.). Elsevier. pp. 533–537. doi:10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.52037-6. ISBN 978-0-08-097087-5.
  14. ^ Partee, Barbara (2011). "Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact". The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication. Vol. 6. BIYCLC. pp. 1–52. doi:10.4148/biyclc.v6i0.1580.
  15. ^ a b c Chomsky, Noam (2015). The Minimalist Program. 20th Anniversary Edition. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-52734-7.
  16. ^ Benmamoun, labbas; Choueiri, Lina (2013). "The Syntax of Arabic From A Generative Perspective". In Owens (ed.). The Oxford handbook of Arabic linguistics. Oxford Umiversity Press. pp. 115–164. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199764136.013.0006. ISBN 978-0199764136.
  17. ^ Chomsky, Noam (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-53007-4.
  18. ^ The Port-Royal Grammar of 1660 identified similar principles; Chomsky, Noam (1972). Language and Mind. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ISBN 0-15-147810-4.
  19. ^ Goldsmith, John A (1995). "Phonological Theory". In John A. Goldsmith (ed.). The Handbook of Phonological Theory. Blackwell Handbooks in Linguistics. Blackwell Publishers. p. 2. ISBN 1-4051-5768-2.
  20. ^ Hjelmslev, Louis (1969) [First published 1943]. Prolegomena to a Theory of Language. University of Wisconsin Press. ISBN 0299024709.
  21. ^ Emmon Bach, An Introduction to Transformational Grammars, Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Inc., 1966, pp. 59–69.
  22. ^ Peters, Stanley; R. Ritchie (1973). "On the generative power of transformational grammars" (PDF). Information Sciences. 6: 49–83. doi:10.1016/0020-0255(73)90027-3.
  23. ^ Chomsky, Noam (1956). (PDF). IRE Transactions on Information Theory. 2 (3): 113–124. doi:10.1109/TIT.1956.1056813. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2010-09-19.
  24. ^ Shieber, Stuart (1985). "Evidence against the context-freeness of natural language" (PDF). Linguistics and Philosophy. 8 (3): 333–343. doi:10.1007/BF00630917. S2CID 222277837.
  25. ^ Pullum, Geoffrey K.; Gerald Gazdar (1982). "Natural languages and context-free languages". Linguistics and Philosophy. 4 (4): 471–504. doi:10.1007/BF00360802. S2CID 189881482.
  26. ^ McLeod, S. "Language Acquisition". Simply Psychology. Retrieved 21 February 2019.
  27. ^ Newmeyer, Frederick J. (1986). Linguistic Theory in America (Second ed.). Academic Press.[page needed]
  28. ^ Chomsky 1957:15
  29. ^ Kordić, Snježana (1991). "Transformacijsko-generativni pristup jeziku u Sintaktičkim strukturama i Aspektima teorije sintakse Noama Chomskog" [Transformational-generative approach to language in Syntactic structures and Aspects of the theory of syntax of Noam Chomsky] (PDF). SOL: Lingvistički časopis (in Serbo-Croatian). 6 (12–13): 105. ISSN 0352-8715. S2CID 186964128. SSRN 3445224. CROSBI 446914. ZDB-ID 1080348-8. (CROLIB). (PDF) from the original on January 16, 2013. Retrieved 7 September 2020.
  30. ^ In a review of The Minimalist Program, Zwart 1998 observed, "D-Structure is eliminated in the sense that there is no base component applying rewrite rules to generate an empty structure which is to be fleshed out later by 'all at once' lexical insertion. Instead, structures are created by combining elements drawn from the lexicon, and there is no stage in the process at which we can stop and say: this is D-Structure." Similarly, "there is no need for language particular S-Structure conditions in order to describe word order variation" and can be handled by LF.
  31. ^ Jackendoff, Ray (1974). Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar. MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-10013-4.
  32. ^ May, Robert C. (1977). The Grammar of Quantification. MIT Phd Dissertation. ISBN 0-8240-1392-1. (Supervised by Noam Chomsky, this dissertation introduced the idea of "logical form.")
