fbpx
Wikipedia

Labor theory of value

The labor theory of value (LTV) is a theory of value that argues that the economic value of a good or service is determined by the total amount of "socially necessary labor" required to produce it.

The LTV is usually associated with Marxian economics, although it originally appeared in the theories of earlier classical economists such as Adam Smith and David Ricardo, and later in anarchist economics. Smith saw the price of a commodity in terms of the labor that the purchaser must expend to buy it, which embodies the concept of how much labor a commodity, a tool for example, can save the purchaser. The LTV is central to Marxist theory, which holds that the working class is exploited under capitalism, and dissociates price and value. However, Marx did not refer to his own theory of value as a "labour theory of value".[1][2]

Orthodox neoclassical economics rejects the LTV, using a theory of value based on subjective preferences.[3][4][5][6]

The revival in interpretation of Marx known as the Neue Marx-Lektüre also rejects Marxian economics and the LTV, calling them "substantialist". This reading claims that the LTV is a misinterpretation of the concept of fetishism in relation to value, and that this understanding never appears in Marx's work. The school heavily emphasizes works such as Capital as explicitly being a critique of political economy, instead of a "more correct" theory.[7]

Definitions of value and labor

When speaking in terms of a labor theory of value, "value", without any qualifying adjective should theoretically refer to the amount of labor necessary to produce a marketable commodity, including the labor necessary to develop any real capital used in the production. Both David Ricardo[8] and Karl Marx tried to quantify and embody all labor components in order to develop a theory of the real price, or natural price of a commodity.[9] The labor theory of value as presented by Adam Smith did not require the quantification of past labor, nor did it deal with the labor needed to create the tools (capital) that might be used in producing a commodity. Smith's theory of value was very similar to the later utility theories in that Smith proclaimed that a commodity was worth whatever labor it would command in others (value in trade) or whatever labor it would "save" the self (value in use), or both. However, this "value" is subject to supply and demand at a particular time:

The real price of every thing, what every thing really costs to the man who wants to acquire it, is the toil and trouble of acquiring it. What every thing is really worth to the man who has acquired it, and who wants to dispose of it or exchange it for something else, is the toil and trouble which it can save to himself, and which it can impose upon other people. (Wealth of Nations Book 1, chapter V)

Smith's theory of price has nothing to do with the past labor spent in producing a commodity. It speaks only of the labor that can be "commanded" or "saved" at present. If there is no use for a buggy whip, then the item is economically worthless in trade or in use, regardless of all the labor spent in creating it.

Distinctions of economically pertinent labor

Value "in use" is the usefulness of this commodity, its utility. A classical paradox often comes up when considering this type of value. In the words of Adam Smith:

The word value, it is to be observed, has two different meanings, and sometimes expresses the utility of some particular object, and sometimes the power of purchasing other goods which the possession of that object conveys. The one may be called "value in use"; the other, "value in exchange." The things which have the greatest value in use have frequently little or no value in exchange; and, on the contrary, those which have the greatest value in exchange have frequently little or no value in use. Nothing is more useful than water: but it will purchase scarce anything; scarce anything can be had in exchange for it. A diamond, on the contrary, has scarce any value in use; but a very great quantity of other goods may frequently be had in exchange for it (Wealth of Nations Book 1, chapter IV).

Value "in exchange" is the relative proportion with which this commodity exchanges for another commodity (in other words, its price in the case of money). It is relative to labor as explained by Adam Smith:

The value of any commodity, [...] to the person who possesses it, and who means not to use or consume it himself, but to exchange it for other commodities, is equal to the quantity of labour which it enables him to purchase or command. Labour, therefore, is the real measure of the exchangeable value of all commodities (Wealth of Nations Book 1, chapter V).

Value (without qualification) is the labor embodied in a commodity under a given structure of production. Marx defined the value of the commodity by this third definition. In his terms, value is the 'socially necessary abstract labor' embodied in a commodity. To David Ricardo and other classical economists, this definition serves as a measure of "real cost", "absolute value", or a "measure of value" invariable under changes in distribution and technology.[10]

Ricardo, other classical economists and Marx began their expositions with the assumption that value in exchange was equal to or proportional to this labor value. They thought this was a good assumption from which to explore the dynamics of development in capitalist societies. Other supporters of the labor theory of value used the word "value" in the second sense to represent "exchange value".[11]

Labor process

Since the term "value" is understood in the LTV as denoting something created by labor, and its "magnitude" as something proportional to the quantity of labor performed, it is important to explain how the labor process both preserves value and adds new value in the commodities it creates.[note 1]

The value of a commodity increases in proportion to the duration and intensity of labor performed on average for its production. Part of what the LTV means by "socially necessary" is that the value only increases in proportion to this labor as it is performed with average skill and average productivity. So though workers may labor with greater skill or more productivity than others, these more skillful and more productive workers thus produce more value through the production of greater quantities of the finished commodity. Each unit still bears the same value as all the others of the same class of commodity. By working sloppily, unskilled workers may drag down the average skill of labor, thus increasing the average labor time necessary for the production of each unit commodity. But these unskillful workers cannot hope to sell the result of their labor process at a higher price (as opposed to value) simply because they have spent more time than other workers producing the same kind of commodities.

However, production not only involves labor, but also certain means of labor: tools, materials, power plants and so on. These means of labor—also known as means of production—are often the product of another labor process as well. So the labor process inevitably involves these means of production that already enter the process with a certain amount of value. Labor also requires other means of production that are not produced with labor and therefore bear no value: such as sunlight, air, uncultivated land, unextracted minerals, etc. While useful, even crucial to the production process, these bring no value to that process. In terms of means of production resulting from another labor process, LTV treats the magnitude of value of these produced means of production as constant throughout the labor process. Due to the constancy of their value, these means of production are referred to, in this light, as constant capital.

Consider for example workers who take coffee beans, use a roaster to roast them, and then use a brewer to brew and dispense a fresh cup of coffee. In performing this labor, these workers add value to the coffee beans and water that comprise the material ingredients of a cup of coffee. The worker also transfers the value of constant capital—the value of the beans; some specific depreciated value of the roaster and the brewer; and the value of the cup—to the value of the final cup of coffee. Again, on average, the worker can transfer no more than the value of these means of labor previously possessed to the finished cup of coffee.[note 2] So the value of coffee produced in a day equals the sum of both the value of the means of labor—this constant capital—and the value newly added by the worker in proportion to the duration and intensity of their work.

Often this is expressed mathematically as:

 ,

where

  •   is the constant capital of materials used in a period plus the depreciated portion of tools and plant used in the process. (A period is typically a day, week, year, or a single turnover: meaning the time required to complete one batch of coffee, for example.)
  •   is the quantity of labor time (average skill and productivity) performed in producing the finished commodities during the period
  •   is the value (or think "worth") of the product of the period (  comes from the German word for value: wert)

Note: if the product resulting from the labor process is homogeneous (all similar in quality and traits, for example, all cups of coffee) then the value of the period's product can be divided by the total number of items (use-values or  ) produced to derive the unit value of each item.   where   is the total items produced.

The LTV further divides the value added during the period of production,  , into two parts. The first part is the portion of the process when the workers add value equivalent to the wages they are paid. For example, if the period in question is one week and these workers collectively are paid $1,000, then the time necessary to add $1,000 to—while preserving the value of—constant capital is considered the necessary labor portion of the period (or week): denoted  . The remaining period is considered the surplus labor portion of the week: or  . The value used to purchase labor-power, for example, the $1,000 paid in wages to these workers for the week, is called variable capital ( ). This is because in contrast to the constant capital expended on means of production, variable capital can add value in the labor process. The amount it adds depends on the duration, intensity, productivity and skill of the labor-power purchased: in this sense, the buyer of labor-power has purchased a commodity of variable use. Finally, the value added during the portion of the period when surplus labor is performed is called surplus value ( ). From the variables defined above, we find two other common expressions for the value produced during a given period:

 

and

 

The first form of the equation expresses the value resulting from production, focusing on the costs   and the surplus value appropriated in the process of production,  . The second form of the equation focuses on the value of production in terms of the values added by the labor performed during the process  .

Relation between values and prices

One issue facing the LTV is the relationship between value quantities on one hand and prices on the other. If a commodity's value is not the same as its price, and therefore the magnitudes of each likely differ, then what is the relation between the two, if any? Various LTV schools of thought provide different answers to this question. For example, some argue that value in the sense of the amount of labor embodied in a good acts as a center of gravity for price.

However, most economists would say that cases where pricing is given as approximately equal to the value of the labour embodied, are in fact only special cases. In General Theory pricing most usually fluctuates. The standard formulation is that prices normally include a level of income for "capital" and "land". These incomes are known as "profit" and "rent" respectively. Yet Marx made the point that value cannot be placed upon labour as a commodity, because capital is a constant, whereas profit is a variable, not an income; thus explaining the importance of profit in relation to pricing variables.[12]

In Book 1, chapter VI, Adam Smith writes:

The real value of all the different component parts of price, it must be observed, is measured by the quantity of labour which they can, each of them, purchase or command. Labour measures the value not only of that part of price which resolves itself into labour, but of that which resolves itself into rent, and of that which resolves itself into profit.

The final sentence explains how Smith sees value of a product as relative to labor of buyer or consumer, as opposite to Marx who sees the value of a product being proportional to labor of laborer or producer. And we value things, price them, based on how much labor we can avoid or command, and we can command labor not only in a simple way but also by trading things for a profit.

The demonstration of the relation between commodities' unit values and their respective prices is known in Marxian terminology as the transformation problem or the transformation of values into prices of production. The transformation problem has probably generated the greatest bulk of debate about the LTV. The problem with transformation is to find an algorithm where the magnitude of value added by labor, in proportion to its duration and intensity, is sufficiently accounted for after this value is distributed through prices that reflect an equal rate of return on capital advanced. If there is an additional magnitude of value or a loss of value after transformation, then the relation between values (proportional to labor) and prices (proportional to total capital advanced) is incomplete. Various solutions and impossibility theorems have been offered for the transformation, but the debate has not reached any clear resolution.

LTV does not deny the role of supply and demand influencing price, since the price of a commodity is something other than its value. In Value, Price and Profit (1865), Karl Marx quotes Adam Smith and sums up:

It suffices to say that if supply and demand equilibrate each other, the market prices of commodities will correspond with their natural prices, that is to say, with their values as determined by the respective quantities of labor required for their production.[13]

The LTV seeks to explain the level of this equilibrium. This could be explained by a cost of production argument—pointing out that all costs are ultimately labor costs, but this does not account for profit, and it is vulnerable to the charge of tautology in that it explains prices by prices.[14] Marx later called this "Smith's adding up theory of value".

