fbpx
Wikipedia

Laws of Form

Laws of Form (hereinafter LoF) is a book by G. Spencer-Brown, published in 1969, that straddles the boundary between mathematics and philosophy. LoF describes three distinct logical systems:

"Boundary algebra" is Meguire's (2011)[1] term for the union of the primary algebra and the primary arithmetic. Laws of Form sometimes loosely refers to the "primary algebra" as well as to LoF.

The book edit

The preface states that the work was first explored in 1959, and Spencer Brown cites Bertrand Russell as being supportive of his endeavour. He also thanks J. C. P. Miller of University College London for helping with the proof reading and offering other guidance. In 1963 Spencer Brown was invited by Harry Frost, staff lecturer in the physical sciences at the department of Extra-Mural Studies of the University of London to deliver a course on the mathematics of logic.

LoF emerged from work in electronic engineering its author did around 1960, and from subsequent lectures on mathematical logic he gave under the auspices of the University of London's extension program. LoF has appeared in several editions. The second series of editions appeared in 1972 with the "Preface to the First American Edition", which emphasised the use of self-referential paradoxes,[2] and the most recent being a 1997 German translation. LoF has never gone out of print.

LoF's mystical and declamatory prose and its love of paradox make it a challenging read for all. Spencer-Brown was influenced by Wittgenstein and R. D. Laing. LoF also echoes a number of themes from the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, Bertrand Russell, and Alfred North Whitehead.

The work has had curious effects on some classes of its readership; for example, on obscure grounds, it has been claimed that the entire book is written in an operational way, giving instructions to the reader instead of telling them what "is", and that in accordance with G. Spencer-Brown's interest in paradoxes, the only sentence that makes a statement that something is, is the statement which says no such statements are used in this book.[3] Furthermore, the claim asserts that except for this one sentence the book can be seen as an example of E-Prime. What prompted such a claim, is obscure, either in terms of incentive, logical merit, or as a matter of fact, because the book routinely and naturally uses the verb to be throughout, and in all its grammatical forms, as may be seen both in the original and in quotes shown below.[4]

Reception edit

Ostensibly a work of formal mathematics and philosophy, LoF became something of a cult classic: it was praised by Heinz von Foerster when he reviewed it for the Whole Earth Catalog.[5] Those who agree point to LoF as embodying an enigmatic "mathematics of consciousness", its algebraic symbolism capturing an (perhaps even "the") implicit root of cognition: the ability to "distinguish". LoF argues that primary algebra reveals striking connections among logic, Boolean algebra, and arithmetic, and the philosophy of language and mind.

Stafford Beer wrote in a review for Nature, "When one thinks of all that Russell went through sixty years ago, to write the Principia, and all we his readers underwent in wrestling with those three vast volumes, it is almost sad".[6]

Banaschewski (1977)[7] argues that the primary algebra is nothing but new notation for Boolean algebra. Indeed, the two-element Boolean algebra 2 can be seen as the intended interpretation of the primary algebra. Yet the notation of the primary algebra:

Moreover, the syntax of the primary algebra can be extended to formal systems other than 2 and sentential logic, resulting in boundary mathematics (see § Related work below).

LoF has influenced, among others, Heinz von Foerster, Louis Kauffman, Niklas Luhmann, Humberto Maturana, Francisco Varela and William Bricken. Some of these authors have modified the primary algebra in a variety of interesting ways.

LoF claimed that certain well-known mathematical conjectures of very long standing, such as the four color theorem, Fermat's Last Theorem, and the Goldbach conjecture, are provable using extensions of the primary algebra. Spencer-Brown eventually circulated a purported proof of the four color theorem, but it met with skepticism.[8]

The form (Chapter 1) edit

The symbol:

 

Also called the "mark" or "cross", is the essential feature of the Laws of Form. In Spencer-Brown's inimitable and enigmatic fashion, the Mark symbolizes the root of cognition, i.e., the dualistic Mark indicates the capability of differentiating a "this" from "everything else but this".

In LoF, a Cross denotes the drawing of a "distinction", and can be thought of as signifying the following, all at once:

  • The act of drawing a boundary around something, thus separating it from everything else;
  • That which becomes distinct from everything by drawing the boundary;
  • Crossing from one side of the boundary to the other.

All three ways imply an action on the part of the cognitive entity (e.g., person) making the distinction. As LoF puts it:

"The first command:

  • Draw a distinction

can well be expressed in such ways as:

  • Let there be a distinction,
  • Find a distinction,
  • See a distinction,
  • Describe a distinction,
  • Define a distinction,

Or:

  • Let a distinction be drawn". (LoF, Notes to chapter 2)

The counterpoint to the Marked state is the Unmarked state, which is simply nothing, the void, or the un-expressable infinite represented by a blank space. It is simply the absence of a Cross. No distinction has been made and nothing has been crossed. The Marked state and the void are the two primitive values of the Laws of Form.

The Cross can be seen as denoting the distinction between two states, one "considered as a symbol" and another not so considered. From this fact arises a curious resonance with some theories of consciousness and language. Paradoxically, the Form is at once Observer and Observed, and is also the creative act of making an observation. LoF (excluding back matter) closes with the words:

...the first distinction, the Mark and the observer are not only interchangeable, but, in the form, identical.

C. S. Peirce came to a related insight in the 1890s; see § Related work.

The primary arithmetic (Chapter 4) edit

The syntax of the primary arithmetic goes as follows. There are just two atomic expressions:

  • The empty Cross    ;
  • All or part of the blank page (the "void").

There are two inductive rules:

  • A Cross   may be written over any expression;
  • Any two expressions may be concatenated.

The semantics of the primary arithmetic are perhaps nothing more than the sole explicit definition in LoF: "Distinction is perfect continence".

Let the "unmarked state" be a synonym for the void. Let an empty Cross denote the "marked state". To cross is to move from one value, the unmarked or marked state, to the other. We can now state the "arithmetical" axioms A1 and A2, which ground the primary arithmetic (and hence all of the Laws of Form):

"A1. The law of Calling". Calling twice from a state is indistinguishable from calling once. To make a distinction twice has the same effect as making it once. For example, saying "Let there be light" and then saying "Let there be light" again, is the same as saying it once. Formally:

      

"A2. The law of Crossing". After crossing from the unmarked to the marked state, crossing again ("recrossing") starting from the marked state returns one to the unmarked state. Hence recrossing annuls crossing. Formally:

   

In both A1 and A2, the expression to the right of '=' has fewer symbols than the expression to the left of '='. This suggests that every primary arithmetic expression can, by repeated application of A1 and A2, be simplified to one of two states: the marked or the unmarked state. This is indeed the case, and the result is the expression's "simplification". The two fundamental metatheorems of the primary arithmetic state that:

  • Every finite expression has a unique simplification. (T3 in LoF);
  • Starting from an initial marked or unmarked state, "complicating" an expression by a finite number of repeated application of A1 and A2 cannot yield an expression whose simplification differs from the initial state. (T4 in LoF).

Thus the relation of logical equivalence partitions all primary arithmetic expressions into two equivalence classes: those that simplify to the Cross, and those that simplify to the void.

A1 and A2 have loose analogs in the properties of series and parallel electrical circuits, and in other ways of diagramming processes, including flowcharting. A1 corresponds to a parallel connection and A2 to a series connection, with the understanding that making a distinction corresponds to changing how two points in a circuit are connected, and not simply to adding wiring.

The primary arithmetic is analogous to the following formal languages from mathematics and computer science:

The phrase "calculus of indications" in LoF is a synonym for "primary arithmetic".

The notion of canon edit

A concept peculiar to LoF is that of "canon". While LoF does not formally define canon, the following two excerpts from the Notes to chpt. 2 are apt:

The more important structures of command are sometimes called canons. They are the ways in which the guiding injunctions appear to group themselves in constellations, and are thus by no means independent of each other. A canon bears the distinction of being outside (i.e., describing) the system under construction, but a command to construct (e.g., 'draw a distinction'), even though it may be of central importance, is not a canon. A canon is an order, or set of orders, to permit or allow, but not to construct or create.

...the primary form of mathematical communication is not description but injunction... Music is a similar art form, the composer does not even attempt to describe the set of sounds he has in mind, much less the set of feelings occasioned through them, but writes down a set of commands which, if they are obeyed by the performer, can result in a reproduction, to the listener, of the composer's original experience.

These excerpts relate to the distinction in metalogic between the object language, the formal language of the logical system under discussion, and the metalanguage, a language (often a natural language) distinct from the object language, employed to exposit and discuss the object language. The first quote seems to assert that the canons are part of the metalanguage. The second quote seems to assert that statements in the object language are essentially commands addressed to the reader by the author. Neither assertion holds in standard metalogic.

The primary algebra (Chapter 6) edit

Syntax edit

Given any valid primary arithmetic expression, insert into one or more locations any number of Latin letters bearing optional numerical subscripts; the result is a primary algebra formula. Letters so employed in mathematics and logic are called variables. A primary algebra variable indicates a location where one can write the primitive value   or its complement  . Multiple instances of the same variable denote multiple locations of the same primitive value.

