fbpx
Wikipedia

Antisymmetry

In linguistics, antisymmetry is a syntactic theory presented in Richard S. Kayne's 1994 monograph The Antisymmetry of Syntax.[1] It asserts that grammatical hierarchies in natural language follow a universal order, namely specifier-head-complement branching order. The theory builds on the foundation of the X-bar theory. Kayne hypothesizes that all phrases whose surface order is not specifier-head-complement have undergone syntactic movements that disrupt this underlying order. Others have posited specifier-complement-head as the basic word order.[2]

Antisymmetry as a principle of word order is reliant on X-bar notions such as specifier and complement, and the existence of order-altering mechanisms such as movement. It is disputed by constituency structure theories (as opposed to dependency structure theories).[citation needed]

Asymmetric c-command edit

C-command is a relation between tree nodes, as defined by Tanya Reinhart.[3] Kayne uses a simple definition of c-command based on the "first node up". However, the definition is complicated by his use of a "segment/category" distinction. Two directly connected nodes that have the same label are "segments" of a single "category". A category "excludes" all categories not "dominated" by all its segments. A "c-commands" B if every category that dominates A also dominates B, and A excludes B. The following tree illustrates these concepts:

 

AP1 and AP2 are both segments of a single category. AP does not c-command BP because it does not exclude BP. CP does not c-command BP because both segments of AP do not dominate BP (so it is not the case that every category that dominates CP dominates BP). BP c-commands CP and A. A c-commands C. The definitions above may perhaps be thought to allow BP to c-command AP, but a c-command relation is not usually assumed to hold between two such categories, and for the purposes of antisymmetry, the question of whether BP c-commands AP is in fact moot.

(The above is not an exhaustive list of c-command relations in the tree, but covers all of those that are significant in the following exposition.)

Asymmetric c-command is the relation that holds between two categories, A and B, if A c-commands B but B does not c-command A.

Precedence and asymmetric c-command edit

Informally, Kayne's theory states that if a nonterminal category A asymmetrically c-commands another nonterminal category B, all the terminal nodes dominated by A must precede all of the terminal nodes dominated by B (this statement is commonly referred to as the "Linear Correspondence Axiom" or LCA). Moreover, this principle must suffice to establish a complete and consistent ordering of all terminal nodes — if it cannot consistently order all of the terminal nodes in a tree, the tree is illicit. Consider the following tree:

 

(S and S' may either be simplex structures like BP, or complex structures with specifiers and complements like CP.)

In this tree, the set of pairs of nonterminal categories such that the first member of the pair asymmetrically c-commands the second member is: ⟨BP, A⟩, ⟨BP, CP⟩, ⟨A, CP⟩}. This gives rise to the total ordering: ⟨b, a, c⟩.

As a result, there is no right adjunction, and hence in practice no rightward movement either.[4] Furthermore, the underlying order must be specifier-head-complement.

Derivation of X-bar theory edit

The example tree in the first section of this article is in accordance with X-bar theory (with the exception that [Spec,CP] (i.e., the specifier of the CP phrase) is treated as an adjunct). It can be seen that removing any of the structures in the tree (e.g., deleting the C dominating the 'c' terminal, so that the complement of A is [CP c]) will destroy the asymmetric c-command relations necessary for linearly ordering the terminals of the tree.

The universal order edit

Kayne notes that his theory permits either a universal specifier-head-complement order or a universal complement-head-specifier order, depending on whether asymmetric c-command establishes precedence or subsequence (S-H-C results from precedence).[5] He prefers S-H-C as the universal underlying order since the most widely attested order in linguistic typology is for specifiers to precede heads and complements (though the order of heads and complements themselves is relatively free). He further argues that a movement approach to deriving non-S-H-C orders is appropriate since it derives asymmetries in typology (such as the fact that "verb-second" languages such as German are not mirrored by any known "verb second-from-last" languages).

Derived orders: the case of Japanese wh-questions edit

Perhaps the biggest challenge for antisymmetry is to explain the wide variety of different surface orders across languages. Any deviation from Spec-Head-Comp order (which implies overall Subject-Verb-Object order, if objects are complements) must be explained by movement. Kayne argues that in some cases, the need for extra movements (previously unnecessary because different underlying orders were assumed for different languages) can explain some otherwise mysterious typological generalizations. His explanation for the lack of wh-movement in Japanese is the most striking example of this. From the mid-1980s onwards, the standard analysis of wh-movement involved the wh-phrase moving leftward to a position on the left edge of the clause called [Spec,CP]. Thus, a derivation of the English question What did John buy? would proceed roughly as follows:

