fbpx
Wikipedia

School of Salamanca

The School of Salamanca (Spanish: Escuela de Salamanca) is the Renaissance of thought in diverse intellectual areas by Spanish theologians, rooted in the intellectual and pedagogical work of Francisco de Vitoria. From the beginning of the 16th century the traditional Catholic conception of man and of his relation to God and to the world had been assaulted by the rise of humanism, by the Protestant Reformation and by the new geographical discoveries and their consequences. These new problems were addressed by the School of Salamanca. The name refers to the University of Salamanca, where de Vitoria and other members of the school were based.

17th century classroom at the University of Salamanca

The juridical doctrine of the School of Salamanca represented the end of medieval concepts of law, with a revindication of liberty not habitual in Europe of that time. The natural rights of man came to be, in one form or another, the center of attention, including rights as a corporeal being (right to life, economic rights such as the right to own property) and spiritual rights (the right to freedom of thought and to human dignity).

The School of Salamanca reformulated the concept of natural law: law originating in nature itself, with all that exists in the natural order sharing in this law. Their conclusion was, given that all humans share the same nature, they also share the same rights to life and liberty. Such views constituted a novelty in European thought and went counter to those then predominant in Spain and Europe that people indigenous to the Americas had no such rights.

History and leading figures

The School of Salamanca in the broad sense comprises two successive schools of thought, the largely Dominican Salmanticenses, then from the end of the 16th century the Jesuit Conimbricenses of the University of Coimbra, reflecting the general transition of intellectual leadership in the Catholic Church from the Dominicans to the Jesuits.

The first school began with Francisco de Vitoria (1483–1546), and reached its high point with Domingo de Soto (1494–1560). Leading Conimbricenses were Luis de Molina (1535–1600), Francisco Suárez (1548–1617), and Giovanni Botero (1544–1617), who would continue the tradition in Italy.

The leading figures of the school, theologians and jurists Francisco de Vitoria, Domingo de Soto, Francisco Suárez, Martín de Azpilcueta (or Azpilicueta), and Tomás de Mercado were all scholars of natural law and of morality, who undertook the reconciliation of the teachings of Thomas Aquinas with the then new political-economic order. The themes of study centered on man and his practical problems (morality, economics, jurisprudence, etc.), but almost equally on a particular body of work accepted by all of them, as the ground against which to test their disagreements, including at times bitter polemics within the School.

Sovereignty

The School of Salamanca distinguished two realms of power, the natural or civil realm and the realm of the supernatural, which were often conflated in the Middle Ages through granting royal control of investiture of bishops, or the temporal powers of the pope. One direct consequence of the separation of realms of power is that the king or emperor does not legitimately have jurisdiction over souls, nor does the pope have legitimate temporal power. This included the idea that there are limits on the legitimate powers of government. Thus, according to Luis de Molina a nation is analogous to the mercantile corporations of his time, in that those who govern are holders of power (effectively sovereigns) but a collective power, to which they are subject, derives from them jointly. Nonetheless, in de Molina's view, the power of society over the individual is greater than that of a mercantile corporation over its members, because the power of the government of a nation emanates from God's divine power (as against merely from the power of individuals sovereign over themselves in their business dealings). At this time, the monarchy of England was extending the theory of the divine right of kings—under which the monarch is the unique legatee of God's power—asserting that subjects must follow the monarch's orders, in order not to contravene God's design. Counter to this, several adherents of the School sustained that the people are the vehicle of divine sovereignty, which they, in turn, pass to a prince under various conditions. In this, the late scholastics were instrumental in the development of early modern theories of political representation.[1] Possibly the one who went furthest in this direction was Francisco Suárez, whose work Defensio Fidei Catholicae adversus Anglicanae sectae errores (The Defense of the Catholic Faith against the errors of the Anglican sect 1613) was the strongest contemporary defense of popular sovereignty. Men are born free by their nature and not as slaves of another man, and can disobey even to the point of deposing an unjust government. As with de Molina, he affirms that political power does not reside in any individual, but he differs subtly in that he considers that the recipient of that power is the people as a whole, not a collection of sovereign individuals—in the same way, Jean-Jacques Rousseau's theory of popular sovereignty would consider the people as a collective group superior to the sum that composes it.[2]

Gabriel Vázquez (1549–1604) held that natural law is not limited to the individual, but obliges societies to respect natural rights and justice.

For Suárez, the political power of society is contractual in origin because the community forms by consensus of free wills. The consequence of this contractualist theory[3] is that the natural form of government is either a democracy or a republic, while oligarchy or monarchy arise as secondary institutions, whose claim to justice is based on consent of the governed organized in a political body.[2]

The law of peoples and international law

Francisco de Vitoria played an important role in the early modern comprehension of ius gentium (the rights of nations). He extrapolated his ideas of legitimate sovereign power to relations between nations, concluding that international society as well ought to be ruled by just forms respecting the rights of all. The common good of the world is of a category superior to the good of each state. This meant that relations between states ought to pass from being justified by force to being justified by law and right.[4] Vitoria has been referred to, along with Grotius, as the “father of international law.”[5]

Francisco Suárez subdivided the concept of ius gentium. Working with already well-formed categories, he carefully distinguished ius inter gentes from ius intra gentes. Ius inter gentes (which corresponds to modern international law) was a just agreement among the majority of countries, although being positive law, not natural law, it was not necessarily universal. On the other hand, ius intra gentes, or civil law, is specific to each nation.[6]

Many scholars have argued for the importance of Vitoria and Suárez as the forerunners and founders of the International law field, and the precursors of the seminal text De iure belli ac pacis by Grotius.[7][8] Others, such as Koskenniemi, have argued that none of these humanist and scholastic thinkers can be understood to have founded international law in the modern sense, instead placing its origins in the post-1870 period.[9]

Just war

Given that war is one of the worst evils suffered by mankind, the adherents of the School reasoned that it ought to be resorted to only when it was necessary to prevent an even greater evil. A diplomatic agreement is preferable, even for the more powerful party, before a war is started. Examples of "just war" are:

  • In self-defense, as long as there is a reasonable possibility of success. If failure is a foregone conclusion, then it is just a wasteful spilling of blood.
  • Preventive war against a tyrant who is about to attack.
  • War to punish a guilty enemy.

