fbpx
Wikipedia

Kruskal's tree theorem

In mathematics, Kruskal's tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well-quasi-ordered set of labels is itself well-quasi-ordered under homeomorphic embedding.

History

The theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vázsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal (1960); a short proof was given by Crispin Nash-Williams (1963). It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved within ATR0 (a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion), and a finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast-growing TREE function.

In 2004, the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson–Seymour theorem, a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even-faster-growing SSCG function which dwarfs TREE(3).

Statement

The version given here is that proven by Nash-Williams; Kruskal's formulation is somewhat stronger. All trees we consider are finite.

Given a tree T with a root, and given vertices v, w, call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v, and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex.

Take X to be a partially ordered set. If T1, T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X, we say that T1 is inf-embeddable in T2 and write T1T2 if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that

  • For all vertices v of T1, the label of v precedes the label of F(v),
  • If w is any successor of v in T1, then F(w) is a successor of F(v), and
  • If w1, w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v, then the path from F(w1) to F(w2) in T2 contains F(v).

Kruskal's tree theorem then states:

If X is well-quasi-ordered, then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well-quasi-ordered under the inf-embeddable order defined above. (That is to say, given any infinite sequence T1, T2, … of rooted trees labeled in X, there is some i < j so that TiTj.)

Weak tree function

Define tree(n), the weak tree function, as the length of the longest sequence of 1-labelled trees (i.e. X = {1}) such that:

  • The tree at position k in the sequence has no more than k + n vertices, for all k.
  • No tree is homeomorphically embeddable into any tree following it in the sequence.

It is known that tree(1) = 1, tree(2) = 2, and tree(3) ≥ 844424930131960, tree(4) > Grahams Number (by a lot)[1][better source needed] but TREE(3) (where the argument specifies the number of labels; see below) is larger than  .

To differentiate the two functions, TREE with all letters capitalized is the big TREE function; tree with all letters in lowercase is the weak tree function.

Friedman's work

For a countable label set  , Kruskal's tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second-order arithmetic. However, like Goodstein's theorem or the Paris–Harrington theorem, some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second-order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved. This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s, an early success of the then-nascent field of reverse mathematics. In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled (that is, in the case where   has order one), Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0,[2] thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof.[3] This case of the theorem is still provable by Π1
1
-CA0, but by adding a "gap condition"[4] to the definition of the order on trees above, he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system.[5][6] Much later, the Robertson–Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by Π1
1
-CA0.

Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal's theorem, with the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal (sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal).[citation needed]

TREE(3)

Suppose that P(n) is the statement:

There is some m such that if T1,...,Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Tk has n+k vertices, then Ti ≤ Tj for some i < j.

All the statements P(n) are true as a consequence of Kruskal's theorem and Kőnig's lemma. For each n, Peano arithmetic can prove that P(n) is true, but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement "P(n) is true for all n".[7] Moreover the length of the shortest proof of P(n) in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n, far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function for example. The least m for which P(n) holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n.

By incorporating labels, Friedman defined a far faster-growing function.[8] For a positive integer n, take TREE(n)[*] to be the largest m so that we have the following:

There is a sequence T1,...,Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels, where each Ti has at most i vertices, such that Ti  ≤  Tj does not hold for any i < j  ≤ m.

The TREE sequence begins TREE(1) = 1, TREE(2) = 3, then suddenly TREE(3) explodes to a value that is so big that many other "large" combinatorial constants, such as Friedman's n(4), nn(5)(5), and Graham's Number, [**] are extremely small by comparison. . A lower bound for n(4), and hence an extremely weak lower bound for TREE(3), is AA(187196)(1),[9] where A(x) taking one argument, is defined as A(x, x), where A(k, n), taking two arguments, is a particular version of Ackermann's function defined as: A(1, n) = 2n, A(k+1, 1) = A(k, 1), A(k+1, n+1) = A(k, A(k+1, n)). Graham's number, for example, is much smaller than the lower bound AA(187196)(1). It can be shown that the growth-rate of the function TREE is at least   in the fast-growing hierarchy. AA(187196)(1) is approximately  , where gx is Graham's function. Using finite arithmetic, the amount of symbols needed to prove TREE(3) is finite is 2↑↑1000 .