[CP {Spec,CP position} John did buy what]
wh-movement
[CP What did John buy]

The Japanese equivalent of this sentence is as follows[6] (note the lack of wh-movement):

John-wa nani-o kaimashita ka
John-topic_marker what-accusative bought question_particle

Japanese has an overt "question particle" (ka), which appears at the end of the sentence in questions. It is generally assumed that languages such as English have a "covert" (i.e. phonologically null) equivalent of this particle in the 'C' position of the clause — the position just to the right of [Spec,CP]. This particle is overtly realised in English by the movement of an auxiliary to C (in the case of the example above, by the movement of did to C). Why is it that this particle is on the left edge of the clause in English, but on the right edge in Japanese? Kayne suggests that in Japanese, the whole of the clause (apart from the question particle in C) has moved to the [Spec,CP] position. So, the structure for the Japanese example above is something like the following:

[CP [John-wa nani-o kaimashita] C ka

Now it is clear why Japanese does not have wh-movement — the [Spec,CP] position is already filled, so no wh-phrase can move to it. The relationship between surface word order and the possibility of wh-movement is seemingly obscure. A possible alternative to the antisymmetric explanation could be based on the difficulty of parsing languages with rightward movement.[7]

Dynamic antisymmetry edit

Andrea Moro proposed Dynamic antisymmetry, a weak version of antisymmetry, which allows the generation of non-LCA compatible structures (points of symmetry) before the hierarchical structure is linearized at Phonetic Form (PF). The unwanted structures are then rescued by movement: deleting the phonetic content of the moved element neutralizes the linearization problem.[8] Dynamic Antisymmetry aims at unifying a movement and phrase structure, which otherwise are independent properties.

Antisymmetry and ternary branching edit

Kayne proposed recasting the antisymmetry of natural language as a condition on "Merge", the operation which combines two elements into one. Kayne proposes that merging a head H and its complement C yields an ordered pair   (rather than the standard symmetric set {H,C}).   involves immediate temporal precedence (or immediate linear precedence) so that H immediately precedes (i-precedes) C. Kayne proposes furthermore that when a specifier S merges, it forms an ordered pair with the head directly,  , or S i-precedes H. Invoking i-precedence prevents more than two elements from merging with H; only one element can i-precede H (the specifier), and H can i-precede only one element (the complement).[9]

Kayne notes that   is not mappable to a tree structure, since H would have two mothers, and that it has the consequence that   and   would seem to be constituents. He suggests that   is replaced by  , "with an ordered triple replacing the two ordered pairs and then being mappable to a ternary-branching tree" (pp. 17). Kayne goes on to say, "This would lead to seeing my [(1981)][10] arguments for binary branching to have two subcomponents, the first being the claim that syntax is n-ary branching with n having a single value, the second being that that value is 2. Mapping [  to  ] would retain the first subcomponent and replace 2 by 3 in the second, arguably with no loss in restrictiveness".[9]

Theoretical arguments edit

Antisymmetry theory rejects the head-directionality parameter as such: it claims that at an underlying level, all languages are head-initial. In fact, it argued that all languages have the underlying order Specifier-Head-Complement. Deviations from this order are accounted for by different syntactic movements applied by languages.

Kayne argues that a theory that allows both directionalities would state that languages are symmetrical, whereas in fact languages are found to be asymmetrical in many respects. Examples of linguistic asymmetries which may be cited in support of the theory (although they do not concern head direction) are:

 
X-bar syntactic tree showing the movement of the specifier (S) relative to the head (H) and complement (C)

In arguing for a universal underlying Head-Complement order, Kayne uses the concept of a probe-goal search (based on the Minimalist program). The idea of probes and goals in syntax is that a head acts as a probe and looks for a goal, namely its complement. Kayne proposes that the direction of the probe-goal search must share the direction of language parsing and production.[15] Parsing and production proceed in a left-to-right direction: the beginning of the sentence is heard or spoken first, and the end of the sentence is heard or spoken last. This implies (according to the theory) an ordering whereby probe comes before the goal, i.e. head precedes complement.

Kayne's theory also addresses the position of the specifier of a phrase. He represents the relevant scheme as follows:[16]

S H [c...S...]

The specifier, at first internal to the complement, is moved to the unoccupied position to the left of the head. In terms of merged pairs, this structure can also be represented as:

⟨S, H⟩ ⟨H, C⟩

This process can be mapped onto X-bar syntactic trees as shown in the adjacent diagram.