Rules governing logical equivalence edit

The sign '=' may link two logically equivalent expressions; the result is an equation. By "logically equivalent" is meant that the two expressions have the same simplification. Logical equivalence is an equivalence relation over the set of primary algebra formulas, governed by the rules R1 and R2. Let "C" and "D" be formulae each containing at least one instance of the subformula A:

  • R1, Substitution of equals. Replace one or more instances of A in C by B, resulting in E. If A=B, then C=E.
  • R2, Uniform replacement. Replace all instances of A in C and D with B. C becomes E and D becomes F. If C=D, then E=F. Note that A=B is not required.

R2 is employed very frequently in primary algebra demonstrations (see below), almost always silently. These rules are routinely invoked in logic and most of mathematics, nearly always unconsciously.

The primary algebra consists of equations, i.e., pairs of formulae linked by an infix operator '='. R1 and R2 enable transforming one equation into another. Hence the primary algebra is an equational formal system, like the many algebraic structures, including Boolean algebra, that are varieties. Equational logic was common before Principia Mathematica (e.g., Peirce,1,2,3 Johnson 1892), and has present-day advocates (Gries and Schneider 1993).

Conventional mathematical logic consists of tautological formulae, signalled by a prefixed turnstile. To denote that the primary algebra formula A is a tautology, simply write "A =  ". If one replaces '=' in R1 and R2 with the biconditional, the resulting rules hold in conventional logic. However, conventional logic relies mainly on the rule modus ponens; thus conventional logic is ponential. The equational-ponential dichotomy distills much of what distinguishes mathematical logic from the rest of mathematics.

Initials edit

An initial is a primary algebra equation verifiable by a decision procedure and as such is not an axiom. LoF lays down the initials:

  • J1:
A
A
= .

The absence of anything to the right of the "=" above, is deliberate.

  • J2:
A
B
C =
A C
B C
.

J2 is the familiar distributive law of sentential logic and Boolean algebra.

Another set of initials, friendlier to calculations, is:

  • J0:
A = A.
  • J1a:
A
A
=
.
  • C2:
A
A B
= A
B
.

It is thanks to C2 that the primary algebra is a lattice. By virtue of J1a, it is a complemented lattice whose upper bound is  . By J0,   is the corresponding lower bound and identity element. J0 is also an algebraic version of A2 and makes clear the sense in which   aliases with the blank page.

T13 in LoF generalizes C2 as follows. Any primary algebra (or sentential logic) formula B can be viewed as an ordered tree with branches. Then:

T13: A subformula A can be copied at will into any depth of B greater than that of A, as long as A and its copy are in the same branch of B. Also, given multiple instances of A in the same branch of B, all instances but the shallowest are redundant.

While a proof of T13 would require induction, the intuition underlying it should be clear.

C2 or its equivalent is named:

  • "Generation" in LoF;
  • "Exclusion" in Johnson (1892);
  • "Pervasion" in the work of William Bricken.

Perhaps the first instance of an axiom or rule with the power of C2 was the "Rule of (De)Iteration", combining T13 and AA=A, of C. S. Peirce's existential graphs.

LoF asserts that concatenation can be read as commuting and associating by default and hence need not be explicitly assumed or demonstrated. (Peirce made a similar assertion about his existential graphs.) Let a period be a temporary notation to establish grouping. That concatenation commutes and associates may then be demonstrated from the:

  • Initial AC.D=CD.A and the consequence AA=A (Byrne 1946). This result holds for all lattices, because AA=A is an easy consequence of the absorption law, which holds for all lattices;
  • Initials AC.D=AD.C and J0. Since J0 holds only for lattices with a lower bound, this method holds only for bounded lattices (which include the primary algebra and 2). Commutativity is trivial; just set A= . Associativity: AC.D = CA.D = CD.A = A.CD.

Having demonstrated associativity, the period can be discarded.

The initials in Meguire (2011) are AC.D=CD.A, called B1; B2, J0 above; B3, J1a above; and B4, C2. By design, these initials are very similar to the axioms for an abelian group, G1-G3 below.

Proof theory edit

The primary algebra contains three kinds of proved assertions:

  • Consequence is a primary algebra equation verified by a demonstration. A demonstration consists of a sequence of steps, each step justified by an initial or a previously demonstrated consequence.
  • Theorem is a statement in the metalanguage verified by a proof, i.e., an argument, formulated in the metalanguage, that is accepted by trained mathematicians and logicians.
  • Initial, defined above. Demonstrations and proofs invoke an initial as if it were an axiom.

The distinction between consequence and theorem holds for all formal systems, including mathematics and logic, but is usually not made explicit. A demonstration or decision procedure can be carried out and verified by computer. The proof of a theorem cannot be.

Let A and B be primary algebra formulas. A demonstration of A=B may proceed in either of two ways:

  • Modify A in steps until B is obtained, or vice versa;
  • Simplify both   and   to  . This is known as a "calculation".

Once A=B has been demonstrated, A=B can be invoked to justify steps in subsequent demonstrations. primary algebra demonstrations and calculations often require no more than J1a, J2, C2, and the consequences   (C3 in LoF),   (C1), and AA=A (C5).

The consequence  , C7' in LoF, enables an algorithm, sketched in LoFs proof of T14, that transforms an arbitrary primary algebra formula to an equivalent formula whose depth does not exceed two. The result is a normal form, the primary algebra analog of the conjunctive normal form. LoF (T14–15) proves the primary algebra analog of the well-known Boolean algebra theorem that every formula has a normal form.

Let A be a subformula of some formula B. When paired with C3, J1a can be viewed as the closure condition for calculations: B is a tautology if and only if A and (A) both appear in depth 0 of B. A related condition appears in some versions of natural deduction. A demonstration by calculation is often little more than:

  • Invoking T13 repeatedly to eliminate redundant subformulae;
  • Erasing any subformulae having the form  .

The last step of a calculation always invokes J1a.

LoF includes elegant new proofs of the following standard metatheory:

  • Completeness: all primary algebra consequences are demonstrable from the initials (T17).
  • Independence: J1 cannot be demonstrated from J2 and vice versa (T18).

That sentential logic is complete is taught in every first university course in mathematical logic. But university courses in Boolean algebra seldom mention the completeness of 2.

Interpretations edit

If the Marked and Unmarked states are read as the Boolean values 1 and 0 (or True and False), the primary algebra interprets 2 (or sentential logic). LoF shows how the primary algebra can interpret the syllogism. Each of these interpretations is discussed in a subsection below. Extending the primary algebra so that it could interpret standard first-order logic has yet to be done, but Peirce's beta existential graphs suggest that this extension is feasible.

Two-element Boolean algebra 2 edit

The primary algebra is an elegant minimalist notation for the two-element Boolean algebra 2. Let:

  • One of Boolean join (+) or meet (×) interpret concatenation;
  • The complement of A interpret  
  • 0 (1) interpret the empty Mark if join (meet) interprets concatenation (because a binary operation applied to zero operands may be regarded as being equal to the identity element of that operation; or to put it in another way, an operand that is missing could be regarded as acting by default like the identity element).

If join (meet) interprets AC, then meet (join) interprets  . Hence the primary algebra and 2 are isomorphic but for one detail: primary algebra complementation can be nullary, in which case it denotes a primitive value. Modulo this detail, 2 is a model of the primary algebra. The primary arithmetic suggests the following arithmetic axiomatization of 2: 1+1=1+0=0+1=1=~0, and 0+0=0=~1.

The set         is the Boolean domain or carrier. In the language of universal algebra, the primary algebra is the algebraic structure   of type  . The expressive adequacy of the Sheffer stroke points to the primary algebra also being a   algebra of type  . In both cases, the identities are J1a, J0, C2, and ACD=CDA. Since the primary algebra and 2 are isomorphic, 2 can be seen as a   algebra of type  . This description of 2 is simpler than the conventional one, namely an   algebra of type  .

The two possible interpretations are dual to each other in the Boolean sense. (In Boolean algebra, exchanging AND ↔ OR and 1 ↔ 0 throughout an equation yields an equally valid equation.) The identities remain invariant regardless of which interpretation is chosen, so the transformations or modes of calculation remain the same; only the interpretation of each form would be different. Example: J1a is  . Interpreting juxtaposition as OR and   as 1, this translates to   which is true. Interpreting juxtaposition as AND and   as 0, this translates to   which is true as well (and the dual of  ).

operator-operand duality edit

The marked state,   , is both an operator (e.g., the complement) and operand (e.g., the value 1). This can be summarized neatly by defining two functions   and   for the marked and unmarked state, respectively: let   and  , where   is a (possibly empty) set of boolean values.

This reveals that   is either the value 0 or the OR operator, while   is either the value 1 or the NOR operator, depending on whether   is the empty set or not. As noted above, there is a dual form of these functions exchanging AND ↔ OR and 1 ↔ 0.

