fbpx
Wikipedia

Chrysippus

Chrysippus of Soli (/krˈsɪpəs, krɪ-/;[1] Greek: Χρύσιππος ὁ Σολεύς, Chrysippos ho Soleus; c. 279 – c. 206 BC[a]) was a Greek Stoic philosopher. He was a native of Soli, Cilicia, but moved to Athens as a young man, where he became a pupil of the Stoic philosopher Cleanthes. When Cleanthes died, around 230 BC, Chrysippus became the third head of the Stoic school. A prolific writer, Chrysippus expanded the fundamental doctrines of Cleanthes' mentor Zeno of Citium, the founder and first head of the school, which earned him the title of the Second Founder of Stoicism.[3]

Chrysippus of Soli
Roman copy of a Hellenistic bust of
Chrysippus (British Museum)
Bornc. 279 BCE
Diedc. 206 BC (aged 73)
Cause of deathDeath from laughter (uncertain)
EraHellenistic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolStoicism
Main interests
Notable ideas

Chrysippus excelled in logic, the theory of knowledge, ethics, and physics. He created an original system of propositional logic in order to better understand the workings of the universe and role of humanity within it. He adhered to a fatalistic view of fate, but nevertheless sought a role for personal agency in thought and action. Ethics, he thought, depended on understanding the nature of the universe, and he taught a therapy of extirpating the unruly passions which depress and crush the soul. He initiated the success of Stoicism as one of the most influential philosophical movements for centuries in the Greek and Roman world. The linguistic orientation of Chrysippus' work made it difficult for its students even within the Stoic school.[4]

Of his several written works, none have survived except as fragments.[b] Recently, segments of some of his works were discovered among the Herculaneum papyri.[c]

Life edit

Chrysippus was the son of Apollonius of Tarsus, and he was born at Soli, Cilicia.[7] He was slight in stature,[8] and is reputed to have trained as a long-distance runner.[9] While still young, he lost his substantial inherited property when it was confiscated to the king's treasury.[10][d] Chrysippus moved to Athens, where he became the disciple of Cleanthes, who was then the head (scholarch) of the Stoic school.[12][e] He is believed to have attended the courses of Arcesilaus and his successor Lacydes, in the Platonic Academy.[14]

Chrysippus threw himself eagerly into the study of the Stoic system. His reputation for learning among his contemporaries was considerable.[9] He was noted for intellectual audacity and self-confidence and his reliance on his own ability was shown, among other things, in the request he is supposed to have made to Cleanthes: "Give me the principles, and I will find the proofs myself."[9] He succeeded Cleanthes as head of the Stoic school when Cleanthes died, in around 230 BC.

Chrysippus was a prolific writer. He is said to rarely have gone without writing 500 lines a day[15] and he composed more than 705 works.[16] His desire to be comprehensive meant that he would take both sides of an argument[14] and his opponents accused him of filling his books with the quotations of others.[17] He was considered diffuse and obscure in his utterances and careless in his style, but his abilities were highly regarded, and he came to be seen as a preeminent authority for the school.[18]

 
Final moments in the life of Chrysippus. Engraving from 1606.

He died during the 143rd Olympiad (208–204 BC) at the age of 73.[2] Diogenes Laërtius gives two different accounts of his death.[19] In the first account, Chrysippus was seized with dizziness having drunk undiluted wine at a feast, and died soon after. In the second account, he was watching a donkey eat some figs and cried out: "Now give the donkey a drink of pure wine to wash down the figs", whereupon he died in a fit of laughter. His nephew Aristocreon erected a statue in his honour in the Kerameikos.[20] Chrysippus was succeeded as head of the Stoic school by his pupil Zeno of Tarsus.[21]

Of his written works, none survived except as fragments quoted in the works of later authors like Cicero, Seneca, Galen, Plutarch, and others. Recently, segments from Logical Questions and On Providence were discovered among the Herculaneum papyri.[6] A third work by Chrysippus may also be among them.[6]

Study edit

Chrysippus had a long and successful career of resisting the attacks of the Academy[22] and hoped not simply to defend Stoicism against the assaults of the past, but also against all possible attack in the future. He took the doctrines of Zeno and Cleanthes and crystallized them into what became the definitive system of Stoicism.[22] He elaborated the physical doctrines of the Stoics and their theory of knowledge[18] and he created much of their formal logic.[23] In short, Chrysippus made the Stoic system what it was. It was said that "without Chrysippus, there would have been no Stoa".[f]

Logic edit

Chrysippus wrote much on the subject of logic and created a system of propositional logic. Aristotle's term logic had been concerned with the interrelations of terms such as "Socrates" or "man" ("all men are mortal, Socrates is a man, so Socrates is mortal"). Stoic logic, on the other hand, was concerned with the interrelations of propositions such as "it is day" ("if it is day, it is light: but it is day: so it is light").[25][26] Though the earlier Megarian dialecticians – Diodorus Cronus and Philo – had worked in this field and the pupils of Aristotle – Theophrastus and Eudemus – had investigated hypothetical syllogisms,[27] it was Chrysippus who developed these principles into a coherent system of propositional logic.[27][28]