Antisymmetry then leads to a universal Specifier-Head-Complement order. The varied ordering found in human languages are explained by syntactic movement away from this underlying base order. It has been pointed out, though, that in predominantly head-final languages such as Japanese and Basque, this would involve complex and massive leftward movement, which violates the ideal of grammatical simplicity.[17] An example of the type of movement scheme that would need to be envisaged is provided by Tokizaki:[18]

  1. [CP C [IP ... [VP V [PP P [NP N [Genitive Affix Stem]]]]]]
  2. [CP C [IP ... [VP V [PP P [NP N [Genitive Stem Affix]]]]]]
  3. [CP C [IP ... [VP V [PP P [NP [Genitive Stem Affix] N]]]]]
  4. [CP C [IP ... [VP V [PP [NP [Genitive Stem Affix] N] P]]]]
  5. [CP C [IP ... [VP [PP [NP [Genitive Stem Affix] N] P] V]]]
  6. [CP [IP ... [VP [PP [NP [Genitive Stem Affix] N] P] V]] C]

Here, at each phrasal level in turn, the head of the phrase moves from left to right position relative to its complement. The eventual result reflects the ordering of complex nested phrases found in languages such as Japanese.

An attempt to provide evidence for Kayne's scheme is made by Lin,[19] who considered Standard Chinese sentences with the sentence-final particle le. This particle is taken to convey perfect aspectual meaning, and thus to be the head of an aspect phrase having the verb phrase as its complement. If phrases are always essentially head-initial, then a case like this must entail movement, since the particle comes after the verb phrase. It is proposed that there, the complement moves into specifier position, which precedes the head.

As evidence for this, Lin considers wh-adverbials such as zenmeyang ("how?"). Based on prior work by James Huang,[20] it is postulated that (a) adverbials of this type are subject to movement at logical form (LF) level (even though, in Chinese, they do not display wh-movement at surface level); and (b) movement is not possible from within a non-complement (Huang's Condition on Extraction Domain or CED[clarification needed]). This would imply that zenmeyang could not appear in a verb phrase with sentence-final le, assuming the above analysis, since that verb phrase has moved into a non-complement (specifier) position, and thus further movement (such as that which zenmeyang is required to undergo at LF level) is not possible. Such a restriction on the occurrence of zenmeyang is indeed found:[21]

(a)

Zhangsan

Zhangsan

zenmeyang

how

xiu

repair

che?

car

Zhangsan zenmeyang xiu che?

Zhangsan how repair car

"How does Zhangsan repair the car?"

(b)

*Zhangsan

Zhangsan

zenmeyang

how

xiu

repair

che

car

le?

PF

*Zhangsan zenmeyang xiu che le?

Zhangsan how repair car PF

("How has Zhangsan repaired the car?")

Sentence (b), in which zenmeyang co-occurs with sentence-final le, is ungrammatical. Lin cites this and other related findings as evidence that the above analysis is correct, supporting the view that Chinese aspect phrases are deeply head-initial.

Surface true approach edit

According to the "surface true" viewpoint, analysis of head direction must take place at the level of surface derivations, or even the Phonetic Form, i.e. the order in which sentences are pronounced in natural speech. This rejects the idea of an underlying ordering which is then subject to movement. In a 2008 article, Marc Richards argued that a head parameter must only reside at PF, as it is unmaintainable in its original form as a structural parameter.[22] In this approach the relative positions of head and complement that are attested at this surface level, which show variation both between and within languages (see above), must be treated as the "true" orderings.

Existence of true head-final languages edit

Takita argues against the conclusion of Kayne's Antisymmetry Theory which states that all languages are head-initial at an underlying level. He claims that a language such as Japanese is truly head-final since the mass movement which would be required to take an underlying head-initial structure to the head-final ones actually found in such languages would violate other constraints. It is implied that such languages are likely following a head-final parameter value, as originally conceived.[23] (For a head-initial/Antisymmetry analysis of Japanese, see Kayne.)[24]

Takita's argument is based on Lin's analysis of Chinese. Since surface head-final structures are derived from underlying head-initial structures by moving the complements, further extraction from within the moved complement violates CED.

One of the examples of movement which Takita looks at is that of VP-fronting in Japanese. Grammatically, the sentence without VP-fronting (a) and the sentence where the VP moves to the matrix clause (b) do not significantly differ.[23]

a.

[CP1

 

Taro-ga

Taro-NOM

[CP2[IP2

 

Hanako-ga

Hanako-NOM

[VP2

 

hon-o

book-ACC

sute]-sae

discard-even

shita

did

to]

C‍

omotteiru]

think

[CP1 Taro-ga [CP2[IP2 Hanako-ga [VP2 hon-o sute]-sae shita to] omotteiru]

{} Taro-NOM {} Hanako-NOM {} book-ACC discard-even did C‍ think

'Taro thinks [that Hanako [even discarded his books]]'
(Takita 2009 57: (33a)

b.