  33. ^ Chomsky, Noam (1986). Knowledge of Language. New York:Praeger. ISBN 0-275-90025-8.[page needed]
  34. ^ Chomsky, Noam (2001). "Derivation by Phase." In other words, in algebraic terms, and the I-language is the actual function, whereas the E-language is the extension of this function. In Michael Kenstowicz (ed.) Ken Hale: A Life in Language. MIT Press. Pages 1-52. (See p. 49 fn. 2 for comment on E-language.)
  35. ^ Chomsky, Noam (1995). The Minimalist Program. MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-53128-3.
  36. ^ Lappin, Shalom; Levine, Robert; Johnson, David (2000). "Topic ... Comment". Natural Language & Linguistic Theory. 18 (3): 665–671. doi:10.1023/A:1006474128258. S2CID 189900915.
  37. ^ Lappin, Shalom; Levine, Robert; Johnson, David (2001). "The Revolution Maximally Confused". Natural Language & Linguistic Theory. 19 (4): 901–919. doi:10.1023/A:1013397516214. S2CID 140876545.
  38. ^ Koerner, E. F. K. (1978). "Towards a historiography of linguistics". Toward a Historiography of Linguistics: Selected Essays. John Benjamins. pp. 21–54.
  39. ^ Koerner, E. F. K. (1983). "The Chomskyan 'revolution' and its historiography: a few critical remarks". Language & Communication. 3 (2): 147–169. doi:10.1016/0271-5309(83)90012-5.

Bibliography

  • Chomsky, Noam (1957), Syntactic Structures, The Hague/Paris: Mouton
  • Chomsky, Noam (1995). The Minimalist Program. MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-53128-3.
  • Bauer, Laurie (2007). The linguistics studentʻs handbook. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 47–55. ISBN 978-0-7486-2758-5.
  • Zwart, Jan-Wouter (1998). "Review Article: The Minimalist Program". Journal of Linguistics. Cambridge University Press. 34: 213–226. doi:10.1017/S0022226797006889. S2CID 1647815.

External links

  • What is I-language? - Chapter 1 of I-language: An Introduction to Linguistics as Cognitive Science.
  • The Syntax of Natural Language – an online textbook on transformational grammar.
  • Isac, Daniela; Charles Reiss (2013). I-language: An Introduction to Linguistics as Cognitive Science, 2nd edition. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953420-3.

transformational, grammar, linguistics, transformational, grammar, transformational, generative, grammar, part, theory, generative, grammar, especially, natural, languages, considers, grammar, system, rules, that, generate, exactly, those, combinations, words,. In linguistics transformational grammar TG or transformational generative grammar TGG is part of the theory of generative grammar especially of natural languages It considers grammar to be a system of rules that generate exactly those combinations of words that form grammatical sentences in a given language and involves the use of defined operations called transformations to produce new sentences from existing ones The method is commonly associated with American linguist Noam Chomsky Generative algebra was first introduced to general linguistics by the structural linguist Louis Hjelmslev 1 although the method was described before him by Albert Sechehaye in 1908 2 Chomsky adopted the concept of transformations from his teacher Zellig Harris who followed the American descriptivist separation of semantics from syntax Hjelmslev s structuralist conception including semantics and pragmatics is incorporated into functional grammar 3 Contents 1 Historical context 2 Basic mechanisms 2 1 Deep structure and surface structure 2 2 Transformations 2 2 1 Formal definition 2 2 2 Mathematical representation 3 Core concepts 3 1 Innate linguistic knowledge 3 2 Grammaticality 3 3 Theory evaluation 3 3 1 Competence versus performance 3 3 2 Descriptive versus explanatory adequacy 4 Development of concepts 4 1 I language and E language 4 2 Minimalist program 5 Critical reception 6 See also 7 References 8 Bibliography 9 External linksHistorical context EditTransformational analysis is a part of the classical Western grammatical tradition based on the metaphysics of Plato and Aristotle and on the grammar of Apollonius Dyscolus These were joined to establish linguistics as a natural science in the Middle Ages Transformational analysis was later developed by humanistic grammarians such as Thomas Linacre 1524 Julius Caesar Scaliger 1540 and Sanctius Francisco Sanchez de las Brozas 1587 The core observation is that grammatical rules alone do not constitute elegance so learning to use a language correctly requires certain additional effects such as ellipsis It is more desirable for example to say Maggie and Alex went to the market than to express the full underlying idea Maggie went to the market and Alex went to the market Such phenomena were described in terms of understood elements In modern terminology the first expression is the surface structure of the second and the second expression is the deep structure of the first The notions of ellipsis and restoration are complementary the deep structure