fbpx
Wikipedia

Turing completeness

In computability theory, a system of data-manipulation rules (such as a computer's instruction set, a programming language, or a cellular automaton) is said to be Turing-complete or computationally universal if it can be used to simulate any Turing machine (devised by English mathematician and computer scientist Alan Turing). This means that this system is able to recognize or decide other data-manipulation rule sets. Turing completeness is used as a way to express the power of such a data-manipulation rule set. Virtually all programming languages today are Turing-complete.

A related concept is that of Turing equivalence – two computers P and Q are called equivalent if P can simulate Q and Q can simulate P. The Church–Turing thesis conjectures that any function whose values can be computed by an algorithm can be computed by a Turing machine, and therefore that if any real-world computer can simulate a Turing machine, it is Turing equivalent to a Turing machine. A universal Turing machine can be used to simulate any Turing machine and by extension the computational aspects of any possible real-world computer.[NB 1]

To show that something is Turing-complete, it is enough to show that it can be used to simulate some Turing-complete system. No physical system can have infinite memory, but if the limitation of finite memory is ignored, most programming languages are otherwise Turing-complete.

Non-mathematical usage

In colloquial usage, the terms "Turing-complete" and "Turing-equivalent" are used to mean that any real-world general-purpose computer or computer language can approximately simulate the computational aspects of any other real-world general-purpose computer or computer language. In real life this leads to the practical concepts of computing virtualization and emulation.[citation needed]

Real computers constructed so far can be functionally analyzed like a single-tape Turing machine (the "tape" corresponding to their memory); thus the associated mathematics can apply by abstracting their operation far enough. However, real computers have limited physical resources, so they are only linear bounded automaton complete. In contrast, a universal computer is defined as a device with a Turing-complete instruction set, infinite memory, and infinite available time.

Formal definitions

In computability theory, several closely related terms are used to describe the computational power of a computational system (such as an abstract machine or programming language):

Turing completeness
A computational system that can compute every Turing-computable function is called Turing-complete (or Turing-powerful). Alternatively, such a system is one that can simulate a universal Turing machine.
Turing equivalence
A Turing-complete system is called Turing-equivalent if every function it can compute is also Turing-computable; i.e., it computes precisely the same class of functions as do Turing machines. Alternatively, a Turing-equivalent system is one that can simulate, and be simulated by, a universal Turing machine. (All known physically-implementable Turing-complete systems are Turing-equivalent, which adds support to the Church–Turing thesis.[citation needed])
(Computational) universality
A system is called universal with respect to a class of systems if it can compute every function computable by systems in that class (or can simulate each of those systems). Typically, the term 'universality' is tacitly used with respect to a Turing-complete class of systems. The term "weakly universal" is sometimes used to distinguish a system (e.g. a cellular automaton) whose universality is achieved only by modifying the standard definition of Turing machine so as to include input streams with infinitely many 1s.

History

Turing completeness is significant in that every real-world design for a computing device can be simulated by a universal Turing machine. The Church–Turing thesis states that this is a law of mathematics – that a universal Turing machine can, in principle, perform any calculation that any other programmable computer can. This says nothing about the effort needed to write the program, or the time it may take for the machine to perform the calculation, or any abilities the machine may possess that have nothing to do with computation.

Charles Babbage's analytical engine (1830s) would have been the first Turing-complete machine if it had been built at the time it was designed. Babbage appreciated that the machine was capable of great feats of calculation, including primitive logical reasoning, but he did not appreciate that no other machine could do better.[citation needed] From the 1830s until the 1940s, mechanical calculating machines such as adders and multipliers were built and improved, but they could not perform a conditional branch and therefore were not Turing-complete.

In the late 19th century, Leopold Kronecker formulated notions of computability, defining primitive recursive functions. These functions can be calculated by rote computation, but they are not enough to make a universal computer, because the instructions that compute them do not allow for an infinite loop. In the early 20th century, David Hilbert led a program to axiomatize all of mathematics with precise axioms and precise logical rules of deduction that could be performed by a machine. Soon it became clear that a small set of deduction rules are enough to produce the consequences of any set of axioms. These rules were proved by Kurt Gödel in 1930 to be enough to produce every theorem.

