fbpx
Wikipedia

Lambda calculus

Lambda calculus (also written as λ-calculus) is a formal system in mathematical logic for expressing computation based on function abstraction and application using variable binding and substitution. It is a universal model of computation that can be used to simulate any Turing machine. It was introduced by the mathematician Alonzo Church in the 1930s as part of his research into the foundations of mathematics.

Lambda calculus consists of constructing lambda terms and performing reduction operations on them. In the simplest form of lambda calculus, terms are built using only the following rules:[a]

  1. : A variable is a character or string representing a parameter.
  2. : A lambda abstraction is a function definition, taking as input the bound variable (between the λ and the punctum/dot .) and returning the body .
  3. : An application, applying a function to an argument . Both and are lambda terms.

The reduction operations include:

  • : α-conversion, renaming the bound variables in the expression. Used to avoid name collisions.
  • : β-reduction,[b] replacing the bound variables with the argument expression in the body of the abstraction.

If De Bruijn indexing is used, then α-conversion is no longer required as there will be no name collisions. If repeated application of the reduction steps eventually terminates, then by the Church–Rosser theorem it will produce a β-normal form.

Variable names are not needed if using a universal lambda function, such as Iota and Jot, which can create any function behavior by calling it on itself in various combinations.

Explanation and applications edit

Lambda calculus is Turing complete, that is, it is a universal model of computation that can be used to simulate any Turing machine.[3] Its namesake, the Greek letter lambda (λ), is used in lambda expressions and lambda terms to denote binding a variable in a function.

Lambda calculus may be untyped or typed. In typed lambda calculus, functions can be applied only if they are capable of accepting the given input's "type" of data. Typed lambda calculi are weaker than the untyped lambda calculus, which is the primary subject of this article, in the sense that typed lambda calculi can express less than the untyped calculus can. On the other hand, typed lambda calculi allow more things to be proven. For example, in the simply typed lambda calculus it is a theorem that every evaluation strategy terminates for every simply typed lambda-term, whereas evaluation of untyped lambda-terms need not terminate (see below). One reason there are many different typed lambda calculi has been the desire to do more (of what the untyped calculus can do) without giving up on being able to prove strong theorems about the calculus.

Lambda calculus has applications in many different areas in mathematics, philosophy,[4] linguistics,[5][6] and computer science.[7][8] Lambda calculus has played an important role in the development of the theory of programming languages. Functional programming languages implement lambda calculus. Lambda calculus is also a current research topic in category theory.[9]

History edit

The lambda calculus was introduced by mathematician Alonzo Church in the 1930s as part of an investigation into the foundations of mathematics.[10][c] The original system was shown to be logically inconsistent in 1935 when Stephen Kleene and J. B. Rosser developed the Kleene–Rosser paradox.[11][12]

Subsequently, in 1936 Church isolated and published just the portion relevant to computation, what is now called the untyped lambda calculus.[13] In 1940, he also introduced a computationally weaker, but logically consistent system, known as the simply typed lambda calculus.[14]

Until the 1960s when its relation to programming languages was clarified, the lambda calculus was only a formalism. Thanks to Richard Montague and other linguists' applications in the semantics of natural language, the lambda calculus has begun to enjoy a respectable place in both linguistics[15] and computer science.[16]

Origin of the λ symbol edit

There is some uncertainty over the reason for Church's use of the Greek letter lambda (λ) as the notation for function-abstraction in the lambda calculus, perhaps in part due to conflicting explanations by Church himself. According to Cardone and Hindley (2006):

By the way, why did Church choose the notation “λ”? In [an unpublished 1964 letter to Harald Dickson] he stated clearly that it came from the notation “ ” used for class-abstraction by Whitehead and Russell, by first modifying “ ” to “ ” to distinguish function-abstraction from class-abstraction, and then changing “ ” to “λ” for ease of printing.

This origin was also reported in [Rosser, 1984, p.338]. On the other hand, in his later years Church told two enquirers that the choice was more accidental: a symbol was needed and λ just happened to be chosen.

Dana Scott has also addressed this question in various public lectures.[17] Scott recounts that he once posed a question about the origin of the lambda symbol to Church's former student and son-in-law John W. Addison Jr., who then wrote his father-in-law a postcard:

Dear Professor Church,

Russell had the iota operator, Hilbert had the epsilon operator. Why did you choose lambda for your operator?

According to Scott, Church's entire response consisted of returning the postcard with the following annotation: "eeny, meeny, miny, moe".

Informal description edit

Motivation edit

Computable functions are a fundamental concept within computer science and mathematics. The lambda calculus provides simple semantics for computation which are useful for formally studying properties of computation. The lambda calculus incorporates two simplifications that make its semantics simple. The first simplification is that the lambda calculus treats functions "anonymously;" it does not give them explicit names. For example, the function

 

can be rewritten in anonymous form as

 

(which is read as "a tuple of x and y is mapped to  ").[d] Similarly, the function

 

can be rewritten in anonymous form as

 

where the input is simply mapped to itself.[d]

The second simplification is that the lambda calculus only uses functions of a single input. An ordinary function that requires two inputs, for instance the   function, can be reworked into an equivalent function that accepts a single input, and as output returns another function, that in turn accepts a single input. For example,

 

can be reworked into

 

This method, known as currying, transforms a function that takes multiple arguments into a chain of functions each with a single argument.

Function application of the   function to the arguments (5, 2), yields at once

 
 
 ,

whereas evaluation of the curried version requires one more step

 
  // the definition of   has been used with   in the inner expression. This is like β-reduction.
  // the definition of   has been used with  . Again, similar to β-reduction.
 

to arrive at the same result.

The lambda calculus edit

The lambda calculus consists of a language of lambda terms, that are defined by a certain formal syntax, and a set of transformation rules for manipulating the lambda terms. These transformation rules can be viewed as an equational theory or as an operational definition.

As described above, having no names, all functions in the lambda calculus are anonymous functions. They only accept one input variable, so currying is used to implement functions of several variables.

Lambda terms edit

The syntax of the lambda calculus defines some expressions as valid lambda calculus expressions and some as invalid, just as some strings of characters are valid C programs and some are not. A valid lambda calculus expression is called a "lambda term".

The following three rules give an inductive definition that can be applied to build all syntactically valid lambda terms:[e]

  • variable x is itself a valid lambda term.
  • if t is a lambda term, and x is a variable, then   [f] is a lambda term (called an abstraction);
  • if t and s are lambda terms, then      is a lambda term (called an application).

Nothing else is a lambda term. Thus a lambda term is valid if and only if it can be obtained by repeated application of these three rules. However, some parentheses can be omitted according to certain rules. For example, the outermost parentheses are usually not written. See §Notation, below for when to include parentheses

An abstraction   denotes an § anonymous function[g] that takes a single input x and returns t. For example,   is an abstraction for the function   using the term   for t. The name   is superfluous when using abstraction.   binds the variable x in the term t. The definition of a function with an abstraction merely "sets up" the function but does not invoke it. See §Notation below for usage of parentheses

An application      represents the application of a function t to an input s, that is, it represents the act of calling function t on input s to produce  .

There is no concept in lambda calculus of variable declaration. In a definition such as   (i.e.  ), in lambda calculus y is a variable that is not yet defined. The abstraction   is syntactically valid, and represents a function that adds its input to the yet-unknown y.

Parentheses may be used and might be needed to disambiguate terms. For example,

  1.   which is of form   — an abstraction, and
  2.     which is of form      — an application.

The examples 1 and 2 denote different terms; except for the scope of the parentheses they would be the same. But example 1 is a function definition, while example 2 is function application. Lambda variable x is a placeholder in both examples.

Here, example 1 defines a function  , where   is  , an anonymous function  , with input  ; while example 2,    , is M applied to N, where   is the lambda term   being applied to the input   which is  . Both examples 1 and 2 would evaluate to the identity function  .

Functions that operate on functions edit

In lambda calculus, functions are taken to be 'first class values', so functions may be used as the inputs, or be returned as outputs from other functions.

For example, the lambda term   represents the identity function,  . Further,   represents the constant function  , the function that always returns  , no matter the input. As an example of a function operating on functions, the function composition can be defined as  .

There are several notions of "equivalence" and "reduction" that allow lambda terms to be "reduced" to "equivalent" lambda terms.

Alpha equivalence edit

A basic form of equivalence, definable on lambda terms, is alpha equivalence. It captures the intuition that the particular choice of a bound variable, in an abstraction, does not (usually) matter. For instance,   and   are alpha-equivalent lambda terms, and they both represent the same function (the identity function). The terms   and   are not alpha-equivalent, because they are not bound in an abstraction. In many presentations, it is usual to identify alpha-equivalent lambda terms.

The following definitions are necessary in order to be able to define β-reduction:

Free variables edit

The free variables [h] of a term are those variables not bound by an abstraction. The set of free variables of an expression is defined inductively:

  • The free variables of   are just  
  • The set of free variables of   is the set of free variables of  , but with   removed
  • The set of free variables of     is the union of the set of free variables of   and the set of free variables of  .

For example, the lambda term representing the identity   has no free variables, but the function     has a single free variable,  .

Capture-avoiding substitutions edit

Suppose  ,   and   are lambda terms, and   and   are variables. The notation   indicates substitution of   for   in   in a capture-avoiding manner. This is defined so that:

  •   ; with   substituted for  ,   becomes  
  •   if   ; with   substituted for  ,   (which is not  ) remains  
  •     ; substitution distributes to both sides of an application
  •   ; a variable bound by an abstraction is not subject to substitution; substituting such variable leaves the abstraction unchanged
  •   if   and   does not appear among the free variables of   (  is said to be "fresh" for  ) ; substituting a variable which is not bound by an abstraction proceeds in the abstraction's body, provided that the abstracted variable   is "fresh" for the substitution term  .

For example,  , and  .

The freshness condition (requiring that   is not in the free variables of  ) is crucial in order to ensure that substitution does not change the meaning of functions.

For example, a substitution that ignores the freshness condition could lead to errors:  . This erroneous substitution would turn the constant function   into the identity  .

In general, failure to meet the freshness condition can be remedied by alpha-renaming first, with a suitable fresh variable. For example, switching back to our correct notion of substitution, in   the abstraction can be renamed with a fresh variable  , to obtain  , and the meaning of the function is preserved by substitution.

β-reduction edit

The β-reduction rule[b] states that an application of the form   reduces to the term  . The notation   is used to indicate that   β-reduces to  . For example, for every  ,  . This demonstrates that   really is the identity. Similarly,  , which demonstrates that   is a constant function.

The lambda calculus may be seen as an idealized version of a functional programming language, like Haskell or Standard ML. Under this view, β-reduction corresponds to a computational step. This step can be repeated by additional β-reductions until there are no more applications left to reduce. In the untyped lambda calculus, as presented here, this reduction process may not terminate. For instance, consider the term  . Here  . That is, the term reduces to itself in a single β-reduction, and therefore the reduction process will never terminate.

Another aspect of the untyped lambda calculus is that it does not distinguish between different kinds of data. For instance, it may be desirable to write a function that only operates on numbers. However, in the untyped lambda calculus, there is no way to prevent a function from being applied to truth values, strings, or other non-number objects.

Formal definition edit

Definition edit

Lambda expressions are composed of:

  • variables v1, v2, ...;
  • the abstraction symbols λ (lambda) and . (dot);
  • parentheses ().

The set of lambda expressions, Λ, can be defined inductively:

  1. If x is a variable, then x ∈ Λ.
  2. If x is a variable and M ∈ Λ, then x.M) ∈ Λ.
  3. If M, N ∈ Λ, then (M N) ∈ Λ.

Instances of rule 2 are known as abstractions and instances of rule 3 are known as applications.[18][19]

Notation edit

To keep the notation of lambda expressions uncluttered, the following conventions are usually applied:

  • Outermost parentheses are dropped: M N instead of (M N).
  • Applications are assumed to be left associative: M N P may be written instead of ((M N) P).[20]
  • When all variables are single-letter, the space in applications may be omitted: MNP instead of M N P.[21]
  • The body of an abstraction extends as far right as possible: λx.M N means λx.(M N) and not (λx.M) N.
  • A sequence of abstractions is contracted: λxyz.N is abbreviated as λxyz.N.[22][20]

Free and bound variables edit

The abstraction operator, λ, is said to bind its variable wherever it occurs in the body of the abstraction. Variables that fall within the scope of an abstraction are said to be bound. In an expression λx.M, the part λx is often called binder, as a hint that the variable x is getting bound by prepending λx to M. All other variables are called free. For example, in the expression λy.x x y, y is a bound variable and x is a free variable. Also a variable is bound by its nearest abstraction. In the following example the single occurrence of x in the expression is bound by the second lambda: λx.yx.z x).

The set of free variables of a lambda expression, M, is denoted as FV(M) and is defined by recursion on the structure of the terms, as follows:

  1. FV(x) = {x}, where x is a variable.
  2. FV(λx.M) = FV(M) \ {x}.[i]
  3. FV(M N) = FV(M) ∪ FV(N).[j]

An expression that contains no free variables is said to be closed. Closed lambda expressions are also known as combinators and are equivalent to terms in combinatory logic.

Reduction edit

The meaning of lambda expressions is defined by how expressions can be reduced.[23]

There are three kinds of reduction:

  • α-conversion: changing bound variables;
  • β-reduction: applying functions to their arguments;
  • η-reduction: which captures a notion of extensionality.