A war is not legitimate or illegitimate simply based on its original motivation: it must comply with a series of additional requirements:

  • It is necessary that the response be commensurate with the evil; use of more violence than is strictly necessary would constitute an unjust war.
  • Governing authorities declare war, but their decision is not sufficient cause to begin a war. If the people oppose a war, then it is illegitimate. The people have a right to depose a government that is waging, or is about to wage, an unjust war.
  • Once war has begun, there remain moral limits to action. For example, one may not attack innocents or kill hostages.
  • War is only legitimate as a last resort, after vigorous attempts at negotiation and diplomacy have failed.

Under this doctrine, expansionist wars, wars of pillage, wars to convert infidels or pagans, and wars for glory are all inherently unjust.

The conquest of America

In the 16th century, the School of Salamanca was the first to use the natural law's principle that rights reside in the individual to question the Spanish colonization on the indigenous people of the Americas.[10]

Francisco de Vitoria began his analysis of conquest by rejecting "illegitimate titles". He was the first to dare to question whether the bulls of Alexander VI known collectively as the Bulls of Donation were a valid title of dominion over the newly discovered territories. In this matter he did not accept the universal primacy of the emperor, the authority of the pope (because the pope, according to him, lacked temporal power), nor the claim of voluntary submission or conversion of the Native Americans. One could not dismiss them as sinners or ignorant savages: they were free people by nature, with legitimate property rights. When the Spanish arrived in America they brought no legitimate title to occupy and rule those lands.

Vitoria also analyzed whether there were legitimate claims of title over discovered lands. He elaborated up to eight legitimate titles of dominion. The first and perhaps most fundamental relates to communication between people, who jointly constitute a universal society. Ius peregrinandi et degendi is the universal right to travel and do commerce in all parts of the earth, independently of who governs or what is the religion of the territory. For him, if the "Indians" of the Americas would not permit free transit, the hindered parties had the right to defend themselves and to remain in land obtained in such a war of self-defense.

The second form of legitimate title over discovered lands referred to the right of the Spanish to preach and proselytize. The Indians could voluntarily refuse conversion, but forbidding missionaries would make the matter analogous to the first case. Nonetheless, Vitoria noted that although this can be grounds for a just war, it is not necessarily prudent because of the resulting death and destruction.

The other cases of this casuistry are:

  • If the pagan sovereigns force converts to return to idolatry.
  • If there come to be a sufficient number of Christians in the newly discovered land that they wish to receive from the Pope a Christian government.
  • In the case of overthrowing a tyranny or a government that is harming innocents (e.g. human sacrifice)
  • If associates and friends have been attacked—as were the Tlaxcaltecas, allied with the Spanish but subjected, like many other people, to the Aztecs—once again, this could justify a war, with the ensuing possibility of legitimate conquest as in the first case.
  • The final "legitimate title" although qualified by Vitoria himself as doubtful, is the suffering of the foreign population from lack of just laws, magistrates, agricultural techniques, etc. In any case, title taken according to this principle must be exercised with Christian charity and for the advantage of the Indians.

Emperor Charles V, then ruler of Spain, took offense to this doctrine of "legitimate" and "illegitimate" titles purporting to limit his prerogatives, and he tried without success to stop its promulgation.

Economics

The School of Salamanca has been described as the "first economic tradition" in the field of economics.[11] This put the origins of economic theory on Europe's mainland, prompting a reassessment of the entire history of the discipline.[12] Much attention has been drawn to the economic thought of the School of Salamanca by Joseph Schumpeter's History of Economic Analysis (1954). It did not coin, but certainly consolidated, the use of the term School of Salamanca in economics. Schumpeter studied scholastic doctrine in general and Spanish scholastic doctrine in particular, and praised the high level of economic science in Spain in the 16th century. He argued that the School of Salamanca most deserves to be considered the founders of economics as a science. The School did not elaborate a complete doctrine of economics, but they established the first modern economic theories to address the new economic problems that had arisen with the end of the medieval order. Unfortunately, there was no continuation of their work until the end of the 17th century and many of their contributions were forgotten, only to be rediscovered later by others.

The thinking of the School was defined as "pro-market, pro-hard money, anti-state in many ways, pro-property, and pro-merchant to a surprising extent."[12]

The English historian of economic thought Marjorie Grice-Hutchinson and Belgian legal historian Wim Decock have published numerous articles and monographs on the School of Salamanca.[13]

Although there does not appear to be any direct influence, the economic thought of the School of Salamanca is in many ways similar to that of the Austrian School. Murray Rothbard referred to them as proto-Austrians.[12]

Antecedents

In 1517, de Vitoria, then at the Sorbonne, was consulted by Spanish merchants based in Antwerp about the moral legitimacy of engaging in commerce to increase one's personal wealth. From today's point of view, one would say they were asking for a consultation about the entrepreneurial spirit. Beginning at that time, Vitoria and other theologians looked at economic matters. They moved away from views that they found to be obsolete, adopting instead new ideas based on principles of natural law.

According to these views, the natural order is based in the "freedom of circulation" of people, goods, and ideas, allowing people to know one another and increase their sentiments of brotherhood.[citation needed] This implies that merchantry is not merely not reprehensible, but that it actually serves the general good.

Private property

The adherents of the School of Salamanca all agreed that property has the beneficial effect of stimulating economic activity, which, in turn, contributed to the general well being. Diego de Covarubias y Leyva (1512–1577) considered that people had not only the right to own property but—again, a specifically modern idea—they had the exclusive right to the benefit from that property, although the community might also benefit. Nonetheless, in times of great necessity, there, all goods become a commons.

Luis de Molina argued that individual owners take better care of their goods than is taken of common property, a form of the tragedy of the commons.

Money, value, and price

The most complete and methodical developments of a Salamancan theory of value were by Martín de Azpilcueta (1493–1586) and Luis de Molina. Interested in the effect of precious metals arriving from the Americas, de Azpilcueta proved that in the countries where precious metals were scarce, prices for them were higher than in those where they were abundant. Precious metals, like any other mercantile good, gained at least some of their value from their scarcity.[14] This scarcity theory of value was a precursor of the quantitative theory of money put forward slightly later by Jean Bodin (1530–1596).

Up until that time, the predominant theory of value had been the medieval theory based on the cost of production as the sole determinant of a just price (a variant of the cost-of-production theory of value, most recently manifested in the labor theory of value). Diego de Covarrubias and Luis de Molina developed a subjective theory of value and prices, which asserted that the usefulness of a good varied from person to person, so just prices would arise from mutual decisions in free commerce, barring the distorting effects of monopoly, fraud, or government intervention. Expressing this in today's terms, the adherents of the School defended the free market, where the fair price of a good would be determined by supply and demand.