Smith argues that labor values are the natural measure of exchange for direct producers like hunters and fishermen.[15] Marx, on the other hand, uses a measurement analogy, arguing that for commodities to be comparable they must have a common element or substance by which to measure them,[13] and that labor is a common substance of what Marx eventually calls commodity-values.[12]

History

Origins

The labor theory of value has developed over many centuries. It had no single originator, but rather many different thinkers arrived at the same conclusion independently. Aristotle is claimed to hold to this view.[16] Some writers trace its origin to Thomas Aquinas.[17][18] In his Summa Theologiae (1265–1274) he expresses the view that "value can, does and should increase in relation to the amount of labor which has been expended in the improvement of commodities."[19] Scholars such as Joseph Schumpeter have cited Ibn Khaldun, who in his Muqaddimah (1377), described labor as the source of value, necessary for all earnings and capital accumulation. He argued that even if earning "results from something other than a craft, the value of the resulting profit and acquired (capital) must (also) include the value of the labor by which it was obtained. Without labor, it would not have been acquired."[20] Scholars have also pointed to Sir William Petty's Treatise of Taxes of 1662[21] and to John Locke's labor theory of property, set out in the Second Treatise on Government (1689), which sees labor as the ultimate source of economic value. Karl Marx himself credited Benjamin Franklin in his 1729 essay entitled "A Modest Enquiry into the Nature and Necessity of a Paper Currency" as being "one of the first" to advance the theory.[22]

Adam Smith accepted the theory for pre-capitalist societies but saw a flaw in its application to contemporary capitalism. He pointed out that if the "labor embodied" in a product equaled the "labor commanded" (i.e. the amount of labor that could be purchased by selling it), then profit was impossible. David Ricardo (seconded by Marx) responded to this paradox by arguing that Smith had confused labor with wages. "Labor commanded", he argued, would always be more than the labor needed to sustain itself (wages). The value of labor, in this view, covered not just the value of wages (what Marx called the value of labor power), but the value of the entire product created by labor.[15]

Ricardo's theory was a predecessor of the modern theory that equilibrium prices are determined solely by production costs associated with Neo-Ricardianism.[23]

Based on the discrepancy between the wages of labor and the value of the product, the "Ricardian socialists"—Charles Hall, Thomas Hodgskin, John Gray, and John Francis Bray, and Percy Ravenstone[24]—applied Ricardo's theory to develop theories of exploitation.

Marx expanded on these ideas, arguing that workers work for a part of each day adding the value required to cover their wages, while the remainder of their labor is performed for the enrichment of the capitalist. The LTV and the accompanying theory of exploitation became central to his economic thought.

19th century American individualist anarchists based their economics on the LTV, with their particular interpretation of it being called "Cost the limit of price". They, as well as contemporary individualist anarchists in that tradition, hold that it is unethical to charge a higher price for a commodity than the amount of labor required to produce it. Hence, they propose that trade should be facilitated by using notes backed by labor.

Adam Smith and David Ricardo

Adam Smith held that, in a primitive society, the amount of labor put into producing a good determined its exchange value, with exchange value meaning, in this case, the amount of labor a good can purchase. However, according to Smith, in a more advanced society the market price is no longer proportional to labor cost since the value of the good now includes compensation for the owner of the means of production: "The whole produce of labour does not always belong to the labourer. He must in most cases share it with the owner of the stock which employs him."[25] According to Whitaker, Smith is claiming that the 'real value' of such a commodity produced in advanced society is measured by the labor which that commodity will command in exchange but "[Smith] disowns what is naturally thought of as the genuine classical labor theory of value, that labor-cost regulates market-value. This theory was Ricardo's, and really his alone."[26]

Classical economist David Ricardo's labor theory of value holds that the value of a good (how much of another good or service it exchanges for in the market) is proportional to how much labor was required to produce it, including the labor required to produce the raw materials and machinery used in the process. David Ricardo stated it as, "The value of a commodity, or the quantity of any other commodity for which it will exchange, depends on the relative quantity of labour which is necessary for its production, and not on the greater or less compensation which is paid for that labour."[27] In this connection Ricardo seeks to differentiate the quantity of labour necessary to produce a commodity from the wages paid to the laborers for its production. Therefore, wages did not always increase with the price of a commodity. However, Ricardo was troubled with some deviations in prices from proportionality with the labor required to produce them.[28] For example, he said "I cannot get over the difficulty of the wine, which is kept in the cellar for three or four years [i.e., while constantly increasing in exchange value], or that of the oak tree, which perhaps originally had not 2 s. expended on it in the way of labour, and yet comes to be worth £100." (Quoted in Whitaker) Of course, a capitalist economy stabilizes this discrepancy until the value added to aged wine is equal to the cost of storage. If anyone can hold onto a bottle for four years and become rich, that would make it hard to find freshly corked wine. There is also the theory that adding to the price of a luxury product increases its exchange-value by mere prestige.

The labor theory as an explanation for value contrasts with the subjective theory of value, which says that value of a good is not determined by how much labor was put into it but by its usefulness in satisfying a want and its scarcity. Ricardo's labor theory of value is not a normative theory, as are some later forms of the labor theory, such as claims that it is immoral for an individual to be paid less for his labor than the total revenue that comes from the sales of all the goods he produces.

It is arguable to what extent these classical theorists held the labor theory of value as it is commonly defined.[29][30][31] For instance, David Ricardo theorized that prices are determined by the amount of labor but found exceptions for which the labor theory could not account. In a letter, he wrote: "I am not satisfied with the explanation I have given of the principles which regulate value." Adam Smith theorized that the labor theory of value holds true only in the "early and rude state of society" but not in a modern economy where owners of capital are compensated by profit. As a result, "Smith ends up making little use of a labor theory of value."[32]

Anarchism

 
Sample labor for labor note for the Cincinnati Time Store. Scanned from Equitable Commerce (1846) by Josiah Warren

Pierre Joseph Proudhon's mutualism[33] and American individualist anarchists such as Josiah Warren, Lysander Spooner and Benjamin Tucker[34] adopted the labor theory of value of classical economics and used it to criticize capitalism while favoring a non-capitalist market system.[35]

Warren is widely regarded as the first American anarchist,[36][37] and the four-page weekly paper he edited during 1833, The Peaceful Revolutionist, was the first anarchist periodical published.[38] Cost the limit of price was a maxim coined by Warren, indicating a (prescriptive) version of the labor theory of value. Warren maintained that the just compensation for labor (or for its product) could only be an equivalent amount of labor (or a product embodying an equivalent amount).[39] Thus, profit, rent, and interest were considered unjust economic arrangements.[40] In keeping with the tradition of Adam Smith's The Wealth of Nations,[41] the "cost" of labor is considered to be the subjective cost; i.e., the amount of suffering involved in it.[39] He put his theories to the test by establishing an experimental "labor for labor store" called the Cincinnati Time Store at the corner of 5th and Elm Streets in what is now downtown Cincinnati, where trade was facilitated by notes backed by a promise to perform labor. "All the goods offered for sale in Warren's store were offered at the same price the merchant himself had paid for them, plus a small surcharge, in the neighborhood of 4 to 7 percent, to cover store overhead."[37] The store stayed open for three years; after it closed, Warren could pursue establishing colonies based on Mutualism. These included "Utopia" and "Modern Times". Warren said that Stephen Pearl Andrews' The Science of Society, published in 1852, was the most lucid and complete exposition of Warren's own theories.[42]

Mutualism is an economic theory and anarchist school of thought that advocates a society where each person might possess a means of production, either individually or collectively, with trade representing equivalent amounts of labor in the free market.[43] Integral to the scheme was the establishment of a mutual-credit bank that would lend to producers at a minimal interest rate, just high enough to cover administration.[44] Mutualism is based on a labor theory of value that holds that when labor or its product is sold, in exchange, it ought to receive goods or services embodying "the amount of labor necessary to produce an article of exactly similar and equal utility".[45] Mutualism originated from the writings of philosopher Pierre-Joseph Proudhon.

Collectivist anarchism as defended by Mikhail Bakunin defended a form of labor theory of value when it advocated a system where "all necessaries for production are owned in common by the labour groups and the free communes ... based on the distribution of goods according to the labour contributed".[46]

Karl Marx

Contrary to popular belief Marx never used the term "Labor theory of value" in any of his works but used the term Law of value,[47] Marx opposed "ascribing a supernatural creative power to labor", arguing as such:

Labor is not the source of all wealth. Nature is just as much a source of use values (and it is surely of such that material wealth consists!) as labor, which is itself only the manifestation of a force of nature, human labor power.[48]

Here, Marx was distinguishing between exchange value (the subject of the LTV) and use value. Marx used the concept of "socially necessary labor time" to introduce a social perspective distinct from his predecessors and neoclassical economics. Whereas most economists start with the individual's perspective, Marx started with the perspective of society as a whole. "Social production" involves a complicated and interconnected division of labor of a wide variety of people who depend on each other for their survival and prosperity. "Abstract" labor refers to a characteristic of commodity-producing labor that is shared by all different kinds of heterogeneous (concrete) types of labor. That is, the concept abstracts from the particular characteristics of all of the labor and is akin to average labor.

"Socially necessary" labor refers to the quantity required to produce a commodity "in a given state of society, under certain social average conditions or production, with a given social average intensity, and average skill of the labor employed."[13] That is, the value of a product is determined more by societal standards than by individual conditions. This explains why technological breakthroughs lower the price of commodities and put less advanced producers out of business. Finally, it is not labor per se that creates value, but labor power sold by free wage workers to capitalists. Another distinction is between productive and unproductive labor. Only wage workers of productive sectors of the economy produce value.[note 3] According to Marx an increase in productiveness of the laborer does not affect the value of a commodity, but rather, increases the surplus value realized by the capitalist.[49] Therefore, decreasing the cost of production does not decrease the value of a commodity, but allows the capitalist to produce more and increases the opportunity to earn a greater profit or surplus value, as long as there is demand for the additional units of production.

Criticism

The Marxist labor theory of value has been criticised on several counts. Some argue that it predicts that profits will be higher in labor-intensive industries than in capital-intensive industries, which would be contradicted by measured empirical data inherent in quantitative analysis. This is sometimes referred to as the "Great Contradiction".[50] In volume 3 of Capital, Marx explains why profits are not distributed according to which industries are the most labor-intensive and why this is consistent with his theory. Whether or not this is consistent with the labor theory of value as presented in volume 1 has been a topic of debate.[50] According to Marx, surplus value is extracted by the capitalist class as a whole and then distributed according to the amount of total capital, not just the variable component. In the example given earlier, of making a cup of coffee, the constant capital involved in production is the coffee beans themselves, and the variable capital is the value added by the coffee maker. The value added by the coffee maker is dependent on its technological capabilities, and the coffee maker can only add so much total value to cups of coffee over its lifespan. The amount of value added to the product is thus the amortization of the value of the coffeemaker. We can also note that not all products have equal proportions of value added by amortized capital. Capital intensive industries such as finance may have a large contribution of capital, while labor-intensive industries like traditional agriculture would have a relatively small one.[51] Critics argue that this turns the LTV into a macroeconomic theory, when it was supposed to explain the exchange ratios of individual commodities in terms of their relation to their labour ratios (making it a microeconomic theory), yet Marx was now maintaining that these ratios must diverge from their labour ratios. Critics thus held that Marx's proposed solution to the "great contradiction" was not so much a solution as it was sidestepping the issue.[52][53]

Steve Keen argues that Marx's idea that only labor can produce value rests on the idea that as capital depreciates over its use, then this is transferring its exchange-value to the product. Keen argues that it is not clear why the value of the machine should depreciate at the same rate it is lost. Keen uses an analogy with labor: If workers receive a subsistence wage and the working day exhausts the capacity to labor, it could be argued that the worker has "depreciated" by the amount equivalent to the subsistence wage. However this depreciation is not the limit of value a worker can add in a day (indeed this is critical to Marx's idea that labor is fundamentally exploited). If it were, then the production of a surplus would be impossible. According to Keen, a machine could have a use-value greater than its exchange-value, meaning it could, along with labor, be a source of surplus. Keen claims that Marx almost reached such a conclusion in the Grundrisse but never developed it any further. Keen further observes that while Marx insisted that the contribution of machines to production is solely their use-value and not their exchange-value, he routinely treated the use-value and exchange-value of a machine as identical, despite the fact that this would contradict his claim that the two were unrelated.[54] Marxists respond by arguing that use-value and exchange-value are incommensurable magnitudes; to claim that a machine can add "more use-value" than it is worth in value-terms is a category error. According to Marx, a machine by definition cannot be a source of human labor.[55][56] Keen responds by arguing that the labor theory of value only works if the use-value and exchange-value of a machine are identical, as Marx argued that machines cannot create surplus value since as their use-value depreciates along with their exchange-value; they simply transfer it to the new product but create no new value in the process.[57] Keen's machinery argument can also be applied to slavery based modes of production, which also profit from extracting more use value from the laborers than they return to laborers.[58][59]