We also speak of the resulting equivalences: two expressions are α-equivalent, if they can be α-converted into the same expression. β-equivalence and η-equivalence are defined similarly.

The term redex, short for reducible expression, refers to subterms that can be reduced by one of the reduction rules. For example, (λx.M) N is a β-redex in expressing the substitution of N for x in M. The expression to which a redex reduces is called its reduct; the reduct of (λx.M) N is M[x := N].[b]

If x is not free in M, λx.M x is also an η-redex, with a reduct of M.

α-conversion edit

α-conversion (alpha-conversion), sometimes known as α-renaming,[24] allows bound variable names to be changed. For example, α-conversion of λx.x might yield λy.y. Terms that differ only by α-conversion are called α-equivalent. Frequently, in uses of lambda calculus, α-equivalent terms are considered to be equivalent.

The precise rules for α-conversion are not completely trivial. First, when α-converting an abstraction, the only variable occurrences that are renamed are those that are bound to the same abstraction. For example, an α-conversion of λxx.x could result in λyx.x, but it could not result in λyx.y. The latter has a different meaning from the original. This is analogous to the programming notion of variable shadowing.

Second, α-conversion is not possible if it would result in a variable getting captured by a different abstraction. For example, if we replace x with y in λxy.x, we get λyy.y, which is not at all the same.

In programming languages with static scope, α-conversion can be used to make name resolution simpler by ensuring that no variable name masks a name in a containing scope (see α-renaming to make name resolution trivial).

In the De Bruijn index notation, any two α-equivalent terms are syntactically identical.

Substitution edit

Substitution, written M[x := N], is the process of replacing all free occurrences of the variable x in the expression M with expression N. Substitution on terms of the lambda calculus is defined by recursion on the structure of terms, as follows (note: x and y are only variables while M and N are any lambda expression):

x[x := N] = N
y[x := N] = y, if xy
(M1 M2)[x := N] = M1[x := N] M2[x := N]
x.M)[x := N] = λx.M
y.M)[x := N] = λy.(M[x := N]), if xy and y ∉ FV(N) See above for the FV

To substitute into an abstraction, it is sometimes necessary to α-convert the expression. For example, it is not correct for (λx.y)[y := x] to result in λx.x, because the substituted x was supposed to be free but ended up being bound. The correct substitution in this case is λz.x, up to α-equivalence. Substitution is defined uniquely up to α-equivalence. See Capture-avoiding substitutions above

β-reduction edit

β-reduction (beta reduction) captures the idea of function application. β-reduction is defined in terms of substitution: the β-reduction of (λx.M) N is M[x := N].[b]

For example, assuming some encoding of 2, 7, ×, we have the following β-reduction: (λn.n × 2) 7 → 7 × 2.

β-reduction can be seen to be the same as the concept of local reducibility in natural deduction, via the Curry–Howard isomorphism.

η-reduction edit

η-reduction (eta reduction) expresses the idea of extensionality,[25] which in this context is that two functions are the same if and only if they give the same result for all arguments. η-reduction converts between λx.f x and f whenever x does not appear free in f.

η-reduction can be seen to be the same as the concept of local completeness in natural deduction, via the Curry–Howard isomorphism.

Normal forms and confluence edit

For the untyped lambda calculus, β-reduction as a rewriting rule is neither strongly normalising nor weakly normalising.

However, it can be shown that β-reduction is confluent when working up to α-conversion (i.e. we consider two normal forms to be equal if it is possible to α-convert one into the other).

Therefore, both strongly normalising terms and weakly normalising terms have a unique normal form. For strongly normalising terms, any reduction strategy is guaranteed to yield the normal form, whereas for weakly normalising terms, some reduction strategies may fail to find it.

Encoding datatypes edit

The basic lambda calculus may be used to model arithmetic, booleans, data structures, and recursion, as illustrated in the following sub-sections i, ii, iii, and § iv.

Arithmetic in lambda calculus edit

There are several possible ways to define the natural numbers in lambda calculus, but by far the most common are the Church numerals, which can be defined as follows:

0 := λfx.x
1 := λfx.f x
2 := λfx.f (f x)
3 := λfx.f (f (f x))

and so on. Or using the alternative syntax presented above in Notation:

0 := λfx.x
1 := λfx.f x
2 := λfx.f (f x)
3 := λfx.f (f (f x))

A Church numeral is a higher-order function—it takes a single-argument function f, and returns another single-argument function. The Church numeral n is a function that takes a function f as argument and returns the n-th composition of f, i.e. the function f composed with itself n times. This is denoted f(n) and is in fact the n-th power of f (considered as an operator); f(0) is defined to be the identity function. Such repeated compositions (of a single function f) obey the laws of exponents, which is why these numerals can be used for arithmetic. (In Church's original lambda calculus, the formal parameter of a lambda expression was required to occur at least once in the function body, which made the above definition of 0 impossible.)

One way of thinking about the Church numeral n, which is often useful when analysing programs, is as an instruction 'repeat n times'. For example, using the PAIR and NIL functions defined below, one can define a function that constructs a (linked) list of n elements all equal to x by repeating 'prepend another x element' n times, starting from an empty list. The lambda term is

λnx.n (PAIR x) NIL

By varying what is being repeated, and varying what argument that function being repeated is applied to, a great many different effects can be achieved.

We can define a successor function, which takes a Church numeral n and returns n + 1 by adding another application of f, where '(mf)x' means the function 'f' is applied 'm' times on 'x':

SUCC := λnfx.f (n f x)

Because the m-th composition of f composed with the n-th composition of f gives the m+n-th composition of f, addition can be defined as follows:

PLUS := λmnfx.m f (n f x)

PLUS can be thought of as a function taking two natural numbers as arguments and returning a natural number; it can be verified that

PLUS 2 3

and

5

are β-equivalent lambda expressions. Since adding m to a number n can be accomplished by adding 1 m times, an alternative definition is:

PLUS := λmn.m SUCC n [26]

Similarly, multiplication can be defined as

MULT := λmnf.m (n f)[22]

Alternatively

MULT := λmn.m (PLUS n) 0

since multiplying m and n is the same as repeating the add n function m times and then applying it to zero. Exponentiation has a rather simple rendering in Church numerals, namely

POW := λbe.e b[1]

The predecessor function defined by PRED n = n − 1 for a positive integer n and PRED 0 = 0 is considerably more difficult. The formula

PRED := λnfx.ngh.h (g f)) (λu.x) (λu.u)

can be validated by showing inductively that if T denotes gh.h (g f)), then T(n)u.x) = (λh.h(f(n−1)(x))) for n > 0. Two other definitions of PRED are given below, one using conditionals and the other using pairs. With the predecessor function, subtraction is straightforward. Defining

SUB := λmn.n PRED m,

SUB m n yields mn when m > n and 0 otherwise.

Logic and predicates edit

By convention, the following two definitions (known as Church booleans) are used for the boolean values TRUE and FALSE:

TRUE := λxy.x
FALSE := λxy.y

Then, with these two lambda terms, we can define some logic operators (these are just possible formulations; other expressions could be equally correct):

AND := λpq.p q p
OR := λpq.p p q
NOT := λp.p FALSE TRUE
IFTHENELSE := λpab.p a b

We are now able to compute some logic functions, for example:

AND TRUE FALSE
≡ (λpq.p q p) TRUE FALSE →β TRUE FALSE TRUE
≡ (λxy.x) FALSE TRUE →β FALSE

and we see that AND TRUE FALSE is equivalent to FALSE.

A predicate is a function that returns a boolean value. The most fundamental predicate is ISZERO, which returns TRUE if its argument is the Church numeral 0, but FALSE if its argument were any other Church numeral:

ISZERO := λn.nx.FALSE) TRUE

The following predicate tests whether the first argument is less-than-or-equal-to the second:

LEQ := λmn.ISZERO (SUB m n),

and since m = n, if LEQ m n and LEQ n m, it is straightforward to build a predicate for numerical equality.

The availability of predicates and the above definition of TRUE and FALSE make it convenient to write "if-then-else" expressions in lambda calculus. For example, the predecessor function can be defined as:

PRED := λn.ngk.ISZERO (g 1) k (PLUS (g k) 1)) (λv.0) 0

which can be verified by showing inductively that ngk.ISZERO (g 1) k (PLUS (g k) 1)) (λv.0) is the add n − 1 function for n > 0.

Pairs edit

A pair (2-tuple) can be defined in terms of TRUE and FALSE, by using the Church encoding for pairs. For example, PAIR encapsulates the pair (x,y), FIRST returns the first element of the pair, and SECOND returns the second.

PAIR := λxyf.f x y
FIRST := λp.p TRUE
SECOND := λp.p FALSE
NIL := λx.TRUE
NULL := λp.pxy.FALSE)

A linked list can be defined as either NIL for the empty list, or the PAIR of an element and a smaller list. The predicate NULL tests for the value NIL. (Alternatively, with NIL := FALSE, the construct lhtz.deal_with_head_h_and_tail_t) (deal_with_nil) obviates the need for an explicit NULL test).

As an example of the use of pairs, the shift-and-increment function that maps (m, n) to (n, n + 1) can be defined as

Φ := λx.PAIR (SECOND x) (SUCC (SECOND x))

which allows us to give perhaps the most transparent version of the predecessor function:

PRED := λn.FIRST (n Φ (PAIR 0 0)).

Additional programming techniques edit

There is a considerable body of programming idioms for lambda calculus. Many of these were originally developed in the context of using lambda calculus as a foundation for programming language semantics, effectively using lambda calculus as a low-level programming language. Because several programming languages include the lambda calculus (or something very similar) as a fragment, these techniques also see use in practical programming, but may then be perceived as obscure or foreign.

Named constants edit

In lambda calculus, a library would take the form of a collection of previously defined functions, which as lambda-terms are merely particular constants. The pure lambda calculus does not have a concept of named constants since all atomic lambda-terms are variables, but one can emulate having named constants by setting aside a variable as the name of the constant, using abstraction to bind that variable in the main body, and apply that abstraction to the intended definition. Thus to use f to mean N (some explicit lambda-term) in M (another lambda-term, the "main program"), one can say

f.M) N

Authors often introduce syntactic sugar, such as let,[k] to permit writing the above in the more intuitive order

let f =N in M

By chaining such definitions, one can write a lambda calculus "program" as zero or more function definitions, followed by one lambda-term using those functions that constitutes the main body of the program.

A notable restriction of this let is that the name f be not defined in N, for N to be outside the scope of the abstraction binding f; this means a recursive function definition cannot be used as the N with let. The letrec[l] construction would allow writing recursive function definitions.

Recursion and fixed points edit

Recursion is the definition of a function using the function itself. A definition containing itself inside itself, by value, leads to the whole value being of infinite size. Other notations which support recursion natively overcome this by referring to the function definition by name. Lambda calculus cannot express this: all functions are anonymous in lambda calculus, so we can't refer by name to a value which is yet to be defined, inside the lambda term defining that same value. However, a lambda expression can receive itself as its own argument, for example in  x.x x) E. Here E should be an abstraction, applying its parameter to a value to express recursion.

Consider the factorial function F(n) recursively defined by

F(n) = 1, if n = 0; else n × F(n − 1).

In the lambda expression which is to represent this function, a parameter (typically the first one) will be assumed to receive the lambda expression itself as its value, so that calling it – applying it to an argument – will amount to recursion. Thus to achieve recursion, the intended-as-self-referencing argument (called r here) must always be passed to itself within the function body, at a call point:

G := λr. λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × (r r (n−1)))
with  r r x = F x = G r x  to hold, so  r = G  and
F := G G = (λx.x x) G

The self-application achieves replication here, passing the function's lambda expression on to the next invocation as an argument value, making it available to be referenced and called there.

This solves it but requires re-writing each recursive call as self-application. We would like to have a generic solution, without a need for any re-writes:

G := λr. λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × (r (n−1)))
with  r x = F x = G r x  to hold, so  r = G r =: FIX G  and
F := FIX G  where  FIX g := (r where r = g r) = g (FIX g)
so that  FIX G = G (FIX G) = (λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × ((FIX G) (n−1))))

Given a lambda term with first argument representing recursive call (e.g. G here), the fixed-point combinator FIX will return a self-replicating lambda expression representing the recursive function (here, F). The function does not need to be explicitly passed to itself at any point, for the self-replication is arranged in advance, when it is created, to be done each time it is called. Thus the original lambda expression (FIX G) is re-created inside itself, at call-point, achieving self-reference.

In fact, there are many possible definitions for this FIX operator, the simplest of them being:

Y := λg.(λx.g (x x)) (λx.g (x x))

In the lambda calculus, Y g  is a fixed-point of g, as it expands to:

Y g
h.(λx.h (x x)) (λx.h (x x))) g
x.g (x x)) (λx.g (x x))
g ((λx.g (x x)) (λx.g (x x)))
g (Y g)

Now, to perform our recursive call to the factorial function, we would simply call (Y G) n,  where n is the number we are calculating the factorial of. Given n = 4, for example, this gives:

(Y G) 4
G (Y G) 4
rn.(1, if n = 0; else n × (r (n−1)))) (Y G) 4
n.(1, if n = 0; else n × ((Y G) (n−1)))) 4
1, if 4 = 0; else 4 × ((Y G) (4−1))
4 × (G (Y G) (4−1))
4 × ((λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × ((Y G) (n−1)))) (4−1))
4 × (1, if 3 = 0; else 3 × ((Y G) (3−1)))
4 × (3 × (G (Y G) (3−1)))
4 × (3 × ((λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × ((Y G) (n−1)))) (3−1)))
4 × (3 × (1, if 2 = 0; else 2 × ((Y G) (2−1))))
4 × (3 × (2 × (G (Y G) (2−1))))
4 × (3 × (2 × ((λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × ((Y G) (n−1)))) (2−1))))
4 × (3 × (2 × (1, if 1 = 0; else 1 × ((Y G) (1−1)))))
4 × (3 × (2 × (1 × (G (Y G) (1−1)))))
4 × (3 × (2 × (1 × ((λn.(1, if n = 0; else n × ((Y G) (n−1)))) (1−1)))))
4 × (3 × (2 × (1 × (1, if 0 = 0; else 0 × ((Y G) (0−1))))))
4 × (3 × (2 × (1 × (1))))
24

Every recursively defined function can be seen as a fixed point of some suitably defined function closing over the recursive call with an extra argument, and therefore, using Y, every recursively defined function can be expressed as a lambda expression. In particular, we can now cleanly define the subtraction, multiplication and comparison predicate of natural numbers recursively.