is converted into the surface structure and restored from it by what were later known as transformational rules 4 It was generally agreed that a degree of simplicity improves the quality of speech and writing but closer inspection of the deep structures of different types of sentences led to many further insights such as the concept of agent and patient in active and passive sentences Transformations were given an explanatory role Sanctius among others argued that surface structures pertaining to the choice of grammatical case in certain Latin expressions could not be understood without the restoration of the deep structure His full transformational system included ellipsis the deletion of understood semantic or syntactic elements pleonasm the occurrence of syntactically superfluous elements syllepsis the violation of a rule of agreement hyperbaton the violation of normal word order 5 Transformational analysis fell out of favor with the rise of historical comparative linguistics in the 19th century and the historical linguist Ferdinand de Saussure argued for limiting linguistic analysis to the surface structure 6 By contrast Edmund Husserl in his 1921 elaboration of the 17th century Port Royal Grammar based his version of generative grammar on classical transformations Modifikationen 7 Husserl s concept influenced Roman Jakobson who advocated it in the Prague linguistic circle which was likewise influenced by Saussure 8 Based on opposition theory Jakobson developed his theory of markedness and having moved to the United States influenced Noam Chomsky especially through Morris Halle Chomsky and his colleagues including Jerrold Katz and Jerry Fodor developed what they called transformational generative grammar in the 1960s 9 10 The transformational grammar of the 1960s differs from the Renaissance linguistics in its relation to the theory of language While the humanistic grammarians considered language manmade Chomsky and his colleagues exploited markedness and transformation theory in their attempt to uncover innate grammar 11 It would be later clarified that such grammar arises from a brain structure caused by a mutation in humans 12 In particular generative linguists tried to reconstruct the underlying innate structure based on deep structure and unmarked forms Thus a modern notion of universal grammar in contrast to the humanistic classics suggested that the basic word order of biological grammar is unmarked and unmodified in transformational terms 13 14 Transformational generative grammar included two kinds of rules phrase structure rules and transformational rules But scholars abandoned the project in the 1970s Based on Chomsky s concept of I language as the proper subject of linguistics as a cognitive science Katz and Fodor had conducted their research on English grammar employing introspection These findings could not be generalized cross linguistically whereby they could not belong to an innate universal grammar 15 The concept of transformation was nevertheless not fully rejected In Chomsky s 1990s Minimalist Program transformations pertain to the lexicon and the move operation 15 This more lenient approach offers more prospects of universalizability It is for example argued that the English SVO word order subject verb object represents the initial state of the cognitive language faculty However in languages like Classical Arabic which has a basic VSO order sentences are automatically transformed by the move operation from the underlying SVO order on which the matrix of all sentences in all languages is reconstructed Therefore there is no longer a need for a separate surface and deep matrix and additional rules of conversion between the two levels According to Chomsky this solution allows sufficient descriptive and explanatory adequacy descriptive because all languages are analyzed on the same matrix and explanatory because the analysis shows in which particular way the sentence is derived from the hypothesized initial cognitive state 16 15 Basic mechanisms EditDeep structure and surface structure Edit Main article Deep structure and surface structure While Chomsky s 1957 book Syntactic Structures followed Harris s distributionalistic practice of excluding semantics from structural analysis his 1965 book Aspects of the Theory of Syntax developed the idea that each sentence in a language has two levels of representation a deep structure and a surface structure 17 18 But these are not quite identical to Hjelmslev s content plane and expression plane 1 The deep structure represents the core semantic relations of a sentence and is mapped onto the surface structure which follows the phonological form of the sentence very closely via transformations The concept of transformations had been proposed before the development of deep structure to increase the mathematical and descriptive power of context free grammars Deep structure was developed largely for technical reasons