In their work Capital as Power, Shimshon Bichler and Jonathan Nitzan argue that while Marxists have claimed to produce empirical evidence of the labor theory of value via numerous studies which show consistent correlations between values and prices, these studies[note 4] do not actually provide evidence for it and are inadequate. According to the authors, these studies attempt to prove the LTV by showing that there is a positive correlation between market prices and labor values. However, the authors argue that these studies measure prices by looking at the price of total output (the unit price of a commodity multiplied by its total quantity) and do these for several sectors of the economy, estimate their total price and value from official statistics and measured for several years. However, Bichler and Nitzan argue that this method has statistical implications as correlations measured this way also reflect the co-variations of the associated quantities of unit values and prices. This means that the unit price and unit value of each sector are multiplied by the same value, which means that the greater the variability of output across different sectors, the tighter the correlation. This means that the overall correlation is substantially larger than the underlying correlation between unit values and unit prices; when sectors are controlled for their size, the correlations often drop to insignificant levels.[60][61] Furthermore, the authors argue that the studies do not seem to actually attempt to measure the correlation between value and price. The authors argue that, according to Marx, the value of a commodity indicates the abstract labor time required for its production; however Marxists have been unable to identify a way to measure a unit (elementary particle) of abstract labor (indeed the authors argue that most have given up and little progress has been made beyond Marx's original work) due to numerous difficulties. This means assumptions must be made and according to the authors, these involve circular reasoning:[60][61]

The most important of these assumptions are that the value of labour power is proportionate to the actual wage rate, that the ratio of variable capital to surplus value is given by the price ratio of wages to profit, and occasionally also that the value of the depreciated constant capital is equal to a fraction of the capital’s money price. In other words, the researcher assumes precisely what the labour theory of value is supposed to demonstrate.[62]

Bichler and Nitzan argue that this amounts to converting prices into values and then determining if they correlate, which the authors argue proves nothing since the studies are simply correlating prices with themselves.[60][61] Paul Cockshott disagreed with Bichler and Nitzan's arguments, arguing that it was possible to measure abstract labour time using wage bills and data on working hours, while also arguing Bichler and Nitzan's claims that the true value-price correlations should be much lower actually relied on poor statistical analysis itself.[63] Most Marxists, however, reject Bichler and Nitzan's interpretation of Marx, arguing that their assertion that individual commodities can have values, rather than prices of production, misunderstands Marx's work.[64] For example, Fred Moseley argues Marx understood "value" to be a "macro-monetary" variable (the total amount of labor added in a given year plus the depreciation of fixed capital in that year), which is then concretized at the level of individual prices of production, meaning that "individual values" of commodities do not exist.[65]

The theory can also be sometimes found in non-Marxist traditions.[note 5] For instance, mutualist theorist Kevin Carson's Studies in Mutualist Political Economy opens with an attempt to integrate marginalist critiques into the labor theory of value.[66]

Additionally, economist Joseph Schumpeter pointed out a couple of issues he believed undermined the validity of the labor theory of value. Firstly he wrote that labor theory of value failed to take into account the intrinsic differences in labor quality between individuals (a difference that, he believed, could not be properly encapsulated through the use of a value multiplier). Furthermore, he claims that labor theory of value, both in its Marxist and Ricardian formulations, would entail that labor be the sole input in an economy alongside all labor being homogenous in nature, a thesis which Schumpeter dismisses as unrealistic and one that could be resolved by Marginalism anyway. Schumpeter goes on to divert his attention towards the supposed self-contradictory nature of how labor theory of value allows for the justification of the Marxian exploitation thesis, highlighting that labor itself could not be valued since it was not itself produced by any labor and that the accumulation of surplus value described by Marx could not occur in a static, perfectly competitive market. Thus, although giving Marx the credit for seeing the need for change inherent in capitalist markets, Schumpeter nonetheless concludes that labor theory of value and its consequences remain problematic theories.[67]

Some post-Keynesian economists have been highly critical of the labor theory of value. Joan Robinson, who herself was considered an expert on the writings of Karl Marx,[68] wrote that the labor theory of value was largely a tautology and "a typical example of the way metaphysical ideas operate".[69] The well-known Marxian economist Roman Rosdolsky replied to Robinson's claims at length,[70] arguing that Robinson failed to understand key components of Marx's theory; for instance, Robinson argued that "Marx's theory, as we have seen, rests on the assumption of a constant rate of exploitation",[71] but as Rosdolsky points out, there is a great deal of contrary evidence.[72]

In ecological economics, the labor theory of value has been criticized, where it is argued that labor is in fact energy over time.[73] Such arguments generally fail to recognize that Marx is inquiring into social relations among human beings, which cannot be reduced to the expenditure of energy, just as democracy cannot be reduced to the expenditure of energy that a voter makes in getting to the polling place.[74] However, echoing Joan Robinson, Alf Hornborg, an environmental historian, argues that both the reliance on "energy theory of value" and "labor theory of value" are problematic as they propose that use-values (or material wealth) are more "real" than exchange-values (or cultural wealth)—yet, use-values are culturally determined.[75] For Hornborg, any Marxist argument that claims uneven wealth is due to the "exploitation" or "underpayment" of use-values is actually a tautological contradiction, since it must necessarily quantify "underpayment" in terms of exchange-value. The alternative would be to conceptualize unequal exchange as "an asymmetric net transfer of material inputs in production (e.g., embodied labor, energy, land, and water), rather than in terms of an underpayment of material inputs or an asymmetric transfer of 'value'".[76] In other words, uneven exchange is characterised by incommensurability, namely: the unequal transfer of material inputs; competing value-judgements of the worth of labor, fuel, and raw materials; differing availability of industrial technologies; and the off-loading of environmental burdens on those with less resources.[76][77]

See also

Competing theories

Notes

  1. ^ Unless otherwise noted, the description of the labor process and the role of the value of means of production in this section are drawn from chapter 7 of Capital vol1 (Marx 1867).
  2. ^ In the case of instruments of labor, such as the roaster and the brewer (or even a ceramic cup), the value transferred to the cup of coffee is only a depreciated value calculated over the life of those instruments of labor according to some accounting convention.
  3. ^ For the difference between wage workers and working animals or slaves confer: John R. Bell: Capitalism and the Dialectic - The Uno-Sekine Approach to Marxian Political Economy, p. 45. London, Pluto Press 2009
  4. ^ Examples of such studies include: Wolff, Edward N. 1975. The Rate of Surplus Value in Puerto Rico. Journal of Political Economy 83 (5, October): 935-950. Ochoa, E. 1989. Values, Prices and Wage-Profit Curves in the U.S. Economy. Cambridge Journal of Economics 13 (3, September): 413-430. Freeman, Alan. 1998. The Transformation of Prices into Values: Comments on the Chapters by Simon Mohum and Anwar M. Shaikh. In Marxian Economics. A Reappraisal. Volume 2: Essays on Volume III of Capital: Profit, Prices and Dynamics, edited by R. Bellofiore. London: Mcmillan, pp. 270-275. Cockshott, Paul, and Allin Cottrell. 2005. Robust Correlations Between Prices and Labour Values: A Comment. Cambridge Journal of Economics 29 (2, March): 309-316.
  5. ^ Confer: Weizsäcker, Carl Christian von (2010): A New Technical Progress Function (1962). German Economic Review 11/3 (first publication of an article written in 1962); Weizsäcker Carl Christian von, and Paul A. Samuelson (1971): A new labor theory of value for rational planning through use of the bourgeois profit rate. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (facsimile).