Standard terms edit

Certain terms have commonly accepted names:[28][29][30]

I := λx.x
S := λxyz.x z (y z)
K := λxy.x
B := λxyz.x (y z)
C := λxyz.x z y
W := λxy.x y y
ω or Δ or U := λx.x x
Ω := ω ω

I is the identity function. SK and BCKW form complete combinator calculus systems that can express any lambda term - see the next section. Ω is UU, the smallest term that has no normal form. YI is another such term. Y is standard and defined above, and can also be defined as Y=BU(CBU), so that Yg=g(Yg). TRUE and FALSE defined above are commonly abbreviated as T and F.

Abstraction elimination edit

If N is a lambda-term without abstraction, but possibly containing named constants (combinators), then there exists a lambda-term T(x,N) which is equivalent to λx.N but lacks abstraction (except as part of the named constants, if these are considered non-atomic). This can also be viewed as anonymising variables, as T(x,N) removes all occurrences of x from N, while still allowing argument values to be substituted into the positions where N contains an x. The conversion function T can be defined by:

T(x, x) := I
T(x, N) := K N if x is not free in N.
T(x, M N) := S T(x, M) T(x, N)

In either case, a term of the form T(x,N) P can reduce by having the initial combinator I, K, or S grab the argument P, just like β-reduction of x.N) P would do. I returns that argument. K throws the argument away, just like x.N) would do if x has no free occurrence in N. S passes the argument on to both subterms of the application, and then applies the result of the first to the result of the second.

The combinators B and C are similar to S, but pass the argument on to only one subterm of an application (B to the "argument" subterm and C to the "function" subterm), thus saving a subsequent K if there is no occurrence of x in one subterm. In comparison to B and C, the S combinator actually conflates two functionalities: rearranging arguments, and duplicating an argument so that it may be used in two places. The W combinator does only the latter, yielding the B, C, K, W system as an alternative to SKI combinator calculus.

Typed lambda calculus edit

A typed lambda calculus is a typed formalism that uses the lambda-symbol ( ) to denote anonymous function abstraction. In this context, types are usually objects of a syntactic nature that are assigned to lambda terms; the exact nature of a type depends on the calculus considered (see Kinds of typed lambda calculi). From a certain point of view, typed lambda calculi can be seen as refinements of the untyped lambda calculus but from another point of view, they can also be considered the more fundamental theory and untyped lambda calculus a special case with only one type.[31]

Typed lambda calculi are foundational programming languages and are the base of typed functional programming languages such as ML and Haskell and, more indirectly, typed imperative programming languages. Typed lambda calculi play an important role in the design of type systems for programming languages; here typability usually captures desirable properties of the program, e.g. the program will not cause a memory access violation.

Typed lambda calculi are closely related to mathematical logic and proof theory via the Curry–Howard isomorphism and they can be considered as the internal language of classes of categories, e.g. the simply typed lambda calculus is the language of Cartesian closed categories (CCCs).

Reduction strategies edit

Whether a term is normalising or not, and how much work needs to be done in normalising it if it is, depends to a large extent on the reduction strategy used. Common lambda calculus reduction strategies include:[32][33][34]

Normal order
The leftmost, outermost redex is always reduced first. That is, whenever possible the arguments are substituted into the body of an abstraction before the arguments are reduced.
Applicative order
The leftmost, innermost redex is always reduced first. Intuitively this means a function's arguments are always reduced before the function itself. Applicative order always attempts to apply functions to normal forms, even when this is not possible.
Full β-reductions
Any redex can be reduced at any time. This means essentially the lack of any particular reduction strategy—with regard to reducibility, "all bets are off".

Weak reduction strategies do not reduce under lambda abstractions:

Call by value
A redex is reduced only when its right hand side has reduced to a value (variable or abstraction). Only the outermost redexes are reduced.
Call by name
As normal order, but no reductions are performed inside abstractions. For example, λx.(λy.y)x is in normal form according to this strategy, although it contains the redex y.y)x.

Strategies with sharing reduce computations that are "the same" in parallel:

Optimal reduction
As normal order, but computations that have the same label are reduced simultaneously.
Call by need
As call by name (hence weak), but function applications that would duplicate terms instead name the argument, which is then reduced only "when it is needed".

Computability edit

There is no algorithm that takes as input any two lambda expressions and outputs TRUE or FALSE depending on whether one expression reduces to the other.[13] More precisely, no computable function can decide the question. This was historically the first problem for which undecidability could be proven. As usual for such a proof, computable means computable by any model of computation that is Turing complete. In fact computability can itself be defined via the lambda calculus: a function F: NN of natural numbers is a computable function if and only if there exists a lambda expression f such that for every pair of x, y in N, F(x)=y if and only if f x =β y,  where x and y are the Church numerals corresponding to x and y, respectively and =β meaning equivalence with β-reduction. See the Church–Turing thesis for other approaches to defining computability and their equivalence.

Church's proof of uncomputability first reduces the problem to determining whether a given lambda expression has a normal form. Then he assumes that this predicate is computable, and can hence be expressed in lambda calculus. Building on earlier work by Kleene and constructing a Gödel numbering for lambda expressions, he constructs a lambda expression e that closely follows the proof of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. If e is applied to its own Gödel number, a contradiction results.

Complexity edit

The notion of computational complexity for the lambda calculus is a bit tricky, because the cost of a β-reduction may vary depending on how it is implemented.[35] To be precise, one must somehow find the location of all of the occurrences of the bound variable V in the expression E, implying a time cost, or one must keep track of the locations of free variables in some way, implying a space cost. A naïve search for the locations of V in E is O(n) in the length n of E. Director strings were an early approach that traded this time cost for a quadratic space usage.[36] More generally this has led to the study of systems that use explicit substitution.

In 2014, it was shown that the number of β-reduction steps taken by normal order reduction to reduce a term is a reasonable time cost model, that is, the reduction can be simulated on a Turing machine in time polynomially proportional to the number of steps.[37] This was a long-standing open problem, due to size explosion, the existence of lambda terms which grow exponentially in size for each β-reduction. The result gets around this by working with a compact shared representation. The result makes clear that the amount of space needed to evaluate a lambda term is not proportional to the size of the term during reduction. It is not currently known what a good measure of space complexity would be.[38]

An unreasonable model does not necessarily mean inefficient. Optimal reduction reduces all computations with the same label in one step, avoiding duplicated work, but the number of parallel β-reduction steps to reduce a given term to normal form is approximately linear in the size of the term. This is far too small to be a reasonable cost measure, as any Turing machine may be encoded in the lambda calculus in size linearly proportional to the size of the Turing machine. The true cost of reducing lambda terms is not due to β-reduction per se but rather the handling of the duplication of redexes during β-reduction.[39] It is not known if optimal reduction implementations are reasonable when measured with respect to a reasonable cost model such as the number of leftmost-outermost steps to normal form, but it has been shown for fragments of the lambda calculus that the optimal reduction algorithm is efficient and has at most a quadratic overhead compared to leftmost-outermost.[38] In addition the BOHM prototype implementation of optimal reduction outperformed both Caml Light and Haskell on pure lambda terms.[39]

Lambda calculus and programming languages edit

As pointed out by Peter Landin's 1965 paper "A Correspondence between ALGOL 60 and Church's Lambda-notation",[40] sequential procedural programming languages can be understood in terms of the lambda calculus, which provides the basic mechanisms for procedural abstraction and procedure (subprogram) application.

Anonymous functions edit

For example, in Python the "square" function can be expressed as a lambda expression as follows:

(lambda x: x**2) 

The above example is an expression that evaluates to a first-class function. The symbol lambda creates an anonymous function, given a list of parameter names, x – just a single argument in this case, and an expression that is evaluated as the body of the function, x**2. Anonymous functions are sometimes called lambda expressions.

For example, Pascal and many other imperative languages have long supported passing subprograms as arguments to other subprograms through the mechanism of function pointers. However, function pointers are not a sufficient condition for functions to be first class datatypes, because a function is a first class datatype if and only if new instances of the function can be created at run-time. And this run-time creation of functions is supported in Smalltalk, JavaScript and Wolfram Language, and more recently in Scala, Eiffel ("agents"), C# ("delegates") and C++11, among others.

Parallelism and concurrency edit

The Church–Rosser property of the lambda calculus means that evaluation (β-reduction) can be carried out in any order, even in parallel. This means that various nondeterministic evaluation strategies are relevant. However, the lambda calculus does not offer any explicit constructs for parallelism. One can add constructs such as Futures to the lambda calculus. Other process calculi have been developed for describing communication and concurrency.

Semantics edit

The fact that lambda calculus terms act as functions on other lambda calculus terms, and even on themselves, led to questions about the semantics of the lambda calculus. Could a sensible meaning be assigned to lambda calculus terms? The natural semantics was to find a set D isomorphic to the function space DD, of functions on itself. However, no nontrivial such D can exist, by cardinality constraints because the set of all functions from D to D has greater cardinality than D, unless D is a singleton set.

In the 1970s, Dana Scott showed that if only continuous functions were considered, a set or domain D with the required property could be found, thus providing a model for the lambda calculus.[41]

This work also formed the basis for the denotational semantics of programming languages.

Variations and extensions edit

These extensions are in the lambda cube:

These formal systems are extensions of lambda calculus that are not in the lambda cube:

These formal systems are variations of lambda calculus:

These formal systems are related to lambda calculus:

  • Combinatory logic – A notation for mathematical logic without variables
  • SKI combinator calculus – A computational system based on the S, K and I combinators, equivalent to lambda calculus, but reducible without variable substitutions

See also edit

Further reading edit

  • Abelson, Harold & Gerald Jay Sussman. Structure and Interpretation of Computer Programs. The MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-51087-1.
  • Barendregt, Hendrik Pieter Introduction to Lambda Calculus.
  • Barendregt, Hendrik Pieter, The Impact of the Lambda Calculus in Logic and Computer Science. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, Volume 3, Number 2, June 1997.
  • Barendregt, Hendrik Pieter, The Type Free Lambda Calculus pp1091–1132 of Handbook of Mathematical Logic, North-Holland (1977) ISBN 0-7204-2285-X
  • Cardone and Hindley, 2006. History of Lambda-calculus and Combinatory Logic. In Gabbay and Woods (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 5. Elsevier.
  • Church, Alonzo, An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory, American Journal of Mathematics, 58 (1936), pp. 345–363. This paper contains the proof that the equivalence of lambda expressions is in general not decidable.
  • Church, Alonzo (1941). The Calculi of Lambda-Conversion. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Retrieved 2020-04-14. (ISBN 978-0-691-08394-0)
  • Frink Jr., Orrin (1944). "Review: The Calculi of Lambda-Conversion by Alonzo Church" (PDF). Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 50 (3): 169–172. doi:10.1090/s0002-9904-1944-08090-7.
  • Kleene, Stephen, A theory of positive integers in formal logic, American Journal of Mathematics, 57 (1935), pp. 153–173 and 219–244. Contains the lambda calculus definitions of several familiar functions.
  • Landin, Peter, A Correspondence Between ALGOL 60 and Church's Lambda-Notation, Communications of the ACM, vol. 8, no. 2 (1965), pages 89–101. Available from the ACM site. A classic paper highlighting the importance of lambda calculus as a basis for programming languages.
  • Larson, Jim, . A gentle introduction for programmers.
  • Michaelson, Greg (10 April 2013). An Introduction to Functional Programming Through Lambda Calculus. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-28029-5.[42]
  • Schalk, A. and Simmons, H. (2005) . Notes for a course in the Mathematical Logic MSc at Manchester University.
  • de Queiroz, Ruy J.G.B. (2008). "On Reduction Rules, Meaning-as-Use and Proof-Theoretic Semantics". Studia Logica. 90 (2): 211–247. doi:10.1007/s11225-008-9150-5. S2CID 11321602. A paper giving a formal underpinning to the idea of 'meaning-is-use' which, even if based on proofs, it is different from proof-theoretic semantics as in the Dummett–Prawitz tradition since it takes reduction as the rules giving meaning.
  • Hankin, Chris, An Introduction to Lambda Calculi for Computer Scientists, ISBN 0954300653
Monographs/textbooks for graduate students
  • Sørensen, Morten Heine and Urzyczyn, Paweł (2006), Lectures on the Curry–Howard isomorphism, Elsevier, ISBN 0-444-52077-5 is a recent monograph that covers the main topics of lambda calculus from the type-free variety, to most typed lambda calculi, including more recent developments like pure type systems and the lambda cube. It does not cover subtyping extensions.
  • Pierce, Benjamin (2002), Types and Programming Languages, MIT Press, ISBN 0-262-16209-1 covers lambda calculi from a practical type system perspective; some topics like dependent types are only mentioned, but subtyping is an important topic.
Documents
  • A Short Introduction to the Lambda Calculus-(PDF) by Achim Jung
  • A timeline of lambda calculus-(PDF) by Dana Scott
  • A Tutorial Introduction to the Lambda Calculus-(PDF) by Raúl Rojas
  • Lecture Notes on the Lambda Calculus-(PDF) by Peter Selinger
  • by Marius Buliga
  • by Peter Kelly, Paul Coddington, and Andrew Wendelborn; mentions graph reduction as a common means of evaluating lambda expressions and discusses the applicability of lambda calculus for distributed computing (due to the Church–Rosser property, which enables parallel graph reduction for lambda expressions).