The actual notion of computation was isolated soon after, starting with Gödel's incompleteness theorem. This theorem showed that axiom systems were limited when reasoning about the computation that deduces their theorems. Church and Turing independently demonstrated that Hilbert's Entscheidungsproblem (decision problem) was unsolvable,[1] thus identifying the computational core of the incompleteness theorem. This work, along with Gödel's work on general recursive functions, established that there are sets of simple instructions, which, when put together, are able to produce any computation. The work of Gödel showed that the notion of computation is essentially unique.

In 1941 Konrad Zuse completed the Z3 computer. Zuse was not familiar with Turing's work on computability at the time. In particular, the Z3 lacked dedicated facilities for a conditional jump, thereby precluding it from being Turing complete. However, in 1998, it was shown by Rojas that the Z3 is capable of simulating conditional jumps, and therefore Turing complete in theory. To do this, its tape program would have to be long enough to execute every possible path through both sides of every branch.[2]

The first computer capable of conditional branching in practice, and therefore Turing complete in practice, was the ENIAC in 1946. Zuse's Z4 computer was operational in 1945, but it did not support conditional branching until 1950.[3]

Computability theory

Computability theory uses models of computation to analyze problems and determine whether they are computable and under what circumstances. The first result of computability theory is that there exist problems for which it is impossible to predict what a (Turing-complete) system will do over an arbitrarily long time.

The classic example is the halting problem: create an algorithm that takes as input a program in some Turing-complete language and some data to be fed to that program, and determines whether the program, operating on the input, will eventually stop or will continue forever. It is trivial to create an algorithm that can do this for some inputs, but impossible to do this in general. For any characteristic of the program's eventual output, it is impossible to determine whether this characteristic will hold.

This impossibility poses problems when analyzing real-world computer programs. For example, one cannot write a tool that entirely protects programmers from writing infinite loops or protects users from supplying input that would cause infinite loops.

One can instead limit a program to executing only for a fixed period of time (timeout) or limit the power of flow-control instructions (for example, providing only loops that iterate over the items of an existing array). However, another theorem shows that there are problems solvable by Turing-complete languages that cannot be solved by any language with only finite looping abilities (i.e., any language guaranteeing that every program will eventually finish to a halt). So any such language is not Turing-complete. For example, a language in which programs are guaranteed to complete and halt cannot compute the computable function produced by Cantor's diagonal argument on all computable functions in that language.

Turing oracles

A computer with access to an infinite tape of data may be more powerful than a Turing machine: for instance, the tape might contain the solution to the halting problem or some other Turing-undecidable problem. Such an infinite tape of data is called a Turing oracle. Even a Turing oracle with random data is not computable (with probability 1), since there are only countably many computations but uncountably many oracles. So a computer with a random Turing oracle can compute things that a Turing machine cannot.

Digital physics

All known laws of physics have consequences that are computable by a series of approximations on a digital computer. A hypothesis called digital physics states that this is no accident because the universe itself is computable on a universal Turing machine. This would imply that no computer more powerful than a universal Turing machine can be built physically.

Examples

The computational systems (algebras, calculi) that are discussed as Turing-complete systems are those intended for studying theoretical computer science. They are intended to be as simple as possible, so that it would be easier to understand the limits of computation. Here are a few:

Most programming languages (their abstract models, maybe with some particular constructs that assume finite memory omitted), conventional and unconventional, are Turing-complete. This includes:

Some rewrite systems are Turing-complete.

Turing completeness is an abstract statement of ability, rather than a prescription of specific language features used to implement that ability. The features used to achieve Turing completeness can be quite different; Fortran systems would use loop constructs or possibly even goto statements to achieve repetition; Haskell and Prolog, lacking looping almost entirely, would use recursion. Most programming languages are describing computations on von Neumann architectures, which have memory (RAM and register) and a control unit. These two elements make this architecture Turing-complete. Even pure functional languages are Turing-complete.[5][NB 2]

Turing completeness in declarative SQL is implemented through recursive common table expressions.[6] Unsurprisingly, procedural extensions to SQL (PLSQL, etc.) are also Turing-complete. This illustrates one reason why relatively powerful non-Turing-complete languages are rare: the more powerful the language is initially, the more complex are the tasks to which it is applied and the sooner its lack of completeness becomes perceived as a drawback, encouraging its extension until it is Turing-complete.