related to early semantic theory Chomsky emphasized the importance of modern formal mathematical devices in the development of grammatical theory But the fundamental reason for the inadequacy of traditional grammars is a more technical one Although it was well understood that linguistic processes are in some sense creative the technical devices for expressing a system of recursive processes were simply not available until much more recently In fact a real understanding of how a language can in Humboldt s words make infinite use of finite means has developed only within the last thirty years in the course of studies in the foundations of mathematics Aspects of the Theory of Syntax Transformations Edit The usual usage of the term transformation in linguistics refers to a rule that takes an input typically called the deep structure in the Standard Theory or D structure in the extended standard theory or government and binding theory and changes it in some restricted way to result in a surface structure or S structure In TG phrase structure rules generate deep structures For example a typical transformation in TG is subject auxiliary inversion SAI That rule takes as its input a declarative sentence with an auxiliary such as John has eaten all the heirloom tomatoes and transforms it into Has John eaten all the heirloom tomatoes In the original formulation Chomsky 1957 those rules were stated as rules that held over strings of terminals constituent symbols or both X NP AUX Y displaystyle Rightarrow X AUX NP Y NP Noun Phrase and AUX Auxiliary In the 1970s by the time of the Extended Standard Theory following Joseph Emonds s work on structure preservation transformations came to be viewed as holding over trees By the end of government and binding theory in the late 1980s transformations were no longer structure changing operations at all instead they add information to already existing trees by copying constituents The earliest conceptions of transformations were that they were construction specific devices For example there was a transformation that turned active sentences into passive ones A different transformation raised embedded subjects into main clause subject position in sentences such as John seems to have gone and a third reordered arguments in the dative alternation With the shift from rules to principles and constraints in the 1970s those construction specific transformations morphed into general rules all the examples just mentioned are instances of NP movement which eventually changed into the single general rule move alpha or Move Transformations actually come in two types the post deep structure kind mentioned above which are string or structure changing and generalized transformations GTs GTs were originally proposed in the earliest forms of generative grammar such as in Chomsky 1957 They take small structures either atomic or generated by other rules and combine them For example the generalized transformation of embedding would take the kernel Dave said X and the kernel Dan likes smoking and combine them into Dave said Dan likes smoking GTs are thus structure building rather than structure changing In the Extended Standard Theory and government and binding theory GTs were abandoned in favor of recursive phrase structure rules but they are still present in tree adjoining grammar as the Substitution and Adjunction operations and have recently reemerged in mainstream generative grammar in Minimalism as the operations Merge and Move In generative phonology another form of transformation is the phonological rule which describes a mapping between an underlying representation the phoneme and the surface form that is articulated during natural speech 19 Formal definition Edit Chomsky s advisor Zellig Harris took transformations to be relations between sentences such as I finally met this talkshow host you always detested and simpler kernel sentences I finally met this talkshow host and You always detested this talkshow host need quotation to verify A transformational generative or simply transformational grammar thus involved two types of productive rules phrase structure rules such as S NP VP a sentence may consist of a noun phrase followed by a verb phrase etc which could be used to generate grammatical sentences with associated parse trees phrase markers or P markers and transformational rules such as rules for converting statements to questions or active to passive voice which acted on the phrase markers to produce other grammatically correct sentences Hjelmslev had called word order conversion rules permutations 20 In this context transformational rules are not strictly necessary to generate the set of grammatical sentences in a language since that can be done using phrase structure rules alone but the use of transformations provides economy in some cases the number of rules can be reduced and it also provides a way of representing the grammatical relations between