Notes edit

  1. ^ These rules produce expressions such as:  . Parentheses can be dropped if the expression is unambiguous. For some applications, terms for logical and mathematical constants and operations may be included.
  2. ^ a b c d Barendregt,Barendsen (2000) call this form
    • axiom β: (λx.M[x]) N = M[N] , rewritten as (λx.M) N = M[x := N], "where M[x := N] denotes the substitution of N for every occurrence of x in M".[1]: 7  Also denoted M[N/x], "the substitution of N for x in M".[2]
  3. ^ For a full history, see Cardone and Hindley's "History of Lambda-calculus and Combinatory Logic" (2006).
  4. ^ a b Note that   is pronounced "maps to".
  5. ^ The expression e can be: variables x, lambda abstractions, or applications —in BNF,   .— from Wikipedia's Simply typed lambda calculus#Syntax for untyped lambda calculus
  6. ^   is sometimes written in ASCII as  
  7. ^ In anonymous form,   gets rewritten to   .
  8. ^ free variables in lambda Notation and its Calculus are comparable to linear algebra and mathematical concepts of the same name
  9. ^ The set of free variables of M, but with {x} removed
  10. ^ The union of the set of free variables of   and the set of free variables of  [1]
  11. ^ f.M) N can be pronounced "let f be N in M".
  12. ^ Ariola and Blom[27] employ 1) axioms for a representational calculus using well-formed cyclic lambda graphs extended with letrec, to detect possibly infinite unwinding trees; 2) the representational calculus with β-reduction of scoped lambda graphs constitute Ariola/Blom's cyclic extension of lambda calculus; 3) Ariola/Blom reason about strict languages using § call-by-value, and compare to Moggi's calculus, and to Hasegawa's calculus. Conclusions on p. 111.[27]

References edit

Some parts of this article are based on material from FOLDOC, used with permission.

  1. ^ a b c Barendregt, Henk; Barendsen, Erik (March 2000), Introduction to Lambda Calculus (PDF)[permanent dead link]
  2. ^ explicit substitution at the nLab
  3. ^ Turing, Alan M. (December 1937). "Computability and λ-Definability". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 2 (4): 153–163. doi:10.2307/2268280. JSTOR 2268280. S2CID 2317046.
  4. ^ Coquand, Thierry (8 February 2006). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Type Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 ed.). Retrieved November 17, 2020.
  5. ^ Moortgat, Michael (1988). Categorial Investigations: Logical and Linguistic Aspects of the Lambek Calculus. Foris Publications. ISBN 9789067653879.
  6. ^ Bunt, Harry; Muskens, Reinhard, eds. (2008). Computing Meaning. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4020-5957-5.
  7. ^ Mitchell, John C. (2003). Concepts in Programming Languages. Cambridge University Press. p. 57. ISBN 978-0-521-78098-8..
  8. ^ Chacón Sartori, Camilo (2023-12-05). (Technical report). Archived from the original on 2023-12-07.
  9. ^ Pierce, Benjamin C. Basic Category Theory for Computer Scientists. p. 53.
  10. ^ Church, Alonzo (1932). "A set of postulates for the foundation of logic". Annals of Mathematics. Series 2. 33 (2): 346–366. doi:10.2307/1968337. JSTOR 1968337.
  11. ^ Kleene, Stephen C.; Rosser, J. B. (July 1935). "The Inconsistency of Certain Formal Logics". The Annals of Mathematics. 36 (3): 630. doi:10.2307/1968646. JSTOR 1968646.
  12. ^ Church, Alonzo (December 1942). "Review of Haskell B. Curry, The Inconsistency of Certain Formal Logics". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 7 (4): 170–171. doi:10.2307/2268117. JSTOR 2268117.
  13. ^ a b Church, Alonzo (1936). "An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory". American Journal of Mathematics. 58 (2): 345–363. doi:10.2307/2371045. JSTOR 2371045.
  14. ^ Church, Alonzo (1940). "A Formulation of the Simple Theory of Types". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 5 (2): 56–68. doi:10.2307/2266170. JSTOR 2266170. S2CID 15889861.
  15. ^ Partee, B. B. H.; ter Meulen, A.; Wall, R. E. (1990). Mathematical Methods in Linguistics. Springer. ISBN 9789027722454. Retrieved 29 Dec 2016.
  16. ^ Alma, Jesse. Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "The Lambda Calculus". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 ed.). Retrieved November 17, 2020.
  17. ^ Dana Scott, "Looking Backward; Looking Forward", Invited Talk at the Workshop in honour of Dana Scott’s 85th birthday and 50 years of domain theory, 7–8 July, FLoC 2018 (talk 7 July 2018). The relevant passage begins at 32:50. (See also this extract of a May 2016 talk at the University of Birmingham, UK.)
  18. ^ Barendregt, Hendrik Pieter (1984). The Lambda Calculus: Its Syntax and Semantics. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol. 103 (Revised ed.). North Holland. ISBN 0-444-87508-5.
  19. ^ [dead link]Corrections[permanent dead link].
  20. ^ a b "Example for Rules of Associativity". Lambda-bound.com. Retrieved 2012-06-18.
  21. ^ "The Basic Grammar of Lambda Expressions". SoftOption. Some other systems use juxtaposition to mean application, so 'ab' means 'a@b'. This is fine except that it requires that variables have length one so that we know that 'ab' is two variables juxtaposed not one variable of length 2. But we want to labels like 'firstVariable' to mean a single variable, so we cannot use this juxtaposition convention.
  22. ^ a b Selinger, Peter (2008), Lecture Notes on the Lambda Calculus (PDF), vol. 0804, Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Ottawa, p. 9, arXiv:0804.3434, Bibcode:2008arXiv0804.3434S
  23. ^ de Queiroz, Ruy J. G. B. (1988). "A Proof-Theoretic Account of Programming and the Role of Reduction Rules". Dialectica. 42 (4): 265–282. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.1988.tb00919.x.
  24. ^ Turbak, Franklyn; Gifford, David (2008), Design concepts in programming languages, MIT press, p. 251, ISBN 978-0-262-20175-9
  25. ^ Luke Palmer (29 Dec 2010) Haskell-cafe: What's the motivation for η rules?
  26. ^ Felleisen, Matthias; Flatt, Matthew (2006), (PDF), p. 26, archived from the original (PDF) on 2009-02-05; A note (accessed 2017) at the original location suggests that the authors consider the work originally referenced to have been superseded by a book.
  27. ^ a b Zena M. Ariola and Stefan Blom, Proc. TACS '94 Sendai, Japan 1997 (1997) Cyclic lambda calculi 114 pages.
  28. ^ Ker, Andrew D. "Lambda Calculus and Types" (PDF). p. 6. Retrieved 14 January 2022.
  29. ^ Dezani-Ciancaglini, Mariangiola; Ghilezan, Silvia (2014). "Preciseness of Subtyping on Intersection and Union Types" (PDF). Rewriting and Typed Lambda Calculi. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 8560. p. 196. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-08918-8_14. hdl:2318/149874. ISBN 978-3-319-08917-1. Retrieved 14 January 2022.
  30. ^ Forster, Yannick; Smolka, Gert (August 2019). "Call-by-Value Lambda Calculus as a Model of Computation in Coq" (PDF). Journal of Automated Reasoning. 63 (2): 393–413. doi:10.1007/s10817-018-9484-2. S2CID 53087112. Retrieved 14 January 2022.
  31. ^ Types and Programming Languages, p. 273, Benjamin C. Pierce
  32. ^ Pierce, Benjamin C. (2002). Types and Programming Languages. MIT Press. p. 56. ISBN 0-262-16209-1.
  33. ^ Sestoft, Peter (2002). "Demonstrating Lambda Calculus Reduction" (PDF). The Essence of Computation. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 2566. pp. 420–435. doi:10.1007/3-540-36377-7_19. ISBN 978-3-540-00326-7. Retrieved 22 August 2022.
  34. ^ Biernacka, Małgorzata; Charatonik, Witold; Drab, Tomasz (2022). Andronick, June; de Moura, Leonardo (eds.). "The Zoo of Lambda-Calculus Reduction Strategies, and Coq" (PDF). 13th International Conference on Interactive Theorem Proving (ITP 2022). Schloss Dagstuhl – Leibniz-Zentrum für Informatik. 237: 7:1–7:19. doi:10.4230/LIPIcs.ITP.2022.7. Retrieved 22 August 2022.
  35. ^ Frandsen, Gudmund Skovbjerg; Sturtivant, Carl (26 August 1991). "What is an efficient implementation of the λ-calculus?". Functional Programming Languages and Computer Architecture. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 523. Springer-Verlag. pp. 289–312. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.139.6913. doi:10.1007/3540543961_14. ISBN 9783540543961. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  36. ^ Sinot, F.-R. (2005). "Director Strings Revisited: A Generic Approach to the Efficient Representation of Free Variables in Higher-order Rewriting" (PDF). Journal of Logic and Computation. 15 (2): 201–218. doi:10.1093/logcom/exi010.
  37. ^ Accattoli, Beniamino; Dal Lago, Ugo (14 July 2014). "Beta reduction is invariant, indeed". Proceedings of the Joint Meeting of the Twenty-Third EACSL Annual Conference on Computer Science Logic (CSL) and the Twenty-Ninth Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science (LICS). pp. 1–10. arXiv:1601.01233. doi:10.1145/2603088.2603105. ISBN 9781450328869. S2CID 11485010.
  38. ^ a b Accattoli, Beniamino (October 2018). "(In)Efficiency and Reasonable Cost Models". Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science. 338: 23–43. doi:10.1016/j.entcs.2018.10.003.
  39. ^ a b Asperti, Andrea (16 Jan 2017). "About the efficient reduction of lambda terms". arXiv:1701.04240v1. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  40. ^ Landin, P. J. (1965). "A Correspondence between ALGOL 60 and Church's Lambda-notation". Communications of the ACM. 8 (2): 89–101. doi:10.1145/363744.363749. S2CID 6505810.
  41. ^ Scott, Dana (1993). "A type-theoretical alternative to ISWIM, CUCH, OWHY" (PDF). Theoretical Computer Science. 121 (1–2): 411–440. doi:10.1016/0304-3975(93)90095-B. Retrieved 2022-12-01. Written 1969, widely circulated as an unpublished manuscript.
  42. ^ "Greg Michaelson's Homepage". Mathematical and Computer Sciences. Riccarton, Edinburgh: Heriot-Watt University. Retrieved 6 November 2022.

External links edit

  • Graham Hutton, Lambda Calculus, a short (12 minutes) Computerphile video on the Lambda Calculus
  • Helmut Brandl, Step by Step Introduction to Lambda Calculus
  • "Lambda-calculus", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
  • David C. Keenan, To Dissect a Mockingbird: A Graphical Notation for the Lambda Calculus with Animated Reduction
  • L. Allison, Some executable λ-calculus examples
  • Georg P. Loczewski, The Lambda Calculus and A++
  • Bret Victor, Alligator Eggs: A Puzzle Game Based on Lambda Calculus
  • Lambda Calculus 2012-10-14 at the Wayback Machine on Safalra's Website 2021-05-02 at the Wayback Machine
  • LCI Lambda Interpreter a simple yet powerful pure calculus interpreter
  • Lambda Calculus links on Lambda-the-Ultimate
  • Mike Thyer, , a graphical Java applet demonstrating alternative reduction strategies.
  • Implementing the Lambda calculus using C++ Templates
  • Shane Steinert-Threlkeld, , Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Anton Salikhmetov, Macro Lambda Calculus