On this Luis Saravia de la Calle wrote in 1544:

Those who measure the just price by the labour, costs, and risk incurred by the person who deals in the merchandise or produces it, or by the cost of transport or the expense of traveling...or by what he has to pay the factors for their industry, risk, and labour, are greatly in error.... For the just price arises from the abundance or scarcity of goods, merchants, and money...and not from costs, labour, and risk.... Why should a bale of linen brought overland from Brittany at great expense be worth more than one which is transported cheaply by sea?... Why should a book written out by hand be worth more than one which is printed, when the latter is better though it costs less to produce?... The just price is found not by counting the cost but by the common estimation.

However the school rarely followed this idea through systematically, and, as Friedrich Hayek has written, "never to the point of realizing that what was relevant was not merely man's relation to a particular thing or a class of things but the position of the thing in the whole...scheme by which men decide how to allocate the resources at their disposal among their different endeavors."[15]

Interest on money

Usury (which in that period meant any charging of interest on a loan) has always been viewed negatively by the Catholic Church. The Third Lateran Council condemned any repayment of a debt with more money than was originally loaned; the Council of Vienne explicitly prohibited usury and declared any legislation tolerant of usury to be heretical; the first scholastics reproved the charging of interest. In the medieval economy, loans were entirely a consequence of necessity (bad harvests, fire in a workplace) and, under those conditions, it was considered morally reproachable to charge interest.

In the Renaissance era, greater mobility of people facilitated an increase in commerce and the appearance of appropriate conditions for entrepreneurs to start new, lucrative businesses. Given that borrowed money was no longer strictly for consumption but for production as well, it could not be viewed in the same manner. The School of Salamanca elaborated various reasons that justified the charging of interest. The person who received a loan benefited; one could consider interest as a premium paid for the risk taken by the loaning party. There was also the question of opportunity cost, in that the loaning party lost other possibilities of utilizing the loaned money. Finally, and perhaps most originally, was the consideration of money itself as a merchandise, and the use of one's money as something for which one should receive a benefit in the form of interest.

Martín de Azpilcueta also considered the effect of time, formulating the time value of money. All things being equal, one would prefer to receive a given good now rather than in the future. This preference indicates greater value. Interest, under this theory, is the payment for the time the loaning individual is deprived of the money.

Theology

In the Renaissance era, theology was generally declining[citation needed] in the face of the rise of humanism, with scholasticism becoming nothing more than an empty and routine methodology[citation needed]. Under Francisco de Vitoria, the University of Salamanca led a period of intense activity in theology, especially a renaissance of Thomism, whose influence extended to European culture in general, but especially to other European universities. Perhaps the fundamental contribution of the School of Salamanca to theology is the study of problems much closer to humanity, which had previously been ignored, and the opening of questions that had previously not been posed. The term positive theology is sometimes used to distinguish this new, more practical, theology from the earlier scholastic theology.

Morality

In an era when religion permeated everything, to analyze the morality of the acts was considered the most practical and useful study one could undertake to serve society. The novel contributions of the School in law and economics were rooted in concrete challenges and moral problems which confronted society under new conditions.

Over the years a casuistry, a fixed set of answers to moral dilemmas, had been developed. However, by its nature, a casuistry can never be complete, leading to a search for more general rules or principles. From this developed probabilism, where the ultimate criterion was not truth, but the certainty of not choosing evil. Developed principally by Bartolomé de Medina and continued by Gabriel Vázquez and Francisco Suárez, Probabilism became the most important school of moral thought in the coming centuries.[citation needed]

The De auxiliis controversy

The De auxiliis controversy was a dispute between Jesuits and Dominicans which occurred at the end of the 16th century. The topic of the controversy was grace and predestination, that is to say how one could reconcile the liberty or free will of humans with divine omniscience. In 1582 the Jesuit Prudencio Montemayor and Fray Luis de León spoke publicly about human liberty. Domingo Báñez considered that they gave free will too great a weight and that they used terminology that sounded heretical; he denounced them to the Spanish Inquisition, accusing them of Pelagianism, a belief in human free will to the detriment of the doctrine of original sin and the grace granted by God. Montemayor and de León were banned from teaching and prohibited from defending such ideas.

Báñez was then denounced to the Holy Office by Leon, who accused him of "committing the error of Lutheranism", that is of following the doctrines of Martin Luther. According to Lutheran doctrine, man is "dead in his trespasses" (Ephesians 2:1) as a consequence of original sin and cannot save himself by his own merit; only God can save man, "For by grace you have been saved through faith. And this is not your own doing; it is the gift of God, not a result of works, so that no one may boast." (Ephesians 2:8–9) Báñez was acquitted.

Nonetheless, this did not end the dispute, which Luis de Molina continued with his Concordia liberi arbitrii cum gratiae donis (1588). This is considered the best expression of the Jesuit position. The polemic continued over the course of years, including an attempt by the Dominicans to get Pope Clement VIII to condemn the Concordia of de Molina. Finally Paul V in 1607 recognized the liberty of Dominicans and Jesuits to defend their ideas, prohibiting that either side of this disagreement be characterized as heresy.

The existence of evil in the world

The existence of evil in a world created and ruled by an infinitely good and powerful God has long been viewed as paradoxical. (See Problem of evil). Vitoria reconciled the paradox by arguing first that free will is a gift from God to each person. It is impossible that each person will always freely choose only the good. Thus, evil results from man's ability not to choose good, by virtue of his free will.

Members

There is discussion about which authors can be assigned to the name of the School of Salamanca, or if one can speak of a School of Salamanca in the first place, but the consensus revolves around the name of Francisco de Vitoria, considered a central figure of the movement . From him, authors refer to three stages, counting in the first the pupils of Vitoria and their pupils, in the second Salamanca contemporaries who had no direct relationship with him and in the third external figures influenced by this current of thought. [16]