[CP1[VP2

 

Hon-o

book-ACC

sute]-saei

discard-even

Taro-ga

Taro-NOM

[CP2[IP2

 

Hanako-ga

Hanako-NOM

shita]

did

to]

C‍

omotteiru

think

[CP1[VP2 Hon-o sute]-saei Taro-ga [CP2[IP2 Hanako-ga shita] to] omotteiru

{} book-ACC discard-even Taro-NOM {} Hanako-NOM did C‍ think

'[Even discarded his books], Taro thinks [that Hanako did ti]'
(Takita 2009 57: (33b)

In (b), the fronted VP precedes the matrix subject, confirming that the VP is located in the matrix clause. If Japanese were head-initial, (b) should not be grammatical because it allows for the extraction of an element (VP2) from the moved complement (CP2).[23]

Thus Takita shows that surface head-final structures in Japanese do not block movement, as they do in Chinese. He concludes that, because Japanese does not block movement as shown in previous sections, it is a genuinely head-final language, and not derived from an underlying, head-initial structure. These results imply that Universal Grammar involves binary head-directionality, and is not antisymmetric. Takita briefly applies the same tests to Turkish, another seemingly head-final language, and reports similar results.[25]

References edit

  1. ^ Kayne 1994.
  2. ^ Li, Yafei (2005). A Theory of the Morphology-Syntax Interface. MIT Press.
  3. ^ Reinhart, Tanya (1979). The Syntactic Domain of Anaphora. Doctoral dissertation (PDF). M.I.T. Press.
  4. ^ Since any rightward movement must also be downward movement if there are no rightward specifiers or right adjunction, and downward movement is generally assumed to be illicit.
  5. ^ Kayne 1994, pp. 34–36.
  6. ^ Jamal Ouhalla (1999). Introducing Transformational Grammar (Second ed.). Arnold/Oxford University Press. (See p. 461 for the Japanese example.)
  7. ^ Neeleman, Ad & Peter Ackema (2002). "Effects of Short-Term Storage in Processing Rightward Movement" In S. Nooteboom et al. (eds.) Storage and Computation in the Language Faculty. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Pages 219-256.
  8. ^ Moro, A. 2000 Dynamic Antisymmetry, Linguistic Inquiry Monograph Series 38, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  9. ^ a b Kayne 2010.
  10. ^ Kayne, Richard S. (1981) "Unambiguous Paths," in Robert May and Jan Koster (eds.) Levels of Syntactic Representation. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Pages 143-183
  11. ^ Nolda, Andreas (2004). Topics Detached to the Left: On ‘Left Dislocation’, ‘Hanging Topic’, and Related Constructions in German. Berlin: ZAS Papers in Linguistics. pp. 423–448.
  12. ^ Kayne 2010, p. 4.
  13. ^ Kayne 2010, p. 7.
  14. ^ Courtney, Ellen H. (2011). "Learning to produce Quechua relative clauses". Acquisition of Relative Clauses : Processing, typology, and function. John Benjamins Publishing Company. p. 150.
  15. ^ Kayne 2010, p. 12.
  16. ^ Kayne 2010, p. 15.
  17. ^ Elordieta, Arantzazu (2014). Biberauer, T.; Sheehan, M., eds. "On the relevance of the Head Parameter in a mixed OV language". Theoretical Approaches to Disharmonic Word Order (Oxford Scholarship Online), p. 5.
  18. ^ Tokizaki, Hisao (2011). "The nature of linear information in the morphosyntax-PF interface". English Linguistics 28 (2), p. 238.
  19. ^ Lin, Tzong-Hong J. (2006), "Complement-to-specifier movement in Mandarin Chinese". Ms., National Tsing Hua University.
  20. ^ Huang, C.-T. J. (1982). "Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar". PhD dissertation, MIT.
  21. ^ Takita 2009, p. 44.
  22. ^ Richards, Marc D. (2008). "Desymmetrization: Parametric variation at the PF-Interface". The Canadian Journal of Linguistics 53 (2-3), p. 283.
  23. ^ a b c Takita 2009, p. 57.
  24. ^ Kayne, Richard S. (2003). "Antisymmetry and Japanese". English Linguistics 20: 1–40.
  25. ^ Takita 2009, p. 59.