The untyped lambda calculus is Turing-complete, but many typed lambda calculi, including System F, are not. The value of typed systems is based in their ability to represent most typical computer programs while detecting more errors.

Rule 110 and Conway's Game of Life, both cellular automata, are Turing-complete.

Unintentional Turing completeness

Some games and other software are Turing-complete by accident, i.e. not by design.

Software:

Video games:

Social media:

Computational languages:

Computer hardware:

  • x86 MOV instruction[17]

Biology:

Non-Turing-complete languages

Many computational languages exist that are not Turing-complete. One such example is the set of regular languages, which are generated by regular expressions and which are recognized by finite automata. A more powerful but still not Turing-complete extension of finite automata is the category of pushdown automata and context-free grammars, which are commonly used to generate parse trees in an initial stage of program compiling. Further examples include some of the early versions of the pixel shader languages embedded in Direct3D and OpenGL extensions.[citation needed]

In total functional programming languages, such as Charity and Epigram, all functions are total and must terminate. Charity uses a type system and control constructs based on category theory, whereas Epigram uses dependent types. The LOOP language is designed so that it computes only the functions that are primitive recursive. All of these compute proper subsets of the total computable functions, since the full set of total computable functions is not computably enumerable. Also, since all functions in these languages are total, algorithms for recursively enumerable sets cannot be written in these languages, in contrast with Turing machines.

Although (untyped) lambda calculus is Turing-complete, simply typed lambda calculus is not.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ A UTM cannot simulate non-computational aspects such as I/O.
  2. ^ The following book provides an introduction for computation models: Rauber, Thomas; Rünger, Gudula (2013). Parallel programming: for multicore and cluster systems (2nd ed.). Springer. ISBN 9783642378010.