sentences which would not be reflected in a system with phrase structure rules alone 21 This notion of transformation proved adequate for subsequent versions including the extended revised extended and Government Binding GB versions of generative grammar but it may no longer be sufficient for minimalist grammar as merge may require a formal definition that goes beyond the tree manipulation characteristic of Move a Mathematical representation Edit An important feature of all transformational grammars is that they are more powerful than context free grammars 22 Chomsky formalized this idea in the Chomsky hierarchy He argued that it is impossible to describe the structure of natural languages with context free grammars 23 His general position on the non context freeness of natural language has held up since then though his specific examples of the inadequacy of CFGs in terms of their weak generative capacity were disproved 24 25 Core concepts EditInnate linguistic knowledge Edit Using a term such as transformation may give the impression that theories of transformational generative grammar are intended as a model of the processes by which the human mind constructs and understands sentences but Chomsky clearly stated that a generative grammar models only the knowledge that underlies the human ability to speak and understand arguing that because most of that knowledge is innate a baby can have a large body of knowledge about the structure of language in general and so need to learn only the idiosyncratic features of the language s to which it is exposed citation needed Chomsky is not the first person to suggest that all languages have certain fundamental things in common He quoted philosophers who posited the same basic idea several centuries ago But Chomsky helped make the innateness theory respectable after a period dominated by more behaviorist attitudes towards language He made concrete and technically sophisticated proposals about the structure of language as well as important proposals about how grammatical theories success should be evaluated 26 Grammaticality Edit Further information Grammaticality Chomsky argued that grammatical and ungrammatical can be meaningfully and usefully defined In contrast an extreme behaviorist linguist would argue that language can be studied only through recordings or transcriptions of actual speech and that the role of the linguist is to look for patterns in such observed speech not to hypothesize about why such patterns might occur or to label particular utterances grammatical or ungrammatical Few linguists in the 1950s actually took such an extreme position but Chomsky was on the opposite extreme defining grammaticality in an unusually mentalistic way for the time 27 He argued that the intuition of a native speaker is enough to define the grammaticality of a sentence that is if a particular string of English words elicits a double take or a feeling of wrongness in a native English speaker with various extraneous factors affecting intuitions controlled for it can be said that the string of words is ungrammatical That according to Chomsky is entirely distinct from the question of whether a sentence is meaningful or can be understood It is possible for a sentence to be both grammatical and meaningless as in Chomsky s famous example colorless green ideas sleep furiously 28 But such sentences manifest a linguistic problem that is distinct from that posed by meaningful but ungrammatical non sentences such as man the bit sandwich the the meaning of which is fairly clear but which no native speaker would accept as well formed The use of such intuitive judgments permitted generative syntacticians to base their research on a methodology in which studying language through a corpus of observed speech became downplayed since the grammatical properties of constructed sentences were considered appropriate data on which to build a grammatical model Theory evaluation Edit In the 1960s Chomsky introduced two central ideas relevant to the construction and evaluation of grammatical theories Competence versus performance Edit One was the distinction between competence and performance 29 Chomsky noted the obvious fact that when people speak in the real world they often make linguistic errors such as starting a sentence and then abandoning it midway through He argued that such errors in linguistic performance are irrelevant to the study of linguistic competence the knowledge that allows people to construct and understand grammatical sentences Consequently the linguist can study an idealised version of language which greatly simplifies linguistic analysis Descriptive versus explanatory adequacy Edit The other idea related directly to evaluation of theories of grammar Chomsky distinguished between grammars that achieve descriptive adequacy and those that go further and achieve explanatory adequacy A descriptively adequate grammar for a particular language defines