References

  1. ^ Beggs, Mike (Summer 2012). "Zombie Marx and Modern Economics, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Forget the Transformation Problem". Journal of Australian Political Economy (70). pp. 11–24, at p. 16.
  2. ^ Mongiovi, Gary (Autumn 2002). "Vulgar economy in Marxian garb: a critique of Temporal Single System Marxism". Review of Radical Political Economics. 34 (4). pp. 393–416, at p. 398. doi:10.1016/S0486-6134(02)00176-6 – via Elsevier Science Direct.
  3. ^ Hansson, Sven Ove; Grüne-Yanoff, Till (November 14, 2017). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Preferences". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). Retrieved November 21, 2020.
  4. ^ Wicksteed, Philip H. (1910). The Common Sense of Political Economy, Including a Study of the Human Basis of Economic Law. London: Macmillan and Co. from the original on October 20, 2020.
  5. ^ Hunt, E. K.; Lautzenheiser, Mark (2011). History of economic thought l: a critical perspective (3rd ed.). Armonk, New York: M. E. Sharpe. ISBN 978-1-317-46859-2. OCLC 903283190.
  6. ^ Darrell M. West (1987). Congress and Economic Policy Making. University of Pittsburgh Pre. p. 71. ISBN 978-0822974352.
  7. ^ Bellofiore, Riccardo; Riva, Tomasso (February 2, 2015). "The Neue Marx-Lektüre: Putting the critique of political economy back into the critique of society". Radical Philosophy. Retrieved February 10, 2021.
  8. ^ It is now interpreted that Ricardo's theory of value is not the labor theory of value, but the cost of production theory of value. See David Ricardo#Value theory
  9. ^ e.g. see - Junankar, P. N., Marx's economics, Oxford : Philip Allan, 1982, ISBN 0-86003-125-X or Peach, Terry "Interpreting Ricardo", Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993, ISBN 0-521-26086-8
  10. ^ Ricardo, David (1823), 'Absolute Value and Exchange Value', in "The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo", Volume 4, Cambridge University Press, 1951 and Sraffa, Piero and Maurice Dobb (1951), 'Introduction', in "The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo", Volume 1, Cambridge University Press, 1951.
  11. ^ Proudhon, Pierre J., 1851, General Idea of the Revolution in the 19th Century, study 6.
  12. ^ a b Marx 1867.
  13. ^ a b c Marx, Karl (1865). "Value and Labour". Value, Price and Profit – via Marxists Internet Archive.
  14. ^ Sraffa, Piero; Dobb, Maurice H. (1951). "General Preface". The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo. Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press.
  15. ^ a b Ormazabal, Kepa M. (2006). "Adam Smith on Labor and Value: Challenging the Standard Interpretation" (PDF). University of the Basque Country.
  16. ^ MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose Justice Which Rationality. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame. p. 199. ISBN 978-0-268-01942-6.
  17. ^ Russel, Bertrand (1946). History of Western philosophy. p. 578.
  18. ^ Baeck, L. (1994). The Mediterranean tradition in economic thought. New York: Routledge. p. 151. ISBN 978-0-415-09301-9.
  19. ^ Jaffe, Austin J.; Lusht, Kenneth M. (2003). "The History of the Value Theory: The Early Years". Essays in honor of William N. Kinnard, Jr. Boston: Kluwer Academic. p. 11. ISBN 978-1-4020-7516-2.
  20. ^ Oweiss, I. M. (1988). "Ibn Khaldun, the Father of Economics". Arab Civilization: Challenges and Responses. New York University Press. ISBN 978-0-88706-698-6.
  21. ^ Parrington, Vernon L. (1927). . Vol. I. Book Two, Part One, Chapter III. Benjamin Franklin: Our First Ambassador. Archived from the original on October 24, 2019.
  22. ^ Karl Marx, Value, Price and Profit, 1865, Part VI.
  23. ^ . New School University. Archived from the original on April 18, 2009. Retrieved August 23, 2004.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link)
  24. ^ . History of Economic Thought, New School University. Archived from the original on February 14, 2004. Retrieved July 12, 2015.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link)
  25. ^ Smith quoted in Whitaker, Albert C. History and Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value 2006-11-07 at the Wayback Machine'l, pp. 15–16
  26. ^ Whitaker, Albert C. History and Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value 2006-11-07 at the Wayback Machine, pp. 15–16
  27. ^ Ricardo, David (1817). "On The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation". www.marxists.org. Retrieved August 19, 2020.
  28. ^ Fernando Vianello, (1990) "The Labour Theory of Value", Eatwell J., Milgate M., Newman P. (eds) in Marxian Economics, The New Palgrave, pp.233-246.
  29. ^ Whitaker, Albert C. History and Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value November 7, 2006, at the Wayback Machine
  30. ^ Gordon, Donald, F. (1959). (PDF). American Economic Review. 49 (2): 462–472. JSTOR 1816138. Archived from the original on November 7, 2006. Retrieved August 8, 2006.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  31. ^ King, Peter and Ripstein, Arthur. "Did Marx Hold a Labor Theory of Value?" University of Toronto
  32. ^ Canterbery, E. Ray, A Brief History of Economics: Artful Approaches to the Dismal Science, World Scientific (2001), pp. 52–53
  33. ^ Fotopoulos, Takis. "Beyond Marx and Proudhon". Thus, the classical solution of expressing the value of goods and services in terms of man hours, which was developed by the orthodox (political) economists of the time, was adopted by both Proudhon and Marx.
  34. ^ "The most basic difference is that the individualist anarchists rooted their ideas in the labour theory of value while the "anarcho"-capitalists favour mainstream marginalist theory." An Anarchist FAQ 2013-03-15 at the Wayback Machine
  35. ^ "Like Proudhon, they desired a (libertarian) socialist system based on the market but without exploitation and which rested on possession rather than capitalist private property."An Anarchist FAQ 2013-03-15 at the Wayback Machine
  36. ^ Palmer, Brian (2010-12-29) What do anarchists want from us?, Slate.com
  37. ^ a b Riggenbach, Jeff (2011-02-25) Josiah Warren: The First American Anarchist, Mises Institute
  38. ^ William Bailie, (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on February 4, 2012. Retrieved June 17, 2013.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link) Josiah Warren: The First American Anarchist — A Sociological Study, Boston: Small, Maynard & Co., 1906, p. 20
  39. ^ a b In Equitable Commerce, Warren writes, "If a priest is required to get a soul out of purgatory, he sets his price according to the value which the relatives set upon his prayers, instead of their cost to the priest. This, again, is cannibalism. The same amount of labor equally disagreeable, with equal wear and tear, performed by his customers, would be a just remuneration
  40. ^ Wendy McElroy, "Individualist Anarchism vs. "Libertarianism" and Anarchocommunism 1998-02-06 at the Wayback Machine," in the New Libertarian, issue #12, October, 1984.
  41. ^ Smith writes: "The real price of every thing, what every thing really costs to the man who wants to acquire it, is the toil and trouble of acquiring it." Note, also, the sense of "labor" meaning "suffering".
  42. ^ Charles A. Madison. "Anarchism in the United States". Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 6, No. 1. (Jan., 1945), pp. 53
  43. ^ "Introduction". Mutualist.org. Retrieved April 29, 2010.
  44. ^ Miller, David. 1987. "Mutualism." The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Political Thought. Blackwell Publishing. p. 11
  45. ^ Tandy, Francis D., 1896, Voluntary Socialism, chapter 6, paragraph 15.
  46. ^ — Darby Tillis. . Infoshop.org. Archived from the original on November 23, 2010. Retrieved September 20, 2010.
  47. ^ cf E F Schumacher,Small Is Beautiful, Pt 1, ch 1. Mike Beggs, "Zombie Marx and Modern Economics, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Forget the Transformation Problem." Journal of Australian Political Economy, issue 70, Summer 2012/13, p. 16 [1]; Gary Mongiovi, "Vulgar economy in Marxian garb: a critique of Temporal Single System Marxism." In: Review of Radical Political Economics, Vol. 34, Issue 4, December 2002, pp. 393-416, at p. 398.
  48. ^ Marx, Karl (1875). "1". Critique of the Gotha Program – via Marxists Internet Archive.
  49. ^ If therefore, the capitalist who applies the new method, sells his commodity at its social value of one shilling, he sells it for threepence above its individual value, and thus realises an extra surplus-value of threepence. On the other hand, the working day of 12 hours is, as regards him, now represented by 24 articles instead of 12. Hence, in order to get rid of the product of one working day, the demand must be double what it was, i.e., the market must become twice as extensive. (Marx et al., 1974)
  50. ^ a b Böhm von Bawerk, "Karl Marx and the Close of His System" Karl Marx and the Close of His System
  51. ^ Ekelund, Jr., Robert B.; Hebert, Robert F. (1997). A History of Economic Theory and Method (4th ed.). pp. 239–241.
  52. ^ Temkin, Gabriel (1998). "Karl Marx and the economics of communism: anniversary recollections". Communist and Post-Communist Studies. 31 (4): 303–328 (321–322).
  53. ^ Sesardić, Neven (1985). Marxian Utopia. pp. 14–15. ISBN 0948027010. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  54. ^ Keen, Steve (Spring 1993). "Use-Value, Exchange Value, and the Demise of Marx's Labor Theory of Value" (PDF). Journal of the History of Economic Thought. 15 (1): 107–121.
  55. ^ Marx, Karl. *Capital*, Vol. I, p. 141, Penguin edition
  56. ^ D'Arcy, Jim, Socialist Economics 4: Do Machines Produce Surplus Value?, Socialist Standard, 1974
  57. ^ Keen, Steve. Debunking economics. ZED Books Limited, 2011, pp.436-438
  58. ^ Kara, Siddharth (2008). Sex Trafficking – Inside the Business of Modern Slavery. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-13960-1.
  59. ^ "Slavery in the United States". eh.net. Retrieved January 30, 2020.
  60. ^ a b c Cockshott, Paul, Shimshon Bichler, and Jonathan Nitzan. "Testing the labour theory of value: An exchange." (2010): 1-15.
  61. ^ a b c Nitzan, Jonathan, and Shimshon Bichler. Capital as power: A study of order and creorder. Routledge, 2009, pp.93-97, 138-144
  62. ^ Nitzan, Jonathan, and Shimshon Bichler. Capital as power: A study of order and creorder. Routledge, 2009, pp.96
  63. ^ Cottrell; Cockshott; Baeza (2014). (PDF). Investigación Económica. 73 (287): 115–134. hdl:10419/157802. S2CID 54996687. Archived from the original (PDF) on February 24, 2019.
  64. ^ Hansen, Bue Rübner. "Review of Capital as Power, p. 151. "For Nitzan and Bichler, the concept ‘abstract labour’ is materialist in a way most Marxists would consider vulgar, and a positive concept that can be understood in isolation from monetary relation".
  65. ^ Moseley, Fred (2015). Money and Totality: A Macro-monetary Interpretation of Marx's Logic in Capital and the End of the 'transformation Problem'. Brill.
  66. ^ Carson, Kevin A. "1–3". . Archived from the original on April 15, 2011.
  67. ^ Schumpeter, Joseph (1949). Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (Third ed.). Harper Perennial Modern Thought. pp. 24–30.
  68. ^ "Joan Robinson". Spartacus Educational. Retrieved July 1, 2020.
  69. ^ Joan Robinson, "Economic Philosophy" p39
  70. ^ Rosdolsky, Roman. The Making of Marx's Capital, Ch. 33
  71. ^ Robinson, Joan Essay on Marxian Economics, p. 38
  72. ^ Marx, Karl. Capital, Vol. 3, Ch. 14. Here Marx directly contradicts Robinson's claim by addressing, at length, "The Increasing Intensity of Exploitation"
  73. ^ Anson Rabinbach, "The human motor: Energy, fatigue, and the origins of modernity"
  74. ^ Rubin, Isaak Illich Essays on Marx's Theory of Value, Ch. 14
  75. ^ Jean Baudrillard, "Pour une critique de l'économie politique du signe"
  76. ^ a b Hornborg, Alf (2014). "Ecological economics, Marxism, and technological progress: Some explorations of the conceptual foundations of theories of ecologically unequal exchange". Ecological Economics. 105: 11–18. doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2014.05.015.
  77. ^ Martinez-Alier, Joan; Munda, Giuseppe; O'Neill, John (1998). "Weak comparability of values as a foundation for ecological economics". Ecological Economics. 26 (3): 277–286. doi:10.1016/S0921-8009(97)00120-1.

Further reading

  • Bhaduri, Amit. 1969. "On the Significance of Recent Controversies on Capital Theory: A Marxian View." Economic Journal. 79(315) September: 532–539.
  • von Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Karl Marx and the Close of His System (Classic criticism of Marxist economic theory).
  • G.A. Cohen 'The Labour Theory of Value and the Concept of Exploitation', in his History Labour and Freedom.
  • Duncan, Colin A.M. 1996. The Centrality of Agriculture: Between Humankind and The Rest of Nature. McGill–Queen's University Press, Montreal.
  • ——2000. The Centrality of Agriculture: History, Ecology and Feasible Socialism. Socialist Register, pp. 187–205.
  • ——2004. Adam Smith's green vision and the future of global socialism. In Albritton, R; Shannon Bell; John R. Bell; and R. Westra [Eds.] New Socialisms: Futures Beyond Globalization. New York/London, Routledge. pp. 90–104.
  • Dussel, Enique (2002), "The four drafts of '"Capital"" (PDF), Rethinking Marxism, 13 (1): 10, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.201.4415, doi:10.1080/089356901101241569, S2CID 145603007, retrieved August 3, 2006
  • Eldred, Michael (1984). Critique of Competitive Freedom and the Bourgeois-Democratic State: Outline of a Form-analytic Extension of Marx's Uncompleted System. With an Appendix 'Value-form Analytic Reconstruction of the Capital-Analysis' by Michael Eldred, Marnie Hanlon, Lucia Kleiber and Mike Roth, Kurasje, Copenhagen. Emended, digitized edition 2010 with a new Preface, lxxiii + 466 pp. ISBN 87-87437-40-6, 978-87-87437-40-0.
  • Ellerman, David P. (1992) Property & Contract in Economics: The Case for Economic Democracy. Blackwell. Chapters 4,5, and 13 critiques of LTV in favor of the labor theory of property.
  • Engels, F. (1880). Socialism: Utopian and Scientific.
  • Freeman, Alan: Price, value and profit – a continuous, general treatment. In: Alan Freeman, Guglielmo Carchedi (editors): Marx and Non-equilibrium Economics. Edward Elgar Publishing. Cheltenham, UK, Brookfield, US 1996. ISBN 978-1-85898-268-7.
  • Hagendorf, Klaus: The Labour Theory of Value. A Historical-Logical Analysis. Paris: EURODOS; 2008.
  • Hagendorf, Klaus: Labour Values and the Theory of the Firm. Part I: The Competitive Firm. Paris: EURODOS; 2009.
  • Hansen, Bue Rübner. (2011). "Review of Capital as Power by Jonathan Nitzan and Shimson Bichler". Historical Materialism 19, no. 2: 144–159.
  • Henderson, James M.; Quandt, Richard E. 1971: Microeconomic Theory – A Mathematical Approach. Second Edition/International Student Edition. McGraw-Hill Kogakusha, Ltd.
  • Keen, Steven Use, Value, and Exchange: The Misinterpretation of Marx.
  • Mason, Paul (2015). PostCapitalism: A Guide to our Future. Allen Lane. ISBN 978-1-84614-738-8.
  • Marx, Karl (1867), Engels, Friedrich (ed.), Capital, vol. 1, Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling, ISBN 978-0-394-72657-1, retrieved July 5, 2006 – via Marxists Internet Archive ([Internet edition: 1999] [1887 English edition]).
  • Marx, Karl (1976) [1867], Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, vol. 1, Ben Fowkes, Penguin Books
  • Moseley, Fred. (2016). Money and Totality Leiden, Netherlands: Brill.
  • Murray, Patrick. (2016). The Mismeasure of Wealth : Essays on Marx and Social Form Leiden, Netherlands: Brill.
  • Ormazabal, Kepa M. (2004). Smith On Labour Value Bilbo, Biscay, Spain: University of the Basque Country Working Paper.
  • Parrington, Vernon Louis. .
  • Pokrovskii, Vladimir (2011). Econodynamics. The Theory of Social Production. Springer, Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New York.
  • Rubin, Isaak Illich (1928). Essays on Marx's Theory of Value
  • Shaikh, Anwar (1998). "The Empirical Strength of the Labour Theory of Value" in Conference Proceedings of Marxian Economics: A Centenary Appraisal, Riccardo Bellofiore (ed.), Macmillan, London.
  • Smith, Adam (1776), , AdamSmith.org, ISBN 978-1-4043-0998-2, archived from the original on September 27, 2007, retrieved August 3, 2006
  • Vianello, F. (1987). "Labour theory of value", in: Eatwell, J. and Milgate, M. and Newman, P. (eds.): The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, Macmillan e Stockton, London e New York, ISBN 978-0-935859-10-2.
  • Wolff, Jonathan (2003). " Karl Marx in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Wolff, Richard D.; Roberts, Bruce B.; Callari, Antonio (1982), "Marx's (not Ricardo's) 'Transformation Problem': A Radical Reconceptualization", History of Political Economy, 14 (4): 564–582, doi:10.1215/00182702-14-4-564.