First group


Second group


Third group

See also

References

  1. ^ * Messarra, Sean (2020). "Representation and scholastic political thought". History of European Ideas. 46 (6): 737–753. doi:10.1080/01916599.2020.1756891. S2CID 219478086.
  2. ^ a b Dellavalle, Sergio (2021-05-27). Paradigms of Social Order: From Holism to Pluralism and Beyond. Springer Nature. p. 129. ISBN 978-3-030-66179-3.
  3. ^ CAMPOS, ANDRE SANTOS (2019). "Francisco Suárez's Conception of the Social Contract". Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia. 75 (2): 1195–1218. doi:10.17990/RPF/2019_75_2_1195. ISSN 0870-5283. JSTOR 26678106. S2CID 199141748.
  4. ^ Lewkowicz, Nicolas (2007). "The Spanish School as a forerunner to the English School of international relations". Estudios Humanísticos. 1:6 (6): 85–96. doi:10.18002/ehh.v0i6.3095.
  5. ^ Pagden, Anthony (2011-05-26). Klosko, George (ed.). "The School of Salamanca". The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199238804.003.0015. Retrieved 2022-01-04.
  6. ^ Iurlaro, Francesca (2021). The Invention of Custom: Natural Law and the Law of Nations, ca. 1550-1750. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-265282-9.
  7. ^ e.g. James Brown Scott, cited in Cavallar, The Rights of Strangers: theories of international hospitality, the global community, and political justice since Vitoria, p. 164
  8. ^ Koskenniemi, Martti (2011). "Empire and International Law: The Real Spanish Contribution". The University of Toronto Law Journal. 61 (1): 1–36. doi:10.3138/utlj.61.1.001. hdl:10138/231005. ISSN 0042-0220. JSTOR 23018686.
  9. ^ Koskenniemi: International Law and raison d'état: Rethinking the Prehistory of International Law in Kingsbury & Strausmann, The Roman Foundations of the Law of Nations, pp. 297–339
  10. ^ Fitzmaurice, Andrew (2007). Mancall, Peter C. (ed.). Moral Uncertainty in The Dispossesion of Native Americans. University of North Caroline Press. p. 383. ISBN 9780807838839.
  11. ^ Jace, Clara (2019-04-13). "An economic theory of economic analysis: the case of the School of Salamanca". Public Choice. 181 (3–4): 375–397. doi:10.1007/s11127-019-00662-y. ISSN 1573-7101. S2CID 159220971.
  12. ^ a b c Grice-Hutchinson, Marjorie (1952). "The School of Salamanca". Mises Institute. Retrieved 2022-01-02.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  13. ^ Decock, Wim (2016-01-28), "Spanish Scholastics on Money and Credit", Money in the Western Legal Tradition, Oxford University Press, pp. 267–283, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198704744.003.0014, ISBN 978-0-19-870474-4, retrieved 2020-07-18
  14. ^ Decock, Wim (2018), "Martín de Azpilcueta", Great Christian Jurists in Spanish History, Cambridge University Press, pp. 116–133, doi:10.1017/9781108624732.007, ISBN 978-1-108-62473-2, retrieved 2020-07-18
  15. ^ Hayek, Friedrich (1992). "The Austrian School of Economics". The Fortunes of Liberalism: Essays on Austrian Economics and the Ideal of Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 43. ISBN 0-226-32064-2.
  16. ^ Parisi, Daniela Fernanda; Solari, Stefano. Humanism and Religion in the History of Economic Thought. Selected Papers from the 10th Aispe Conference: Selected Papers from the 10th Aispe Conference. Franco/Angeli. p. 96-98.
  17. ^ Baltés, Carlos (2022). Escrito por el Tiempo 2ª Edición Corregida, Aumentada y Definitiva: Relatos, Ensayos y librepensamientos. Visión Libros.

Bibliography

  • Alves, André Azevedo (2010). The Salamanca School (Major Conservative and Libertarian Thinkers), edited by John Meadowcroft, Continuum International Publishing.
  • Chaufen, Alejandro A. (2008). "Scholastics/School of Salamanca". In Hamowy, Ronald (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE; Cato Institute. pp. 450–52. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n275. ISBN 978-1-4129-6580-4. LCCN 2008009151. OCLC 750831024.
  • Chojnowski, Peter (January 2005) "'Corporation Christendom': The True School of Salamanca". The Angelus XXVIII (1). Kansas City, MO: Angelus Press. ISSN 1073-5003. Contends that the alleged economic liberalism is based on a misreading of scholastic texts.
  • Grice-Hutchinson, Marjorie (1952). The School of Salamanca: Readings in Spanish Monetary Theory, 1544–1605
  • Grice-Hutchinson, Marjorie (1978). Early Economic Thought in Spain, 1177–1740.
  • Grice-Hutchinson, Marjorie (1993). Economic thought in Spain. Selected Essays of Marjorie Grice-Hutchinson, edited with an introduction by Laurence Moss and Christopher K. Ryan.
  • Liggio, Leonard P. (Jan & Feb 2000) "The Heritage of the Spanish Scholastics". Religion & Liberty. 10 (1). Grand Rapids, MI: Acton Institute.
  • Messarra, Sean (2020). "Representation and scholastic political thought". History of European Ideas. 46 (6): 737–753. doi:10.1080/01916599.2020.1756891. S2CID 219478086.
  • Rothbard, Murray, New Light on the Prehistory of the Austrian School Essay originally published in The Foundations of Modern Austrian Economics, edited by Edwin Dolan (Kansas City: Sheed and Ward, 1976), pp. 52–74.
  • Schumpeter, Joseph (1954). History of Economic Analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Van Ittersum, M. J. (2007). "Preparing Mare liberum for the Press: Hugo Grotius' Rewriting of Chapter 12 of De iure praedae in November–December 1608". Grotiana. 26: 246–80. doi:10.1163/187607508X366445.: Puts into context of truce negotiations 1608–1809. Ittersum (p. 18) notes Grotius' citing of School of Salamanca figures, as well as the Ancient Greek, Roman and early Church Fathers (p. 12).
  • Velasco Sánchez, José Tomás (2015). La Escuela de Salamanca. Concepto, miembros, problemas, influencias, pervivencias. Bubok Publishing, S.L. Madrid. ISBN 978-84-686-6627-3.