Sources edit

  • Kayne, Richard S. (1994). The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Linguistic Inquiry Monograph Twenty-Five. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262611077.
  • Kayne, Richard S. (February 12, 2010). Why are there no directionality parameters?. 28th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics. University of Southern California. ISBN 978-1-57473-441-6.
  • Takita, Kensuke (February 2009). "If Chinese is head-initial, Japanese cannot be". Journal of East Asian Linguistics. 18 (1): 41–61. doi:10.1007/s10831-009-9038-z. ISSN 0925-8558. S2CID 121661611.

antisymmetry, property, matrices, skew, symmetric, matrix, property, mathematical, relations, antisymmetric, relation, other, uses, antisymmetric, disambiguation, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn. For the property of matrices see Skew symmetric matrix For the property of mathematical relations see Antisymmetric relation For other uses see Antisymmetric disambiguation This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article may be too technical for most readers to understand Please help improve it to make it understandable to non experts without removing the technical details August 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message This article may require copy editing for grammar style cohesion tone or spelling You can assist by editing it October 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Learn how and when to remove this template message In linguistics antisymmetry is a syntactic theory presented in Richard S Kayne s 1994 monograph The Antisymmetry of Syntax 1 It asserts that grammatical hierarchies in natural language follow a universal order namely specifier head complement branching order The theory builds on the foundation of the X bar theory Kayne hypothesizes that all phrases whose surface order is not specifier head complement have undergone syntactic movements that disrupt this underlying order Others have posited specifier complement head as the basic word order 2 Antisymmetry as a principle of word order is reliant on X bar notions such as specifier and complement and the existence of order altering mechanisms such as movement It is disputed by constituency structure theories as opposed to dependency structure theories citation needed Contents 1 Asymmetric c command 2 Precedence and asymmetric c command 3 Derivation of X bar theory 4 The universal order 5 Derived orders the case of Japanese wh questions 6 Dynamic antisymmetry 7 Antisymmetry and ternary branching 8 Theoretical arguments 8 1 Surface true approach 8 2 Existence of true head final languages 9 References 10 SourcesAsymmetric c command editC command is a relation between tree nodes as defined by Tanya Reinhart 3 Kayne uses a simple definition of c command based on the first node up However the definition is complicated by his use of a segment category distinction Two directly connected nodes that have the same label are segments of a single category A category excludes all categories not dominated by all its segments A c commands B if every category that dominates A also dominates B and A excludes B The following tree illustrates these concepts nbsp AP1 and AP2 are both segments of a single category AP does not c command BP because it does not exclude BP CP does not c command BP because both segments of AP do not dominate BP so it is not the case that every category that dominates CP dominates BP BP c commands CP and A A c commands C The definitions above may perhaps be thought to allow BP to c command AP but a c command relation is not usually assumed to hold between two such categories and for the purposes of antisymmetry the question of whether BP c commands AP is in fact moot The above is not an exhaustive list of c command relations in the tree but covers all of those that are significant in the following exposition Asymmetric c command is the relation that holds between two categories A and B if A c commands B but B does not c command A Precedence and asymmetric c command editInformally Kayne s theory states that if a nonterminal category A asymmetrically c commands another nonterminal category B all the terminal nodes dominated by A must precede all of the terminal nodes dominated by B this statement is commonly referred to as the Linear Correspondence Axiom or LCA Moreover this principle must suffice to establish a complete and consistent ordering of all terminal nodes if it cannot consistently order all of the terminal nodes in a tree the tree is illicit Consider the following tree nbsp S and S may either be simplex structures like BP or complex structures with specifiers and complements like CP In this tree the set of pairs of nonterminal categories such that the first member of the pair asymmetrically c commands the second member is BP A BP CP A CP This gives rise to the total ordering b a c As a result there is no right adjunction and hence in practice no rightward movement either 4 Furthermore the underlying order must be specifier head complement Derivation of X bar theory editThe example tree in the first section of this article is in accordance with X bar theory with the exception that Spec CP i e the specifier of the CP phrase is treated as an adjunct It can be seen that removing any of the structures in the tree e g deleting the C dominating the c terminal so that the complement of A is CP c will destroy the asymmetric c command relations necessary for linearly ordering the terminals of the tree The universal order editKayne notes that his theory permits either a