labor, theory, value, labor, theory, value, theory, value, that, argues, that, economic, value, good, service, determined, total, amount, socially, necessary, labor, required, produce, usually, associated, with, marxian, economics, although, originally, appear. The labor theory of value LTV is a theory of value that argues that the economic value of a good or service is determined by the total amount of socially necessary labor required to produce it The LTV is usually associated with Marxian economics although it originally appeared in the theories of earlier classical economists such as Adam Smith and David Ricardo and later in anarchist economics Smith saw the price of a commodity in terms of the labor that the purchaser must expend to buy it which embodies the concept of how much labor a commodity a tool for example can save the purchaser The LTV is central to Marxist theory which holds that the working class is exploited under capitalism and dissociates price and value However Marx did not refer to his own theory of value as a labour theory of value 1 2 Orthodox neoclassical economics rejects the LTV using a theory of value based on subjective preferences 3 4 5 6 The revival in interpretation of Marx known as the Neue Marx Lekture also rejects Marxian economics and the LTV calling them substantialist This reading claims that the LTV is a misinterpretation of the concept of fetishism in relation to value and that this understanding never appears in Marx s work The school heavily emphasizes works such as Capital as explicitly being a critique of political economy instead of a more correct theory 7 Contents 1 Definitions of value and labor 1 1 Distinctions of economically pertinent labor 2 Labor process 3 Relation between values and prices 4 History 4 1 Origins 4 2 Adam Smith and David Ricardo 4 3 Anarchism 4 4 Karl Marx 5 Criticism 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 Further readingDefinitions of value and labor EditWhen speaking in terms of a labor theory of value value without any qualifying adjective should theoretically refer to the amount of labor necessary to produce a marketable commodity including the labor necessary to develop any real capital used in the production Both David Ricardo 8 and Karl Marx tried to quantify and embody all labor components in order to develop a theory of the real price or natural price of a commodity 9 The labor theory of value as presented by Adam Smith did not require the quantification of past labor nor did it deal with the labor needed to create the tools capital that might be used in producing a commodity Smith s theory of value was very similar to the later utility theories in that Smith proclaimed that a commodity was worth whatever labor it would command in others value in trade or whatever labor it would save the self value in use or both However this value is subject to supply and demand at a particular time The real price of every thing what every thing really costs to the man who wants to acquire it is the toil and trouble of acquiring it What every thing is really worth to the man who has acquired it and who wants to dispose of it or exchange it for something else is the toil and trouble which it can save to himself and which it can impose upon other people Wealth of Nations Book 1 chapter V Smith s theory of price has nothing to do with the past labor spent in producing a commodity It speaks only of the labor that can be commanded or saved at present If there is no use for a buggy whip then the item is economically worthless in trade or in use regardless of all the labor spent in creating it Distinctions of economically pertinent labor EditValue in use is the usefulness of this commodity its utility A classical paradox often comes up when considering this type of value In the words of Adam Smith The word value it is to be observed has two different meanings and sometimes expresses the utility of some particular object and sometimes the power of purchasing other goods which the possession of that object conveys The one may be called value in use the other value in exchange The things which have the greatest value in use have frequently little or no value in exchange and on the contrary those which have the greatest value in exchange have frequently little or no value in use Nothing is more useful than water but it will purchase scarce anything scarce anything can be had in exchange for it A diamond on the contrary has scarce any value in use but a very great quantity of other goods may frequently be had in exchange for it Wealth of Nations Book 1 chapter IV Value in exchange is the relative proportion with which this commodity exchanges for another commodity in other words its price in the case of money It is relative to labor as explained by Adam Smith The value of any commodity to the person who possesses it and who means not to use or consume it himself but to exchange it for other commodities is equal to the quantity of labour which it enables him to purchase or command Labour therefore is the real measure of the exchangeable value of all commodities Wealth of Nations Book 1 chapter V Value without qualification is the labor embodied in a commodity under a given structure of production Marx defined the value of the commodity by this third definition In his terms value is the socially necessary abstract labor embodied in a commodity To David Ricardo and other classical economists this definition serves as a measure of real cost absolute value or a measure of value invariable under changes in distribution and technology 10 Ricardo other classical economists and Marx began their expositions with the assumption that value in exchange was equal to or proportional to this labor value They thought this was a good assumption from which to explore the dynamics of development in capitalist societies Other supporters of the labor theory of value used the word value in the second sense to represent exchange value 11 Labor process EditSince the term value is understood in the LTV as denoting something created by labor and its magnitude as something proportional to the quantity of labor performed it is important to explain how the labor process both preserves value and adds new value in the commodities it creates note 1 The value of a commodity increases in proportion to the duration and intensity of labor performed on average for its production Part of what the LTV means by socially necessary is that the value only increases in proportion to this labor as it is performed with average skill and average productivity So though workers may labor with greater skill or more productivity than others these more skillful and more productive workers thus produce more value through the production of greater quantities of the finished commodity Each unit still bears the same value as all the others of the same class of commodity By working sloppily unskilled workers may drag down the average skill of labor thus increasing the average labor time necessary for the production of each unit commodity But these unskillful workers cannot hope to sell the result of their labor process at a higher price as opposed to value simply because they have spent more time than other workers producing the same kind of commodities However production not only involves labor but also certain means of labor tools materials power plants and so on These means of labor also known as means of production are often the product of another labor process as well So the labor process inevitably involves these means of production that already enter the process with a certain amount of value Labor also requires other means of production that are not produced with labor and therefore bear no value such as sunlight air uncultivated land unextracted minerals etc While useful even crucial to the production process these bring no value to that process In terms of means of production resulting from another labor process LTV treats the magnitude of value of these produced means of production as constant throughout the labor process Due to the constancy of their value these means of production are referred to in this light as constant capital Consider for example workers who take coffee beans use a roaster to roast them and then use a brewer to brew and dispense a fresh cup of coffee In performing this labor these workers add value to the coffee beans and water that comprise the material ingredients of a cup of coffee The worker also transfers the value of constant capital the value of the beans some specific depreciated value of the roaster and the brewer and the value of the cup to the value of the final cup of coffee Again on average the worker can transfer no more than the value of these means of labor previously possessed to the finished cup of coffee note 2 So the value of coffee produced in a day equals the sum of both the value of the means of labor this constant capital and the value newly added by the worker in proportion to the duration and intensity of their work Often this is expressed mathematically as c L W displaystyle c L W where c displaystyle c is the constant capital of materials used in a period plus the depreciated portion of tools and plant used in the process A period is typically a day week year or a single turnover meaning the time required to complete one batch of coffee for example L displaystyle L is the quantity of labor time average skill and productivity performed in producing the finished commodities during the period W displaystyle W is the value or think worth of the product of the period w displaystyle w comes from the German word for value wert Note if the product resulting from the labor process is homogeneous all similar in quality and traits for example all cups of coffee then the value of the period s product can be divided by the total number of items use values or v u displaystyle v u produced to derive the unit value of each item w i W v u displaystyle begin matrix w i frac W sum v u end matrix where v u displaystyle begin matrix sum v u end matrix is the total items produced The LTV further divides the value added during the period of production L displaystyle L into two parts The first part is the portion of the process when the workers add value equivalent to the wages they are paid For example if the period in question is one week and these workers collectively are paid 1 000 then the time necessary to add 1 000 to while preserving the value of constant capital is considered the necessary labor portion of the period or week denoted N L displaystyle NL The remaining period is considered the surplus labor portion of the week or S L displaystyle SL The value used to purchase labor power for example the 1 000 paid in wages to these workers for the week is called variable capital v displaystyle v This is because in contrast to the constant capital expended on means of production variable capital can add value in the labor process The amount it adds depends on the duration intensity productivity and skill of the labor power purchased in this sense the buyer of labor power has purchased a commodity of variable use Finally the value added during the portion of the period when surplus labor is performed is called surplus value s displaystyle s From the variables defined above we find two other common expressions for the value produced during a given period c v s W displaystyle c v s W and c N L S L W displaystyle c NL SL W The first form of the equation expresses the value resulting from production focusing on the costs c v displaystyle c v and the surplus value appropriated in the process of production s displaystyle s The second form of the equation focuses on the value of production in terms of the values added by the labor performed during the process N L S L displaystyle NL SL Relation between values and prices EditOne issue facing the LTV is the relationship between value quantities on one hand and prices on the other If a commodity s value is not the same as its price and therefore the magnitudes of each likely differ then what is the relation between the two if any Various LTV schools of thought provide different answers to this question For example some argue that value in the sense of the amount of labor embodied in a good acts as a center of gravity for price However most economists would say that cases where pricing is given as approximately equal to the value of the labour embodied are in fact only special cases In General Theory pricing most usually fluctuates The standard formulation is that prices normally include a level of income for capital and land These incomes are known as profit and rent respectively Yet Marx made the point that value cannot be placed upon labour as a commodity because capital is a constant whereas profit is a variable not an income thus explaining the importance of profit in relation to pricing variables 12 In Book 1 chapter VI Adam Smith writes The real value of all the different component parts of price it must be observed is measured by the quantity of labour which they can each of them purchase or command Labour measures the value not only of that part of price which resolves itself into labour but of that which resolves itself into rent and of that which resolves itself into profit The final sentence explains how Smith sees value of a product as relative to labor of buyer or consumer as opposite to Marx who sees the value of a product being proportional to labor of laborer or producer And we value things price them based on how much labor we can avoid or command and we can command labor not only in a simple way but also by trading things for a profit The demonstration of the relation between commodities unit values and their respective prices is known in Marxian terminology as the transformation problem or the transformation of values into prices of production The transformation problem has probably generated the greatest bulk of debate about the LTV The problem with transformation is to find an algorithm where the magnitude of value added by labor in proportion to its duration and intensity is sufficiently accounted for after this value is distributed through prices that reflect an equal rate of return on capital advanced If there is an additional magnitude of value or a loss of value after transformation then the