External links

  • The School of Salamanca A Digital Collection of Sources and a Dictionary of its Juridical-Political Language.
  • Izbicki, Thomas; Kaufmann, Matthias. "The School of Salamanca". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • on the History of Economic Thought website.

school, salamanca, spanish, escuela, salamanca, renaissance, thought, diverse, intellectual, areas, spanish, theologians, rooted, intellectual, pedagogical, work, francisco, vitoria, from, beginning, 16th, century, traditional, catholic, conception, relation, . The School of Salamanca Spanish Escuela de Salamanca is the Renaissance of thought in diverse intellectual areas by Spanish theologians rooted in the intellectual and pedagogical work of Francisco de Vitoria From the beginning of the 16th century the traditional Catholic conception of man and of his relation to God and to the world had been assaulted by the rise of humanism by the Protestant Reformation and by the new geographical discoveries and their consequences These new problems were addressed by the School of Salamanca The name refers to the University of Salamanca where de Vitoria and other members of the school were based University of Salamanca 17th century classroom at the University of Salamanca The juridical doctrine of the School of Salamanca represented the end of medieval concepts of law with a revindication of liberty not habitual in Europe of that time The natural rights of man came to be in one form or another the center of attention including rights as a corporeal being right to life economic rights such as the right to own property and spiritual rights the right to freedom of thought and to human dignity The School of Salamanca reformulated the concept of natural law law originating in nature itself with all that exists in the natural order sharing in this law Their conclusion was given that all humans share the same nature they also share the same rights to life and liberty Such views constituted a novelty in European thought and went counter to those then predominant in Spain and Europe that people indigenous to the Americas had no such rights Contents 1 History and leading figures 2 Sovereignty 3 The law of peoples and international law 4 Just war 5 The conquest of America 6 Economics 6 1 Antecedents 6 2 Private property 6 3 Money value and price 6 4 Interest on money 7 Theology 7 1 Morality 7 2 The De auxiliis controversy 7 3 The existence of evil in the world 8 Members 9 See also 10 References 11 Bibliography 12 External linksHistory and leading figures EditThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed October 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message The School of Salamanca in the broad sense comprises two successive schools of thought the largely Dominican Salmanticenses then from the end of the 16th century the Jesuit Conimbricenses of the University of Coimbra reflecting the general transition of intellectual leadership in the Catholic Church from the Dominicans to the Jesuits The first school began with Francisco de Vitoria 1483 1546 and reached its high point with Domingo de Soto 1494 1560 Leading Conimbricenses were Luis de Molina 1535 1600 Francisco Suarez 1548 1617 and Giovanni Botero 1544 1617 who would continue the tradition in Italy The leading figures of the school theologians and jurists Francisco de Vitoria Domingo de Soto Francisco Suarez Martin de Azpilcueta or Azpilicueta and Tomas de Mercado were all scholars of natural law and of morality who undertook the reconciliation of the teachings of Thomas Aquinas with the then new political economic order The themes of study centered on man and his practical problems morality economics jurisprudence etc but almost equally on a particular body of work accepted by all of them as the ground against which to test their disagreements including at times bitter polemics within the School Sovereignty EditThis section includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this section by introducing more precise citations October 2011 Learn how and when to remove this template message The School of Salamanca distinguished two realms of power the natural or civil realm and the realm of the supernatural which were often conflated in the Middle Ages through granting royal control of investiture of bishops or the temporal powers of the pope One direct consequence of the separation of realms of power is that the king or emperor does not legitimately have jurisdiction over souls nor does the pope have legitimate temporal power This included the idea that there are limits on the legitimate powers of government Thus according to Luis de Molina a nation is analogous to the mercantile corporations of his time in that those who govern are holders of power effectively sovereigns but a collective power to which they are subject derives from them jointly Nonetheless in de Molina s view the power of society over the individual is greater than that of a mercantile corporation over its members because the power of the government of a nation emanates from God s divine power as against merely from the power of individuals sovereign over themselves in their business dealings At this time the monarchy of England was extending the theory of the divine right of kings under which the monarch is the unique legatee of God s power asserting that subjects must follow the monarch s orders in order not to contravene God s design Counter to this several adherents of the School sustained that the people are the vehicle of divine sovereignty which they in turn pass to a prince under various conditions In this the late scholastics were instrumental in the development of early modern theories of political representation 1 Possibly the one who went furthest in this direction was Francisco Suarez whose work Defensio Fidei Catholicae adversus Anglicanae sectae errores The Defense of the Catholic Faith against the errors of the Anglican sect 1613 was the strongest contemporary defense of popular sovereignty Men are born free by their nature and not as slaves of another man and can disobey even to the point of deposing an unjust government As with de Molina he affirms that political power does not reside in any individual but he differs subtly in that he considers that the recipient of that power is the people as a whole not a collection of sovereign individuals in the same way Jean Jacques Rousseau s theory of popular sovereignty would consider the people as a collective group superior to the sum that composes it 2 Gabriel Vazquez 1549 1604 held that natural law is not limited to the individual but obliges societies to respect natural rights and justice For Suarez the political power of society is contractual in origin because the community forms by consensus of free wills The consequence of this contractualist theory 3 is that the natural form of government is either a democracy or a republic while oligarchy or monarchy arise as secondary institutions whose claim to justice is based on consent of the governed organized in a political body 2 The law of peoples and international law Edit Francisco Suarez Francisco de Vitoria played an important role in the early modern comprehension of ius gentium the rights of nations He extrapolated his ideas of legitimate sovereign power to relations between nations concluding that international society as well ought to be ruled by just forms respecting the rights of all The common good of the world is of a category superior to the good of each state This meant that relations between states ought to pass from being justified by force to being justified by law and right 4 Vitoria has been referred to along with Grotius as the father of international law 5 Francisco Suarez subdivided the concept of ius gentium Working with already well formed categories he carefully distinguished ius inter gentes from ius intra gentes Ius inter gentes which corresponds to modern international law was a just agreement among the majority of countries although being positive law not natural law it was not necessarily universal On the other hand ius intra gentes or civil law is specific to each nation 6 Many scholars have argued for the importance of Vitoria and Suarez as the forerunners and founders of the International law field