the infinite set of grammatical sentences in that language that is it describes the language in its entirety A grammar that achieves explanatory adequacy has the additional property that it gives insight into the mind s underlying linguistic structures In other words it does not merely describe the grammar of a language but makes predictions about how linguistic knowledge is mentally represented For Chomsky such mental representations are largely innate and so if a grammatical theory has explanatory adequacy it must be able to explain different languages grammatical nuances as relatively minor variations in the universal pattern of human language Chomsky argued that even though linguists were still a long way from constructing descriptively adequate grammars progress in descriptive adequacy would come only if linguists held explanatory adequacy as their goal real insight into individual languages structure can be gained only by comparative study of a wide range of languages on the assumption that they are all cut from the same cloth citation needed Development of concepts EditThough transformations continue to be important in Chomsky s theories he has now abandoned the original notion of deep structure and surface structure Initially two additional levels of representation were introduced logical form LF and phonetic form PF but in the 1990s Chomsky sketched a new program of research known at first as Minimalism in which deep structure and surface structure are no longer featured and PF and LF remain as the only levels of representation 30 To complicate the understanding of the development of Chomsky s theories the precise meanings of deep structure and surface structure have changed over time By the 1970s Chomskyan linguists normally called them D Structure and S Structure In particular Chomskyan linguists dropped for good the idea that a sentence s deep structure determined its meaning taken to its logical conclusions by generative semanticists during the same period when LF took over this role previously Chomsky and Ray Jackendoff had begun to argue that both deep and surface structure determined meaning 31 32 I language and E language Edit E language redirects here Not to be confused with E language or E programming language In 1986 Chomsky proposed a distinction between I language and E language that is similar but not identical to the competence performance distinction 33 I language is internal language E language is external language I language is taken to be the object of study in linguistic theory it is the mentally represented linguistic knowledge a native speaker of a language has and thus a mental object From that perspective most of theoretical linguistics is a branch of psychology E language encompasses all other notions of what a language is such as a body of knowledge or behavioural habits shared by a community Thus E language is not a coherent concept by itself 34 and Chomsky argues that such notions of language are not useful in the study of innate linguistic knowledge or competence even though they may seem sensible and intuitive and useful in other areas of study Competence he argues can be studied only if languages are treated as mental objects Minimalist program Edit Further information Minimalist program From the mid 1990s onward much research in transformational grammar has been inspired by Chomsky s minimalist program 35 It aims to further develop ideas involving economy of derivation and economy of representation which had started to become significant in the early 1990s but were still rather peripheral aspects of transformational generative grammar theory Economy of derivation is the principle that movements or transformations occur only to match interpretable features with uninterpretable features An example of an interpretable feature is the plural inflection on regular English nouns e g dogs The word dogs can be used to refer only to several dogs not a single dog and so the inflection contributes to meaning by making it interpretable English verbs are inflected according to the number of their subject Dogs bite v A dog bites but in most sentences that inflection just duplicates the information about number that the subject noun already has and the inflection is therefore uninterpretable Economy of representation is the principle that grammatical structures must exist for a purpose the structure of a sentence should be no larger or more complex than required to satisfy constraints on grammaticality Both notions as described here are somewhat vague and their precise formulation is controversial 36 37 An additional aspect of minimalist thought is the idea that the derivation of syntactic structures should be uniform rules should not be stipulated as applying at arbitrary points in a derivation but instead apply throughout derivations Minimalist approaches to phrase structure have resulted in Bare Phrase Structure an attempt to eliminate X bar