See also

Notes

^ * Friedman originally denoted this function by TR[n].
^ ** n(k) is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k-letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi,...,x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj,...,x2j.[10]  .

References

Citations
  1. ^ "TREE sequence". Googology Wiki | Fandom. Retrieved 9 July 2020.
  2. ^ Simpson 1985, Theorem 1.8
  3. ^ Friedman 2002, p. 60
  4. ^ Simpson 1985, Definition 4.1
  5. ^ Simpson 1985, Theorem 5.14
  6. ^ Marcone 2001, p. 8–9
  7. ^ Smith 1985, p. 120
  8. ^ Friedman, Harvey (28 March 2006). "273:Sigma01/optimal/size". Ohio State University Department of Maths. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
  9. ^ Friedman, Harvey M. (1 June 2000). "Enormous Integers In Real Life" (PDF). Ohio State University. Retrieved 8 August 2017.
  10. ^ Friedman, Harvey M. (8 October 1998). "Long Finite Sequences" (PDF). Ohio State University Department of Mathematics. pp. 5, 48 (Thm.6.8). Retrieved 8 August 2017.
Bibliography
  • Friedman, Harvey M. (2002), Internal finite tree embeddings. Reflections on the foundations of mathematics (Stanford, CA, 1998), Lect. Notes Log., vol. 15, Urbana, IL: Assoc. Symbol. Logic, pp. 60–91, MR 1943303
  • Gallier, Jean H. (1991), "What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γ0? A survey of some results in proof theory" (PDF), Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 53 (3): 199–260, doi:10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E, MR 1129778
  • Kruskal, J. B. (May 1960), "Well-quasi-ordering, the tree theorem, and Vazsonyi's conjecture" (PDF), Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, American Mathematical Society, 95 (2): 210–225, doi:10.2307/1993287, JSTOR 1993287, MR 0111704
  • Marcone, Alberto (2001). "Wqo and bqo theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic" (PDF). Reverse Mathematics. 21: 303–330.
  • Nash-Williams, C. St.J. A. (1963), "On well-quasi-ordering finite trees", Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc., 59 (4): 833–835, Bibcode:1963PCPS...59..833N, doi:10.1017/S0305004100003844, MR 0153601, S2CID 251095188
  • Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60 (1): 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-g.
  • Simpson, Stephen G. (1985), "Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees", in Harrington, L. A.; Morley, M.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.), Harvey Friedman's Research on the Foundations of Mathematics, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North-Holland, pp. 87–117
  • Smith, Rick L. (1985), "The consistency strengths of some finite forms of the Higman and Kruskal theorems", in Harrington, L. A.; Morley, M.; Scedrov, A.; et al. (eds.), Harvey Friedman's Research on the Foundations of Mathematics, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North-Holland, pp. 119–136