Sentential logic edit

Let the blank page denote False, and let a Cross be read as Not. Then the primary arithmetic has the following sentential reading:

 =   False
   =  True  =  not False
   =  Not True  =  False

The primary algebra interprets sentential logic as follows. A letter represents any given sentential expression. Thus:

  interprets Not A
  interprets A Or B
  interprets Not A Or B or If A Then B.
  interprets Not (Not A Or Not B)
or Not (If A Then Not B)
or A And B.
        
a
b
a
b
,
a
b
a b
both interpret A if and only if B or A is equivalent to B.

Thus any expression in sentential logic has a primary algebra translation. Equivalently, the primary algebra interprets sentential logic. Given an assignment of every variable to the Marked or Unmarked states, this primary algebra translation reduces to a primary arithmetic expression, which can be simplified. Repeating this exercise for all possible assignments of the two primitive values to each variable, reveals whether the original expression is tautological or satisfiable. This is an example of a decision procedure, one more or less in the spirit of conventional truth tables. Given some primary algebra formula containing N variables, this decision procedure requires simplifying 2N primary arithmetic formulae. For a less tedious decision procedure more in the spirit of Quine's "truth value analysis", see Meguire (2003).

Schwartz (1981) proved that the primary algebra is equivalent — syntactically, semantically, and proof theoretically — with the classical propositional calculus. Likewise, it can be shown that the primary algebra is syntactically equivalent with expressions built up in the usual way from the classical truth values true and false, the logical connectives NOT, OR, and AND, and parentheses.

Interpreting the Unmarked State as False is wholly arbitrary; that state can equally well be read as True. All that is required is that the interpretation of concatenation change from OR to AND. IF A THEN B now translates as   instead of  . More generally, the primary algebra is "self-dual", meaning that any primary algebra formula has two sentential or Boolean readings, each the dual of the other. Another consequence of self-duality is the irrelevance of De Morgan's laws; those laws are built into the syntax of the primary algebra from the outset.

The true nature of the distinction between the primary algebra on the one hand, and 2 and sentential logic on the other, now emerges. In the latter formalisms, complementation/negation operating on "nothing" is not well-formed. But an empty Cross is a well-formed primary algebra expression, denoting the Marked state, a primitive value. Hence a nonempty Cross is an operator, while an empty Cross is an operand because it denotes a primitive value. Thus the primary algebra reveals that the heretofore distinct mathematical concepts of operator and operand are in fact merely different facets of a single fundamental action, the making of a distinction.

Syllogisms edit

Appendix 2 of LoF shows how to translate traditional syllogisms and sorites into the primary algebra. A valid syllogism is simply one whose primary algebra translation simplifies to an empty Cross. Let A* denote a literal, i.e., either A or  , indifferently. Then every syllogism that does not require that one or more terms be assumed nonempty is one of 24 possible permutations of a generalization of Barbara whose primary algebra equivalent is  . These 24 possible permutations include the 19 syllogistic forms deemed valid in Aristotelian and medieval logic. This primary algebra translation of syllogistic logic also suggests that the primary algebra can interpret monadic and term logic, and that the primary algebra has affinities to the Boolean term schemata of Quine (1982: Part II).

An example of calculation edit

The following calculation of Leibniz's nontrivial Praeclarum Theorema exemplifies the demonstrative power of the primary algebra. Let C1 be   =A, C2 be  , C3 be  , J1a be  , and let OI mean that variables and subformulae have been reordered in a way that commutativity and associativity permit.

[(PR)∧(QS)]→[(PQ)→(RS)]. Praeclarum Theorema.
P
R
Q
S
P
Q
R
S
.
primary algebra translation
P
R
Q
S
P
Q
R
S
.
C1.
P
R
Q
S
P
Q
R
S
.
C1.
P
P
R
Q
S
Q
R
S
.
OI.
P
R
Q
S
Q
R
S
.
C2.
P
R
Q
Q
S
R
S
.
OI.
P
R
Q
S
R
S
.
C2.
P
Q
S
R
R
S
.
OI.
P
Q
S
R
S
.
C2.
P
Q
S
R
S .
C1.
P
Q
S
S
R
.
OI.
P
Q
B
R
.
J1a.
B
P
Q
R
.
OI.
B
C3.  

Relation to magmas edit

The primary algebra embodies a point noted by Huntington in 1933: Boolean algebra requires, in addition to one unary operation, one, and not two, binary operations. Hence the seldom-noted fact that Boolean algebras are magmas. (Magmas were called groupoids until the latter term was appropriated by category theory.) To see this, note that the primary algebra is a commutative:

Groups also require a unary operation, called inverse, the group counterpart of Boolean complementation. Let   denote the inverse of a. Let   denote the group identity element. Then groups and the primary algebra have the same signatures, namely they are both   algebras of type 〈2,1,0〉. Hence the primary algebra is a boundary algebra. The axioms for an abelian group, in boundary notation, are:

  • G1. abc = acb (assuming association from the left);
  • G2.  
  • G3.  .

From G1 and G2, the commutativity and associativity of concatenation may be derived, as above. Note that G3 and J1a are identical. G2 and J0 would be identical if     =     replaced A2. This is the defining arithmetical identity of group theory, in boundary notation.

The primary algebra differs from an abelian group in two ways:

  • From A2, it follows that   . If the primary algebra were a group,   =   would hold, and one of     a =     or   a   = a   would have to be a primary algebra consequence. Note that   and   are mutual primary algebra complements, as group theory requires, so that   is true of both group theory and the primary algebra;
  • C2 most clearly demarcates the primary algebra from other magmas, because C2 enables demonstrating the absorption law that defines lattices, and the distributive law central to Boolean algebra.

Both A2 and C2 follow from B's being an ordered set.

Equations of the second degree (Chapter 11) edit

Chapter 11 of LoF introduces equations of the second degree, composed of recursive formulae that can be seen as having "infinite" depth. Some recursive formulae simplify to the marked or unmarked state. Others "oscillate" indefinitely between the two states depending on whether a given depth is even or odd. Specifically, certain recursive formulae can be interpreted as oscillating between true and false over successive intervals of time, in which case a formula is deemed to have an "imaginary" truth value. Thus the flow of time may be introduced into the primary algebra.

Turney (1986) shows how these recursive formulae can be interpreted via Alonzo Church's Restricted Recursive Arithmetic (RRA). Church introduced RRA in 1955 as an axiomatic formalization of finite automata. Turney (1986) presents a general method for translating equations of the second degree into Church's RRA, illustrating his method using the formulae E1, E2, and E4 in chapter 11 of LoF. This translation into RRA sheds light on the names Spencer-Brown gave to E1 and E4, namely "memory" and "counter". RRA thus formalizes and clarifies LoF's notion of an imaginary truth value.

Related work edit

Gottfried Leibniz, in memoranda not published before the late 19th and early 20th centuries, invented Boolean logic. His notation was isomorphic to that of LoF: concatenation read as conjunction, and "non-(X)" read as the complement of X. Recognition of Leibniz's pioneering role in algebraic logic was foreshadowed by Lewis (1918) and Rescher (1954). But a full appreciation of Leibniz's accomplishments had to await the work of Wolfgang Lenzen, published in the 1980s and reviewed in Lenzen (2004).

Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) anticipated the primary algebra in three veins of work:

  1. Two papers he wrote in 1886 proposed a logical algebra employing but one symbol, the streamer, nearly identical to the Cross of LoF. The semantics of the streamer are identical to those of the Cross, except that Peirce never wrote a streamer with nothing under it. An excerpt from one of these papers was published in 1976,[9] but they were not published in full until 1993.[10]
  2. In a 1902 encyclopedia article,[11] Peirce notated Boolean algebra and sentential logic in the manner of this entry, except that he employed two styles of brackets, toggling between '(', ')' and '[', ']' with each increment in formula depth.
  3. The syntax of his alpha existential graphs is merely concatenation, read as conjunction, and enclosure by ovals, read as negation.[12] If primary algebra concatenation is read as conjunction, then these graphs are isomorphic to the primary algebra (Kauffman 2001).

Ironically, LoF cites vol. 4 of Peirce's Collected Papers, the source for the formalisms in (2) and (3) above. (1)-(3) were virtually unknown at the time when (1960s) and in the place where (UK) LoF was written. Peirce's semiotics, about which LoF is silent, may yet shed light on the philosophical aspects of LoF.

Kauffman (2001) discusses another notation similar to that of LoF, that of a 1917 article by Jean Nicod, who was a disciple of Bertrand Russell's.

The above formalisms are, like the primary algebra, all instances of boundary mathematics, i.e., mathematics whose syntax is limited to letters and brackets (enclosing devices). A minimalist syntax of this nature is a "boundary notation". Boundary notation is free of infix operators, prefix, or postfix operator symbols. The very well known curly braces ('{', '}') of set theory can be seen as a boundary notation.