Propositions edit

Chrysippus defined a proposition as "that which is capable of being denied or affirmed as it is in itself" and gave examples of propositions such as "it is day" and "Dion is walking."[29][30] He distinguished between simple and non-simple propositions, which in modern terminology are known as atomic and molecular propositions.[27] A simple proposition is an elementary statement such as "it is day."[31] Simple propositions are linked together to form non-simple propositions by the use of logical connectives. Chrysippus enumerated five kinds of molecular propositions according to the connective used:[31]

Logical connectives
Type Example
if if it is day, it is light
and it is day and it is light
either ... or either it is day or it is night
because because it is day, it is light
more/less likely ... than more likely it is day than it is night

Thus several types of molecular propositions, familiar to modern logic, were listed by Chrysippus, including the conjunction, the disjunction, and the conditional,[32] and Chrysippus studied their criteria of truth closely.[32]

Conditional propositions edit

The first logicians to debate conditional statements were Diodorus Cronus and his pupil Philo. Writing five-hundred years later, Sextus Empiricus refers to a debate between Diodorus and Philo.[33] Philo regarded all conditionals as true except those which with a correct antecedent had an incorrect consequent, and this meant a proposition such as "if it is day, then I am talking," is true unless it is day and I fall silent.[34] But Diodorus argued that a true conditional is one in which the antecedent clause could never lead to an untrue conclusion – thus, because the proposition "if it is day, then I am talking" can be false, it is invalid.[33] However, paradoxical propositions were still possible such as "if atomic elements of things do not exist, atomic elements exists."[34] Chrysippus adopted a much stricter view regarding conditional propositions, which made such paradoxes impossible:[g] to him, a conditional is true if denial of the consequent is logically incompatible with the antecedent.[36] This corresponds to the modern-day strict conditional.[36]

Syllogistic edit

Chrysippus developed a syllogistic or system of deduction in which he made use of five types of basic arguments or argument forms called indemonstrable syllogisms,[37] which played the role of axioms, and four inference rules, called themata by means of which complex syllogisms could be reduced to these axioms.[38][39] The forms of the five indemonstrables were:[40][41]

Name[h] Description Example
Modus ponens If A, then B.  A.  Therefore, B. If it is day, it is light. It is day. Therefore, it is light.
Modus tollens If A, then B.  Not B.  Therefore, not A. If it is day, it is light. It is not light. Therefore, it is not day.
Modus ponendo tollens  i Not both A and B.  A.  Therefore, not B.  It is not both day and night. It is day. Therefore, it is not night. 
ii Either A or B.  A.  Therefore, not B. It is either day or night. It is day. Therefore, it is not night.
Modus tollendo ponens Either A or B.  Not A.  Therefore, B. It is either day or night. It is not day. Therefore, it is night.

Of the four inference rules (themata, θέματα),[43] only two survived. One, the so-called first thema, was a rule of antilogism. The other, the third thema, was a cut rule by which chain syllogisms could be reduced to simple syllogisms.[44][45] The purpose of Stoic syllogistic was not merely to create a formal system. It was also understood as the study of the operations of reason, the divine reason (logos) which governs the universe, of which human beings are a part.[46] The goal was to find valid rules of inference and forms of proof to help people find their way in life.[27]

 
Chrysippus argued dogs reason.

According to Sextus Empiricus, Chrysippus held that dogs use disjunctive syllogism, such as when using scent to pick which path to run down. This was in contrast to a tradition since Aristotle, who saw reasoning (and reasoning deductively) as man's defining aspect.[47]

Other logical work edit

Chrysippus analyzed speech and the handling of names and terms.[18] He also devoted much effort in refuting fallacies and paradoxes.[18] According to Diogenes Laërtius, Chrysippus wrote twelve works in 23 books on the Liar paradox; seven works in 17 books on amphiboly; and another nine works in 26 books on other conundrums.[48] In all, 28 works or 66 books were given over to puzzles or paradoxes.[48] Chrysippus is the first Stoic for whom the third of the four Stoic categories, i.e. the category somehow disposed is attested.[49] In the surviving evidence, Chrysippus frequently makes use of the categories of substance and quality, but makes little use of the other two Stoic categories (somehow disposed and somehow disposed in relation to something).[50] It is not clear whether the categories had any special significance for Chrysippus, and a clear doctrine of categories may be the work of later Stoics.[50]

Later reception edit

Chrysippus came to be renowned as one of the foremost logicians of ancient Greece. When Clement of Alexandria wanted to mention one who was master among logicians, as Homer was master among poets, it was Chrysippus, not Aristotle, he chose.[51] Diogenes Laërtius wrote: "If the gods use dialectic, they would use none other than that of Chrysippus."[52] The logical work by Chrysippus came to be neglected and forgotten. Aristotle's logic prevailed, partly because it was seen as more practical, and partly because it was taken up by the Neoplatonists.[46] As recently as the 19th century, Stoic logic was treated with contempt, a barren formulaic system, which was merely clothing the logic of Aristotle with new terminology.[53] It was not until the 20th century, with the advances in logic, and the modern propositional calculus, that it became clear that Stoic logic constituted a significant achievement.[27]