lambda, calculus, also, written, calculus, formal, system, mathematical, logic, expressing, computation, based, function, abstraction, application, using, variable, binding, substitution, universal, model, computation, that, used, simulate, turing, machine, in. Lambda calculus also written as l calculus is a formal system in mathematical logic for expressing computation based on function abstraction and application using variable binding and substitution It is a universal model of computation that can be used to simulate any Turing machine It was introduced by the mathematician Alonzo Church in the 1930s as part of his research into the foundations of mathematics Lambda calculus consists of constructing lambda terms and performing reduction operations on them In the simplest form of lambda calculus terms are built using only the following rules a x textstyle x A variable is a character or string representing a parameter l x M textstyle lambda x M A lambda abstraction is a function definition taking as input the bound variable x displaystyle x between the l and the punctum dot and returning the body M textstyle M M N textstyle M N An application applying a function M textstyle M to an argument N textstyle N Both M textstyle M and N textstyle N are lambda terms The reduction operations include l x M x l y M y textstyle lambda x M x rightarrow lambda y M y a conversion renaming the bound variables in the expression Used to avoid name collisions l x M N M x N textstyle lambda x M N rightarrow M x N b reduction b replacing the bound variables with the argument expression in the body of the abstraction If De Bruijn indexing is used then a conversion is no longer required as there will be no name collisions If repeated application of the reduction steps eventually terminates then by the Church Rosser theorem it will produce a b normal form Variable names are not needed if using a universal lambda function such as Iota and Jot which can create any function behavior by calling it on itself in various combinations Contents 1 Explanation and applications 2 History 2 1 Origin of the l symbol 3 Informal description 3 1 Motivation 3 2 The lambda calculus 3 2 1 Lambda terms 3 2 2 Functions that operate on functions 3 2 3 Alpha equivalence 3 2 4 Free variables 3 2 5 Capture avoiding substitutions 3 2 6 b reduction 4 Formal definition 4 1 Definition 4 2 Notation 4 3 Free and bound variables 5 Reduction 5 1 a conversion 5 1 1 Substitution 5 2 b reduction 5 3 h reduction 6 Normal forms and confluence 7 Encoding datatypes 7 1 Arithmetic in lambda calculus 7 2 Logic and predicates 7 3 Pairs 8 Additional programming techniques 8 1 Named constants 8 2 Recursion and fixed points 8 3 Standard terms 8 4 Abstraction elimination 9 Typed lambda calculus 10 Reduction strategies 11 Computability 12 Complexity 13 Lambda calculus and programming languages 13 1 Anonymous functions 13 2 Parallelism and concurrency 14 Semantics 15 Variations and extensions 16 See also 17 Further reading 18 Notes 19 References 20 External linksExplanation and applications editLambda calculus is Turing complete that is it is a universal model of computation that can be used to simulate any Turing machine 3 Its namesake the Greek letter lambda l is used in lambda expressions and lambda terms to denote binding a variable in a function Lambda calculus may be untyped or typed In typed lambda calculus functions can be applied only if they are capable of accepting the given input s type of data Typed lambda calculi are weaker than the untyped lambda calculus which is the primary subject of this article in the sense that typed lambda calculi can express less than the untyped calculus can On the other hand typed lambda calculi allow more things to be proven For example in the simply typed lambda calculus it is a theorem that every evaluation strategy terminates for every simply typed lambda term whereas evaluation of untyped lambda terms need not terminate see below One reason there are many different typed lambda calculi has been the desire to do more of what the untyped calculus can do without giving up on being able to prove strong theorems about the calculus Lambda calculus has applications in many different areas in mathematics philosophy 4 linguistics 5 6 and computer science 7 8 Lambda calculus has played an important role in the development of the theory of programming languages Functional programming languages implement lambda calculus Lambda calculus is also a current research topic in category theory 9 History editThe lambda calculus was introduced by mathematician Alonzo Church in the 1930s as part of an investigation into the foundations of mathematics 10 c The original system was shown to be logically inconsistent in 1935 when Stephen Kleene and J B Rosser developed the Kleene Rosser paradox 11 12 Subsequently in 1936 Church isolated and published just the portion relevant to computation what is now called the untyped lambda calculus 13 In 1940 he also introduced a computationally weaker but logically consistent system known as the simply typed lambda calculus 14 Until the 1960s when its relation to programming languages was clarified the lambda calculus was only a formalism Thanks to Richard Montague and other linguists applications in the semantics of natural language the lambda calculus has begun to enjoy a respectable place in both linguistics 15 and computer science 16 Origin of the l symbol edit There is some uncertainty over the reason for Church s use of the Greek letter lambda l as the notation for function abstraction in the lambda calculus perhaps in part due to conflicting explanations by Church himself According to Cardone and Hindley 2006 By the way why did Church choose the notation l In an unpublished 1964 letter to Harald Dickson he stated clearly that it came from the notation x displaystyle hat x nbsp used for class abstraction by Whitehead and Russell by first modifying x displaystyle hat x nbsp to x displaystyle land x nbsp to distinguish function abstraction from class abstraction and then changing displaystyle land nbsp to l for ease of printing This origin was also reported in Rosser 1984 p 338 On the other hand in his later years Church told two enquirers that the choice was more accidental a symbol was needed and l just happened to be chosen Dana Scott has also addressed this question in various public lectures 17 Scott recounts that he once posed a question about the origin of the lambda symbol to Church s former student and son in law John W Addison Jr who then wrote his father in law a postcard Dear Professor Church Russell had the iota operator Hilbert had the epsilon operator Why did you choose lambda for your operator According to Scott Church s entire response consisted of returning the postcard with the following annotation eeny meeny miny moe Informal description editMotivation edit Computable functions are a fundamental concept within computer science and mathematics The lambda calculus provides simple semantics for computation which are useful for formally studying properties of computation The lambda calculus incorporates two simplifications that make its semantics simple The first simplification is that the lambda calculus treats functions anonymously it does not give them explicit names For example the function s q u a r e s u m x y x 2 y 2 displaystyle operatorname square sum x y x 2 y 2 nbsp can be rewritten in anonymous form as x y x 2 y 2 displaystyle x y mapsto x 2 y 2 nbsp which is read as a tuple of x and y is mapped to x 2 y 2 textstyle x 2 y 2 nbsp d Similarly the function id x x displaystyle operatorname id x x nbsp can be rewritten in anonymous form as x x displaystyle x mapsto x nbsp where the input is simply mapped to itself d The second simplification is that the lambda calculus only uses functions of a single input An ordinary function that requires two inputs for instance the s q u a r e s u m textstyle operatorname square sum nbsp function can be reworked into an equivalent function that accepts a single input and as output returns another function that in turn accepts a single input For example x y x 2 y 2 displaystyle x y mapsto x 2 y 2 nbsp can be reworked into x y x 2 y 2 displaystyle x mapsto y mapsto x 2 y 2 nbsp This method known as currying transforms a function that takes multiple arguments into a chain of functions each with a single argument Function application of the s q u a r e s u m textstyle operatorname square sum nbsp function to the arguments 5 2 yields at once x y x 2 y 2 5 2 textstyle x y mapsto x 2 y 2 5 2 nbsp 5 2 2 2 textstyle 5 2 2 2 nbsp 29 textstyle 29 nbsp whereas evaluation of the curried version requires one more step x y x 2 y 2 5 2 textstyle Bigl bigl x mapsto y mapsto x 2 y 2 bigr 5 Bigr 2 nbsp y 5 2 y 2 2 textstyle y mapsto 5 2 y 2 2 nbsp the definition of x displaystyle x nbsp has been used with 5 displaystyle 5 nbsp in the inner expression This is like b reduction 5 2 2 2 textstyle 5 2 2 2 nbsp the definition of y displaystyle y nbsp has been used with 2 displaystyle 2 nbsp Again similar to b reduction 29 textstyle 29 nbsp to arrive at the same result The lambda calculus edit The lambda calculus consists of a language of lambda terms that are defined by a certain formal syntax and a set of transformation rules for manipulating the lambda terms These transformation rules can be viewed as an equational theory or as an operational definition As described above having no names all functions in the lambda calculus are anonymous functions They only accept one input variable so currying is used to implement functions of several variables Lambda terms edit The syntax of the lambda calculus defines some expressions as valid lambda calculus expressions and some as invalid just as some strings of characters are valid C programs and some are not A valid lambda calculus expression is called a lambda term The following three rules give an inductive definition that can be applied to build all syntactically valid lambda terms e variable x is itself a valid lambda term if t is a lambda term and x is a variable then l x t displaystyle lambda x t nbsp f is a lambda term called an abstraction if t and s are lambda terms then t displaystyle t nbsp s displaystyle s nbsp is a lambda term called an application Nothing else is a lambda term Thus a lambda term is valid if and only if it can be obtained by repeated application of these three rules However some parentheses can be omitted according to certain rules For example the outermost parentheses are usually not written See Notation below for when to include parenthesesAn abstraction l x t displaystyle lambda x t nbsp denotes an anonymous function g that takes a single input x and returns t For example l x x 2 2 displaystyle lambda x x 2 2 nbsp is an abstraction for the function f x x 2 2 displaystyle f x x 2 2 nbsp using the term x 2 2 displaystyle x 2 2 nbsp for t The name f x displaystyle f x nbsp is superfluous when using abstraction l x t displaystyle lambda x t nbsp binds the variable x in the term t The definition of a function with an abstraction merely sets up the function but does not invoke it See Notation below for usage of parenthesesAn application t displaystyle t nbsp s displaystyle s nbsp represents the application of a function t to an input s that is it represents the act of calling function t on input s to produce t s displaystyle t s nbsp There is no concept in lambda calculus of variable declaration In a definition such as l x x y displaystyle lambda x x y nbsp i e f x x y displaystyle f x x y nbsp in lambda calculus y is a variable that is not yet defined The abstraction l x x y displaystyle lambda x x y nbsp is syntactically valid and represents a function that adds its input to the yet unknown y Parentheses may be used and might be needed to disambiguate terms For example l x l x x x displaystyle lambda x lambda x x x nbsp which is of form l x B displaystyle lambda x B nbsp an abstraction and l x l x x displaystyle lambda x lambda x x nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp which is of form M displaystyle M nbsp N displaystyle N nbsp an application The examples 1 and 2 denote different terms except for the scope of the parentheses they would be the same But example 1 is a function definition while example 2 is function application Lambda variable x is a placeholder in both examples Here example 1 defines a function l x B displaystyle lambda x B nbsp where B displaystyle B nbsp is l x x x displaystyle lambda x x x nbsp an anonymous function l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp with input x displaystyle x nbsp while example 2 M displaystyle M nbsp N displaystyle N nbsp is M applied to N where M displaystyle M nbsp is the lambda term l x l x x displaystyle lambda x lambda x x nbsp being applied to the input N displaystyle N nbsp which is x displaystyle x nbsp Both examples 1 and 2 would evaluate to the identity function l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp Functions that operate on functions edit In lambda calculus functions are taken to be first class values so functions may be used as the inputs or be returned as outputs from other functions For example the lambda term l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp represents the identity function x x displaystyle x mapsto x nbsp Further l x y displaystyle lambda x y nbsp represents the constant function x y displaystyle x mapsto y nbsp the function that always returns y displaystyle y nbsp no matter the input As an example of a function operating on functions the function composition can be defined as l f l g l x f g x displaystyle lambda f lambda g lambda x f gx nbsp There are several notions of equivalence and reduction that allow lambda terms to be reduced to equivalent lambda terms Alpha equivalence edit A basic form of equivalence definable on lambda terms is alpha equivalence It captures the intuition that the particular choice of a bound variable in an abstraction does not usually matter For instance l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp and l y y displaystyle lambda y y nbsp are alpha equivalent lambda terms and they both represent the same function the identity function The terms x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp are not alpha equivalent because they are not bound in an abstraction In many presentations it is usual to identify alpha equivalent lambda terms The following definitions are necessary in order to be able to define b reduction Free variables edit The free variables h of a term are those variables not bound by an abstraction The set of free variables of an expression is defined inductively The free variables of x displaystyle x nbsp are just x displaystyle x nbsp The set of free variables of l x t displaystyle lambda x t nbsp is the set of free variables of t displaystyle t nbsp but with x displaystyle x nbsp removed The set of free variables of t displaystyle t nbsp s displaystyle s nbsp is the union of the set of free variables of t displaystyle t nbsp and the set of free variables of s displaystyle s nbsp For example the lambda term representing the identity l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp has no free variables but the function l x y displaystyle lambda x y nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp has a single free variable y displaystyle y nbsp Capture avoiding substitutions edit Suppose t displaystyle t nbsp s displaystyle s nbsp and r displaystyle r nbsp are lambda terms and x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp are variables The notation t x r displaystyle t x r nbsp indicates substitution of r displaystyle r nbsp for x displaystyle x nbsp in t displaystyle t nbsp in a capture avoiding manner This is defined so that x x r r displaystyle x x r r nbsp with r displaystyle r nbsp substituted for x displaystyle x nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp becomes r displaystyle r nbsp y x r y displaystyle y x r y nbsp if x y displaystyle x neq y nbsp with r displaystyle r nbsp substituted for x displaystyle x nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp which is not x displaystyle x nbsp remains y displaystyle y nbsp t displaystyle t nbsp s x r t x r s x r displaystyle s x r t x r s x r nbsp substitution distributes to both sides of an application l x t x r l x t displaystyle lambda x t x r lambda x t nbsp a variable bound by an