universal specifier head complement order or a universal complement head specifier order depending on whether asymmetric c command establishes precedence or subsequence S H C results from precedence 5 He prefers S H C as the universal underlying order since the most widely attested order in linguistic typology is for specifiers to precede heads and complements though the order of heads and complements themselves is relatively free He further argues that a movement approach to deriving non S H C orders is appropriate since it derives asymmetries in typology such as the fact that verb second languages such as German are not mirrored by any known verb second from last languages Derived orders the case of Japanese wh questions editPerhaps the biggest challenge for antisymmetry is to explain the wide variety of different surface orders across languages Any deviation from Spec Head Comp order which implies overall Subject Verb Object order if objects are complements must be explained by movement Kayne argues that in some cases the need for extra movements previously unnecessary because different underlying orders were assumed for different languages can explain some otherwise mysterious typological generalizations His explanation for the lack of wh movement in Japanese is the most striking example of this From the mid 1980s onwards the standard analysis of wh movement involved the wh phrase moving leftward to a position on the left edge of the clause called Spec CP Thus a derivation of the English question What did John buy would proceed roughly as follows CP Spec CP position John did buy what wh movement dd CP What did John buy The Japanese equivalent of this sentence is as follows 6 note the lack of wh movement John wa nani o kaimashita kaJohn topic marker what accusative bought question particleJapanese has an overt question particle ka which appears at the end of the sentence in questions It is generally assumed that languages such as English have a covert i e phonologically null equivalent of this particle in the C position of the clause the position just to the right of Spec CP This particle is overtly realised in English by the movement of an auxiliary to C in the case of the example above by the movement of did to C Why is it that this particle is on the left edge of the clause in English but on the right edge in Japanese Kayne suggests that in Japanese the whole of the clause apart from the question particle in C has moved to the Spec CP position So the structure for the Japanese example above is something like the following CP John wa nani o kaimashita C kaNow it is clear why Japanese does not have wh movement the Spec CP position is already filled so no wh phrase can move to it The relationship between surface word order and the possibility of wh movement is seemingly obscure A possible alternative to the antisymmetric explanation could be based on the difficulty of parsing languages with rightward movement 7 Dynamic antisymmetry editAndrea Moro proposed Dynamic antisymmetry a weak version of antisymmetry which allows the generation of non LCA compatible structures points of symmetry before the hierarchical structure is linearized at Phonetic Form PF The unwanted structures are then rescued by movement deleting the phonetic content of the moved element neutralizes the linearization problem 8 Dynamic Antisymmetry aims at unifying a movement and phrase structure which otherwise are independent properties Antisymmetry and ternary branching editKayne proposed recasting the antisymmetry of natural language as a condition on Merge the operation which combines two elements into one Kayne proposes that merging a head H and its complement C yields an ordered pair H C displaystyle langle H C rangle nbsp rather than the standard symmetric set H C H C displaystyle langle H C rangle nbsp involves immediate temporal precedence or immediate linear precedence so that H immediately precedes i precedes C Kayne proposes furthermore that when a specifier S merges it forms an ordered pair with the head directly S H displaystyle langle S H rangle nbsp or S i precedes H Invoking i precedence prevents more than two elements from merging with H only one element can i precede H the specifier and H can i precede only one element the complement 9 Kayne notes that S H H C displaystyle langle S H rangle langle H C rangle nbsp is not mappable to a tree structure since H would have two mothers and that it has the consequence that S H displaystyle langle S H rangle nbsp and H C displaystyle langle H C rangle nbsp would seem to be constituents He suggests that S H H C displaystyle langle S H rangle langle H C rangle nbsp is replaced by S H C displaystyle langle S H C rangle nbsp with an ordered triple replacing the two ordered pairs and then being mappable to a ternary branching tree pp 17 Kayne goes on to say This would lead to seeing my 1981 10 arguments for binary branching to have two subcomponents the first being the claim that syntax is n ary branching with n having a single value the second being that that value is 2 Mapping S H H C displaystyle langle S H rangle langle H C rangle nbsp to S H C displaystyle langle S H C rangle nbsp would retain the first subcomponent and replace 2 by 3 in the second arguably with no loss in restrictiveness 9 Theoretical arguments editAntisymmetry theory rejects the head directionality parameter as such it claims that at an underlying level all languages are head initial In fact it argued that all languages have the underlying order Specifier Head Complement Deviations from this order are accounted for by