References

  1. ^ Hodges, Andrew (1992) [1983], Alan Turing: The Enigma, London: Burnett Books, p. 111, ISBN 0-04-510060-8
  2. ^ Rojas, Raul (1998). "How to make Zuse's Z3 a universal computer". Annals of the History of Computing. 20 (3): 51–54. doi:10.1109/85.707574.
  3. ^ Rojas, Raúl (1 February 2014). Google translation, pdf is also translatable. "Konrad Zuse und der bedingte Sprung" [Konrad Zuse and the conditional jump]. Informatik-Spektrum (in German). 37 (1): 50–53. doi:10.1007/s00287-013-0717-9. ISSN 0170-6012. S2CID 1086397. {{cite journal}}: External link in |others= (help)
  4. ^ Lyons, Bob (30 March 2001). "Universal Turing Machine in XSLT". B2B Integration Solutions from Unidex. from the original on 17 July 2011. Retrieved 5 July 2010.
  5. ^ Boyer, Robert S.; Moore, J. Strother (May 1983). A Mechanical Proof of the Turing Completeness of Pure Lisp (PDF) (Technical report). Institute for Computing Science, University of Texas at Austin. 37. (PDF) from the original on 22 September 2017.
  6. ^ Dfetter; Breinbaas (8 August 2011). "Cyclic Tag System". PostgreSQL wiki. Retrieved 10 September 2014.
  7. ^ "Announcing LAMBDA: Turn Excel formulas into custom functions". TECHCOMMUNITY.MICROSOFT.COM. 3 December 2020. Retrieved 8 December 2020.
  8. ^ Wildenhain, Tom (9 April 2020). "On Turing Completeness of MS PowerPoint" (PDF).[self-published source]
  9. ^ Cedotal, Andrew (16 April 2010). "Man Uses World's Most Difficult Computer Game to Create … A Working Turing Machine". The Mary Sue. from the original on 27 June 2015. Retrieved 2 June 2015.
  10. ^ Plunkett, Luke (16 July 2019). "Cities: Skylines Map Becomes A Poop-Powered Computer". Kotaku. Retrieved 16 July 2019.
  11. ^ Caldwell, Brendan (20 November 2017). "Opus Magnum player makes an alchemical computer". Rock Paper Shotgun. Retrieved 23 September 2019.
  12. ^ Crider, Michael. "This 8-bit processor built in Minecraft can run its own games". PCWorld. Retrieved 21 July 2022.
  13. ^ "Habbo's Twitter thread on the implementation of a Turing machine inside the game". 9 November 2020. Retrieved 11 November 2020.
  14. ^ Meyers, Scott (Scott Douglas) (2005). Effective C++ : 55 specific ways to improve your programs and designs (3rd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Addison-Wesley. ISBN 0321334876. OCLC 60425273.
  15. ^ A 27th IOCCC Winner
    Carlini, Nicolas; Barresi, Antonio; Payer, Mathias; Wagner, David; Gross, Thomas R. (August 2015). "Control-flow bending: on the effectiveness of control-flow integrity". Proceedings of the 24th USENIX Conference on Security Symposium. pp. 161–176. ISBN 9781931971232.
  16. ^ Dabler, Ryan (23 September 2021). "TypeScript and Turing Completeness". ITNEXT. LINKIT. Retrieved 12 November 2022.
  17. ^ Dolan, Stephen. (PDF). stedolan.net. Archived from the original (PDF) on 14 February 2021. Retrieved 9 May 2019.
  18. ^ Shah, Shalin; Wee, Jasmine; Song, Tianqi; Ceze, Luis; Strauss, Karin; Chen, Yuan-Jyue; Reif, John (4 May 2020). "Using Strand Displacing Polymerase To Program Chemical Reaction Networks". Journal of the American Chemical Society. 142 (21): 9587–9593. doi:10.1021/jacs.0c02240. ISSN 0002-7863. PMID 32364723. S2CID 218504535.
  19. ^ Chen, Yuan-Jyue; Dalchau, Neil; Srinivas, Niranjan; Phillips, Andrew; Cardelli, Luca; Soloveichik, David; Seelig, Georg (October 2013). "Programmable chemical controllers made from DNA". Nature Nanotechnology. 8 (10): 755–762. Bibcode:2013NatNa...8..755C. doi:10.1038/nnano.2013.189. ISSN 1748-3395. PMC 4150546. PMID 24077029.
  20. ^ Srinivas, Niranjan; Parkin, James; Seelig, Georg; Winfree, Erik; Soloveichik, David (15 December 2017). "Enzyme-free nucleic acid dynamical systems". Science. 358 (6369): eaal2052. doi:10.1126/science.aal2052. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 29242317.
  21. ^ Soloveichik, David; Seelig, Georg; Winfree, Erik (23 March 2010). "DNA as a universal substrate for chemical kinetics". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 107 (12): 5393–5398. Bibcode:2010PNAS..107.5393S. doi:10.1073/pnas.0909380107. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 2851759. PMID 20203007.
  22. ^ Shapiro, Ehud (7 December 1999). . Interface Focus. Weizmann Institute of Science. 2 (4): 497–503. doi:10.1098/rsfs.2011.0118. PMC 3363030. PMID 22649583. Archived from the original on 3 January 2009. Retrieved 13 August 2009.

Further reading

  • Brainerd, W. S.; Landweber, L. H. (1974). Theory of Computation. Wiley. ISBN 0-471-09585-0.
  • Giles, Jim (24 October 2007). "Simplest 'universal computer' wins student $25,000". New Scientist.
  • Herken, Rolf, ed. (1995). The Universal Turing Machine: A Half-Century Survey. Springer Verlag. ISBN 3-211-82637-8.
  • Turing, A. M. (1936). "On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem" (PDF). Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. 2. 42: 230–265. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-42.1.230. S2CID 73712.
  • Turing, A. M. (1938). "On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem: A correction". Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. 2. 43: 544–546. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-43.6.544.