relation between values proportional to labor and prices proportional to total capital advanced is incomplete Various solutions and impossibility theorems have been offered for the transformation but the debate has not reached any clear resolution LTV does not deny the role of supply and demand influencing price since the price of a commodity is something other than its value In Value Price and Profit 1865 Karl Marx quotes Adam Smith and sums up It suffices to say that if supply and demand equilibrate each other the market prices of commodities will correspond with their natural prices that is to say with their values as determined by the respective quantities of labor required for their production 13 The LTV seeks to explain the level of this equilibrium This could be explained by a cost of production argument pointing out that all costs are ultimately labor costs but this does not account for profit and it is vulnerable to the charge of tautology in that it explains prices by prices 14 Marx later called this Smith s adding up theory of value Smith argues that labor values are the natural measure of exchange for direct producers like hunters and fishermen 15 Marx on the other hand uses a measurement analogy arguing that for commodities to be comparable they must have a common element or substance by which to measure them 13 and that labor is a common substance of what Marx eventually calls commodity values 12 History EditOrigins Edit The labor theory of value has developed over many centuries It had no single originator but rather many different thinkers arrived at the same conclusion independently Aristotle is claimed to hold to this view 16 Some writers trace its origin to Thomas Aquinas 17 18 In his Summa Theologiae 1265 1274 he expresses the view that value can does and should increase in relation to the amount of labor which has been expended in the improvement of commodities 19 Scholars such as Joseph Schumpeter have cited Ibn Khaldun who in his Muqaddimah 1377 described labor as the source of value necessary for all earnings and capital accumulation He argued that even if earning results from something other than a craft the value of the resulting profit and acquired capital must also include the value of the labor by which it was obtained Without labor it would not have been acquired 20 Scholars have also pointed to Sir William Petty s Treatise of Taxes of 1662 21 and to John Locke s labor theory of property set out in the Second Treatise on Government 1689 which sees labor as the ultimate source of economic value Karl Marx himself credited Benjamin Franklin in his 1729 essay entitled A Modest Enquiry into the Nature and Necessity of a Paper Currency as being one of the first to advance the theory 22 Adam Smith accepted the theory for pre capitalist societies but saw a flaw in its application to contemporary capitalism He pointed out that if the labor embodied in a product equaled the labor commanded i e the amount of labor that could be purchased by selling it then profit was impossible David Ricardo seconded by Marx responded to this paradox by arguing that Smith had confused labor with wages Labor commanded he argued would always be more than the labor needed to sustain itself wages The value of labor in this view covered not just the value of wages what Marx called the value of labor power but the value of the entire product created by labor 15 Ricardo s theory was a predecessor of the modern theory that equilibrium prices are determined solely by production costs associated with Neo Ricardianism 23 Based on the discrepancy between the wages of labor and the value of the product the Ricardian socialists Charles Hall Thomas Hodgskin John Gray and John Francis Bray and Percy Ravenstone 24 applied Ricardo s theory to develop theories of exploitation Marx expanded on these ideas arguing that workers work for a part of each day adding the value required to cover their wages while the remainder of their labor is performed for the enrichment of the capitalist The LTV and the accompanying theory of exploitation became central to his economic thought 19th century American individualist anarchists based their economics on the LTV with their particular interpretation of it being called Cost the limit of price They as well as contemporary individualist anarchists in that tradition hold that it is unethical to charge a higher price for a commodity than the amount of labor required to produce it Hence they propose that trade should be facilitated by using notes backed by labor Adam Smith and David Ricardo Edit Adam Smith held that in a primitive society the amount of labor put into producing a good determined its exchange value with exchange value meaning in this case the amount of labor a good can purchase However according to Smith in a more advanced society the market price is no longer proportional to labor cost since the value of the good now includes compensation for the owner of the means of production The whole produce of labour does not always belong to the labourer He must in most cases share it with the owner of the stock which employs him 25 According to Whitaker Smith is claiming that the real value of such a commodity produced in advanced society is measured by the labor which that commodity will command in exchange but Smith disowns what is naturally thought of as the genuine classical labor theory of value that labor cost regulates market value This theory was Ricardo s and really his alone 26 Classical economist David Ricardo s labor theory of value holds that the value of a good how much of another good or service it exchanges for in the market is proportional to how much labor was required to produce it including the labor required to produce the raw materials and machinery used in the process David Ricardo stated it as The value of a commodity or the quantity of any other commodity for which it will exchange depends on the relative quantity of labour which is necessary for its production and not on the greater or less compensation which is paid for that labour 27 In this connection Ricardo seeks to differentiate the quantity of labour necessary to produce a commodity from the wages paid to the laborers for its production Therefore wages did not always increase with the price of a commodity However Ricardo was troubled with some deviations in prices from proportionality with the labor required to produce them 28 For example he said I cannot get over the difficulty of the wine which is kept in the cellar for three or four years i e while constantly increasing in exchange value or that of the oak tree which perhaps originally had not 2 s expended on it in the way of labour and yet comes to be worth 100 Quoted in Whitaker Of course a capitalist economy stabilizes this discrepancy until the value added to aged wine is equal to the cost of storage If anyone can hold onto a bottle for four years and become rich that would make it hard to find freshly corked wine There is also the theory that adding to the price of a luxury product increases its exchange value by mere prestige The labor theory as an explanation for value contrasts with the subjective theory of value which says that value of a good is not determined by how much labor was put into it but by its usefulness in satisfying a want and its scarcity Ricardo s labor theory of value is not a normative theory as are some later forms of the labor theory such as claims that it is immoral for an individual to be paid less for his labor than the total revenue that comes from the sales of all the goods he produces It is arguable to what extent these classical theorists held the labor theory of value as it is commonly defined 29 30 31 For instance David Ricardo theorized that prices are determined by the amount of labor but found exceptions for which the labor theory could not account In a letter he wrote I am not satisfied with the explanation I have given of the principles which regulate value Adam Smith theorized that the labor theory of value holds true only in the early and rude state of society but not in a modern economy where owners of capital are compensated by profit As a result Smith ends up making little use of a labor theory of value 32 Anarchism Edit See also Anarchist economics and Cost the limit of price Sample labor for labor note for the Cincinnati Time Store Scanned from Equitable Commerce 1846 by Josiah WarrenPierre Joseph Proudhon s mutualism 33 and American individualist anarchists such as Josiah Warren Lysander Spooner and Benjamin Tucker 34 adopted the labor theory of value of classical economics and used it to criticize capitalism while favoring a non capitalist market system 35 Warren is widely regarded as the first American anarchist 36 37 and the four page weekly paper he edited during 1833 The Peaceful Revolutionist was the first anarchist periodical published 38 Cost the limit of price was a maxim coined by Warren indicating a prescriptive version of the labor theory of value Warren maintained that the just compensation for labor or for its product could only be an equivalent amount of labor or a product embodying an equivalent amount 39 Thus profit rent and interest were considered unjust economic arrangements 40 In keeping with the tradition of Adam Smith s The Wealth of Nations 41 the cost of labor is considered to be the subjective cost i e the amount of suffering involved in it 39 He put his theories to the test by establishing an experimental labor for labor store called the Cincinnati Time Store at the corner of 5th and Elm Streets in what is now downtown Cincinnati where trade was facilitated by notes backed by a promise to perform labor All the goods offered for sale in Warren s store were offered at the same price the merchant himself had paid for them plus a small surcharge in the neighborhood of 4 to 7 percent to cover store overhead 37 The store stayed open for three years after it closed Warren could pursue establishing colonies based on Mutualism These included Utopia and Modern Times Warren said that Stephen Pearl Andrews The Science of Society published in 1852 was the most lucid and complete exposition of Warren s own theories 42 Mutualism is an economic theory and anarchist school of thought that advocates a society where each person might possess a means of production either individually or collectively with trade representing equivalent amounts of labor in the free market 43 Integral to the scheme was the establishment of a mutual credit bank that would lend to producers at a minimal interest rate just high enough to cover administration 44 Mutualism is based on a labor theory of value that holds that when labor or its product is sold in exchange it ought to receive goods or services embodying the amount of labor necessary to produce an article of exactly similar and equal utility 45 Mutualism originated from the writings of philosopher Pierre Joseph Proudhon Collectivist anarchism as defended by Mikhail Bakunin defended a form of labor theory of value when it advocated a system where all necessaries for production are owned in common by the labour groups and the free communes based on the distribution of goods according to the labour contributed 46 Karl Marx Edit Contrary to popular belief Marx never used the term Labor theory of value in any of his works but used the term Law of value 47 Marx opposed ascribing a supernatural creative power to labor arguing as such Labor is not the source of all wealth Nature is just as much a source of use values and it is surely of such that material wealth consists as labor which is itself only the manifestation of a force of nature human labor power 48 Here Marx was distinguishing between exchange value the subject of the LTV and use value Marx used the concept of socially necessary labor time to introduce a social perspective distinct from his predecessors and neoclassical economics Whereas most economists start with the individual s perspective Marx started with the perspective of society as a whole Social production involves a complicated and interconnected division of labor of a wide variety of people who depend on each other for their survival and prosperity Abstract labor refers to a characteristic of commodity producing labor that is shared by all different kinds of heterogeneous concrete types of labor That is the concept abstracts from the particular characteristics of all of the labor and is akin to average labor Socially necessary labor refers to the quantity required to produce a commodity in a given state of society under certain social average conditions or production with a given social average intensity and average skill of the labor employed 13 That is the value of a product is determined more by societal standards than by individual conditions This explains why technological breakthroughs lower the price of commodities and put less advanced producers out of business Finally it is not labor per se that creates value but labor power sold by free wage workers to capitalists Another distinction is between productive and unproductive labor Only wage workers of productive sectors of the economy produce value note 3 According to Marx an increase in productiveness of the laborer does not affect the value of a commodity but rather increases the surplus value realized by the capitalist 49 Therefore decreasing the cost of production does not decrease the value of a commodity but allows the capitalist to produce more and increases the opportunity to earn a greater profit or surplus value as long as there is demand for the additional units of production Criticism EditMain article Criticisms of the labour theory of value The Marxist labor theory of value has been criticised on several counts Some argue that it predicts that profits will be higher in labor intensive industries than in capital intensive industries which would be contradicted by measured empirical data inherent in quantitative analysis This is sometimes referred to as the Great Contradiction 50 In volume 3 of Capital Marx explains why profits are not distributed according to which industries are the most labor intensive and why this is consistent with his theory Whether or not this is consistent with the labor theory of value as presented in volume 1 has been a topic of debate 50 According