The work of Leibniz, Peirce, and Nicod is innocent of metatheory, as they wrote before Emil Post's landmark 1920 paper (which LoF cites), proving that sentential logic is complete, and before Hilbert and Łukasiewicz showed how to prove axiom independence using models.

Craig (1979) argued that the world, and how humans perceive and interact with that world, has a rich Boolean structure. Craig was an orthodox logician and an authority on algebraic logic.

Second-generation cognitive science emerged in the 1970s, after LoF was written. On cognitive science and its relevance to Boolean algebra, logic, and set theory, see Lakoff (1987) (see index entries under "Image schema examples: container") and Lakoff and Núñez (2001). Neither book cites LoF.

The biologists and cognitive scientists Humberto Maturana and his student Francisco Varela both discuss LoF in their writings, which identify "distinction" as the fundamental cognitive act. The Berkeley psychologist and cognitive scientist Eleanor Rosch has written extensively on the closely related notion of categorization.

Other formal systems with possible affinities to the primary algebra include:

  • Mereology which typically has a lattice structure very similar to that of Boolean algebra. For a few authors, mereology is simply a model of Boolean algebra and hence of the primary algebra as well.
  • Mereotopology, which is inherently richer than Boolean algebra;
  • The system of Whitehead (1934), whose fundamental primitive is "indication".

The primary arithmetic and algebra are a minimalist formalism for sentential logic and Boolean algebra. Other minimalist formalisms having the power of set theory include:

  • The lambda calculus;
  • Combinatory logic with two (S and K) or even one (X) primitive combinators;
  • Mathematical logic done with merely three primitive notions: one connective, NAND (whose primary algebra translation is   or, dually,  ), universal quantification, and one binary atomic formula, denoting set membership. This is the system of Quine (1951).
  • The beta existential graphs, with a single binary predicate denoting set membership. This has yet to be explored. The alpha graphs mentioned above are a special case of the beta graphs.

Editions edit

  • 1969. London: Allen & Unwin, hardcover.
  • 1972. Crown Publishers, hardcover: ISBN 0-517-52776-6
  • 1973. Bantam Books, paperback. ISBN 0-553-07782-1
  • 1979. E.P. Dutton, paperback. ISBN 0-525-47544-3
  • 1994. Portland OR: Cognizer Company, paperback. ISBN 0-9639899-0-1
  • 1997 German translation, titled Gesetze der Form. Lübeck: Bohmeier Verlag. ISBN 3-89094-321-7
  • 2008 Bohmeier Verlag, Leipzig, 5th international edition. ISBN 978-3-89094-580-4

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Meguire, P. (2011) Boundary Algebra: A Simpler Approach to Basic Logic and Boolean Algebra. Saarbrücken: VDM Publishing Ltd. 168pp
  2. ^ Schönwälder-Kuntze, Tatjana; Wille, Katrin; Hölscher, Thomas; Spencer Brown, George (2009). "George Spencer Brown: Eine Einführung in die Laws of Form, 2. Auflage". Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. ISBN 978-3-531-16105-1.
  3. ^ Felix Lau: Die Form der Paradoxie, 2005 Carl-Auer Verlag, ISBN 9783896703521
  4. ^ George Spencer-Brown. Laws of form. 1969, Pub. George Allen and Unwin. SBN 04 510028 4
  5. ^ Müller, Albert (2008). "Computing a Reality Heinz von Foerster's Lecture at the A.U.M Conference in 1973" (PDF). Constructivist Foundations. 4 (1): 62–69.
  6. ^ Beer, Stafford (1969). "Maths Created". Nature. 223 (5213): 1392–1393. Bibcode:1969Natur.223.1392B. doi:10.1038/2231392b0. S2CID 5223774.
  7. ^ B. Banaschewski (July 1977). "On G. Spencer Brown's Laws of Form". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 18 (3): 507–509. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093888028.
  8. ^ For a sympathetic evaluation, see Kauffman (2001).
  9. ^ "Qualitative Logic", MS 736 (c. 1886) in Eisele, Carolyn, ed. 1976. The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce. Vol. 4, Mathematical Philosophy. (The Hague) Mouton: 101-15.1
  10. ^ "Qualitative Logic", MS 582 (1886) in Kloesel, Christian et al., eds., 1993. Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Vol. 5, 1884–1886. Indiana University Press: 323-71. "The Logic of Relatives: Qualitative and Quantitative", MS 584 (1886) in Kloesel, Christian et al., eds., 1993. Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Vol. 5, 1884–1886. Indiana University Press: 372-78.
  11. ^ Reprinted in Peirce, C.S. (1933) Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. 4, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, eds. Harvard University Press. Paragraphs 378–383
  12. ^ The existential graphs are described at length in Peirce, C.S. (1933) Collected Papers, Vol. 4, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, eds. Harvard University Press. Paragraphs 347–529.

Bibliography edit

  • Bostock, David, 1997. Intermediate Logic. Oxford Univ. Press.
  • Byrne, Lee, 1946, "Two Formulations of Boolean Algebra", Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society: 268–71.
  • Craig, William (1979). "Boolean Logic and the Everyday Physical World". Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association. 52 (6): 751–78. doi:10.2307/3131383. JSTOR 3131383.
  • David Gries, and Schneider, F B, 1993. A Logical Approach to Discrete Math. Springer-Verlag.
  • William Ernest Johnson, 1892, "The Logical Calculus", Mind 1 (n.s.): 3–30.
  • Louis H. Kauffman, 2001, "The Mathematics of C.S. Peirce", Cybernetics and Human Knowing 8: 79–110.
  • ------, 2006, "Reformulating the Map Color Theorem."
  • ------, 2006a. "Laws of Form – An Exploration in Mathematics and Foundations." Book draft (hence big).
  • Lenzen, Wolfgang, 2004, "Leibniz's Logic" in Gabbay, D., and Woods, J., eds., The Rise of Modern Logic: From Leibniz to Frege (Handbook of the History of Logic – Vol. 3). Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1–83.
  • Lakoff, George, 1987. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things. University of Chicago Press.
  • -------- and Rafael E. Núñez, 2001. Where Mathematics Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being. Basic Books.
  • Meguire, P. G. (2003). "Discovering Boundary Algebra: A Simplified Notation for Boolean Algebra and the Truth Functors". International Journal of General Systems. 32: 25–87. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.106.634. doi:10.1080/0308107031000075690. S2CID 9460101.
  • --------, 2011. Boundary Algebra: A Simpler Approach to Basic Logic and Boolean Algebra. VDM Publishing Ltd. ISBN 978-3639367492. The source for much of this entry, including the notation which encloses in parentheses what LoF places under a cross. Steers clear of the more speculative aspects of LoF.
  • Willard Quine, 1951. Mathematical Logic, 2nd ed. Harvard University Press.
  • --------, 1982. Methods of Logic, 4th ed. Harvard University Press.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (1954). "Leibniz's Interpretation of His Logical Calculi". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 18 (1): 1–13. doi:10.2307/2267644. JSTOR 2267644. S2CID 689315.
  • Schwartz, Daniel G. (1981). "Isomorphisms of G. Spencer-Brown's Laws of Form and F. Varela's Calculus for Self-Reference". International Journal of General Systems. 6 (4): 239–55. doi:10.1080/03081078108934802.
  • Turney, P. D. (1986). "Laws of Form and Finite Automata". International Journal of General Systems. 12 (4): 307–18. doi:10.1080/03081078608934939.
  • A. N. Whitehead, 1934, "Indication, classes, number, validation", Mind 43 (n.s.): 281–97, 543. The corrigenda on p. 543 are numerous and important, and later reprints of this article do not incorporate them.
  • Dirk Baecker (ed.) (1993), Kalkül der Form. Suhrkamp; Dirk Baecker (ed.), Probleme der Form. Suhrkamp.
  • Dirk Baecker (ed.) (1999), Problems of Form, Stanford University Press.
  • Dirk Baecker (ed.) (2013), A Mathematics of Form, A Sociology of Observers, Cybernetics & Human Knowing, vol. 20, no. 3-4.
  • Louis H. Kauffman (ed.) (2019), Cybernetics & Human Knowing, vol. 26, no. 2-3. Special Issue, Laws of Form: Spencer-Brown at Esalen, 1973.