abstraction is not subject to substitution substituting such variable leaves the abstraction unchanged l y t x r l y t x r displaystyle lambda y t x r lambda y t x r nbsp if x y displaystyle x neq y nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp does not appear among the free variables of r displaystyle r nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp is said to be fresh for r displaystyle r nbsp substituting a variable which is not bound by an abstraction proceeds in the abstraction s body provided that the abstracted variable y displaystyle y nbsp is fresh for the substitution term r displaystyle r nbsp For example l x x y y l x x y y l x x displaystyle lambda x x y y lambda x x y y lambda x x nbsp and l x y x x y l x y x y x x y l x y y displaystyle lambda x y x x y lambda x y x y x x y lambda x y y nbsp The freshness condition requiring that y displaystyle y nbsp is not in the free variables of r displaystyle r nbsp is crucial in order to ensure that substitution does not change the meaning of functions For example a substitution that ignores the freshness condition could lead to errors l x y y x l x y y x l x x displaystyle lambda x y y x lambda x y y x lambda x x nbsp This erroneous substitution would turn the constant function l x y displaystyle lambda x y nbsp into the identity l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp In general failure to meet the freshness condition can be remedied by alpha renaming first with a suitable fresh variable For example switching back to our correct notion of substitution in l x y y x displaystyle lambda x y y x nbsp the abstraction can be renamed with a fresh variable z displaystyle z nbsp to obtain l z y y x l z y y x l z x displaystyle lambda z y y x lambda z y y x lambda z x nbsp and the meaning of the function is preserved by substitution b reduction edit The b reduction rule b states that an application of the form l x t s displaystyle lambda x t s nbsp reduces to the term t x s displaystyle t x s nbsp The notation l x t s t x s displaystyle lambda x t s to t x s nbsp is used to indicate that l x t s displaystyle lambda x t s nbsp b reduces to t x s displaystyle t x s nbsp For example for every s displaystyle s nbsp l x x s x x s s displaystyle lambda x x s to x x s s nbsp This demonstrates that l x x displaystyle lambda x x nbsp really is the identity Similarly l x y s y x s y displaystyle lambda x y s to y x s y nbsp which demonstrates that l x y displaystyle lambda x y nbsp is a constant function The lambda calculus may be seen as an idealized version of a functional programming language like Haskell or Standard ML Under this view b reduction corresponds to a computational step This step can be repeated by additional b reductions until there are no more applications left to reduce In the untyped lambda calculus as presented here this reduction process may not terminate For instance consider the term W l x x x l x x x displaystyle Omega lambda x xx lambda x xx nbsp Here l x x x l x x x x x x l x x x x x l x x x x x l x x x l x x x l x x x displaystyle lambda x xx lambda x xx to xx x lambda x xx x x lambda x xx x x lambda x xx lambda x xx lambda x xx nbsp That is the term reduces to itself in a single b reduction and therefore the reduction process will never terminate Another aspect of the untyped lambda calculus is that it does not distinguish between different kinds of data For instance it may be desirable to write a function that only operates on numbers However in the untyped lambda calculus there is no way to prevent a function from being applied to truth values strings or other non number objects Formal definition editMain article Lambda calculus definition Definition edit Lambda expressions are composed of variables v1 v2 the abstraction symbols l lambda and dot parentheses The set of lambda expressions L can be defined inductively If x is a variable then x L If x is a variable and M L then lx M L If M N L then M N L Instances of rule 2 are known as abstractions and instances of rule 3 are known as applications 18 19 Notation edit To keep the notation of lambda expressions uncluttered the following conventions are usually applied Outermost parentheses are dropped M N instead of M N Applications are assumed to be left associative M N P may be written instead of M N P 20 When all variables are single letter the space in applications may be omitted MNP instead of M N P 21 The body of an abstraction extends as far right as possible lx M N means lx M N and not lx M N A sequence of abstractions is contracted lx ly lz N is abbreviated as lxyz N 22 20 Free and bound variables edit The abstraction operator l is said to bind its variable wherever it occurs in the body of the abstraction Variables that fall within the scope of an abstraction are said to be bound In an expression lx M the part lx is often called binder as a hint that the variable x is getting bound by prepending lx to M All other variables are called free For example in the expression ly x x y y is a bound variable and x is a free variable Also a variable is bound by its nearest abstraction In the following example the single occurrence of x in the expression is bound by the second lambda lx y lx z x The set of free variables of a lambda expression M is denoted as FV M and is defined by recursion on the structure of the terms as follows FV x x where x is a variable FV lx M FV M x i FV M N FV M FV N j An expression that contains no free variables is said to be closed Closed lambda expressions are also known as combinators and are equivalent to terms in combinatory logic Reduction editThe meaning of lambda expressions is defined by how expressions can be reduced 23 There are three kinds of reduction a conversion changing bound variables b reduction applying functions to their arguments h reduction which captures a notion of extensionality We also speak of the resulting equivalences two expressions are a equivalent if they can be a converted into the same expression b equivalence and h equivalence are defined similarly The term redex short for reducible expression refers to subterms that can be reduced by one of the reduction rules For example lx M N is a b redex in expressing the substitution of N for x in M The expression to which a redex reduces is called its reduct the reduct of lx M N is M x N b If x is not free in M lx M x is also an h redex with a reduct of M a conversion edit a conversion alpha conversion sometimes known as a renaming 24 allows bound variable names to be changed For example a conversion of lx x might yield ly y Terms that differ only by a conversion are called a equivalent Frequently in uses of lambda calculus a equivalent terms are considered to be equivalent The precise rules for a conversion are not completely trivial First when a converting an abstraction the only variable occurrences that are renamed are those that are bound to the same abstraction For example an a conversion of lx lx x could result in ly lx x but it could not result in ly lx y The latter has a different meaning from the original This is analogous to the programming notion of variable shadowing Second a conversion is not possible if it would result in a variable getting captured by a different abstraction For example if we replace x with y in lx ly x we get ly ly y which is not at all the same In programming languages with static scope a conversion can be used to make name resolution simpler by ensuring that no variable name masks a name in a containing scope see a renaming to make name resolution trivial In the De Bruijn index notation any two a equivalent terms are syntactically identical Substitution edit Substitution written M x N is the process of replacing all free occurrences of the variable x in the expression M with expression N Substitution on terms of the lambda calculus is defined by recursion on the structure of terms as follows note x and y are only variables while M and N are any lambda expression x x N N y x N y if x y M1 M2 x N M1 x N M2 x N lx M x N lx M ly M x N ly M x N if x y and y FV N See above for the FVTo substitute into an abstraction it is sometimes necessary to a convert the expression For example it is not correct for lx y y x to result in lx x because the substituted x was supposed to be free but ended up being bound The correct substitution in this case is lz x up to a equivalence Substitution is defined uniquely up to a equivalence See Capture avoiding substitutions above b reduction edit b reduction beta reduction captures the idea of function application b reduction is defined in terms of substitution the b reduction of lx M N is M x N b For example assuming some encoding of 2 7 we have the following b reduction ln n 2 7 7 2 b reduction can be seen to be the same as the concept of local reducibility in natural deduction via the Curry Howard isomorphism h reduction edit h reduction eta reduction expresses the idea of extensionality 25 which in this context is that two functions are the same if and only if they give the same result for all arguments h reduction converts between lx f x and f whenever x does not appear free in f h reduction can be seen to be the same as the concept of local completeness in natural deduction via the Curry Howard isomorphism Normal forms and confluence editMain article Normalization property abstract rewriting For the untyped lambda calculus b reduction as a rewriting rule is neither strongly normalising nor weakly normalising However it can be shown that b reduction is confluent when working up to a conversion i e we consider two normal forms to be equal if it is possible to a convert one into the other Therefore both strongly normalising terms and weakly normalising terms have a unique normal form For strongly normalising terms any reduction strategy is guaranteed to yield the normal form whereas for weakly normalising terms some reduction strategies may fail to find it Encoding datatypes editMain articles Church encoding and Mogensen Scott encoding The basic lambda calculus may be used to model arithmetic booleans data structures and recursion as illustrated in the following sub sections i ii iii and iv Arithmetic in lambda calculus edit There are several possible ways to define the natural numbers in lambda calculus but by far the most common are the Church numerals which can be defined as follows 0 lf lx x 1 lf lx f x 2 lf lx f f x 3 lf lx f f f x and so on Or using the alternative syntax presented above in Notation 0 lfx x 1 lfx f x 2 lfx f f x 3 lfx f f f x A Church numeral is a higher order function it takes a single argument function f and returns another single argument function The Church numeral n is a function that takes a function f as argument and returns the n th composition of f i e the function f composed with itself n times This is denoted f n and is in fact the n th power of f considered as an operator f 0 is defined to be the identity function Such repeated compositions of a single function f obey the laws of exponents which is why these numerals can be used for arithmetic In Church s original lambda calculus the formal parameter of a lambda expression was required to occur at least once in the function body which made the above definition of 0 impossible One way of thinking about the Church numeral n which is often useful when analysing programs is as an instruction repeat n times For example using the PAIR and NIL functions defined below one can define a function that constructs a linked list of n elements all equal to x by repeating prepend another x element n times starting from an empty list The lambda term is ln lx n PAIR x NILBy varying what is being repeated and varying what argument that function being repeated is applied to a great many different effects can be achieved We can define a successor function which takes a Church numeral n and returns n 1 by adding another application of f where mf x means the function f is applied m times on x SUCC ln lf lx f n f x Because the m th composition of f composed with the n th composition of f gives the m n th composition of f addition can be defined as follows PLUS lm ln lf lx m f n f x PLUS can be thought of as a function taking two natural numbers as arguments and returning a natural number it can be verified that PLUS 2 3and 5are b equivalent lambda expressions Since adding m to a number n can be accomplished by adding 1 m times an alternative definition is PLUS lm ln m SUCC n 26 Similarly multiplication can be defined as MULT lm ln lf m n f 22 Alternatively MULT lm ln m PLUS n 0since multiplying m and n is the same as repeating the add n function m times and then applying it to zero Exponentiation has a rather simple rendering in Church numerals namely POW lb le e b 1 The predecessor function defined by PRED n n 1 for a positive integer n and PRED 0 0 is considerably more difficult The formula PRED ln lf lx n lg lh h g f lu x lu u can be validated by showing inductively that if T denotes lg lh h g f then T n lu x lh h f n 1 x for n gt 0 Two other definitions of PRED are given below one using conditionals and the other using pairs With the predecessor function subtraction is straightforward Defining SUB lm ln n PRED m SUB m n yields m n when m gt n and 0 otherwise Logic and predicates edit By convention the following two definitions known as Church booleans are used for the boolean values TRUE and FALSE TRUE lx ly x FALSE lx ly yThen with these two lambda terms we can define some logic operators these are just possible formulations other expressions could be equally correct AND lp lq p q p OR lp lq p p q NOT lp p FALSE TRUE IFTHENELSE lp la lb p a bWe are now able to compute some logic functions for example AND TRUE FALSE lp lq p q p TRUE FALSE b TRUE FALSE TRUE lx ly x FALSE TRUE b FALSE dd and we see that AND TRUE FALSE is equivalent to FALSE A predicate is a function that returns a boolean value The most fundamental predicate is ISZERO which returns TRUE if its argument is the Church numeral 0 but FALSE if its argument were any other Church numeral ISZERO ln n lx FALSE TRUEThe following predicate tests whether the first argument is less than or equal to the second LEQ lm ln ISZERO SUB m n and since m n if LEQ m n and LEQ n m it is straightforward to build a predicate for numerical equality The availability of predicates and the above definition of TRUE and FALSE make it convenient to write if then else expressions in lambda calculus For example the predecessor function can be defined as PRED ln n lg lk ISZERO g 1 k PLUS g k 1 lv 0 0which can be verified by showing inductively that n lg lk ISZERO g 1 k PLUS g k 1 lv 0 is the add n 1 function for n gt 0 Pairs edit A pair 2 tuple can be defined in terms of TRUE and FALSE by using the Church encoding for pairs For example PAIR encapsulates the pair x y FIRST returns the first element of the pair and SECOND returns the second PAIR lx ly lf f x y FIRST lp p TRUE SECOND lp p FALSE NIL lx TRUE NULL lp p lx ly FALSE A linked list can be defined as either NIL for the empty list or the PAIR of an element and a smaller list The predicate NULL tests for the value NIL Alternatively with NIL FALSE the construct l lh lt lz deal with head h and tail t deal with nil obviates the need for an explicit NULL test As an example of the use of pairs the shift and increment function that maps m n to n n 1 can be defined as F lx PAIR SECOND x SUCC SECOND x which allows us to give perhaps the most transparent version of the predecessor function PRED ln FIRST n F PAIR 0 0 Additional programming techniques editThere is a considerable body of programming idioms for lambda calculus Many of these were originally developed in the context of using lambda calculus as a foundation for programming language semantics effectively using lambda calculus as a low level programming language Because several programming languages include the lambda calculus or something very similar as a fragment these techniques also see use in practical programming but may then be perceived as obscure or foreign Named constants edit In lambda calculus a library would take the form of a collection of previously defined functions which as lambda terms are merely particular constants The pure lambda calculus does not have a concept of named constants since all atomic lambda terms are variables but one can emulate having named constants by setting aside a variable as the name of the constant using abstraction to bind