to Marx surplus value is extracted by the capitalist class as a whole and then distributed according to the amount of total capital not just the variable component In the example given earlier of making a cup of coffee the constant capital involved in production is the coffee beans themselves and the variable capital is the value added by the coffee maker The value added by the coffee maker is dependent on its technological capabilities and the coffee maker can only add so much total value to cups of coffee over its lifespan The amount of value added to the product is thus the amortization of the value of the coffeemaker We can also note that not all products have equal proportions of value added by amortized capital Capital intensive industries such as finance may have a large contribution of capital while labor intensive industries like traditional agriculture would have a relatively small one 51 Critics argue that this turns the LTV into a macroeconomic theory when it was supposed to explain the exchange ratios of individual commodities in terms of their relation to their labour ratios making it a microeconomic theory yet Marx was now maintaining that these ratios must diverge from their labour ratios Critics thus held that Marx s proposed solution to the great contradiction was not so much a solution as it was sidestepping the issue 52 53 This article may lend undue weight to Steve Keen Please help improve it by rewriting it in a balanced fashion that contextualizes different points of view April 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Steve Keen argues that Marx s idea that only labor can produce value rests on the idea that as capital depreciates over its use then this is transferring its exchange value to the product Keen argues that it is not clear why the value of the machine should depreciate at the same rate it is lost Keen uses an analogy with labor If workers receive a subsistence wage and the working day exhausts the capacity to labor it could be argued that the worker has depreciated by the amount equivalent to the subsistence wage However this depreciation is not the limit of value a worker can add in a day indeed this is critical to Marx s idea that labor is fundamentally exploited If it were then the production of a surplus would be impossible According to Keen a machine could have a use value greater than its exchange value meaning it could along with labor be a source of surplus Keen claims that Marx almost reached such a conclusion in the Grundrisse but never developed it any further Keen further observes that while Marx insisted that the contribution of machines to production is solely their use value and not their exchange value he routinely treated the use value and exchange value of a machine as identical despite the fact that this would contradict his claim that the two were unrelated 54 Marxists respond by arguing that use value and exchange value are incommensurable magnitudes to claim that a machine can add more use value than it is worth in value terms is a category error According to Marx a machine by definition cannot be a source of human labor 55 56 Keen responds by arguing that the labor theory of value only works if the use value and exchange value of a machine are identical as Marx argued that machines cannot create surplus value since as their use value depreciates along with their exchange value they simply transfer it to the new product but create no new value in the process 57 Keen s machinery argument can also be applied to slavery based modes of production which also profit from extracting more use value from the laborers than they return to laborers 58 59 In their work Capital as Power Shimshon Bichler and Jonathan Nitzan argue that while Marxists have claimed to produce empirical evidence of the labor theory of value via numerous studies which show consistent correlations between values and prices these studies note 4 do not actually provide evidence for it and are inadequate According to the authors these studies attempt to prove the LTV by showing that there is a positive correlation between market prices and labor values However the authors argue that these studies measure prices by looking at the price of total output the unit price of a commodity multiplied by its total quantity and do these for several sectors of the economy estimate their total price and value from official statistics and measured for several years However Bichler and Nitzan argue that this method has statistical implications as correlations measured this way also reflect the co variations of the associated quantities of unit values and prices This means that the unit price and unit value of each sector are multiplied by the same value which means that the greater the variability of output across different sectors the tighter the correlation This means that the overall correlation is substantially larger than the underlying correlation between unit values and unit prices when sectors are controlled for their size the correlations often drop to insignificant levels 60 61 Furthermore the authors argue that the studies do not seem to actually attempt to measure the correlation between value and price The authors argue that according to Marx the value of a commodity indicates the abstract labor time required for its production however Marxists have been unable to identify a way to measure a unit elementary particle of abstract labor indeed the authors argue that most have given up and little progress has been made beyond Marx s original work due to numerous difficulties This means assumptions must be made and according to the authors these involve circular reasoning 60 61 The most important of these assumptions are that the value of labour power is proportionate to the actual wage rate that the ratio of variable capital to surplus value is given by the price ratio of wages to profit and occasionally also that the value of the depreciated constant capital is equal to a fraction of the capital s money price In other words the researcher assumes precisely what the labour theory of value is supposed to demonstrate 62 Bichler and Nitzan argue that this amounts to converting prices into values and then determining if they correlate which the authors argue proves nothing since the studies are simply correlating prices with themselves 60 61 Paul Cockshott disagreed with Bichler and Nitzan s arguments arguing that it was possible to measure abstract labour time using wage bills and data on working hours while also arguing Bichler and Nitzan s claims that the true value price correlations should be much lower actually relied on poor statistical analysis itself 63 Most Marxists however reject Bichler and Nitzan s interpretation of Marx arguing that their assertion that individual commodities can have values rather than prices of production misunderstands Marx s work 64 For example Fred Moseley argues Marx understood value to be a macro monetary variable the total amount of labor added in a given year plus the depreciation of fixed capital in that year which is then concretized at the level of individual prices of production meaning that individual values of commodities do not exist 65 The theory can also be sometimes found in non Marxist traditions note 5 For instance mutualist theorist Kevin Carson s Studies in Mutualist Political Economy opens with an attempt to integrate marginalist critiques into the labor theory of value 66 Additionally economist Joseph Schumpeter pointed out a couple of issues he believed undermined the validity of the labor theory of value Firstly he wrote that labor theory of value failed to take into account the intrinsic differences in labor quality between individuals a difference that he believed could not be properly encapsulated through the use of a value multiplier Furthermore he claims that labor theory of value both in its Marxist and Ricardian formulations would entail that labor be the sole input in an economy alongside all labor being homogenous in nature a thesis which Schumpeter dismisses as unrealistic and one that could be resolved by Marginalism anyway Schumpeter goes on to divert his attention towards the supposed self contradictory nature of how labor theory of value allows for the justification of the Marxian exploitation thesis highlighting that labor itself could not be valued since it was not itself produced by any labor and that the accumulation of surplus value described by Marx could not occur in a static perfectly competitive market Thus although giving Marx the credit for seeing the need for change inherent in capitalist markets Schumpeter nonetheless concludes that labor theory of value and its consequences remain problematic theories 67 Some post Keynesian economists have been highly critical of the labor theory of value Joan Robinson who herself was considered an expert on the writings of Karl Marx 68 wrote that the labor theory of value was largely a tautology and a typical example of the way metaphysical ideas operate 69 The well known Marxian economist Roman Rosdolsky replied to Robinson s claims at length 70 arguing that Robinson failed to understand key components of Marx s theory for instance Robinson argued that Marx s theory as we have seen rests on the assumption of a constant rate of exploitation 71 but as Rosdolsky points out there is a great deal of contrary evidence 72 In ecological economics the labor theory of value has been criticized where it is argued that labor is in fact energy over time 73 Such arguments generally fail to recognize that Marx is inquiring into social relations among human beings which cannot be reduced to the expenditure of energy just as democracy cannot be reduced to the expenditure of energy that a voter makes in getting to the polling place 74 However echoing Joan Robinson Alf Hornborg an environmental historian argues that both the reliance on energy theory of value and labor theory of value are problematic as they propose that use values or material wealth are more real than exchange values or cultural wealth yet use values are culturally determined 75 For Hornborg any Marxist argument that claims uneven wealth is due to the exploitation or underpayment of use values is actually a tautological contradiction since it must necessarily quantify underpayment in terms of exchange value The alternative would be to conceptualize unequal exchange as an asymmetric net transfer of material inputs in production e g embodied labor energy land and water rather than in terms of an underpayment of material inputs or an asymmetric transfer of value 76 In other words uneven exchange is characterised by incommensurability namely the unequal transfer of material inputs competing value judgements of the worth of labor fuel and raw materials differing availability of industrial technologies and the off loading of environmental burdens on those with less resources 76 77 See also Edit Business and economics portalAbstract labor and concrete labor Cost the limit of price Division of labor Labor notes currency Law of value Prices of production Producerism Productive and unproductive labor Social division of labor Surplus labor Surplus product Surplus value Transformation problem Value form Anarchy of Production Competing theories Anarcho communism Entitlement theory Marginalism Neo Ricardianism Subjective theory of valueNotes Edit Unless otherwise noted the description of the labor process and the role of the value of means of production in this section are drawn from chapter 7 of Capital vol1 Marx 1867 In the case of instruments of labor such as the roaster and the brewer or even a ceramic cup the value transferred to the cup of coffee is only a depreciated value calculated over the life of those instruments of labor according to some accounting convention For the difference between wage workers and working animals or slaves confer John R Bell Capitalism and the Dialectic The Uno Sekine Approach to Marxian Political Economy p 45 London Pluto Press 2009 Examples of such studies include Wolff Edward N 1975 The Rate of Surplus Value in Puerto Rico Journal of Political Economy 83 5 October 935 950 Ochoa E 1989 Values Prices and Wage Profit Curves in the U S Economy Cambridge Journal of Economics 13 3 September 413 430 Freeman Alan 1998 The Transformation of Prices into Values Comments on the Chapters by Simon Mohum and Anwar M Shaikh In Marxian Economics A Reappraisal Volume 2 Essays on Volume III of Capital Profit Prices and Dynamics edited by R Bellofiore London Mcmillan pp 270 275 Cockshott Paul and Allin Cottrell 2005 Robust Correlations Between Prices and Labour Values A Comment Cambridge Journal of Economics 29 2 March 309 316 Confer Weizsacker Carl Christian von 2010 A New Technical Progress Function 1962 German Economic Review 11 3 first publication of an article written in 1962 Weizsacker Carl Christian von and Paul A Samuelson 1971 A new labor theory of value for rational planning through use of the bourgeois profit rate Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences facsimile References Edit Beggs Mike Summer 2012 Zombie Marx and Modern Economics or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Forget the Transformation Problem Journal of Australian Political Economy 70 pp 11 24 at p 16 Mongiovi Gary Autumn 2002 Vulgar economy in Marxian garb a critique of Temporal Single System Marxism Review of Radical Political Economics 34 4 pp 393 416 at p 398 doi 10 1016 S0486 6134 02 00176 6 via Elsevier Science Direct Hansson Sven Ove Grune Yanoff Till November 14 2017 Zalta Edward N ed Preferences The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2018 Edition Retrieved November 21 2020 Wicksteed Philip H 1910 The Common Sense of Political Economy Including a Study of the Human Basis of Economic Law London Macmillan and Co Archived from the original on October 20 2020 Hunt E K Lautzenheiser Mark 2011 History of economic thought l a critical perspective 3rd ed Armonk New York M E Sharpe ISBN 978 1 317 46859 2 OCLC 903283190 Darrell M West 1987 Congress and Economic Policy Making University of Pittsburgh Pre p 71 ISBN 978 0822974352 Bellofiore Riccardo Riva Tomasso February 2 2015 The Neue Marx Lekture Putting the critique of political economy back into the critique of society Radical Philosophy