and the precursors of the seminal text De iure belli ac pacis by Grotius 7 8 Others such as Koskenniemi have argued that none of these humanist and scholastic thinkers can be understood to have founded international law in the modern sense instead placing its origins in the post 1870 period 9 Just war EditThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed October 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message Given that war is one of the worst evils suffered by mankind the adherents of the School reasoned that it ought to be resorted to only when it was necessary to prevent an even greater evil A diplomatic agreement is preferable even for the more powerful party before a war is started Examples of just war are In self defense as long as there is a reasonable possibility of success If failure is a foregone conclusion then it is just a wasteful spilling of blood Preventive war against a tyrant who is about to attack War to punish a guilty enemy A war is not legitimate or illegitimate simply based on its original motivation it must comply with a series of additional requirements It is necessary that the response be commensurate with the evil use of more violence than is strictly necessary would constitute an unjust war Governing authorities declare war but their decision is not sufficient cause to begin a war If the people oppose a war then it is illegitimate The people have a right to depose a government that is waging or is about to wage an unjust war Once war has begun there remain moral limits to action For example one may not attack innocents or kill hostages War is only legitimate as a last resort after vigorous attempts at negotiation and diplomacy have failed Under this doctrine expansionist wars wars of pillage wars to convert infidels or pagans and wars for glory are all inherently unjust The conquest of America EditThis section includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this section by introducing more precise citations November 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message In the 16th century the School of Salamanca was the first to use the natural law s principle that rights reside in the individual to question the Spanish colonization on the indigenous people of the Americas 10 Francisco de Vitoria began his analysis of conquest by rejecting illegitimate titles He was the first to dare to question whether the bulls of Alexander VI known collectively as the Bulls of Donation were a valid title of dominion over the newly discovered territories In this matter he did not accept the universal primacy of the emperor the authority of the pope because the pope according to him lacked temporal power nor the claim of voluntary submission or conversion of the Native Americans One could not dismiss them as sinners or ignorant savages they were free people by nature with legitimate property rights When the Spanish arrived in America they brought no legitimate title to occupy and rule those lands Vitoria also analyzed whether there were legitimate claims of title over discovered lands He elaborated up to eight legitimate titles of dominion The first and perhaps most fundamental relates to communication between people who jointly constitute a universal society Ius peregrinandi et degendi is the universal right to travel and do commerce in all parts of the earth independently of who governs or what is the religion of the territory For him if the Indians of the Americas would not permit free transit the hindered parties had the right to defend themselves and to remain in land obtained in such a war of self defense The second form of legitimate title over discovered lands referred to the right of the Spanish to preach and proselytize The Indians could voluntarily refuse conversion but forbidding missionaries would make the matter analogous to the first case Nonetheless Vitoria noted that although this can be grounds for a just war it is not necessarily prudent because of the resulting death and destruction The other cases of this casuistry are If the pagan sovereigns force converts to return to idolatry If there come to be a sufficient number of Christians in the newly discovered land that they wish to receive from the Pope a Christian government In the case of overthrowing a tyranny or a government that is harming innocents e g human sacrifice If associates and friends have been attacked as were the Tlaxcaltecas allied with the Spanish but subjected like many other people to the Aztecs once again this could justify a war with the ensuing possibility of legitimate conquest as in the first case The final legitimate title although qualified by Vitoria himself as doubtful is the suffering of the foreign population from lack of just laws magistrates agricultural techniques etc In any case title taken according to this principle must be exercised with Christian charity and for the advantage of the Indians Emperor Charles V then ruler of Spain took offense to this doctrine of legitimate and illegitimate titles purporting to limit his prerogatives and he tried without success to stop its promulgation Economics EditThis section includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this section by introducing more precise citations October 2011 Learn how and when to remove this template message The School of Salamanca has been described as the first economic tradition in the field of economics 11 This put the origins of economic theory on Europe s mainland prompting a reassessment of the entire history of the discipline 12 Much attention has been drawn to the economic thought of the School of Salamanca by Joseph Schumpeter s History of Economic Analysis 1954 It did not coin but certainly consolidated the use of the term School of Salamanca in economics Schumpeter studied scholastic doctrine in general and Spanish scholastic doctrine in particular and praised the high level of economic science in Spain in the 16th century He argued that the School of Salamanca most deserves to be considered the founders of economics as a science The School did not elaborate a complete doctrine of economics but they established the first modern economic theories to address the new economic problems that had arisen with the end of the medieval order Unfortunately there was no continuation of their work until the end of the 17th century and many of their contributions were forgotten only to be rediscovered later by others The thinking of the School was defined as pro market pro hard money anti state in many ways pro property and pro merchant to a surprising extent 12 The English historian of economic thought Marjorie Grice Hutchinson and Belgian legal historian Wim Decock have published numerous articles and monographs on the School of Salamanca 13 Although there does not appear to be any direct influence the economic thought of the School of Salamanca is in many ways similar to that of the Austrian School Murray Rothbard referred to them as proto Austrians 12 Antecedents Edit Diego de Covarrubias In 1517 de Vitoria then at the Sorbonne was consulted by Spanish merchants based in Antwerp about the moral legitimacy of engaging in commerce to increase one s personal wealth From today s point of view one would say they were asking for a consultation about the entrepreneurial spirit Beginning at that time Vitoria and other theologians looked at economic matters They moved away from views that they found to be obsolete adopting instead new ideas based on principles of natural law According to these views the natural order is based in the freedom of circulation of people goods and ideas allowing people to know one another and increase their sentiments of brotherhood citation needed This implies that merchantry is not merely not reprehensible but that it actually serves the general good Private property Edit The adherents of the School of Salamanca all agreed that property has the beneficial effect of stimulating economic activity which in turn contributed to the general well being Diego de Covarubias y Leyva 1512 1577 considered that people had not only the right to own property but again a specifically modern idea they had the exclusive right to the benefit from that property although the community might also benefit Nonetheless in times of great