External links

  • "Turing Complete". wiki.c2.com.

turing, completeness, usage, this, term, theory, relative, computability, oracle, machines, turing, reduction, computability, theory, system, data, manipulation, rules, such, computer, instruction, programming, language, cellular, automaton, said, turing, comp. For the usage of this term in the theory of relative computability by oracle machines see Turing reduction In computability theory a system of data manipulation rules such as a computer s instruction set a programming language or a cellular automaton is said to be Turing complete or computationally universal if it can be used to simulate any Turing machine devised by English mathematician and computer scientist Alan Turing This means that this system is able to recognize or decide other data manipulation rule sets Turing completeness is used as a way to express the power of such a data manipulation rule set Virtually all programming languages today are Turing complete A related concept is that of Turing equivalence two computers P and Q are called equivalent if P can simulate Q and Q can simulate P The Church Turing thesis conjectures that any function whose values can be computed by an algorithm can be computed by a Turing machine and therefore that if any real world computer can simulate a Turing machine it is Turing equivalent to a Turing machine A universal Turing machine can be used to simulate any Turing machine and by extension the computational aspects of any possible real world computer NB 1 To show that something is Turing complete it is enough to show that it can be used to simulate some Turing complete system No physical system can have infinite memory but if the limitation of finite memory is ignored most programming languages are otherwise Turing complete Contents 1 Non mathematical usage 2 Formal definitions 3 History 4 Computability theory 5 Turing oracles 6 Digital physics 7 Examples 7 1 Unintentional Turing completeness 8 Non Turing complete languages 9 See also 10 Notes 11 References 12 Further reading 13 External linksNon mathematical usage EditIn colloquial usage the terms Turing complete and Turing equivalent are used to mean that any real world general purpose computer or computer language can approximately simulate the computational aspects of any other real world general purpose computer or computer language In real life this leads to the practical concepts of computing virtualization and emulation citation needed Real computers constructed so far can be functionally analyzed like a single tape Turing machine the tape corresponding to their memory thus the associated mathematics can apply by abstracting their operation far enough However real computers have limited physical resources so they are only linear bounded automaton complete In contrast a universal computer is defined as a device with a Turing complete instruction set infinite memory and infinite available time Formal definitions EditIn computability theory several closely related terms are used to describe the computational power of a computational system such as an abstract machine or programming language Turing completeness A computational system that can compute every Turing computable function is called Turing complete or Turing powerful Alternatively such a system is one that can simulate a universal Turing machine Turing equivalence A Turing complete system is called Turing equivalent if every function it can compute is also Turing computable i e it computes precisely the same class of functions as do Turing machines Alternatively a Turing equivalent system is one that can simulate and be simulated by a universal Turing machine All known physically implementable Turing complete systems are Turing equivalent which adds support to the Church Turing thesis citation needed Computational universality A system is called universal with respect to a class of systems if it can compute every function computable by systems in that class or can simulate each of those systems Typically the term universality is tacitly used with respect to a Turing complete class of systems The term weakly universal is sometimes used to distinguish a system e g a cellular automaton whose universality is achieved only by modifying the standard definition of Turing machine so as to include input streams with infinitely many 1s History EditTuring completeness is significant in that every real world design for a computing device can be simulated by a universal Turing machine The Church Turing thesis states that this is a law of mathematics that a universal Turing machine can in principle perform any calculation that any other programmable computer can This says nothing about the effort needed to write the program or the time it may take for the machine to perform the calculation or any abilities the machine may possess that have nothing to do with computation Charles Babbage s analytical engine 1830s would have been the first Turing complete machine if it had been built at the time it was designed Babbage appreciated that the machine was capable of great feats of calculation including primitive logical