that variable in the main body and apply that abstraction to the intended definition Thus to use f to mean N some explicit lambda term in M another lambda term the main program one can say lf M NAuthors often introduce syntactic sugar such as let k to permit writing the above in the more intuitive order let f Nin MBy chaining such definitions one can write a lambda calculus program as zero or more function definitions followed by one lambda term using those functions that constitutes the main body of the program A notable restriction of this let is that the name f be not defined in N for N to be outside the scope of the abstraction binding f this means a recursive function definition cannot be used as the N with let The letrec l construction would allow writing recursive function definitions Recursion and fixed points edit Main article Fixed point combinator See also SKI combinator calculus Self application and recursion Recursion is the definition of a function using the function itself A definition containing itself inside itself by value leads to the whole value being of infinite size Other notations which support recursion natively overcome this by referring to the function definition by name Lambda calculus cannot express this all functions are anonymous in lambda calculus so we can t refer by name to a value which is yet to be defined inside the lambda term defining that same value However a lambda expression can receive itself as its own argument for example in lx x x E Here E should be an abstraction applying its parameter to a value to express recursion Consider the factorial function F n recursively defined by F n 1 if n 0 else n F n 1 In the lambda expression which is to represent this function a parameter typically the first one will be assumed to receive the lambda expression itself as its value so that calling it applying it to an argument will amount to recursion Thus to achieve recursion the intended as self referencing argument called r here must always be passed to itself within the function body at a call point G lr ln 1 if n 0 else n r r n 1 with r r x F x G r x to hold so r G and dd dd F G G lx x x GThe self application achieves replication here passing the function s lambda expression on to the next invocation as an argument value making it available to be referenced and called there This solves it but requires re writing each recursive call as self application We would like to have a generic solution without a need for any re writes G lr ln 1 if n 0 else n r n 1 with r x F x G r x to hold so r G r FIX G and dd dd F FIX G where FIX g r where r g r g FIX g so that FIX G G FIX G ln 1 if n 0 else n FIX G n 1 dd dd Given a lambda term with first argument representing recursive call e g G here the fixed point combinator FIX will return a self replicating lambda expression representing the recursive function here F The function does not need to be explicitly passed to itself at any point for the self replication is arranged in advance when it is created to be done each time it is called Thus the original lambda expression FIX G is re created inside itself at call point achieving self reference In fact there are many possible definitions for this FIX operator the simplest of them being Y lg lx g x x lx g x x In the lambda calculus Y g is a fixed point of g as it expands to Y g lh lx h x x lx h x x g lx g x x lx g x x g lx g x x lx g x x g Y g Now to perform our recursive call to the factorial function we would simply call Y G n where n is the number we are calculating the factorial of Given n 4 for example this gives Y G 4 G Y G 4 lr ln 1 if n 0 else n r n 1 Y G 4 ln 1 if n 0 else n Y G n 1 4 1 if 4 0 else 4 Y G 4 1 4 G Y G 4 1 4 ln 1 if n 0 else n Y G n 1 4 1 4 1 if 3 0 else 3 Y G 3 1 4 3 G Y G 3 1 4 3 ln 1 if n 0 else n Y G n 1 3 1 4 3 1 if 2 0 else 2 Y G 2 1 4 3 2 G Y G 2 1 4 3 2 ln 1 if n 0 else n Y G n 1 2 1 4 3 2 1 if 1 0 else 1 Y G 1 1 4 3 2 1 G Y G 1 1 4 3 2 1 ln 1 if n 0 else n Y G n 1 1 1 4 3 2 1 1 if 0 0 else 0 Y G 0 1 4 3 2 1 1 24Every recursively defined function can be seen as a fixed point of some suitably defined function closing over the recursive call with an extra argument and therefore using Y every recursively defined function can be expressed as a lambda expression In particular we can now cleanly define the subtraction multiplication and comparison predicate of natural numbers recursively Standard terms edit Certain terms have commonly accepted names 28 29 30 I lx x S lx ly lz x z y z K lx ly x B lx ly lz x y z C lx ly lz x z y W lx ly x y y w or D or U lx x x W w wI is the identity function SK and BCKW form complete combinator calculus systems that can express any lambda term see the next section W is UU the smallest term that has no normal form YI is another such term Y is standard and defined above and can also be defined as Y BU CBU so that Yg g Yg TRUE and FALSE defined above are commonly abbreviated as T and F Abstraction elimination edit Main article Combinatory logic Completeness of the S K basis If N is a lambda term without abstraction but possibly containing named constants combinators then there exists a lambda term T x N which is equivalent to lx N but lacks abstraction except as part of the named constants if these are considered non atomic This can also be viewed as anonymising variables as T x N removes all occurrences of x from N while still allowing argument values to be substituted into the positions where N contains an x The conversion function T can be defined by T x x I T x N K N if x is not free in N T x M N S T x M T x N In either case a term of the form T x N P can reduce by having the initial combinator I K or S grab the argument P just like b reduction of lx N P would do I returns that argument K throws the argument away just like lx N would do if x has no free occurrence in N S passes the argument on to both subterms of the application and then applies the result of the first to the result of the second The combinators B and C are similar to S but pass the argument on to only one subterm of an application B to the argument subterm and C to the function subterm thus saving a subsequent K if there is no occurrence of x in one subterm In comparison to B and C the S combinator actually conflates two functionalities rearranging arguments and duplicating an argument so that it may be used in two places The W combinator does only the latter yielding the B C K W system as an alternative to SKI combinator calculus Typed lambda calculus editMain article Typed lambda calculus A typed lambda calculus is a typed formalism that uses the lambda symbol l displaystyle lambda nbsp to denote anonymous function abstraction In this context types are usually objects of a syntactic nature that are assigned to lambda terms the exact nature of a type depends on the calculus considered see Kinds of typed lambda calculi From a certain point of view typed lambda calculi can be seen as refinements of the untyped lambda calculus but from another point of view they can also be considered the more fundamental theory and untyped lambda calculus a special case with only one type 31 Typed lambda calculi are foundational programming languages and are the base of typed functional programming languages such as ML and Haskell and more indirectly typed imperative programming languages Typed lambda calculi play an important role in the design of type systems for programming languages here typability usually captures desirable properties of the program e g the program will not cause a memory access violation Typed lambda calculi are closely related to mathematical logic and proof theory via the Curry Howard isomorphism and they can be considered as the internal language of classes of categories e g the simply typed lambda calculus is the language of Cartesian closed categories CCCs Reduction strategies editMain article Reduction strategy Lambda calculus Whether a term is normalising or not and how much work needs to be done in normalising it if it is depends to a large extent on the reduction strategy used Common lambda calculus reduction strategies include 32 33 34 Normal order The leftmost outermost redex is always reduced first That is whenever possible the arguments are substituted into the body of an abstraction before the arguments are reduced Applicative order The leftmost innermost redex is always reduced first Intuitively this means a function s arguments are always reduced before the function itself Applicative order always attempts to apply functions to normal forms even when this is not possible Full b reductions Any redex can be reduced at any time This means essentially the lack of any particular reduction strategy with regard to reducibility all bets are off Weak reduction strategies do not reduce under lambda abstractions Call by value A redex is reduced only when its right hand side has reduced to a value variable or abstraction Only the outermost redexes are reduced Call by name As normal order but no reductions are performed inside abstractions For example lx ly y x is in normal form according to this strategy although it contains the redex ly y x Strategies with sharing reduce computations that are the same in parallel Optimal reduction As normal order but computations that have the same label are reduced simultaneously Call by need As call by name hence weak but function applications that would duplicate terms instead name the argument which is then reduced only when it is needed Computability editThere is no algorithm that takes as input any two lambda expressions and outputs TRUE or FALSE depending on whether one expression reduces to the other 13 More precisely no computable function can decide the question This was historically the first problem for which undecidability could be proven As usual for such a proof computable means computable by any model of computation that is Turing complete In fact computability can itself be defined via the lambda calculus a function F N N of natural numbers is a computable function if and only if there exists a lambda expression f such that for every pair of x y in N F x y if and only if f x b y where x and y are the Church numerals corresponding to x and y respectively and b meaning equivalence with b reduction See the Church Turing thesis for other approaches to defining computability and their equivalence Church s proof of uncomputability first reduces the problem to determining whether a given lambda expression has a normal form Then he assumes that this predicate is computable and can hence be expressed in lambda calculus Building on earlier work by Kleene and constructing a Godel numbering for lambda expressions he constructs a lambda expression e that closely follows the proof of Godel s first incompleteness theorem If e is applied to its own Godel number a contradiction results Complexity editThe notion of computational complexity for the lambda calculus is a bit tricky because the cost of a b reduction may vary depending on how it is implemented 35 To be precise one must somehow find the location of all of the occurrences of the bound variable V in the expression E implying a time cost or one must keep track of the locations of free variables in some way implying a space cost A naive search for the locations of V in E is O n in the length n of E Director strings were an early approach that traded this time cost for a quadratic space usage 36 More generally this has led to the study of systems that use explicit substitution In 2014 it was shown that the number of b reduction steps taken by normal order reduction to reduce a term is a reasonable time cost model that is the reduction can be simulated on a Turing machine in time polynomially proportional to the number of steps 37 This was a long standing open problem due to size explosion the existence of lambda terms which grow exponentially in size for each b reduction The result gets around this by working with a compact shared representation The result makes clear that the amount of space needed to evaluate a lambda term is not proportional to the size of the term during reduction It is not currently known what a good measure of space complexity would be 38 An unreasonable model does not necessarily mean inefficient Optimal reduction reduces all computations with the same label in one step avoiding duplicated work but the number of parallel b reduction steps to reduce a given term to normal form is approximately linear in the size of the term This is far too small to be a reasonable cost measure as any Turing machine may be encoded in the lambda calculus in size linearly proportional to the size of the Turing machine The true cost of reducing lambda terms is not due to b reduction per se but rather the handling of the duplication of redexes during b reduction 39 It is not known if optimal reduction implementations are reasonable when measured with respect to a reasonable cost model such as the number of leftmost outermost steps to normal form but it has been shown for fragments of the lambda calculus that the optimal reduction algorithm is efficient and has at most a quadratic overhead compared to leftmost outermost 38 In addition the BOHM prototype implementation of optimal reduction outperformed both Caml Light and Haskell on pure lambda terms 39 Lambda calculus and programming languages editAs pointed out by Peter Landin s 1965 paper A Correspondence between ALGOL 60 and Church s Lambda notation 40 sequential procedural programming languages can be understood in terms of the lambda calculus which provides the basic mechanisms for procedural abstraction and procedure subprogram application Anonymous functions edit Main article Anonymous function For example in Python the square function can be expressed as a lambda expression as follows lambda x x 2 The above example is an expression that evaluates to a first class function The symbol lambda creates an anonymous function given a list of parameter names x just a single argument in this case and an expression that is evaluated as the body of the function x 2 Anonymous functions are sometimes called lambda expressions For example Pascal and many other imperative languages have long supported passing subprograms as arguments to other subprograms through the mechanism of function pointers However function pointers are not a sufficient condition for functions to be first class datatypes because a function is a first class datatype if and only if new instances of the function can be created at run time And this run time creation of functions is supported in Smalltalk JavaScript and Wolfram Language and more recently in Scala Eiffel agents C delegates and C 11 among others Parallelism and concurrency edit The Church Rosser property of the lambda calculus means that evaluation b reduction can be carried out in any order even in parallel This means that various nondeterministic evaluation strategies are relevant However the lambda calculus does not offer any explicit constructs for parallelism One can add constructs such as Futures to the lambda calculus Other process calculi have been developed for describing communication and concurrency Semantics editThe fact that lambda calculus terms act as functions on other lambda calculus terms and even on themselves led to questions about the semantics of the lambda calculus Could a sensible meaning be assigned to lambda calculus terms The natural semantics was to find a set D isomorphic to the function space D D of functions on itself However no nontrivial such D can exist by cardinality constraints because the set of all functions from D to D has greater cardinality than D unless D is a singleton set In the 1970s Dana Scott showed that if only continuous functions were considered a set or domain D with the required property could be found thus providing a model for the lambda calculus 41 This work also formed the basis for the denotational semantics of programming languages Variations and extensions editThese extensions are in the lambda cube Typed lambda calculus Lambda calculus with typed variables and functions System F A typed lambda calculus with type variables Calculus of constructions A typed lambda calculus with types as first class valuesThese formal systems are extensions of lambda calculus that are not in the lambda cube Binary lambda calculus A version of lambda calculus with binary I O a binary encoding of terms and a designated universal