External links edit

  • , archive of website by Richard Shoup.
  • Self-referential forms are introduced in the section entitled "Degree of Equations and the Theory of Types".
  • Audio recording of the opening session, 1973 AUM Conference at Esalen.
  • Louis H. Kauffman, "Box Algebra, Boundary Mathematics, Logic, and Laws of Form."
  • Kissel, Matthias, ""
  • The Laws of Form Forum, where the primary algebra and related formalisms have been discussed since 2002.
  • A meeting with G.S.B by Moshe Klein
  • The Markable Mark, an introduction by easy stages to the ideas of Laws of Form
  • The BF Calculus and the Square Root of Negation by Louis Kauffman and Arthur Collings; it extends the Laws of Form by adding an imaginary logical value. (Imaginary logical values are introduced in chapter 11 of the book Laws of Form.)
  • Laws of Form Course - a free on-line course taking people through the main body of the text of Laws of Form by Leon Conrad, Spencer-Brown's last student, who studied the work with the author.

laws, form, hereinafter, book, spencer, brown, published, 1969, that, straddles, boundary, between, mathematics, philosophy, describes, three, distinct, logical, systems, primary, arithmetic, described, chapter, whose, models, include, boolean, arithmetic, pri. Laws of Form hereinafter LoF is a book by G Spencer Brown published in 1969 that straddles the boundary between mathematics and philosophy LoF describes three distinct logical systems The primary arithmetic described in Chapter 4 of LoF whose models include Boolean arithmetic The primary algebra Chapter 6 of LoF whose models include the two element Boolean algebra hereinafter abbreviated 2 Boolean logic and the classical propositional calculus Equations of the second degree Chapter 11 whose interpretations include finite automata and Alonzo Church s Restricted Recursive Arithmetic RRA Boundary algebra is Meguire s 2011 1 term for the union of the primary algebra and the primary arithmetic Laws of Form sometimes loosely refers to the primary algebra as well as to LoF Contents 1 The book 2 Reception 3 The form Chapter 1 4 The primary arithmetic Chapter 4 4 1 The notion of canon 5 The primary algebra Chapter 6 5 1 Syntax 5 2 Rules governing logical equivalence 5 3 Initials 5 4 Proof theory 5 5 Interpretations 5 5 1 Two element Boolean algebra 2 5 5 1 1 operator operand duality 5 5 2 Sentential logic 5 5 3 Syllogisms 5 6 An example of calculation 5 7 Relation to magmas 6 Equations of the second degree Chapter 11 7 Related work 8 Editions 9 See also 10 Notes 11 Bibliography 12 External linksThe book editThe preface states that the work was first explored in 1959 and Spencer Brown cites Bertrand Russell as being supportive of his endeavour He also thanks J C P Miller of University College London for helping with the proof reading and offering other guidance In 1963 Spencer Brown was invited by Harry Frost staff lecturer in the physical sciences at the department of Extra Mural Studies of the University of London to deliver a course on the mathematics of logic LoF emerged from work in electronic engineering its author did around 1960 and from subsequent lectures on mathematical logic he gave under the auspices of the University of London s extension program LoF has appeared in several editions The second series of editions appeared in 1972 with the Preface to the First American Edition which emphasised the use of self referential paradoxes 2 and the most recent being a 1997 German translation LoF has never gone out of print LoF s mystical and declamatory prose and its love of paradox make it a challenging read for all Spencer Brown was influenced by Wittgenstein and R D Laing LoF also echoes a number of themes from the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead The work has had curious effects on some classes of its readership for example on obscure grounds it has been claimed that the entire book is written in an operational way giving instructions to the reader instead of telling them what is and that in accordance with G Spencer Brown s interest in paradoxes the only sentence that makes a statement that something is is the statement which says no such statements are used in this book 3 Furthermore the claim asserts that except for this one sentence the book can be seen as an example of E Prime What prompted such a claim is obscure either in terms of incentive logical merit or as a matter of fact because the book routinely and naturally uses the verb to be throughout and in all its grammatical forms as may be seen both in the original and in quotes shown below 4 Reception editOstensibly a work of formal mathematics and philosophy LoF became something of a cult classic it was praised by Heinz von Foerster when he reviewed it for the Whole Earth Catalog 5 Those who agree point to LoF as embodying an enigmatic mathematics of consciousness its algebraic symbolism capturing an perhaps even the implicit root of cognition the ability to distinguish LoF argues that primary algebra reveals striking connections among logic Boolean algebra and arithmetic and the philosophy of language and mind Stafford Beer wrote in a review for Nature When one thinks of all that Russell went through sixty years ago to write the Principia and all we his readers underwent in wrestling with those three vast volumes it is almost sad 6 Banaschewski 1977 7 argues that the primary algebra is nothing but new notation for Boolean algebra Indeed the two element Boolean algebra 2 can be seen as the intended interpretation of the primary algebra Yet the notation of the primary algebra Fully exploits the duality characterizing not just Boolean algebras but all lattices Highlights how syntactically distinct statements in logic and 2 can have identical semantics Dramatically simplifies Boolean algebra calculations and proofs in sentential and syllogistic logic Moreover the syntax of the primary algebra can be extended to formal systems other than 2 and sentential logic resulting in boundary mathematics see Related work below LoF has influenced among others Heinz von Foerster Louis Kauffman Niklas Luhmann Humberto Maturana Francisco Varela and William Bricken Some of these authors have modified the primary algebra in a variety of interesting ways LoF claimed that certain well known mathematical conjectures of very long standing such as the four color theorem Fermat s Last Theorem and the Goldbach conjecture are provable using extensions of the primary algebra Spencer Brown eventually circulated a purported proof of the four color theorem but it met with skepticism 8 The form Chapter 1 editThe symbol nbsp Also called the mark or cross is the essential feature of the Laws of Form In Spencer Brown s inimitable and enigmatic fashion the Mark symbolizes the root of cognition i e the dualistic Mark indicates the capability of differentiating a this from everything else but this In LoF a Cross denotes the drawing of a distinction and can be thought of as signifying the following all at once The act of drawing a boundary around something thus separating it from everything else That which becomes distinct from everything by drawing the boundary Crossing from one side of the boundary to the other All three ways imply an action on the part of the cognitive entity e g person making the distinction As LoF puts it The first command Draw a distinction can well be expressed in such ways as Let there be a distinction Find a distinction See a distinction Describe a distinction Define a distinction Or Let a distinction be drawn LoF Notes to chapter 2 The counterpoint to the Marked state is the Unmarked state which is simply nothing the void or the un expressable infinite represented by a blank space It is simply the absence of a Cross No distinction has been made and nothing has been crossed The Marked state and the void are the two primitive values of the Laws of Form The Cross can be seen as denoting the distinction between two states one considered as a symbol and another not so considered From this fact arises a curious resonance with some theories of consciousness and language Paradoxically the Form is at once Observer and Observed and is also the creative act of making an observation LoF excluding back matter closes with the words the first distinction the Mark and the observer are not only interchangeable but in the form identical C S Peirce came to a related insight in the 1890s see Related work The primary arithmetic Chapter 4 editThe syntax of the primary arithmetic goes as follows There are just two atomic expressions The empty Cross nbsp All or part of the blank page the void There are two inductive rules A Cross nbsp may be written over any expression Any two expressions may be concatenated The semantics of the primary arithmetic are perhaps nothing more than the sole explicit definition in LoF Distinction is perfect continence Let the unmarked state be a synonym for the void Let an empty Cross denote the marked state To cross is to move from one value the unmarked or marked state to the other We can now state the arithmetical axioms A1 and A2 which ground the primary arithmetic and hence all of the Laws of Form A1 The law of Calling Calling twice from a state is indistinguishable from calling once To make a distinction twice has the same effect as making it once For example saying Let there be light and then saying Let there be light again is the same as saying it once Formally nbsp nbsp displaystyle nbsp nbsp dd A2 The law of Crossing After crossing from the unmarked to the marked state crossing again recrossing starting from the marked state returns one to the unmarked state Hence recrossing annuls crossing Formally nbsp displaystyle nbsp dd In both A1 and A2 the expression to the right of has fewer symbols than the expression to the left of This suggests that every primary arithmetic expression can by repeated application of A1 and A2 be simplified to one of two states the marked or the unmarked state This is indeed the case and the result is the expression s simplification The two fundamental metatheorems of the primary arithmetic state that Every finite expression has a unique simplification T3 in LoF Starting from an initial marked or unmarked state complicating an expression by a finite number of repeated application of A1 and A2 cannot yield an expression whose simplification differs from the initial state T4 in LoF Thus the relation of logical equivalence partitions all primary arithmetic expressions into two equivalence classes those that simplify to the Cross and those that simplify to the void A1 and A2 have loose analogs in the properties of series and parallel electrical circuits and in other ways of diagramming processes including flowcharting