necessity there all goods become a commons Luis de Molina argued that individual owners take better care of their goods than is taken of common property a form of the tragedy of the commons Money value and price Edit Martin de Azpilcueta The most complete and methodical developments of a Salamancan theory of value were by Martin de Azpilcueta 1493 1586 and Luis de Molina Interested in the effect of precious metals arriving from the Americas de Azpilcueta proved that in the countries where precious metals were scarce prices for them were higher than in those where they were abundant Precious metals like any other mercantile good gained at least some of their value from their scarcity 14 This scarcity theory of value was a precursor of the quantitative theory of money put forward slightly later by Jean Bodin 1530 1596 Up until that time the predominant theory of value had been the medieval theory based on the cost of production as the sole determinant of a just price a variant of the cost of production theory of value most recently manifested in the labor theory of value Diego de Covarrubias and Luis de Molina developed a subjective theory of value and prices which asserted that the usefulness of a good varied from person to person so just prices would arise from mutual decisions in free commerce barring the distorting effects of monopoly fraud or government intervention Expressing this in today s terms the adherents of the School defended the free market where the fair price of a good would be determined by supply and demand On this Luis Saravia de la Calle wrote in 1544 Those who measure the just price by the labour costs and risk incurred by the person who deals in the merchandise or produces it or by the cost of transport or the expense of traveling or by what he has to pay the factors for their industry risk and labour are greatly in error For the just price arises from the abundance or scarcity of goods merchants and money and not from costs labour and risk Why should a bale of linen brought overland from Brittany at great expense be worth more than one which is transported cheaply by sea Why should a book written out by hand be worth more than one which is printed when the latter is better though it costs less to produce The just price is found not by counting the cost but by the common estimation However the school rarely followed this idea through systematically and as Friedrich Hayek has written never to the point of realizing that what was relevant was not merely man s relation to a particular thing or a class of things but the position of the thing in the whole scheme by which men decide how to allocate the resources at their disposal among their different endeavors 15 Interest on money Edit Usury which in that period meant any charging of interest on a loan has always been viewed negatively by the Catholic Church The Third Lateran Council condemned any repayment of a debt with more money than was originally loaned the Council of Vienne explicitly prohibited usury and declared any legislation tolerant of usury to be heretical the first scholastics reproved the charging of interest In the medieval economy loans were entirely a consequence of necessity bad harvests fire in a workplace and under those conditions it was considered morally reproachable to charge interest In the Renaissance era greater mobility of people facilitated an increase in commerce and the appearance of appropriate conditions for entrepreneurs to start new lucrative businesses Given that borrowed money was no longer strictly for consumption but for production as well it could not be viewed in the same manner The School of Salamanca elaborated various reasons that justified the charging of interest The person who received a loan benefited one could consider interest as a premium paid for the risk taken by the loaning party There was also the question of opportunity cost in that the loaning party lost other possibilities of utilizing the loaned money Finally and perhaps most originally was the consideration of money itself as a merchandise and the use of one s money as something for which one should receive a benefit in the form of interest Martin de Azpilcueta also considered the effect of time formulating the time value of money All things being equal one would prefer to receive a given good now rather than in the future This preference indicates greater value Interest under this theory is the payment for the time the loaning individual is deprived of the money Theology EditThis section includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this section by introducing more precise citations October 2011 Learn how and when to remove this template message Fray Luis de Leon Luis de Molina In the Renaissance era theology was generally declining citation needed in the face of the rise of humanism with scholasticism becoming nothing more than an empty and routine methodology citation needed Under Francisco de Vitoria the University of Salamanca led a period of intense activity in theology especially a renaissance of Thomism whose influence extended to European culture in general but especially to other European universities Perhaps the fundamental contribution of the School of Salamanca to theology is the study of problems much closer to humanity which had previously been ignored and the opening of questions that had previously not been posed The term positive theology is sometimes used to distinguish this new more practical theology from the earlier scholastic theology Morality Edit In an era when religion permeated everything to analyze the morality of the acts was considered the most practical and useful study one could undertake to serve society The novel contributions of the School in law and economics were rooted in concrete challenges and moral problems which confronted society under new conditions Over the years a casuistry a fixed set of answers to moral dilemmas had been developed However by its nature a casuistry can never be complete leading to a search for more general rules or principles From this developed probabilism where the ultimate criterion was not truth but the certainty of not choosing evil Developed principally by Bartolome de Medina and continued by Gabriel Vazquez and Francisco Suarez Probabilism became the most important school of moral thought in the coming centuries citation needed The De auxiliis controversy Edit Main article Congregatio de Auxiliis The De auxiliis controversy was a dispute between Jesuits and Dominicans which occurred at the end of the 16th century The topic of the controversy was grace and predestination that is to say how one could reconcile the liberty or free will of humans with divine omniscience In 1582 the Jesuit Prudencio Montemayor and Fray Luis de Leon spoke publicly about human liberty Domingo Banez considered that they gave free will too great a weight and that they used terminology that sounded heretical he denounced them to the Spanish Inquisition accusing them of Pelagianism a belief in human free will to the detriment of the doctrine of original sin and the grace granted by God Montemayor and de Leon were banned from teaching and prohibited from defending such ideas Banez was then denounced to the Holy Office by Leon who accused him of committing the error of Lutheranism that is of following the doctrines of Martin Luther According to Lutheran doctrine man is dead in his trespasses Ephesians 2 1 as a consequence of original sin and cannot save himself by his own merit only God can save man For by grace you have been saved through faith And this is not your own doing it is the gift of God not a result of works so that no one may boast Ephesians 2 8 9 Banez was acquitted Nonetheless this did not end the dispute which Luis de Molina continued with his Concordia liberi arbitrii cum gratiae donis 1588 This is considered the best expression of the Jesuit position The polemic continued over the course of years including an attempt by the Dominicans to get Pope Clement VIII to condemn the Concordia of de Molina Finally Paul V in 1607 recognized the liberty of Dominicans and Jesuits to defend their ideas prohibiting that either side of this disagreement be characterized as heresy The existence of evil in the world Edit The existence of