theory In 1998 Chomsky suggested that derivations proceed in phases The distinction between deep structure and surface structure is absent in Minimalist theories of syntax and the most recent phase based theories also eliminate LF and PF as unitary levels of representation Critical reception EditIn 1978 linguist and historian E F K Koerner hailed transformational grammar as the third and last Kuhnian revolution in linguistics arguing that it had brought about a shift from Ferdinand de Saussure s sociological approach to a Chomskyan conception of linguistics as analogous to chemistry and physics Koerner also praised the philosophical and psychological value of Chomsky s theory 38 In 1983 Koerner retracted his earlier statement suggesting that transformational grammar was a 1960s fad that had spread across the U S at a time when the federal government had invested heavily in new linguistic departments But he claims Chomsky s work is unoriginal when compared to other syntactic models of the time According to Koerner Chomsky s rise to fame was orchestrated by Bernard Bloch editor of Language the journal of the Linguistic Society of America and Roman Jakobson a personal friend of Chomsky s father Koerner suggests that great sums of money were spent to fly foreign students to the 1962 International Congress at Harvard where an exceptional opportunity was arranged for Chomsky to give a keynote speech making questionable claims of belonging to the rationalist tradition of Saussure Humboldt and the Port Royal Grammar in order to win popularity among the Europeans The transformational agenda was subsequently forced through at American conferences where students instructed by Chomsky regularly verbally attacked and ridiculed his potential opponents 39 See also EditAntisymmetry Biolinguistics Generalised phrase structure grammar Generative semantics Head driven phrase structure grammar Heavy NP shift Jerzy Kurylowicz Lexical functional grammar Minimalist program Parasitic gap Structural linguistics Transformational syntaxReferences Edit a b Seuren Pieter A M 1998 Western linguistics An historical introduction Wiley Blackwell ISBN 0 631 20891 7 Seuren Pieter 2018 Saussure and Sechehaye Myth and Genius Brill ISBN 978 90 04 37815 5 Butler Christopher S 2003 Structure and Function A Guide to Three Major Structural Functional Theories part 1 PDF John Benjamins ISBN 9781588113580 Retrieved 2020 01 19 Percival William Keith 1976 Deep and surface structure concepts in renaissance and mediaeval syntactic theory In Parret ed History of Linguistic Thought and Contemporary Linguistics Walter de Gruyter pp 238 253 Percival William Keith 1976 Deep and surface structure concepts in renaissance and mediaeval syntactic theory In Parret ed History of Linguistic Thought and Contemporary Linguistics Walter de Gruyter pp 238 253 de Saussure Ferdinand 1959 First published 1916 Course in general linguistics PDF New York Philosophy Library ISBN 9780231157278 Archived from the original PDF on 2020 04 14 Retrieved 2022 08 08 Bianchin Matteo 2018 Husserl on Meaning Grammar and the Structure of Content PDF Husserl Studies 34 2 101 121 doi 10 1007 s10743 017 9223 2 S2CID 254553890 Retrieved 2022 08 08 Holenstein Elmar 2018 Jakobson und Husserl Ein beitrag zur genealogie Des strukturalismus PDF Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 35 3 560 607 JSTOR 40882437 Retrieved 2022 08 08 Battistella Edwin 2015 Markedness in Linguistics In Wright James D ed International Encyclopedia of the Social amp Behavioral Sciences 2nd ed Elsevier pp 533 537 doi 10 1016 B978 0 08 097086 8 52037 6 ISBN 978 0 08 097087 5 Partee Barbara 2011 Formal Semantics Origins Issues Early Impact The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition Logic and Communication Vol 6 BIYCLC pp 1 52 doi 10 4148 biyclc v6i0 1580 Percival William Keith 1976 Deep and surface structure concepts in renaissance and mediaeval syntactic theory In Parret ed History of Linguistic Thought and Contemporary Linguistics Walter de Gruyter pp 238 253 de Boer Bart Thompson Bill Ravigniani Andrea Boeckx Cedric 2020 Evolutionary Dynamics Do Not Motivate a Single Mutant Theory of Human Language Scientific Reports 10 451 doi 10 1038 s41598 019 57235 8 S2CID 92035839 Retrieved 2022 08 10 Battistella Edwin 2015 Markedness in Linguistics In Wright James D ed International Encyclopedia of the Social amp Behavioral Sciences 2nd ed Elsevier pp 533 537 doi 10 1016 B978 0 08 097086 8 52037 6 ISBN 978 0 08 097087 5 Partee Barbara 2011 Formal Semantics Origins Issues Early Impact The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition Logic and Communication Vol 6 BIYCLC pp 1 52 doi 10 4148 biyclc v6i0 1580 a b c Chomsky Noam 2015 The Minimalist Program 20th Anniversary Edition MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 52734 7 Benmamoun labbas Choueiri Lina 2013 The Syntax of Arabic From A Generative Perspective In Owens ed The Oxford handbook