different syntactic movements applied by languages Kayne argues that a theory that allows both directionalities would state that languages are symmetrical whereas in fact languages are found to be asymmetrical in many respects Examples of linguistic asymmetries which may be cited in support of the theory although they do not concern head direction are Hanging topics appear at the start of sentences as in Henry I ve known that guy for a long time 11 They are not attested at the end of sentences 12 Number agreement is stronger when the noun phrase precedes the verb Greenberg s Universal 33 Examples of this are found in English sentences such as There s books on the table where the verb frequently fails to agree with the following plural noun and in French and Italian compound tenses 13 where the past participle may agree with a preceding direct object but not with the following one Relative clauses that precede the noun as in Chinese and Japanese tend to differ from those that follow the noun they more often lack complementizers akin to English that or relative pronouns and are more likely to be non finite this can be found for example in Quechuan languages 14 Other areas in which asymmetries are found according to Kayne include clitics and clitic dislocation serial verb constructions coordination and forward and backward pronominalization nbsp X bar syntactic tree showing the movement of the specifier S relative to the head H and complement C In arguing for a universal underlying Head Complement order Kayne uses the concept of a probe goal search based on the Minimalist program The idea of probes and goals in syntax is that a head acts as a probe and looks for a goal namely its complement Kayne proposes that the direction of the probe goal search must share the direction of language parsing and production 15 Parsing and production proceed in a left to right direction the beginning of the sentence is heard or spoken first and the end of the sentence is heard or spoken last This implies according to the theory an ordering whereby probe comes before the goal i e head precedes complement Kayne s theory also addresses the position of the specifier of a phrase He represents the relevant scheme as follows 16 S H c S The specifier at first internal to the complement is moved to the unoccupied position to the left of the head In terms of merged pairs this structure can also be represented as S H H C This process can be mapped onto X bar syntactic trees as shown in the adjacent diagram Antisymmetry then leads to a universal Specifier Head Complement order The varied ordering found in human languages are explained by syntactic movement away from this underlying base order It has been pointed out though that in predominantly head final languages such as Japanese and Basque this would involve complex and massive leftward movement which violates the ideal of grammatical simplicity 17 An example of the type of movement scheme that would need to be envisaged is provided by Tokizaki 18 CP C IP VP V PP P NP N Genitive Affix Stem CP C IP VP V PP P NP N Genitive Stem Affix CP C IP VP V PP P NP Genitive Stem Affix N CP C IP VP V PP NP Genitive Stem Affix N P CP C IP VP PP NP Genitive Stem Affix N P V CP IP VP PP NP Genitive Stem Affix N P V C Here at each phrasal level in turn the head of the phrase moves from left to right position relative to its complement The eventual result reflects the ordering of complex nested phrases found in languages such as Japanese An attempt to provide evidence for Kayne s scheme is made by Lin 19 who considered Standard Chinese sentences with the sentence final particle le This particle is taken to convey perfect aspectual meaning and thus to be the head of an aspect phrase having the verb phrase as its complement If phrases are always essentially head initial then a case like this must entail movement since the particle comes after the verb phrase It is proposed that there the complement moves into specifier position which precedes the head As evidence for this Lin considers wh adverbials such as zenmeyang how Based on prior work by James Huang 20 it is postulated that a adverbials of this type are subject to movement at logical form LF level even though in Chinese they do not display wh movement at surface level and b movement is not possible from within a non complement Huang s Condition on Extraction Domain or CED clarification needed This would imply that zenmeyang could not appear in a verb phrase with sentence final le assuming the above analysis since that verb phrase has moved into a non complement specifier position and thus further movement such as that which zenmeyang is required to undergo at LF level is not possible Such a restriction on the occurrence of zenmeyang is indeed found 21 a ZhangsanZhangsanzenmeyanghowxiurepairche carZhangsan zenmeyang xiu che Zhangsan how repair car How does Zhangsan repair the car b ZhangsanZhangsanzenmeyanghowxiurepairchecarle PF Zhangsan zenmeyang xiu che le Zhangsan how repair car PF How has Zhangsan repaired the car Sentence b in which zenmeyang co occurs with sentence final le is ungrammatical Lin cites this and other related findings as evidence that the above analysis is correct supporting the view that Chinese aspect phrases are deeply head initial Surface true approach edit According to the surface true viewpoint analysis of head direction must take place at the level of surface derivations or even the Phonetic Form i e the order in which sentences are pronounced in natural speech This rejects the idea of an underlying ordering which is then subject