reasoning but he did not appreciate that no other machine could do better citation needed From the 1830s until the 1940s mechanical calculating machines such as adders and multipliers were built and improved but they could not perform a conditional branch and therefore were not Turing complete In the late 19th century Leopold Kronecker formulated notions of computability defining primitive recursive functions These functions can be calculated by rote computation but they are not enough to make a universal computer because the instructions that compute them do not allow for an infinite loop In the early 20th century David Hilbert led a program to axiomatize all of mathematics with precise axioms and precise logical rules of deduction that could be performed by a machine Soon it became clear that a small set of deduction rules are enough to produce the consequences of any set of axioms These rules were proved by Kurt Godel in 1930 to be enough to produce every theorem The actual notion of computation was isolated soon after starting with Godel s incompleteness theorem This theorem showed that axiom systems were limited when reasoning about the computation that deduces their theorems Church and Turing independently demonstrated that Hilbert s Entscheidungsproblem decision problem was unsolvable 1 thus identifying the computational core of the incompleteness theorem This work along with Godel s work on general recursive functions established that there are sets of simple instructions which when put together are able to produce any computation The work of Godel showed that the notion of computation is essentially unique In 1941 Konrad Zuse completed the Z3 computer Zuse was not familiar with Turing s work on computability at the time In particular the Z3 lacked dedicated facilities for a conditional jump thereby precluding it from being Turing complete However in 1998 it was shown by Rojas that the Z3 is capable of simulating conditional jumps and therefore Turing complete in theory To do this its tape program would have to be long enough to execute every possible path through both sides of every branch 2 The first computer capable of conditional branching in practice and therefore Turing complete in practice was the ENIAC in 1946 Zuse s Z4 computer was operational in 1945 but it did not support conditional branching until 1950 3 Computability theory EditComputability theory uses models of computation to analyze problems and determine whether they are computable and under what circumstances The first result of computability theory is that there exist problems for which it is impossible to predict what a Turing complete system will do over an arbitrarily long time The classic example is the halting problem create an algorithm that takes as input a program in some Turing complete language and some data to be fed to that program and determines whether the program operating on the input will eventually stop or will continue forever It is trivial to create an algorithm that can do this for some inputs but impossible to do this in general For any characteristic of the program s eventual output it is impossible to determine whether this characteristic will hold This impossibility poses problems when analyzing real world computer programs For example one cannot write a tool that entirely protects programmers from writing infinite loops or protects users from supplying input that would cause infinite loops One can instead limit a program to executing only for a fixed period of time timeout or limit the power of flow control instructions for example providing only loops that iterate over the items of an existing array However another theorem shows that there are problems solvable by Turing complete languages that cannot be solved by any language with only finite looping abilities i e any language guaranteeing that every program will eventually finish to a halt So any such language is not Turing complete For example a language in which programs are guaranteed to complete and halt cannot compute the computable function produced by Cantor s diagonal argument on all computable functions in that language Turing oracles EditMain article Oracle machine A computer with access to an infinite tape of data may be more powerful than a Turing machine for instance the tape might contain the solution to the halting problem or some other Turing undecidable problem Such an infinite tape of data is called a Turing oracle Even a Turing oracle with random data is not computable with probability 1 since there are only countably many computations but uncountably many oracles So a computer with a random Turing oracle can compute things that a Turing machine cannot Digital physics EditSee also Church Turing thesis Philosophical implications This section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed November 2017 Learn how and when to remove this template message All known laws of physics have consequences that are computable by a series of approximations on a digital computer A hypothesis called digital physics states that this is no accident because the universe itself is computable on a