A1 corresponds to a parallel connection and A2 to a series connection with the understanding that making a distinction corresponds to changing how two points in a circuit are connected and not simply to adding wiring The primary arithmetic is analogous to the following formal languages from mathematics and computer science A Dyck language with a null alphabet The simplest context free language in the Chomsky hierarchy A rewrite system that is strongly normalizing and confluent The phrase calculus of indications in LoF is a synonym for primary arithmetic The notion of canon edit A concept peculiar to LoF is that of canon While LoF does not formally define canon the following two excerpts from the Notes to chpt 2 are apt The more important structures of command are sometimes called canons They are the ways in which the guiding injunctions appear to group themselves in constellations and are thus by no means independent of each other A canon bears the distinction of being outside i e describing the system under construction but a command to construct e g draw a distinction even though it may be of central importance is not a canon A canon is an order or set of orders to permit or allow but not to construct or create the primary form of mathematical communication is not description but injunction Music is a similar art form the composer does not even attempt to describe the set of sounds he has in mind much less the set of feelings occasioned through them but writes down a set of commands which if they are obeyed by the performer can result in a reproduction to the listener of the composer s original experience These excerpts relate to the distinction in metalogic between the object language the formal language of the logical system under discussion and the metalanguage a language often a natural language distinct from the object language employed to exposit and discuss the object language The first quote seems to assert that the canons are part of the metalanguage The second quote seems to assert that statements in the object language are essentially commands addressed to the reader by the author Neither assertion holds in standard metalogic The primary algebra Chapter 6 editSyntax edit Given any valid primary arithmetic expression insert into one or more locations any number of Latin letters bearing optional numerical subscripts the result is a primary algebra formula Letters so employed in mathematics and logic are called variables A primary algebra variable indicates a location where one can write the primitive value nbsp or its complement nbsp Multiple instances of the same variable denote multiple locations of the same primitive value Rules governing logical equivalence edit The sign may link two logically equivalent expressions the result is an equation By logically equivalent is meant that the two expressions have the same simplification Logical equivalence is an equivalence relation over the set of primary algebra formulas governed by the rules R1 and R2 Let C and D be formulae each containing at least one instance of the subformula A R1 Substitution of equals Replace one or more instances of A in C by B resulting in E If A B then C E R2 Uniform replacement Replace all instances of A in C and D with B C becomes E and D becomes F If C D then E F Note that A B is not required R2 is employed very frequently in primary algebra demonstrations see below almost always silently These rules are routinely invoked in logic and most of mathematics nearly always unconsciously The primary algebra consists of equations i e pairs of formulae linked by an infix operator R1 and R2 enable transforming one equation into another Hence the primary algebra is an equational formal system like the many algebraic structures including Boolean algebra that are varieties Equational logic was common before Principia Mathematica e g Peirce 1 2 3 Johnson 1892 and has present day advocates Gries and Schneider 1993 Conventional mathematical logic consists of tautological formulae signalled by a prefixed turnstile To denote that the primary algebra formula A is a tautology simply write A nbsp If one replaces in R1 and R2 with the biconditional the resulting rules hold in conventional logic However conventional logic relies mainly on the rule modus ponens thus conventional logic is ponential The equational ponential dichotomy distills much of what distinguishes mathematical logic from the rest of mathematics Initials edit An initial is a primary algebra equation verifiable by a decision procedure and as such is not an axiom LoF lays down the initials J1 A A The absence of anything to the right of the above is deliberate J2 A B C A C B C J2 is the familiar distributive law of sentential logic and Boolean algebra Another set of initials friendlier to calculations is J0 A A J1a A A C2 A A B A B It is thanks to C2 that the primary algebra is a lattice By virtue of J1a it is a complemented lattice whose upper bound is nbsp By J0 nbsp is the corresponding lower bound and identity element J0 is also an algebraic version of A2 and makes clear the sense in which nbsp aliases with the blank page T13 in LoF generalizes C2 as follows Any primary algebra or sentential logic formula B can be viewed as an ordered tree with branches Then T13 A subformula A can be copied at will into any depth of B greater than that of A as long as A and its copy are in the same branch of B Also given multiple instances of A in the same branch of B all instances but the shallowest are redundant While a proof of T13 would require induction the intuition underlying it should be clear C2 or its equivalent is named Generation in LoF Exclusion in Johnson 1892 Pervasion in the work of William Bricken Perhaps the first instance of an axiom or rule with the power of C2 was the Rule of De Iteration combining T13 and AA A of C S Peirce s existential graphs LoF asserts that concatenation can be read as commuting and associating by default and hence need not be explicitly assumed or demonstrated Peirce made a similar assertion about his existential graphs Let a period be a temporary notation to establish grouping That concatenation commutes and associates may then be demonstrated from the Initial AC D CD A and the consequence AA A Byrne 1946 This result holds for all lattices because AA A is an easy consequence of the absorption law which holds for all lattices Initials AC D AD C and J0 Since J0 holds only for lattices with a lower bound this method holds only for bounded lattices which include the primary algebra and 2 Commutativity is trivial just set A nbsp Associativity AC D CA D CD A A CD Having demonstrated associativity the period can be discarded The initials in Meguire 2011 are AC D CD A called B1 B2 J0 above B3 J1a above and B4 C2 By design these initials are very similar to the axioms for an abelian group G1 G3 below Proof theory edit The primary algebra contains three kinds of proved assertions Consequence is a primary algebra equation verified by a demonstration A demonstration consists of a sequence of steps each step justified by an initial or a previously demonstrated consequence Theorem is a statement in the metalanguage verified by a proof i e an argument formulated in the metalanguage that is accepted by trained mathematicians and logicians Initial defined above Demonstrations and proofs invoke an initial as if it were an axiom The distinction between consequence and theorem holds for all formal systems including mathematics and logic but is usually not made explicit A demonstration or decision procedure can be carried out and verified by computer The proof of a theorem cannot be Let A and B be primary algebra formulas A demonstration of A B may proceed in either of two ways Modify A in steps until B is obtained or vice versa Simplify both nbsp and nbsp to nbsp This is known as a calculation Once A B has been demonstrated A B can be invoked to justify steps in subsequent demonstrations primary algebra demonstrations and calculations often require no more than J1a J2 C2 and the consequences nbsp C3 in LoF nbsp C1 and AA A C5 The consequence nbsp C7 inLoF enables an algorithm sketched inLoFs proof of T14 that transforms an arbitrary primary algebra formula to an equivalent formula whose depth does not exceed two The result is a normal form the primary algebra analog of the conjunctive normal form LoF T14 15 proves the primary algebra analog of the well known Boolean algebra theorem that every formula has a normal form Let A be a subformula of some formula B When paired with C3 J1a can be viewed as the closure condition for calculations B is a tautology if and only if A and A both appear in depth 0 of B A related condition appears in some versions of natural deduction A demonstration by calculation is often little more than Invoking T13 repeatedly to eliminate redundant subformulae Erasing any subformulae having the form nbsp The last step of a calculation always invokes J1a LoF includes elegant new proofs of the following standard metatheory Completeness all primary algebra consequences are demonstrable from the initials T17 Independence J1 cannot be demonstrated from J2 and vice versa T18 That sentential logic is complete is taught in every first university course in mathematical logic But university courses in Boolean algebra seldom mention the completeness of 2 Interpretations edit If the Marked and Unmarked states are read as the Boolean values 1 and 0 or True and False the primary algebra interprets 2 or sentential logic LoF shows how the primary algebra can interpret the syllogism Each of these interpretations is discussed in a subsection below Extending the primary algebra so that it could interpret standard first order logic has yet to be done but Peirce s beta existential graphs suggest that this extension is feasible Two element Boolean algebra 2 edit The primary algebra is an elegant minimalist notation for the two element Boolean algebra 2 Let One of Boolean join or meet interpret concatenation The complement of A interpret nbsp 0 1 interpret the empty Mark if join meet interprets concatenation because a binary operation applied to zero operands may be regarded as being equal to the identity element of that operation or to put it in another way an operand that is missing could be regarded as acting by default like the identity element If join meet interprets AC then meet join interprets A C displaystyle overline overline A overline C Big nbsp Hence the primary algebra and 2 are isomorphic but for one detail primary algebra complementation can be nullary in which case it denotes a primitive value Modulo this detail 2 is a model of the primary algebra The primary arithmetic suggests the following arithmetic axiomatization of 2 1 