Retrieved February 10 2021 It is now interpreted that Ricardo s theory of value is not the labor theory of value but the cost of production theory of value See David Ricardo Value theory e g see Junankar P N Marx s economics Oxford Philip Allan 1982 ISBN 0 86003 125 X or Peach Terry Interpreting Ricardo Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1993 ISBN 0 521 26086 8 Ricardo David 1823 Absolute Value and Exchange Value in The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo Volume 4 Cambridge University Press 1951 and Sraffa Piero and Maurice Dobb 1951 Introduction in The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo Volume 1 Cambridge University Press 1951 Proudhon Pierre J 1851 General Idea of the Revolution in the 19th Century study 6 a b Marx 1867 a b c Marx Karl 1865 Value and Labour Value Price and Profit via Marxists Internet Archive Sraffa Piero Dobb Maurice H 1951 General Preface The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo Vol 1 Cambridge University Press a b Ormazabal Kepa M 2006 Adam Smith on Labor and Value Challenging the Standard Interpretation PDF University of the Basque Country MacIntyre A 1988 Whose Justice Which Rationality Notre Dame University of Notre Dame p 199 ISBN 978 0 268 01942 6 Russel Bertrand 1946 History of Western philosophy p 578 Baeck L 1994 The Mediterranean tradition in economic thought New York Routledge p 151 ISBN 978 0 415 09301 9 Jaffe Austin J Lusht Kenneth M 2003 The History of the Value Theory The Early Years Essays in honor of William N Kinnard Jr Boston Kluwer Academic p 11 ISBN 978 1 4020 7516 2 Oweiss I M 1988 Ibn Khaldun the Father of Economics Arab Civilization Challenges and Responses New York University Press ISBN 978 0 88706 698 6 Parrington Vernon L 1927 Main Currents in American Thought 1620 1800 Vol I Book Two Part One Chapter III Benjamin Franklin Our First Ambassador Archived from the original on October 24 2019 Karl Marx Value Price and Profit 1865 Part VI The Neo Ricardians New School University Archived from the original on April 18 2009 Retrieved August 23 2004 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint bot original URL status unknown link Utopians and Socialists Ricardian Socialists History of Economic Thought New School University Archived from the original on February 14 2004 Retrieved July 12 2015 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint bot original URL status unknown link Smith quoted in Whitaker Albert C History and Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value Archived 2006 11 07 at the Wayback Machine l pp 15 16 Whitaker Albert C History and Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value Archived 2006 11 07 at the Wayback Machine pp 15 16 Ricardo David 1817 On The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation www marxists org Retrieved August 19 2020 Fernando Vianello 1990 The Labour Theory of Value Eatwell J Milgate M Newman P eds in Marxian Economics The New Palgrave pp 233 246 Whitaker Albert C History and Criticism of the Labor Theory of Value Archived November 7 2006 at the Wayback Machine Gordon Donald F 1959 What Was the Labor Theory of Value PDF American Economic Review 49 2 462 472 JSTOR 1816138 Archived from the original on November 7 2006 Retrieved August 8 2006 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link King Peter and Ripstein Arthur Did Marx Hold a Labor Theory of Value University of Toronto Canterbery E Ray A Brief History of Economics Artful Approaches to the Dismal Science World Scientific 2001 pp 52 53 Fotopoulos Takis Beyond Marx and Proudhon Thus the classical solution of expressing the value of goods and services in terms of man hours which was developed by the orthodox political economists of the time was adopted by both Proudhon and Marx The most basic difference is that the individualist anarchists rooted their ideas in the labour theory of value while the anarcho capitalists favour mainstream marginalist theory An Anarchist FAQ Archived 2013 03 15 at the Wayback Machine Like Proudhon they desired a libertarian socialist system based on the market but without exploitation and which rested on possession rather than capitalist private property An Anarchist FAQ Archived 2013 03 15 at the Wayback Machine Palmer Brian 2010 12 29 What do anarchists want from us Slate com a b Riggenbach Jeff 2011 02 25 Josiah Warren The First American Anarchist Mises Institute William Bailie Archived copy PDF Archived from the original PDF on February 4 2012 Retrieved June 17 2013 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link Josiah Warren The First American Anarchist A Sociological Study Boston Small Maynard amp Co 1906 p 20 a b In Equitable Commerce Warren writes If a priest is required to get a soul out of purgatory he sets his price according to the value which the relatives set upon his prayers instead of their cost to the priest This again is cannibalism The same amount of labor equally disagreeable with equal wear and tear performed by his customers would be a just remuneration Wendy McElroy Individualist Anarchism vs Libertarianism and Anarchocommunism Archived 1998 02 06 at the Wayback Machine in the New Libertarian issue 12 October 1984 Smith writes The real price of every thing what every thing really costs to the man who wants to acquire it is the toil and trouble of acquiring it Note also the sense of labor meaning suffering Charles A Madison Anarchism in the United States Journal of the History of Ideas Vol 6 No 1 Jan 1945 pp 53 Introduction Mutualist org Retrieved April 29 2010 Miller David 1987 Mutualism The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Political Thought Blackwell Publishing p 11 Tandy Francis D 1896 Voluntary Socialism chapter 6 paragraph 15 Darby Tillis An Anarchist FAQ Infoshop org Archived from the original on November 23 2010 Retrieved September 20 2010 cf E F Schumacher Small Is Beautiful Pt 1 ch 1 Mike Beggs Zombie Marx and Modern Economics or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Forget the Transformation Problem Journal of Australian Political Economy issue 70 Summer 2012 13 p 16 1 Gary Mongiovi Vulgar economy in Marxian garb a critique of Temporal Single System Marxism In Review of Radical Political Economics Vol 34 Issue 4 December 2002 pp 393 416 at p 398 Marx Karl 1875 1 Critique of the Gotha Program via Marxists Internet Archive If therefore the capitalist who applies the new method sells his commodity at its social value of one shilling he sells it for threepence above its individual value and thus realises an extra surplus value of threepence On the other hand the working day of 12 hours is as regards him now represented by 24 articles instead of 12 Hence in order to get rid of the product of one working day the demand must be double what it was i e the market must become twice as extensive Marx et al 1974 a b Bohm von Bawerk Karl Marx and the Close of His System Karl Marx and the Close of His System Ekelund Jr Robert B Hebert Robert F 1997 A History of Economic Theory and Method 4th ed pp 239 241 Temkin Gabriel 1998 Karl Marx and the economics of communism anniversary recollections Communist and Post Communist Studies 31 4 303 328 321 322 Sesardic Neven 1985 Marxian Utopia pp 14 15 ISBN 0948027010 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Keen Steve Spring 1993 Use Value Exchange Value and the Demise of Marx s Labor Theory of Value PDF Journal of the History of Economic Thought 15 1 107 121 Marx Karl Capital Vol I p 141 Penguin edition D Arcy Jim Socialist Economics 4 Do Machines Produce Surplus Value Socialist Standard 1974 Keen Steve Debunking economics ZED Books Limited 2011 pp 436 438 Kara Siddharth 2008 Sex Trafficking Inside the Business of Modern Slavery Columbia University Press ISBN 978 0 231 13960 1 Slavery in the United States eh net Retrieved January 30 2020 a b c Cockshott Paul Shimshon Bichler and Jonathan Nitzan Testing the labour theory of value An exchange 2010 1 15 a b c Nitzan Jonathan and Shimshon Bichler Capital as power A study of order and creorder Routledge 2009 pp 93 97 138 144 Nitzan Jonathan and Shimshon Bichler Capital as power A study of order and creorder Routledge 2009 pp 96 Cottrell Cockshott Baeza 2014 The empirics of the labour theory of value Reply to Nitzan and Bichler PDF Investigacion Economica 73 287 115 134 hdl 10419 157802 S2CID 54996687 Archived from the original PDF on February 24 2019 Hansen Bue Rubner Review of Capital as Power p 151 For Nitzan and Bichler the concept abstract labour is materialist in a way most Marxists would consider vulgar and a positive concept that can be understood in isolation from monetary relation Moseley Fred 2015 Money and Totality A Macro monetary Interpretation of Marx s Logic in Capital and the End of the transformation Problem Brill Carson Kevin A 1 3 Studies in Mutualist Political Economy Archived from the original on April 15 2011 Schumpeter Joseph 1949 Capitalism Socialism and Democracy Third ed Harper Perennial Modern Thought pp 24 30 Joan Robinson Spartacus Educational Retrieved July 1 2020 Joan Robinson Economic Philosophy p39 Rosdolsky Roman The Making of Marx s Capital Ch 33 Robinson Joan Essay on Marxian Economics p 38 Marx Karl Capital Vol 3 Ch 14 Here Marx directly contradicts Robinson s claim by addressing at length The Increasing Intensity of Exploitation Anson Rabinbach The human motor Energy fatigue and the origins of modernity Rubin Isaak Illich Essays on Marx s Theory of Value Ch 14 Jean Baudrillard Pour une critique de l economie politique du signe a b Hornborg Alf 2014 Ecological economics Marxism and technological progress Some explorations of the conceptual foundations of theories of ecologically unequal exchange Ecological Economics 105 11 18 doi 10 1016 j ecolecon 2014 05 015 Martinez Alier Joan Munda Giuseppe O Neill John 1998 Weak comparability of values as a foundation for ecological economics Ecological Economics 26 3 277 286 doi 10 1016 S0921 8009 97 00120 1 Further reading EditBhaduri Amit 1969 On the Significance of Recent Controversies on Capital Theory A Marxian View Economic Journal 79 315 September 532 539 von Bohm Bawerk Eugen Karl Marx and the Close of His System Classic criticism of Marxist economic theory G A Cohen The Labour Theory of Value and the Concept of Exploitation in his History Labour and Freedom Duncan Colin A M 1996 The Centrality of Agriculture Between Humankind and The Rest of Nature McGill Queen s University Press Montreal 2000 The Centrality of Agriculture History Ecology and Feasible Socialism Socialist Register pp 187 205 2004 Adam Smith s green vision and the future of global socialism In Albritton R Shannon Bell John R Bell and R Westra Eds New Socialisms Futures Beyond Globalization New York London Routledge pp 90 104 Dussel Enique 2002 The four drafts of Capital PDF Rethinking Marxism 13 1 10 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 201 4415 doi 10 1080 089356901101241569 S2CID 145603007 retrieved August 3 2006 Eldred Michael 1984 Critique of Competitive Freedom and the Bourgeois Democratic State Outline of a Form analytic Extension of Marx s Uncompleted System With an Appendix Value form Analytic Reconstruction of the Capital Analysis by Michael Eldred Marnie Hanlon Lucia Kleiber and Mike Roth Kurasje Copenhagen Emended digitized edition 2010 with a new Preface lxxiii 466 pp ISBN 87 87437 40 6 978 87 87437 40 0 Ellerman David P 1992 Property amp Contract in Economics The Case for Economic Democracy Blackwell Chapters 4 5 and 13 critiques of LTV in favor of the labor theory of property Engels F 1880 Socialism Utopian and Scientific Freeman Alan Price value and profit a continuous general treatment In Alan Freeman Guglielmo Carchedi editors Marx and Non equilibrium Economics Edward Elgar Publishing Cheltenham UK Brookfield US 1996 ISBN 978 1 85898 268 7 Hagendorf Klaus The Labour Theory of Value A Historical Logical Analysis Paris EURODOS 2008 Hagendorf Klaus Labour Values and the Theory of the Firm Part I The Competitive Firm Paris EURODOS 2009 Hansen Bue Rubner 2011 Review of Capital as Power by Jonathan Nitzan and Shimson Bichler Historical Materialism 19 no 2 144 159 Henderson James M Quandt Richard E 1971 Microeconomic Theory A Mathematical Approach Second Edition International Student Edition McGraw Hill Kogakusha Ltd Keen Steven Use Value and Exchange The Misinterpretation of Marx Mason Paul 2015 PostCapitalism A Guide to our Future Allen Lane ISBN 978 1 84614 738 8 Marx Karl 1867 Engels Friedrich ed Capital vol 1 Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling ISBN 978 0 394 72657 1 retrieved July 5 2006 via Marxists Internet Archive Internet edition 1999 1887 English edition Marx Karl 1976 1867 Capital A Critique of Political Economy vol 1 Ben Fowkes Penguin Books Moseley Fred 2016 Money and Totality Leiden Netherlands Brill Murray Patrick 2016 The Mismeasure of Wealth Essays on Marx and Social Form Leiden Netherlands Brill Ormazabal Kepa M 2004 Smith On Labour Value Bilbo Biscay Spain University of the Basque Country Working Paper Parrington Vernon Louis The Autobiography of Benjamin Franklin Pokrovskii Vladimir 2011 Econodynamics The Theory of Social Production Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York Rubin Isaak Illich 1928 Essays on Marx s Theory of Value Shaikh Anwar 1998 The Empirical Strength of the Labour Theory of Value in Conference Proceedings of Marxian Economics A Centenary Appraisal Riccardo Bellofiore ed Macmillan London Smith Adam 1776 An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations AdamSmith org ISBN 978 1 4043 0998 2 archived from the original on September 27 2007 retrieved August 3 2006 Vianello F 1987 Labour theory of value in Eatwell J and Milgate M and Newman P eds The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics Macmillan e Stockton London e New York ISBN 978 0 935859 10 2 Wolff Jonathan 2003 Karl Marx in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Wolff Richard D Roberts Bruce B Callari Antonio 1982 Marx s not Ricardo s Transformation Problem A Radical Reconceptualization History of Political Economy 14 4 564 582 doi 10 1215 00182702 14 4 564 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Labor theory of value amp oldid 1171757421, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.