universal Turing machine This would imply that no computer more powerful than a universal Turing machine can be built physically Examples EditThe computational systems algebras calculi that are discussed as Turing complete systems are those intended for studying theoretical computer science They are intended to be as simple as possible so that it would be easier to understand the limits of computation Here are a few Automata theory Formal grammar language generators Formal language language recognizers Lambda calculus Post Turing machines Process calculusMost programming languages their abstract models maybe with some particular constructs that assume finite memory omitted conventional and unconventional are Turing complete This includes All general purpose languages in wide use Procedural programming languages such as C Pascal Object oriented languages such as Java Smalltalk or C Multi paradigm languages such as Ada C Common Lisp Fortran JavaScript Object Pascal Perl Python R Most languages using less common paradigms Functional languages such as Lisp and Haskell Logic programming languages such as Prolog General purpose macro processor such as m4 Declarative languages such as XSLT 4 VHDL and other hardware description languages TeX a typesetting system Esoteric programming languages a form of mathematical recreation in which programmers work out how to achieve basic programming constructs in an extremely difficult but mathematically Turing equivalent language Some rewrite systems are Turing complete Turing completeness is an abstract statement of ability rather than a prescription of specific language features used to implement that ability The features used to achieve Turing completeness can be quite different Fortran systems would use loop constructs or possibly even goto statements to achieve repetition Haskell and Prolog lacking looping almost entirely would use recursion Most programming languages are describing computations on von Neumann architectures which have memory RAM and register and a control unit These two elements make this architecture Turing complete Even pure functional languages are Turing complete 5 NB 2 Turing completeness in declarative SQL is implemented through recursive common table expressions 6 Unsurprisingly procedural extensions to SQL PLSQL etc are also Turing complete This illustrates one reason why relatively powerful non Turing complete languages are rare the more powerful the language is initially the more complex are the tasks to which it is applied and the sooner its lack of completeness becomes perceived as a drawback encouraging its extension until it is Turing complete The untyped lambda calculus is Turing complete but many typed lambda calculi including System F are not The value of typed systems is based in their ability to represent most typical computer programs while detecting more errors Rule 110 and Conway s Game of Life both cellular automata are Turing complete Unintentional Turing completeness Edit Some games and other software are Turing complete by accident i e not by design Software Microsoft Excel 7 Microsoft PowerPoint 8 Video games Dwarf Fortress 9 Cities Skylines 10 Opus Magnum 11 Minecraft 12 Social media Habbo Hotel 13 Computational languages C templates 14 printf format string 15 TypeScript s type system 16 Computer hardware x86 MOV instruction 17 Biology Chemical reaction networks 18 19 20 21 and enzyme based DNA computers 22 have been shown to be Turing equivalentNon Turing complete languages EditMany computational languages exist that are not Turing complete One such example is the set of regular languages which are generated by regular expressions and which are recognized by finite automata A more powerful but still not Turing complete extension of finite automata is the category of pushdown automata and context free grammars which are commonly used to generate parse trees in an initial stage of program compiling Further examples include some of the early versions of the pixel shader languages embedded in Direct3D and OpenGL extensions citation needed In total functional programming languages such as Charity and Epigram all functions are total and must terminate Charity uses a type system and control constructs based on category theory whereas Epigram uses dependent types The LOOP language is designed so that it computes only the functions that are primitive recursive All of these compute proper subsets of the total computable functions since the full set of total computable functions is not computably enumerable Also since all functions in these languages are total algorithms for recursively enumerable sets cannot be written in these languages in contrast with Turing machines Although untyped lambda calculus is Turing complete simply typed lambda calculus is not See also EditAI completeness Algorithmic information theory Chomsky hierarchy Church Turing thesis Computability theory Inner loop Loop computing Machine that always halts Rice s theorem smn theorem Structured program theorem Turing tarpit Virtualization Emulation computing Notes Edit A UTM cannot simulate non computational aspects such as I