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 and 0 0 0 1 The set B displaystyle B nbsp nbsp displaystyle nbsp nbsp displaystyle nbsp is the Boolean domain or carrier In the language of universal algebra the primary algebra is the algebraic structure B displaystyle langle B overline overline rangle nbsp of type 2 1 0 displaystyle langle 2 1 0 rangle nbsp The expressive adequacy of the Sheffer stroke points to the primary algebra also being a B displaystyle langle B overline overline rangle nbsp algebra of type 2 0 displaystyle langle 2 0 rangle nbsp In both cases the identities are J1a J0 C2 and ACD CDA Since the primary algebra and 2 are isomorphic 2 can be seen as a B 1 displaystyle langle B lnot 1 rangle nbsp algebra of type 2 1 0 displaystyle langle 2 1 0 rangle nbsp This description of 2 is simpler than the conventional one namely an B 1 0 displaystyle langle B times lnot 1 0 rangle nbsp algebra of type 2 2 1 0 0 displaystyle langle 2 2 1 0 0 rangle nbsp The two possible interpretations are dual to each other in the Boolean sense In Boolean algebra exchanging AND OR and 1 0 throughout an equation yields an equally valid equation The identities remain invariant regardless of which interpretation is chosen so the transformations or modes of calculation remain the same only the interpretation of each form would be different Example J1a is nbsp Interpreting juxtaposition as OR and nbsp as 1 this translates to A A 1 displaystyle neg A lor A 1 nbsp which is true Interpreting juxtaposition as AND and nbsp as 0 this translates to A A 0 displaystyle neg A land A 0 nbsp which is true as well and the dual of A A 1 displaystyle neg A lor A 1 nbsp operator operand duality edit The marked state nbsp is both an operator e g the complement and operand e g the value 1 This can be summarized neatly by defining two functions m x displaystyle m x nbsp and u x displaystyle u x nbsp for the marked and unmarked state respectively let m x 1 max 0 x displaystyle m x 1 max 0 cup x nbsp and u x max 0 x displaystyle u x max 0 cup x nbsp where x displaystyle x nbsp is a possibly empty set of boolean values This reveals that u displaystyle u nbsp is either the value 0 or the OR operator while m displaystyle m nbsp is either the value 1 or the NOR operator depending on whether x displaystyle x nbsp is the empty set or not As noted above there is a dual form of these functions exchanging AND OR and 1 0 Sentential logic edit Let the blank page denote False and let a Cross be read as Not Then the primary arithmetic has the following sentential reading False dd dd nbsp True not False dd nbsp Not True False dd The primary algebra interprets sentential logic as follows A letter represents any given sentential expression Thus nbsp interprets Not A dd nbsp interprets A Or B dd nbsp interprets Not A Or B or If A Then B dd nbsp interprets Not Not A Or Not B or Not If A Then Not B or A And B dd dd dd dd a b a b a b a b both interpret A if and only if B or A is equivalent to B Thus any expression in sentential logic has a primary algebra translation Equivalently the primary algebra interprets sentential logic Given an assignment of every variable to the Marked or Unmarked states this primary algebra translation reduces to a primary arithmetic expression which can be simplified Repeating this exercise for all possible assignments of the two primitive values to each variable reveals whether the original expression is tautological or satisfiable This is an example of a decision procedure one more or less in the spirit of conventional truth tables Given some primary algebra formula containing N variables this decision procedure requires simplifying 2N primary arithmetic formulae For a less tedious decision procedure more in the spirit of Quine s truth value analysis see Meguire 2003 Schwartz 1981 proved that the primary algebra is equivalent syntactically semantically and proof theoretically with the classical propositional calculus Likewise it can be shown that the primary algebra is syntactically equivalent with expressions built up in the usual way from the classical truth values true and false the logical connectives NOT OR and AND and parentheses Interpreting the Unmarked State as False is wholly arbitrary that state can equally well be read as True All that is required is that the interpretation of concatenation change from OR to AND IF A THEN B now translates as nbsp instead of nbsp More generally the primary algebra is self dual meaning that any primary algebra formula has two sentential or Boolean readings each the dual of the other Another consequence of self duality is the irrelevance of De Morgan s laws those laws are built into the syntax of the primary algebra from the outset The true nature of the distinction between the primary algebra on the one hand and 2 and sentential logic on the other now emerges In the latter formalisms complementation negation operating on nothing is not well formed But an empty Cross is a well formed primary algebra expression denoting the Marked state a primitive value Hence a nonempty Cross is an operator while an empty Cross is an operand because it denotes a primitive value Thus the primary algebra reveals that the heretofore distinct mathematical concepts of operator and operand are in fact merely different facets of a single fundamental action the making of a distinction Syllogisms edit Appendix 2 of LoF shows how to translate traditional syllogisms and sorites into the primary algebra A valid syllogism is simply one whose primary algebra translation simplifies to an empty Cross Let A denote a literal i e either A or A displaystyle overline A nbsp indifferently Then every syllogism that does not require that one or more terms be assumed nonempty is one of 24 possible permutations of a generalization of Barbara whose primary algebra equivalent is A B B C A C displaystyle overline A B overline overline B C Big A C nbsp These 24 possible permutations include the 19 syllogistic forms deemed valid in Aristotelian and medieval logic This primary algebra translation of syllogistic logic also suggests that the primary algebra can interpret monadic and term logic and that the primary algebra has affinities to the Boolean term schemata of Quine 1982 Part II An example of calculation edit The following calculation of Leibniz s nontrivial Praeclarum Theorema exemplifies the demonstrative power of the primary algebra Let C1 be A displaystyle overline overline A Big nbsp A C2 be A A B A B displaystyle A overline A B A overline B nbsp C3 be A displaystyle overline A overline nbsp J1a be A A displaystyle overline A A overline nbsp and let OI mean that variables and subformulae have been reordered in a way that commutativity and associativity permit P R Q S P Q R S Praeclarum Theorema P R Q S P Q R S primary algebra translation P R Q S P Q R S C1 P R Q S P Q R S C1 P P R Q S Q R S OI P R Q S Q R S C2 P R Q Q S R S OI P R Q S R S C2 P Q S R R S OI P Q S R S C2 P Q S R S C1 P Q S S R OI P Q B R J1a B P Q R OI B C3 displaystyle square nbsp Relation to magmas edit The primary algebra embodies a point noted by Huntington in 1933 Boolean algebra requires in addition to one unary operation one and not two binary operations Hence the seldom noted fact that Boolean algebras are magmas Magmas were called groupoids until the latter term was appropriated by category theory To see this note that the primary algebra is a commutative Semigroup because primary algebra juxtaposition commutes and associates Monoid with identity element nbsp by virtue of J0 Groups also require a unary operation called inverse the group counterpart of Boolean complementation Let nbsp denote the inverse of a Let nbsp denote the group identity element Then groups and the primary algebra have the same signatures namely they are both displaystyle langle overline overline rangle nbsp algebras of type 2 1 0 Hence the primary algebra is a boundary algebra The axioms for an abelian group in boundary notation are G1 abc acb assuming association from the left G2 nbsp G3 nbsp From G1 and G2 the commutativity and associativity of concatenation may be derived as above Note that G3 and J1a are identical G2 and J0 would be identical if nbsp nbsp replaced A2 This is the defining arithmetical identity of group theory in boundary notation The primary algebra differs from an abelian group in two ways From A2 it follows that nbsp nbsp If the primary algebra were a group nbsp nbsp would hold and one of nbsp a nbsp or a nbsp a would have to be a primary algebra consequence Note that nbsp and nbsp are mutual primary algebra complements as group theory requires so that displaystyle overline overline overline Big Bigg overline nbsp is true of both group theory and the primary algebra C2 most clearly demarcates the primary algebra from other magmas because C2 enables demonstrating the absorption law that defines lattices and the distributive law central to Boolean algebra Both A2 and C2 follow from B s being an ordered set Equations of the second degree Chapter 11 editChapter 11 of LoF introduces equations of the second degree composed of recursive formulae that can be seen as having infinite depth Some recursive formulae simplify to the marked or unmarked state Others oscillate indefinitely between the two states depending on whether a given depth is even or odd Specifically certain recursive formulae can be interpreted as oscillating between true and false over successive intervals of time in which case a formula is deemed to have an imaginary truth value Thus the flow of time may be introduced into the primary algebra Turney 1986 shows how these recursive formulae can be interpreted via Alonzo Church s Restricted Recursive Arithmetic RRA Church introduced RRA in 1955 as an axiomatic formalization of finite automata Turney 1986 presents a general method for translating equations of the second degree into Church s RRA illustrating his method using the formulae E1 E2 and E4 in chapter 11 of LoF This translation into RRA sheds light on the names Spencer Brown gave to E1 and E4 namely memory and counter RRA thus formalizes and clarifies LoF s notion of an imaginary truth value Related work editGottfried Leibniz in memoranda not published before the late 19th and early 20th centuries invented Boolean logic His notation was isomorphic to that of LoF concatenation read as conjunction and non X read as the complement of X Recognition of Leibniz s pioneering role in algebraic logic was foreshadowed by Lewis 1918 and Rescher 1954 But a full appreciation of Leibniz s accomplishments had to await the work of Wolfgang Lenzen published in the 1980s and reviewed in Lenzen 2004 Charles Sanders Peirce 1839 1914 anticipated the primary algebra in three veins of work Two