kruskal, tree, theorem, mathematics, states, that, finite, trees, over, well, quasi, ordered, labels, itself, well, quasi, ordered, under, homeomorphic, embedding, contents, history, statement, weak, tree, function, friedman, work, tree, also, notes, reference. In mathematics Kruskal s tree theorem states that the set of finite trees over a well quasi ordered set of labels is itself well quasi ordered under homeomorphic embedding Contents 1 History 2 Statement 3 Weak tree function 4 Friedman s work 4 1 TREE 3 5 See also 6 Notes 7 ReferencesHistory EditThe theorem was conjectured by Andrew Vazsonyi and proved by Joseph Kruskal 1960 a short proof was given by Crispin Nash Williams 1963 It has since become a prominent example in reverse mathematics as a statement that cannot be proved within ATR0 a form of arithmetical transfinite recursion and a finitary application of the theorem gives the existence of the fast growing TREE function In 2004 the result was generalized from trees to graphs as the Robertson Seymour theorem a result that has also proved important in reverse mathematics and leads to the even faster growing SSCG function which dwarfs TREE 3 Statement EditThe version given here is that proven by Nash Williams Kruskal s formulation is somewhat stronger All trees we consider are finite Given a tree T with a root and given vertices v w call w a successor of v if the unique path from the root to w contains v and call w an immediate successor of v if additionally the path from v to w contains no other vertex Take X to be a partially ordered set If T1 T2 are rooted trees with vertices labeled in X we say that T1 is inf embeddable in T2 and write T1 T2 if there is an injective map F from the vertices of T1 to the vertices of T2 such that For all vertices v of T1 the label of v precedes the label of F v If w is any successor of v in T1 then F w is a successor of F v and If w1 w2 are any two distinct immediate successors of v then the path from F w1 to F w2 in T2 contains F v Kruskal s tree theorem then states If X is well quasi ordered then the set of rooted trees with labels in X is well quasi ordered under the inf embeddable order defined above That is to say given any infinite sequence T1 T2 of rooted trees labeled in X there is some i lt j so that Ti Tj Weak tree function EditDefine tree n the weak tree function as the length of the longest sequence of 1 labelled trees i e X 1 such that The tree at position k in the sequence has no more than k n vertices for all k No tree is homeomorphically embeddable into any tree following it in the sequence It is known that tree 1 1 tree 2 2 and tree 3 844424930131960 tree 4 gt Grahams Number by a lot 1 better source needed but TREE 3 where the argument specifies the number of labels see below is larger than t r e e t r e e t r e e t r e e t r e e 8 7 7 7 7 7 displaystyle mathrm tree mathrm tree mathrm tree mathrm tree mathrm tree 8 7 7 7 7 7 To differentiate the two functions TREE with all letters capitalized is the big TREE function tree with all letters in lowercase is the weak tree function Friedman s work EditFor a countable label set X displaystyle X Kruskal s tree theorem can be expressed and proven using second order arithmetic However like Goodstein s theorem or the Paris Harrington theorem some special cases and variants of the theorem can be expressed in subsystems of second order arithmetic much weaker than the subsystems where they can be proved This was first observed by Harvey Friedman in the early 1980s an early success of the then nascent field of reverse mathematics In the case where the trees above are taken to be unlabeled that is in the case where X displaystyle X has order one Friedman found that the result was unprovable in ATR0 2 thus giving the first example of a predicative result with a provably impredicative proof 3 This case of the theorem is still provable by P11 CA0 but by adding a gap condition 4 to the definition of the order on trees above he found a natural variation of the theorem unprovable in this system 5 6 Much later the Robertson Seymour theorem would give another theorem unprovable by P11 CA0 Ordinal analysis confirms the strength of Kruskal s theorem with the proof theoretic ordinal of the theorem equaling the small Veblen ordinal sometimes confused with the smaller Ackermann ordinal citation needed TREE 3 Edit Suppose that P n is the statement There is some m such that if T1 Tm is a finite sequence of unlabeled rooted trees where Tk has n k vertices then Ti Tj for some i lt j All the statements P n are true