to movement In a 2008 article Marc Richards argued that a head parameter must only reside at PF as it is unmaintainable in its original form as a structural parameter 22 In this approach the relative positions of head and complement that are attested at this surface level which show variation both between and within languages see above must be treated as the true orderings Existence of true head final languages edit Takita argues against the conclusion of Kayne s Antisymmetry Theory which states that all languages are head initial at an underlying level He claims that a language such as Japanese is truly head final since the mass movement which would be required to take an underlying head initial structure to the head final ones actually found in such languages would violate other constraints It is implied that such languages are likely following a head final parameter value as originally conceived 23 For a head initial Antisymmetry analysis of Japanese see Kayne 24 Takita s argument is based on Lin s analysis of Chinese Since surface head final structures are derived from underlying head initial structures by moving the complements further extraction from within the moved complement violates CED One of the examples of movement which Takita looks at is that of VP fronting in Japanese Grammatically the sentence without VP fronting a and the sentence where the VP moves to the matrix clause b do not significantly differ 23 a CP1 Taro gaTaro NOM CP2 IP2 Hanako gaHanako NOM VP2 hon obook ACCsute saediscard evenshitadidto C omotteiru think CP1 Taro ga CP2 IP2 Hanako ga VP2 hon o sute sae shita to omotteiru Taro NOM Hanako NOM book ACC discard even did C think Taro thinks that Hanako even discarded his books Takita 2009 57 33a b CP1 VP2 Hon obook ACCsute saeidiscard evenTaro gaTaro NOM CP2 IP2 Hanako gaHanako NOMshita didto C omotteiruthink CP1 VP2 Hon o sute saei Taro ga CP2 IP2 Hanako ga shita to omotteiru book ACC discard even Taro NOM Hanako NOM did C think Even discarded his books Taro thinks that Hanako did ti Takita 2009 57 33b In b the fronted VP precedes the matrix subject confirming that the VP is located in the matrix clause If Japanese were head initial b should not be grammatical because it allows for the extraction of an element VP2 from the moved complement CP2 23 Thus Takita shows that surface head final structures in Japanese do not block movement as they do in Chinese He concludes that because Japanese does not block movement as shown in previous sections it is a genuinely head final language and not derived from an underlying head initial structure These results imply that Universal Grammar involves binary head directionality and is not antisymmetric Takita briefly applies the same tests to Turkish another seemingly head final language and reports similar results 25 References edit Kayne 1994 Li Yafei 2005 A Theory of the Morphology Syntax Interface MIT Press Reinhart Tanya 1979 The Syntactic Domain of Anaphora Doctoral dissertation PDF M I T Press Since any rightward movement must also be downward movement if there are no rightward specifiers or right adjunction and downward movement is generally assumed to be illicit Kayne 1994 pp 34 36 Jamal Ouhalla 1999 Introducing Transformational Grammar Second ed Arnold Oxford University Press See p 461 for the Japanese example Neeleman Ad amp Peter Ackema 2002 Effects of Short Term Storage in Processing Rightward Movement In S Nooteboom et al eds Storage and Computation in the Language Faculty Dordrecht Kluwer Pages 219 256 Moro A 2000 Dynamic Antisymmetry Linguistic Inquiry Monograph Series 38 MIT Press Cambridge Massachusetts a b Kayne 2010 Kayne Richard S 1981 Unambiguous Paths in Robert May and Jan Koster eds Levels of Syntactic Representation Dordrecht Kluwer Pages 143 183 Nolda Andreas 2004 Topics Detached to the Left On Left Dislocation Hanging Topic and Related Constructions in German Berlin ZAS Papers in Linguistics pp 423 448 Kayne 2010 p 4 Kayne 2010 p 7 Courtney Ellen H 2011 Learning to produce Quechua relative clauses Acquisition of Relative Clauses Processing typology and function John Benjamins Publishing Company p 150 Kayne 2010 p 12 Kayne 2010 p 15 Elordieta Arantzazu 2014 Biberauer T Sheehan M eds On the relevance of the Head Parameter in a mixed OV language Theoretical Approaches to Disharmonic Word Order Oxford Scholarship Online p 5 Tokizaki Hisao 2011 The nature of linear information in the morphosyntax PF interface English Linguistics 28 2 p 238 Lin Tzong Hong J 2006 Complement to specifier movement in Mandarin Chinese Ms National Tsing Hua University Huang C T J 1982 Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar PhD dissertation MIT Takita 2009 p 44 Richards Marc D 2008 Desymmetrization Parametric variation at the PF Interface The Canadian Journal of Linguistics 53 2 3 p 283 a b c Takita 2009 p 57 Kayne Richard S 2003 Antisymmetry and Japanese English Linguistics 20 1 40 Takita 2009 p 59 Sources editKayne Richard S 1994 The Antisymmetry of Syntax Linguistic Inquiry Monograph Twenty Five MIT Press ISBN 978 0262611077 Kayne Richard S February 12 2010 Why are there no directionality parameters 28th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics University of Southern California ISBN 978 1 57473 441 6 Takita Kensuke February 2009 If Chinese is head initial Japanese cannot be Journal of East Asian Linguistics 18 1 41 61 doi 10 1007 s10831 009 9038 z ISSN 0925 8558 S2CID 121661611 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Antisymmetry amp oldid 1183209114, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.