papers he wrote in 1886 proposed a logical algebra employing but one symbol the streamer nearly identical to the Cross of LoF The semantics of the streamer are identical to those of the Cross except that Peirce never wrote a streamer with nothing under it An excerpt from one of these papers was published in 1976 9 but they were not published in full until 1993 10 In a 1902 encyclopedia article 11 Peirce notated Boolean algebra and sentential logic in the manner of this entry except that he employed two styles of brackets toggling between and with each increment in formula depth The syntax of his alpha existential graphs is merely concatenation read as conjunction and enclosure by ovals read as negation 12 If primary algebra concatenation is read as conjunction then these graphs are isomorphic to the primary algebra Kauffman 2001 Ironically LoF cites vol 4 of Peirce s Collected Papers the source for the formalisms in 2 and 3 above 1 3 were virtually unknown at the time when 1960s and in the place where UK LoF was written Peirce s semiotics about which LoF is silent may yet shed light on the philosophical aspects of LoF Kauffman 2001 discusses another notation similar to that of LoF that of a 1917 article by Jean Nicod who was a disciple of Bertrand Russell s The above formalisms are like the primary algebra all instances of boundary mathematics i e mathematics whose syntax is limited to letters and brackets enclosing devices A minimalist syntax of this nature is a boundary notation Boundary notation is free of infix operators prefix or postfix operator symbols The very well known curly braces of set theory can be seen as a boundary notation The work of Leibniz Peirce and Nicod is innocent of metatheory as they wrote before Emil Post s landmark 1920 paper which LoF cites proving that sentential logic is complete and before Hilbert and Lukasiewicz showed how to prove axiom independence using models Craig 1979 argued that the world and how humans perceive and interact with that world has a rich Boolean structure Craig was an orthodox logician and an authority on algebraic logic Second generation cognitive science emerged in the 1970s after LoF was written On cognitive science and its relevance to Boolean algebra logic and set theory see Lakoff 1987 see index entries under Image schema examples container and Lakoff and Nunez 2001 Neither book cites LoF The biologists and cognitive scientists Humberto Maturana and his student Francisco Varela both discuss LoF in their writings which identify distinction as the fundamental cognitive act The Berkeley psychologist and cognitive scientist Eleanor Rosch has written extensively on the closely related notion of categorization Other formal systems with possible affinities to the primary algebra include Mereology which typically has a lattice structure very similar to that of Boolean algebra For a few authors mereology is simply a model of Boolean algebra and hence of the primary algebra as well Mereotopology which is inherently richer than Boolean algebra The system of Whitehead 1934 whose fundamental primitive is indication The primary arithmetic and algebra are a minimalist formalism for sentential logic and Boolean algebra Other minimalist formalisms having the power of set theory include The lambda calculus Combinatory logic with two S and K or even one X primitive combinators Mathematical logic done with merely three primitive notions one connective NAND whose primary algebra translation is A B displaystyle overline A B nbsp or dually A B displaystyle overline A overline B nbsp universal quantification and one binary atomic formula denoting set membership This is the system of Quine 1951 The beta existential graphs with a single binary predicate denoting set membership This has yet to be explored The alpha graphs mentioned above are a special case of the beta graphs Editions edit1969 London Allen amp Unwin hardcover 1972 Crown Publishers hardcover ISBN 0 517 52776 6 1973 Bantam Books paperback ISBN 0 553 07782 1 1979 E P Dutton paperback ISBN 0 525 47544 3 1994 Portland OR Cognizer Company paperback ISBN 0 9639899 0 1 1997 German translation titled Gesetze der Form Lubeck Bohmeier Verlag ISBN 3 89094 321 7 2008 Bohmeier Verlag Leipzig 5th international edition ISBN 978 3 89094 580 4See also editBoolean algebra Algebraic manipulation of true and false Boolean algebras canonically defined A technical treatment of Boolean algebras Entitative graph Element of the diagrammatic syntax for logic Existential graph Type of diagrammatic or visual notation for logical expressions Mark and space States of a communications signal Programming and Metaprogramming 1968 non fiction book by John C Lilly Propositional calculus Branch of logic Two element Boolean algebra Boolean algebra List of Boolean algebra topicsNotes edit Meguire P 2011 Boundary Algebra A Simpler Approach to Basic Logic and Boolean Algebra Saarbrucken VDM Publishing Ltd 168pp Schonwalder Kuntze Tatjana Wille Katrin Holscher Thomas Spencer Brown George 2009 George Spencer Brown Eine Einfuhrung in dieLaws of Form 2 Auflage Wiesbaden VS Verlag fur Sozialwissenschaften ISBN 978 3 531 16105 1 Felix Lau Die Form der Paradoxie 2005 Carl Auer Verlag ISBN 9783896703521 George Spencer Brown Laws of form 1969 Pub George Allen and Unwin SBN 04 510028 4 Muller Albert 2008 Computing a Reality Heinz von Foerster s Lecture at the A U M Conference in 1973 PDF Constructivist Foundations 4 1 62 69 Beer Stafford 1969 Maths Created Nature 223 5213 1392 1393 Bibcode 1969Natur 223 1392B doi 10 1038 2231392b0 S2CID 5223774 B Banaschewski July 1977 On G Spencer Brown s Laws of Form Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 18 3 507 509 doi 10 1305 ndjfl 1093888028 For a sympathetic evaluation see Kauffman 2001 Qualitative Logic MS 736 c 1886 in Eisele Carolyn ed 1976 The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S Peirce Vol 4 Mathematical Philosophy The Hague Mouton 101 15 1 Qualitative Logic MS 582 1886 in Kloesel Christian et al eds 1993 Writings of Charles S Peirce A Chronological Edition Vol 5 1884 1886 Indiana University Press 323 71 The Logic of Relatives Qualitative and Quantitative MS 584 1886 in Kloesel Christian et al eds 1993 Writings of Charles S Peirce A Chronological Edition Vol 5 1884 1886 Indiana University Press 372 78 Reprinted in Peirce C S 1933 Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce Vol 4 Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds Harvard University Press Paragraphs 378 383 The existential graphs are described at length in Peirce C S 1933 Collected Papers Vol 4 Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds Harvard University Press Paragraphs 347 529 Bibliography editBostock David 1997 Intermediate Logic Oxford Univ Press Byrne Lee 1946 Two Formulations of Boolean Algebra Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 268 71 Craig William 1979 Boolean Logic and the Everyday Physical World Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 52 6 751 78 doi 10 2307 3131383 JSTOR 3131383 David Gries and Schneider F B 1993 A Logical Approach to Discrete Math Springer Verlag William Ernest Johnson 1892 The Logical Calculus Mind 1 n s 3 30 Louis H Kauffman 2001 The Mathematics of C S Peirce Cybernetics and Human Knowing 8 79 110 2006 Reformulating the Map Color Theorem 2006a Laws of Form An Exploration in Mathematics and Foundations Book draft hence big Lenzen Wolfgang 2004 Leibniz s Logic in Gabbay D and Woods J eds The Rise of Modern Logic From Leibniz to Frege Handbook of the History of Logic Vol 3 Amsterdam Elsevier 1 83 Lakoff George 1987 Women Fire and Dangerous Things University of Chicago Press and Rafael E Nunez 2001 Where Mathematics Comes From How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being Basic Books Meguire P G 2003 Discovering Boundary Algebra A Simplified Notation for Boolean Algebra and the Truth Functors International Journal of General Systems 32 25 87 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 106 634 doi 10 1080 0308107031000075690 S2CID 9460101 2011 Boundary Algebra A Simpler Approach to Basic Logic and Boolean Algebra VDM Publishing Ltd ISBN 978 3639367492 The source for much of this entry including the notation which encloses in parentheses what LoF places under a cross Steers clear of the more speculative aspects of LoF Willard Quine 1951 Mathematical Logic 2nd ed Harvard University Press 1982 Methods of Logic 4th ed Harvard University Press Rescher Nicholas 1954 Leibniz s Interpretation of His Logical Calculi Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 1 1 13 doi 10 2307 2267644 JSTOR 2267644 S2CID 689315 Schwartz Daniel G 1981 Isomorphisms of G Spencer Brown s Laws of Form and F Varela s Calculus for Self Reference International Journal of General Systems 6 4 239 55 doi 10 1080 03081078108934802 Turney P D 1986 Laws of Form and Finite Automata International Journal of General Systems 12 4 307 18 doi 10 1080 03081078608934939 A N Whitehead 1934 Indication classes number validation Mind 43 n s 281 97 543 The corrigenda on p 543 are numerous and important and later reprints of this article do not incorporate them Dirk Baecker ed 1993 Kalkul der Form Suhrkamp Dirk Baecker ed Probleme der Form Suhrkamp Dirk Baecker ed 1999 Problems of Form Stanford University Press Dirk Baecker ed 2013 A Mathematics of Form A Sociology of Observers Cybernetics amp Human Knowing vol 20 no 3 4 Louis H Kauffman ed 2019 Cybernetics amp Human Knowing vol 26 no 2 3 Special Issue Laws of Form Spencer Brown at Esalen 1973 External links editLaws of Form archive of website by Richard Shoup Spencer Brown s talks at Esalen 1973 Self referential forms are introduced in the section entitled Degree of Equations and the Theory of Types Audio recording of the opening session 1973 AUM Conference at Esalen Louis H Kauffman Box Algebra Boundary Mathematics Logic and Laws of Form Kissel Matthias A nonsystematic but easy to understand introduction to Laws of Form The Laws of Form Forum where the primary algebra and related formalisms have been discussed since 2002 A meeting with G S B by Moshe Klein The Markable Mark an introduction by easy stages to the ideas of Laws of Form The BF Calculus and the Square Root of Negation by Louis Kauffman and Arthur Collings it extends the Laws of Form by adding an imaginary logical value Imaginary logical values are introduced in chapter 11 of the book Laws of Form Laws of Form Course a free on line course taking people through the main body of the text of Laws of Form by Leon Conrad Spencer Brown s last student who studied the work with the author Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Laws of Form amp oldid 1213407896, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.