evil in a world created and ruled by an infinitely good and powerful God has long been viewed as paradoxical See Problem of evil Vitoria reconciled the paradox by arguing first that free will is a gift from God to each person It is impossible that each person will always freely choose only the good Thus evil results from man s ability not to choose good by virtue of his free will Members EditThere is discussion about which authors can be assigned to the name of the School of Salamanca or if one can speak of a School of Salamanca in the first place but the consensus revolves around the name of Francisco de Vitoria considered a central figure of the movement From him authors refer to three stages counting in the first the pupils of Vitoria and their pupils in the second Salamanca contemporaries who had no direct relationship with him and in the third external figures influenced by this current of thought 16 First group Arias Pinel 1512 1563 Antonio de Padilla y Meneses 1580 Bartolome de Albornoz 1519 1573 Bartolome de Medina 1527 1581 Diego de Chaves 1507 1592 Diego de Covarrubias 1512 1577 Diego Perez de Mesa 1563 1632 Domingo Banez 1528 1604 Domingo de Soto 1494 1560 Fernan Perez de Oliva 1494 1531 Francisco de Vitoria 1492 1546 Francisco Sarmiento de Mendoza 1525 1595 Francisco Suarez 1548 1617 Gregorio de Valencia 1549 1603 Jeronimo Munoz 1520 1591 Juan de Horozco y Covarrubias 1540 1610 Juan de la Pena 1513 1565 Juan de Matienzo 1520 1579 Juan de Ribera 1532 1611 Juan Gil de la Nava 1551 Leonardus Lessius 1554 1623 Luis de Leon 1527 1591 Martin de Azpilcueta 1492 1586 Martin de Ledesma 1509 1574 Melchor Cano 1509 1560 Pedro de Sotomayor 1511 1564 Tomas de Mercado 1523 1575 Second group Alonso de la Vera Cruz 1507 1584 Cristobal de Villalon 1588 Fernando Vazquez de Menchaca 1512 1569 Francisco Cervantes de Salazar 1575 Juan de Lugo y Quiroga 1583 1660 Juan de Salas 1553 1612 Luis de Molina 1535 1600 Pedro de Aragon 1545 1546 Pedro de Valencia 1555 1620 Third group Antonio de Hervias 1590 Bartolome de Carranza 1503 1576 Bartolome de las Casas 1484 1566 Cristobal de Fonseca 1550 1621 Domingo de Salazar 1512 1594 Domingo de Santo Tomas 1499 1570 Gabriel Vasquez 1549 1604 Gomez Pereira 1500 1567 17 Juan de Mariana 1536 1624 Juan de Medina 1489 1545 Juan Perez de Menacho 1565 1626 Luis de Alcala 1490 1549 Luis Saravia de la Calle Miguel Bartolome Salon 1539 1621 Pedro de Fonseca 1528 1599 Pedro de Onate 1567 1646 Rodrigo de Arriaga 1592 1667 See also Edit Philosophy portalConimbricenses Second scholasticism Casuistry Rule According to Higher Law Social contract Valladolid debate Spanish Universalist School of the 18th centuryReferences Edit Messarra Sean 2020 Representation and scholastic political thought History of European Ideas 46 6 737 753 doi 10 1080 01916599 2020 1756891 S2CID 219478086 a b Dellavalle Sergio 2021 05 27 Paradigms of Social Order From Holism to Pluralism and Beyond Springer Nature p 129 ISBN 978 3 030 66179 3 CAMPOS ANDRE SANTOS 2019 Francisco Suarez s Conception of the Social Contract Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 75 2 1195 1218 doi 10 17990 RPF 2019 75 2 1195 ISSN 0870 5283 JSTOR 26678106 S2CID 199141748 Lewkowicz Nicolas 2007 The Spanish School as a forerunner to the English School of international relations Estudios Humanisticos 1 6 6 85 96 doi 10 18002 ehh v0i6 3095 Pagden Anthony 2011 05 26 Klosko George ed The School of Salamanca The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199238804 003 0015 Retrieved 2022 01 04 Iurlaro Francesca 2021 The Invention of Custom Natural Law and the Law of Nations ca 1550 1750 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 265282 9 e g James Brown Scott cited in Cavallar The Rights of Strangers theories of international hospitality the global community and political justice since Vitoria p 164 Koskenniemi Martti 2011 Empire and International Law The Real Spanish Contribution The University of Toronto Law Journal 61 1 1 36 doi 10 3138 utlj 61 1 001 hdl 10138 231005 ISSN 0042 0220 JSTOR 23018686 Koskenniemi International Law and raison d etat Rethinking the Prehistory of International Law in Kingsbury amp Strausmann The Roman Foundations of the Law of Nations pp 297 339 Fitzmaurice Andrew 2007 Mancall Peter C ed Moral Uncertainty in The Dispossesion of Native Americans University of North Caroline Press p 383 ISBN 9780807838839 Jace Clara 2019 04 13 An economic theory of economic analysis the case of the School of Salamanca Public Choice 181 3 4 375 397 doi 10 1007 s11127 019 00662 y ISSN 1573 7101 S2CID 159220971 a b c Grice Hutchinson Marjorie 1952 The School of Salamanca Mises Institute Retrieved 2022 01 02 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Decock Wim 2016 01 28 Spanish Scholastics on Money and Credit Money in the Western Legal Tradition Oxford University Press pp 267 283 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780198704744 003 0014 ISBN 978 0 19 870474 4 retrieved 2020 07 18 Decock Wim 2018 Martin de Azpilcueta Great Christian Jurists in Spanish History Cambridge University Press pp 116 133 doi 10 1017 9781108624732 007 ISBN 978 1 108 62473 2 retrieved 2020 07 18 Hayek Friedrich 1992 The Austrian School of Economics The Fortunes of Liberalism Essays on Austrian Economics and the Ideal of Freedom Chicago University of Chicago Press p 43 ISBN 0 226 32064 2 Parisi Daniela Fernanda Solari Stefano Humanism and Religion in the History of Economic Thought Selected Papers from the 10th Aispe Conference Selected Papers from the 10th Aispe Conference Franco Angeli p 96 98 Baltes Carlos 2022 Escrito por el Tiempo 2ª Edicion Corregida Aumentada y Definitiva Relatos Ensayos y librepensamientos Vision Libros Bibliography EditAlves Andre Azevedo 2010 The Salamanca School Major Conservative and Libertarian Thinkers edited by John Meadowcroft Continuum International Publishing Chaufen Alejandro A 2008 Scholastics School of Salamanca In Hamowy Ronald ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA SAGE Cato Institute pp 450 52 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 n275 ISBN 978 1 4129 6580 4 LCCN 2008009151 OCLC 750831024 Chojnowski Peter January 2005 Corporation Christendom The True School of Salamanca The Angelus XXVIII 1 Kansas City MO Angelus Press ISSN 1073 5003 Contends that the alleged economic liberalism is based on a misreading of scholastic texts Grice Hutchinson Marjorie 1952 The School of Salamanca Readings in Spanish Monetary Theory 1544 1605 Grice Hutchinson Marjorie 1978 Early Economic Thought in Spain 1177 1740 Grice Hutchinson Marjorie 1993 Economic thought in Spain Selected Essays of Marjorie Grice Hutchinson edited with an introduction by Laurence Moss and Christopher K Ryan Liggio Leonard P Jan amp Feb 2000 The Heritage of the Spanish Scholastics Religion amp Liberty 10 1 Grand Rapids MI Acton Institute Messarra Sean 2020 Representation and scholastic political thought History of European Ideas 46 6 737 753 doi 10 1080 01916599 2020 1756891 S2CID 219478086 Rothbard Murray New Light on the Prehistory of the Austrian School Essay originally published in The Foundations of Modern Austrian Economics edited by Edwin Dolan Kansas City Sheed and Ward 1976 pp 52 74 Schumpeter Joseph 1954 History of Economic Analysis New York Oxford University Press Van Ittersum M J 2007 Preparing Mare liberum for the Press Hugo Grotius Rewriting of Chapter 12 of De iure praedae in November December 1608 Grotiana 26 246 80 doi 10 1163 187607508X366445 Puts into context of truce negotiations 1608 1809 Ittersum p 18 notes Grotius citing of School of Salamanca figures as well as the Ancient Greek Roman and early Church Fathers p 12 Velasco Sanchez Jose Tomas 2015 La Escuela de Salamanca Concepto miembros problemas influencias pervivencias Bubok Publishing S L Madrid ISBN 978 84 686 6627 3 External links EditThe School of Salamanca A Digital Collection of Sources and a Dictionary of its Juridical Political Language Izbicki Thomas Kaufmann Matthias The School of Salamanca In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The School of Salamanca on the History of Economic Thought website Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title School of Salamanca amp oldid 1143607230, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.