of Arabic linguistics Oxford Umiversity Press pp 115 164 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199764136 013 0006 ISBN 978 0199764136 Chomsky Noam 1965 Aspects of the Theory of Syntax MIT Press ISBN 0 262 53007 4 The Port Royal Grammar of 1660 identified similar principles Chomsky Noam 1972 Language and Mind Harcourt Brace Jovanovich ISBN 0 15 147810 4 Goldsmith John A 1995 Phonological Theory In John A Goldsmith ed The Handbook of Phonological Theory Blackwell Handbooks in Linguistics Blackwell Publishers p 2 ISBN 1 4051 5768 2 Hjelmslev Louis 1969 First published 1943 Prolegomena to a Theory of Language University of Wisconsin Press ISBN 0299024709 Emmon Bach An Introduction to Transformational Grammars Holt Rinehart and Winston Inc 1966 pp 59 69 Peters Stanley R Ritchie 1973 On the generative power of transformational grammars PDF Information Sciences 6 49 83 doi 10 1016 0020 0255 73 90027 3 Chomsky Noam 1956 Three models for the description of language PDF IRE Transactions on Information Theory 2 3 113 124 doi 10 1109 TIT 1956 1056813 Archived from the original PDF on 2010 09 19 Shieber Stuart 1985 Evidence against the context freeness of natural language PDF Linguistics and Philosophy 8 3 333 343 doi 10 1007 BF00630917 S2CID 222277837 Pullum Geoffrey K Gerald Gazdar 1982 Natural languages and context free languages Linguistics and Philosophy 4 4 471 504 doi 10 1007 BF00360802 S2CID 189881482 McLeod S Language Acquisition Simply Psychology Retrieved 21 February 2019 Newmeyer Frederick J 1986 Linguistic Theory in America Second ed Academic Press page needed Chomsky 1957 15 Kordic Snjezana 1991 Transformacijsko generativni pristup jeziku u Sintaktickim strukturama i Aspektima teorije sintakse Noama Chomskog Transformational generative approach to language in Syntactic structures and Aspects of the theory of syntax of Noam Chomsky PDF SOL Lingvisticki casopis in Serbo Croatian 6 12 13 105 ISSN 0352 8715 S2CID 186964128 SSRN 3445224 CROSBI 446914 ZDB ID 1080348 8 CROLIB Archived PDF from the original on January 16 2013 Retrieved 7 September 2020 In a review of The Minimalist Program Zwart 1998 observed D Structure is eliminated in the sense that there is no base component applying rewrite rules to generate an empty structure which is to be fleshed out later by all at once lexical insertion Instead structures are created by combining elements drawn from the lexicon and there is no stage in the process at which we can stop and say this is D Structure Similarly there is no need for language particular S Structure conditions in order to describe word order variation and can be handled by LF Jackendoff Ray 1974 Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar MIT Press ISBN 0 262 10013 4 May Robert C 1977 The Grammar of Quantification MIT Phd Dissertation ISBN 0 8240 1392 1 Supervised by Noam Chomsky this dissertation introduced the idea of logical form Chomsky Noam 1986 Knowledge of Language New York Praeger ISBN 0 275 90025 8 page needed Chomsky Noam 2001 Derivation by Phase In other words in algebraic terms and the I language is the actual function whereas the E language is the extension of this function In Michael Kenstowicz ed Ken Hale A Life in Language MIT Press Pages 1 52 See p 49 fn 2 for comment on E language Chomsky Noam 1995 The Minimalist Program MIT Press ISBN 0 262 53128 3 Lappin Shalom Levine Robert Johnson David 2000 Topic Comment Natural Language amp Linguistic Theory 18 3 665 671 doi 10 1023 A 1006474128258 S2CID 189900915 Lappin Shalom Levine Robert Johnson David 2001 The Revolution Maximally Confused Natural Language amp Linguistic Theory 19 4 901 919 doi 10 1023 A 1013397516214 S2CID 140876545 Koerner E F K 1978 Towards a historiography of linguistics Toward a Historiography of Linguistics Selected Essays John Benjamins pp 21 54 Koerner E F K 1983 The Chomskyan revolution and its historiography a few critical remarks Language amp Communication 3 2 147 169 doi 10 1016 0271 5309 83 90012 5 Bibliography EditChomsky Noam 1957 Syntactic Structures The Hague Paris Mouton Chomsky Noam 1995 The Minimalist Program MIT Press ISBN 0 262 53128 3 Bauer Laurie 2007 The linguistics studentʻs handbook Edinburgh University Press pp 47 55 ISBN 978 0 7486 2758 5 Zwart Jan Wouter 1998 Review Article The Minimalist Program Journal of Linguistics Cambridge University Press 34 213 226 doi 10 1017 S0022226797006889 S2CID 1647815 External links EditWhat is I language Chapter 1 of I language An Introduction to Linguistics as Cognitive Science The Syntax of Natural Language an online textbook on transformational grammar Isac Daniela Charles Reiss 2013 I language An Introduction to Linguistics as Cognitive Science 2nd edition Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 953420 3 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Transformational grammar amp oldid 1136443852 I language and E language, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.