as a consequence of Kruskal s theorem and Konig s lemma For each n Peano arithmetic can prove that P n is true but Peano arithmetic cannot prove the statement P n is true for all n 7 Moreover the length of the shortest proof of P n in Peano arithmetic grows phenomenally fast as a function of n far faster than any primitive recursive function or the Ackermann function for example The least m for which P n holds similarly grows extremely quickly with n By incorporating labels Friedman defined a far faster growing function 8 For a positive integer n take TREE n to be the largest m so that we have the following There is a sequence T1 Tm of rooted trees labelled from a set of n labels where each Ti has at most i vertices such that Ti Tj does not hold for any i lt j m The TREE sequence begins TREE 1 1 TREE 2 3 then suddenly TREE 3 explodes to a value that is so big that many other large combinatorial constants such as Friedman s n 4 nn 5 5 and Graham s Number are extremely small by comparison A lower bound for n 4 and hence an extremely weak lower bound for TREE 3 is AA 187196 1 9 where A x taking one argument is defined as A x x where A k n taking two arguments is a particular version of Ackermann s function defined as A 1 n 2n A k 1 1 A k 1 A k 1 n 1 A k A k 1 n Graham s number for example is much smaller than the lower bound AA 187196 1 It can be shown that the growth rate of the function TREE is at least f 8 W w w displaystyle f theta Omega omega omega in the fast growing hierarchy AA 187196 1 is approximately g 3 187196 3 displaystyle g 3 uparrow 187196 3 where gx is Graham s function Using finite arithmetic the amount of symbols needed to prove TREE 3 is finite is 2 1000 See also EditParis Harrington theorem Kanamori McAloon theorem Robertson Seymour theoremNotes Edit Friedman originally denoted this function by TR n n k is defined as the length of the longest possible sequence that can be constructed with a k letter alphabet such that no block of letters xi x2i is a subsequence of any later block xj x2j 10 n 1 3 n 2 11 and n 3 gt 2 7197 158386 displaystyle n 1 3 n 2 11 textrm and n 3 gt 2 uparrow 7197 158386 References EditCitations TREE sequence Googology Wiki Fandom Retrieved 9 July 2020 Simpson 1985 Theorem 1 8 Friedman 2002 p 60 Simpson 1985 Definition 4 1 Simpson 1985 Theorem 5 14 Marcone 2001 p 8 9 Smith 1985 p 120 Friedman Harvey 28 March 2006 273 Sigma01 optimal size Ohio State University Department of Maths Retrieved 8 August 2017 Friedman Harvey M 1 June 2000 Enormous Integers In Real Life PDF Ohio State University Retrieved 8 August 2017 Friedman Harvey M 8 October 1998 Long Finite Sequences PDF Ohio State University Department of Mathematics pp 5 48 Thm 6 8 Retrieved 8 August 2017 BibliographyFriedman Harvey M 2002 Internal finite tree embeddings Reflections on the foundations of mathematics Stanford CA 1998 Lect Notes Log vol 15 Urbana IL Assoc Symbol Logic pp 60 91 MR 1943303 Gallier Jean H 1991 What s so special about Kruskal s theorem and the ordinal G0 A survey of some results in proof theory PDF Ann Pure Appl Logic 53 3 199 260 doi 10 1016 0168 0072 91 90022 E MR 1129778 Kruskal J B May 1960 Well quasi ordering the tree theorem and Vazsonyi s conjecture PDF Transactions of the American Mathematical Society American Mathematical Society 95 2 210 225 doi 10 2307 1993287 JSTOR 1993287 MR 0111704 Marcone Alberto 2001 Wqo and bqo theory in subsystems of second order arithmetic PDF Reverse Mathematics 21 303 330 Nash Williams C St J A 1963 On well quasi ordering finite trees Proc Camb Phil Soc 59 4 833 835 Bibcode 1963PCPS 59 833N doi 10 1017 S0305004100003844 MR 0153601 S2CID 251095188 Rathjen Michael Weiermann Andreas 1993 Proof theoretic investigations on Kruskal s theorem Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 60 1 49 88 doi 10 1016 0168 0072 93 90192 g Simpson Stephen G 1985 Nonprovability of certain combinatorial properties of finite trees in Harrington L A Morley M Scedrov A et al eds Harvey Friedman s Research on the Foundations of Mathematics Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics North Holland pp 87 117 Smith Rick L 1985 The consistency strengths of some finite forms of the Higman and Kruskal theorems in Harrington L A Morley M Scedrov A et al eds Harvey Friedman s Research on the Foundations of Mathematics Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics North Holland pp 119 136 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Kruskal 27s tree theorem amp oldid 1144718933, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.