O The following book provides an introduction for computation models Rauber Thomas Runger Gudula 2013 Parallel programming for multicore and cluster systems 2nd ed Springer ISBN 9783642378010 References Edit Hodges Andrew 1992 1983 Alan Turing The Enigma London Burnett Books p 111 ISBN 0 04 510060 8 Rojas Raul 1998 How to make Zuse s Z3 a universal computer Annals of the History of Computing 20 3 51 54 doi 10 1109 85 707574 Rojas Raul 1 February 2014 Google translation pdf is also translatable Konrad Zuse und der bedingte Sprung Konrad Zuse and the conditional jump Informatik Spektrum in German 37 1 50 53 doi 10 1007 s00287 013 0717 9 ISSN 0170 6012 S2CID 1086397 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a External link in code class cs1 code others code help Lyons Bob 30 March 2001 Universal Turing Machine in XSLT B2B Integration Solutions from Unidex Archived from the original on 17 July 2011 Retrieved 5 July 2010 Boyer Robert S Moore J Strother May 1983 A Mechanical Proof of the Turing Completeness of Pure Lisp PDF Technical report Institute for Computing Science University of Texas at Austin 37 Archived PDF from the original on 22 September 2017 Dfetter Breinbaas 8 August 2011 Cyclic Tag System PostgreSQL wiki Retrieved 10 September 2014 Announcing LAMBDA Turn Excel formulas into custom functions TECHCOMMUNITY MICROSOFT COM 3 December 2020 Retrieved 8 December 2020 Wildenhain Tom 9 April 2020 On Turing Completeness of MS PowerPoint PDF self published source Cedotal Andrew 16 April 2010 Man Uses World s Most Difficult Computer Game to Create A Working Turing Machine The Mary Sue Archived from the original on 27 June 2015 Retrieved 2 June 2015 Plunkett Luke 16 July 2019 Cities Skylines Map Becomes A Poop Powered Computer Kotaku Retrieved 16 July 2019 Caldwell Brendan 20 November 2017 Opus Magnum player makes an alchemical computer Rock Paper Shotgun Retrieved 23 September 2019 Crider Michael This 8 bit processor built in Minecraft can run its own games PCWorld Retrieved 21 July 2022 Habbo s Twitter thread on the implementation of a Turing machine inside the game 9 November 2020 Retrieved 11 November 2020 Meyers Scott Scott Douglas 2005 Effective C 55 specific ways to improve your programs and designs 3rd ed Upper Saddle River NJ Addison Wesley ISBN 0321334876 OCLC 60425273 A 27th IOCCC WinnerCarlini Nicolas Barresi Antonio Payer Mathias Wagner David Gross Thomas R August 2015 Control flow bending on the effectiveness of control flow integrity Proceedings of the 24th USENIX Conference on Security Symposium pp 161 176 ISBN 9781931971232 Dabler Ryan 23 September 2021 TypeScript and Turing Completeness ITNEXT LINKIT Retrieved 12 November 2022 Dolan Stephen mov is Turing complete PDF stedolan net Archived from the original PDF on 14 February 2021 Retrieved 9 May 2019 Shah Shalin Wee Jasmine Song Tianqi Ceze Luis Strauss Karin Chen Yuan Jyue Reif John 4 May 2020 Using Strand Displacing Polymerase To Program Chemical Reaction Networks Journal of the American Chemical Society 142 21 9587 9593 doi 10 1021 jacs 0c02240 ISSN 0002 7863 PMID 32364723 S2CID 218504535 Chen Yuan Jyue Dalchau Neil Srinivas Niranjan Phillips Andrew Cardelli Luca Soloveichik David Seelig Georg October 2013 Programmable chemical controllers made from DNA Nature Nanotechnology 8 10 755 762 Bibcode 2013NatNa 8 755C doi 10 1038 nnano 2013 189 ISSN 1748 3395 PMC 4150546 PMID 24077029 Srinivas Niranjan Parkin James Seelig Georg Winfree Erik Soloveichik David 15 December 2017 Enzyme free nucleic acid dynamical systems Science 358 6369 eaal2052 doi 10 1126 science aal2052 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 29242317 Soloveichik David Seelig Georg Winfree Erik 23 March 2010 DNA as a universal substrate for chemical kinetics Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 107 12 5393 5398 Bibcode 2010PNAS 107 5393S doi 10 1073 pnas 0909380107 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 2851759 PMID 20203007 Shapiro Ehud 7 December 1999 A Mechanical Turing Machine Blueprint for a Biomolecular Computer Interface Focus Weizmann Institute of Science 2 4 497 503 doi 10 1098 rsfs 2011 0118 PMC 3363030 PMID 22649583 Archived from the original on 3 January 2009 Retrieved 13 August 2009 Further reading EditBrainerd W S Landweber L H 1974 Theory of Computation Wiley ISBN 0 471 09585 0 Giles Jim 24 October 2007 Simplest universal computer wins student 25 000 New Scientist Herken Rolf ed 1995 The Universal Turing Machine A Half Century Survey Springer Verlag ISBN 3 211 82637 8 Turing A M 1936 On Computable Numbers with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem PDF Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 2 42 230 265 doi 10 1112 plms s2 42 1 230 S2CID 73712 Turing A M 1938 On Computable Numbers with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem A correction Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 2 43 544 546 doi 10 1112 plms s2 43 6 544 External links Edit Turing Complete wiki c2 com Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Turing completeness amp oldid 1134730126, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.