machine Lambda mu calculus An extension of the lambda calculus for treating classical logicThese formal systems are variations of lambda calculus Kappa calculus A first order analogue of lambda calculusThese formal systems are related to lambda calculus Combinatory logic A notation for mathematical logic without variables SKI combinator calculus A computational system based on the S K and I combinators equivalent to lambda calculus but reducible without variable substitutionsSee also edit nbsp Mathematics portalApplicative computing systems Treatment of objects in the style of the lambda calculus Cartesian closed category A setting for lambda calculus in category theory Categorical abstract machine A model of computation applicable to lambda calculus Clojure programming language Curry Howard isomorphism The formal correspondence between programs and proofs De Bruijn index notation disambiguating alpha conversions De Bruijn notation notation using postfix modification functions Deductive lambda calculus The consideration of the problems associated with considering lambda calculus as a Deductive system Domain theory Study of certain posets giving denotational semantics for lambda calculus Evaluation strategy Rules for the evaluation of expressions in programming languages Explicit substitution The theory of substitution as used in b reduction Functional programming Harrop formula A kind of constructive logical formula such that proofs are lambda terms Interaction nets Kleene Rosser paradox A demonstration that some form of lambda calculus is inconsistent Knights of the Lambda Calculus A semi fictional organization of LISP and Scheme hackers Krivine machine An abstract machine to interpret call by name in lambda calculus Lambda calculus definition Formal definition of the lambda calculus Let expression An expression closely related to an abstraction Minimalism computing Rewriting Transformation of formulae in formal systems SECD machine A virtual machine designed for the lambda calculus Scott Curry theorem A theorem about sets of lambda terms To Mock a Mockingbird An introduction to combinatory logic Universal Turing machine A formal computing machine that is equivalent to lambda calculus Unlambda An esoteric functional programming language based on combinatory logicFurther reading editAbelson Harold amp Gerald Jay Sussman Structure and Interpretation of Computer Programs The MIT Press ISBN 0 262 51087 1 Barendregt Hendrik Pieter Introduction to Lambda Calculus Barendregt Hendrik Pieter The Impact of the Lambda Calculus in Logic and Computer Science The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic Volume 3 Number 2 June 1997 Barendregt Hendrik Pieter The Type Free Lambda Calculus pp1091 1132 of Handbook of Mathematical Logic North Holland 1977 ISBN 0 7204 2285 X Cardone and Hindley 2006 History of Lambda calculus and Combinatory Logic In Gabbay and Woods eds Handbook of the History of Logic vol 5 Elsevier Church Alonzo An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory American Journal of Mathematics 58 1936 pp 345 363 This paper contains the proof that the equivalence of lambda expressions is in general not decidable Church Alonzo 1941 The Calculi of Lambda Conversion Princeton Princeton University Press Retrieved 2020 04 14 ISBN 978 0 691 08394 0 Frink Jr Orrin 1944 Review The Calculi of Lambda Conversion by Alonzo Church PDF Bull Amer Math Soc 50 3 169 172 doi 10 1090 s0002 9904 1944 08090 7 Kleene Stephen A theory of positive integers in formal logic American Journal of Mathematics 57 1935 pp 153 173 and 219 244 Contains the lambda calculus definitions of several familiar functions Landin Peter A Correspondence Between ALGOL 60 and Church s Lambda Notation Communications of the ACM vol 8 no 2 1965 pages 89 101 Available from the ACM site A classic paper highlighting the importance of lambda calculus as a basis for programming languages Larson Jim An Introduction to Lambda Calculus and Scheme A gentle introduction for programmers Michaelson Greg 10 April 2013 An Introduction to Functional Programming Through Lambda Calculus Courier Corporation ISBN 978 0 486 28029 5 42 Schalk A and Simmons H 2005 An introduction to l calculi and arithmetic with a decent selection of exercises Notes for a course in the Mathematical Logic MSc at Manchester University de Queiroz Ruy J G B 2008 On Reduction Rules Meaning as Use and Proof Theoretic Semantics Studia Logica 90 2 211 247 doi 10 1007 s11225 008 9150 5 S2CID 11321602 A paper giving a formal underpinning to the idea of meaning is use which even if based on proofs it is different from proof theoretic semantics as in the Dummett Prawitz tradition since it takes reduction as the rules giving meaning Hankin Chris An Introduction to Lambda Calculi for Computer Scientists ISBN 0954300653Monographs textbooks for graduate studentsSorensen Morten Heine and Urzyczyn Pawel 2006 Lectures on the Curry Howard isomorphism Elsevier ISBN 0 444 52077 5 is a recent monograph that covers the main topics of lambda calculus from the type free variety to most typed lambda calculi including more recent developments like pure type systems and the lambda cube It does not cover subtyping extensions Pierce Benjamin 2002 Types and Programming Languages MIT Press ISBN 0 262 16209 1 covers lambda calculi from a practical type system perspective some topics like dependent types are only mentioned but subtyping is an important topic DocumentsA Short Introduction to the Lambda Calculus PDF by Achim Jung A timeline of lambda calculus PDF by Dana Scott A Tutorial Introduction to the Lambda Calculus PDF by Raul Rojas Lecture Notes on the Lambda Calculus PDF by Peter Selinger Graphic lambda calculus by Marius Buliga Lambda Calculus as a Workflow Model by Peter Kelly Paul Coddington and Andrew Wendelborn mentions graph reduction as a common means of evaluating lambda expressions and discusses the applicability of lambda calculus for distributed computing due to the Church Rosser property which enables parallel graph reduction for lambda expressions Notes edit These rules produce expressions such as l x l y l z l x z x l y z y x y displaystyle lambda x lambda y lambda z lambda x z x lambda y z y x y nbsp Parentheses can be dropped if the expression is unambiguous For some applications terms for logical and mathematical constants and operations may be included a b c d Barendregt Barendsen 2000 call this form axiom b lx M x N M N rewritten as lx M N M x N where M x N denotes the substitution of N for every occurrence of x in M 1 7 Also denoted M N x the substitution of N for x in M 2 For a full history see Cardone and Hindley s History of Lambda calculus and Combinatory Logic 2006 a b Note that displaystyle mapsto nbsp is pronounced maps to The expression e can be variables x lambda abstractions or applications in BNF e x l x e e e displaystyle e x mid lambda x e mid e e nbsp from Wikipedia s Simply typed lambda calculus Syntax for untyped lambda calculus l x t displaystyle lambda x t nbsp is sometimes written in ASCII as L x t displaystyle Lx t nbsp In anonymous form l x t displaystyle lambda x t nbsp gets rewritten to x t displaystyle x mapsto t nbsp free variables in lambda Notation and its Calculus are comparable to linear algebra and mathematical concepts of the same name The set of free variables of M but with x removed The union of the set of free variables of M displaystyle M nbsp and the set of free variables of N displaystyle N nbsp 1 lf M N can be pronounced let f be N in M Ariola and Blom 27 employ 1 axioms for a representational calculus using well formed cyclic lambda graphs extended with letrec to detect possibly infinite unwinding trees 2 the representational calculus with b reduction of scoped lambda graphs constitute Ariola Blom s cyclic extension of lambda calculus 3 Ariola Blom reason about strict languages using call by value and compare to Moggi s calculus and to Hasegawa s calculus Conclusions on p 111 27 References editSome parts of this article are based on material from FOLDOC used with permission a b c Barendregt Henk Barendsen Erik March 2000 Introduction to Lambda Calculus PDF permanent dead link explicit substitution at the nLab Turing Alan M December 1937 Computability and l Definability The Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 4 153 163 doi 10 2307 2268280 JSTOR 2268280 S2CID 2317046 Coquand Thierry 8 February 2006 Zalta Edward N ed Type Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2013 ed Retrieved November 17 2020 Moortgat Michael 1988 Categorial Investigations Logical and Linguistic Aspects of the Lambek Calculus Foris Publications ISBN 9789067653879 Bunt Harry Muskens Reinhard eds 2008 Computing Meaning Springer ISBN 978 1 4020 5957 5 Mitchell John C 2003 Concepts in Programming Languages Cambridge University Press p 57 ISBN 978 0 521 78098 8 Chacon Sartori Camilo 2023 12 05 Introduction to Lambda Calculus using Racket Technical report Archived from the original on 2023 12 07 Pierce Benjamin C Basic Category Theory for Computer Scientists p 53 Church Alonzo 1932 A set of postulates for the foundation of logic Annals of Mathematics Series 2 33 2 346 366 doi 10 2307 1968337 JSTOR 1968337 Kleene Stephen C Rosser J B July 1935 The Inconsistency of Certain Formal Logics The Annals of Mathematics 36 3 630 doi 10 2307 1968646 JSTOR 1968646 Church Alonzo December 1942 Review of Haskell B Curry The Inconsistency of Certain Formal Logics The Journal of Symbolic Logic 7 4 170 171 doi 10 2307 2268117 JSTOR 2268117 a b Church Alonzo 1936 An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory American Journal of Mathematics 58 2 345 363 doi 10 2307 2371045 JSTOR 2371045 Church Alonzo 1940 A Formulation of the Simple Theory of Types Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 2 56 68 doi 10 2307 2266170 JSTOR 2266170 S2CID 15889861 Partee B B H ter Meulen A Wall R E 1990 Mathematical Methods in Linguistics Springer ISBN 9789027722454 Retrieved 29 Dec 2016 Alma Jesse Zalta Edward N ed The Lambda Calculus The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2013 ed Retrieved November 17 2020 Dana Scott Looking Backward Looking Forward Invited Talk at the Workshop in honour of Dana Scott s 85th birthday and 50 years of domain theory 7 8 July FLoC 2018 talk 7 July 2018 The relevant passage begins at 32 50 See also this extract of a May 2016 talk at the University of Birmingham UK Barendregt Hendrik Pieter 1984 The Lambda Calculus Its Syntax and Semantics Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics Vol 103 Revised ed North Holland ISBN 0 444 87508 5 dead link Corrections permanent dead link a b Example for Rules of Associativity Lambda bound com Retrieved 2012 06 18 The Basic Grammar of Lambda Expressions SoftOption Some other systems use juxtaposition to mean application so ab means a b This is fine except that it requires that variables have length one so that we know that ab is two variables juxtaposed not one variable of length 2 But we want to labels like firstVariable to mean a single variable so we cannot use this juxtaposition convention a b Selinger Peter 2008 Lecture Notes on the Lambda Calculus PDF vol 0804 Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa p 9 arXiv 0804 3434 Bibcode 2008arXiv0804 3434S de Queiroz Ruy J G B 1988 A Proof Theoretic Account of Programming and the Role of Reduction Rules Dialectica 42 4 265 282 doi 10 1111 j 1746 8361 1988 tb00919 x Turbak Franklyn Gifford David 2008 Design concepts in programming languages MIT press p 251 ISBN 978 0 262 20175 9 Luke Palmer 29 Dec 2010 Haskell cafe What s the motivation for h rules Felleisen Matthias Flatt Matthew 2006 Programming Languages and Lambda Calculi PDF p 26 archived from the original PDF on 2009 02 05 A note accessed 2017 at the original location suggests that the authors consider the work originally referenced to have been superseded by a book a b Zena M Ariola and Stefan Blom Proc TACS 94 Sendai Japan 1997 1997 Cyclic lambda calculi 114 pages Ker Andrew D Lambda Calculus and Types PDF p 6 Retrieved 14 January 2022 Dezani Ciancaglini Mariangiola Ghilezan Silvia 2014 Preciseness of Subtyping on Intersection and Union Types PDF Rewriting and Typed Lambda Calculi Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 8560 p 196 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 08918 8 14 hdl 2318 149874 ISBN 978 3 319 08917 1 Retrieved 14 January 2022 Forster Yannick Smolka Gert August 2019 Call by Value Lambda Calculus as a Model of Computation in Coq PDF Journal of Automated Reasoning 63 2 393 413 doi 10 1007 s10817 018 9484 2 S2CID 53087112 Retrieved 14 January 2022 Types and Programming Languages p 273 Benjamin C Pierce Pierce Benjamin C 2002 Types and Programming Languages MIT Press p 56 ISBN 0 262 16209 1 Sestoft Peter 2002 Demonstrating Lambda Calculus Reduction PDF The Essence of Computation Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 2566 pp 420 435 doi 10 1007 3 540 36377 7 19 ISBN 978 3 540 00326 7 Retrieved 22 August 2022 Biernacka Malgorzata Charatonik Witold Drab Tomasz 2022 Andronick June de Moura Leonardo eds The Zoo of Lambda Calculus Reduction Strategies and Coq PDF 13th International Conference on Interactive Theorem Proving ITP 2022 Schloss Dagstuhl Leibniz Zentrum fur Informatik 237 7 1 7 19 doi 10 4230 LIPIcs ITP 2022 7 Retrieved 22 August 2022 Frandsen Gudmund Skovbjerg Sturtivant Carl 26 August 1991 What is an efficient implementation of the l calculus Functional Programming Languages and Computer Architecture Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 523 Springer Verlag pp 289 312 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 139 6913 doi 10 1007 3540543961 14 ISBN 9783540543961 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help Sinot F R 2005 Director Strings Revisited A Generic Approach to the Efficient Representation of Free Variables in Higher order Rewriting PDF Journal of Logic and Computation 15 2 201 218 doi 10 1093 logcom exi010 Accattoli Beniamino Dal Lago Ugo 14 July 2014 Beta reduction is invariant indeed Proceedings of the Joint Meeting of the Twenty Third EACSL Annual Conference on Computer Science Logic CSL and the Twenty Ninth Annual ACM IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science LICS pp 1 10 arXiv 1601 01233 doi 10 1145 2603088 2603105 ISBN 9781450328869 S2CID 11485010 a b Accattoli Beniamino October 2018 In Efficiency and Reasonable Cost Models Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 338 23 43 doi 10 1016 j entcs 2018 10 003 a b Asperti Andrea 16 Jan 2017 About the efficient reduction of lambda terms arXiv 1701 04240v1 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Landin P J 1965 A Correspondence between ALGOL 60 and Church s Lambda notation Communications of the ACM 8 2 89 101 doi 10 1145 363744 363749 S2CID 6505810 Scott Dana 1993 A type theoretical alternative to ISWIM CUCH OWHY PDF Theoretical Computer Science 121 1 2 411 440 doi 10 1016 0304 3975 93 90095 B Retrieved 2022 12 01 Written 1969 widely circulated as an unpublished manuscript Greg Michaelson s Homepage Mathematical and Computer Sciences Riccarton Edinburgh Heriot Watt University Retrieved 6 November 2022 External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Lambda calculus Graham Hutton Lambda Calculus a short 12 minutes Computerphile video on the Lambda Calculus Helmut Brandl Step by Step Introduction to Lambda Calculus Lambda calculus Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 David C Keenan To Dissect a Mockingbird A Graphical Notation for the Lambda Calculus with Animated Reduction L Allison Some executable l calculus examples Georg P Loczewski The Lambda Calculus and A Bret Victor Alligator Eggs A Puzzle Game Based on Lambda Calculus Lambda Calculus Archived 2012 10 14 at the Wayback Machine on Safalra s Website Archived 2021 05 02 at the Wayback Machine LCI Lambda Interpreter a simple yet powerful pure calculus interpreter Lambda Calculus links on Lambda the Ultimate Mike Thyer Lambda Animator a graphical Java applet demonstrating alternative reduction strategies Implementing the Lambda calculus using C Templates Shane Steinert Threlkeld Lambda Calculi Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Anton Salikhmetov Macro Lambda Calculus Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Lambda calculus amp oldid 1202833836 CE B2 reduction, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.