Epistemology edit

For the Stoics, truth is distinguished from error by the sage who possesses right reason.[54] Chrysippus's theory of knowledge was empirical.[55] The senses transmit messages from the external world, and their reports are controlled not by referring them to innate ideas, but by comparing them to previous reports stored in the mind.[55] Zeno had defined impressions of sense as "an impression in the soul"[56] and this was interpreted literally by Cleanthes, who compared the impression on the soul to the impression made by a seal on wax.[57] Chrysippus preferred to regard it as an alteration or change in the soul;[56] that is, the soul receives a modification from every external object that acts upon it, just as the air receives countless strokes when many people are speaking at once.[56]

In the receipt of an impression, the soul is purely passive and the impression reveals not only its own existence, but that also of its cause – just as light displays itself and the elements that are in it.[56] The power to name the object resides in the understanding. First must come the impression, and the understanding – having the power of utterance – expresses in speech the affection it receives from the object.[58] True presentations are distinguished from those that are false by the use of memory, classification and comparison.[55] If the sense organ and the mind are healthy – and provided that an external object can be really seen or heard – the presentation, due to its clearness and distinctness, has the power to extort the assent that always lies in our power, to give or to withhold.[59] In a context in which people are understood to be rational beings, reason is developed out of these notions.[60]

Physics edit

 
A partial marble bust of Chrysippus that is a Roman copy of a Hellenistic original (Louvre Museum).

Chrysippus insisted on the organic unity of the universe, as well as the correlation and mutual interdependence of all of its parts.[61] He said, the universe is "the soul and guide of itself."[62] Following Zeno, Chrysippus determined fiery breath or aether to be the primitive substance of the universe.[63] Objects are made up of inert formless matter and an informing soul, "pneuma", provides form to the undifferentiated matter.[64] The pneuma pervades all of substance and maintains the unity of the universe and constitutes the soul of the human being.[64]

The classical elements change into one another by a process of condensation and rarefaction.[65] Fire first becomes solidified into air; then air into water; and lastly, water into earth. The process of dissolution takes place in the reverse order: earth being rarefied into water, water into air and air into fire.[65]

The human soul was divided by Chrysippus into eight faculties: the five senses, the power of reproduction, the power of speech, and the "ruling part" that is located in the chest rather than the head.[66] Individual souls are perishable; but, according to the view originated by Chrysippus, the souls of wise people survive longer after their death.[66] No individual soul can, however, survive beyond the periodic conflagration, when the universe is renewed.[66]

There were no universals or abstract objects for Chrysippus, making him a kind of nominalist.[i]

Fate edit

For Chrysippus, all things happen according to fate: what seems to be accidental has always some hidden cause.[69] The unity of the world consists in the chain-like dependence of cause upon cause.[70] Nothing can take place without a sufficient cause.[71] According to Chrysippus, every proposition is either true or false, and this must apply to future events as well:[72]

If any motion exists without a cause, then not every proposition will be either true or false. For that which has not efficient causes is neither true nor false. But every proposition is either true or false. Therefore, there is no motion without a cause. And if this is so, then all effects owe their existence to prior causes. And if this is so, all things happen by fate. It follows therefore that whatever happens, happens by fate.[73]

The Stoic view of fate is entirely based on a view of the universe as a whole. Individual things and persons only come into consideration as dependent parts of this whole.[74] Everything is, in every respect, determined by this relation, and is consequently subject to the general order of the world.[70]

If his opponents objected that, if everything is determined by destiny, there is no individual responsibility, since what has been once foreordained must happen, come what may, Chrysippus replied that there is a distinction to be made between simple and complex predestination.[75] Becoming ill may be fated whatever happens but, if a person's recovery is linked to consulting a doctor, then consulting the doctor is fated to occur together with that person's recovery, and this becomes a complex fact.[76] All human actions – in fact, our destiny – are decided by our relation to things,[77] or as Chrysippus put it, events are "co-fated" to occur:[76]

The non-destruction of one's coat, he says, is not fated simply, but co-fated with its being taken care of, and someone's being saved from his enemies is co-fated with his fleeing those enemies; and having children is co-fated with being willing to lie with a woman. ... For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur in conjunction with this personal effort. ... But it will be in our power, he says, with what is in our power being included in fate.[78]

Thus our actions are predetermined, and are causally related to the overarching network of fate, but nevertheless the moral responsibility of how we respond to impressions remains our own.[79] The one all-determining power is active everywhere, working in each particular being according to its nature, whether in rational or irrational creatures or in inorganic objects.[80] Every action is brought about by the co-operation of causes depending on the nature of things and the character of the agent.[80] Our actions would only be involuntary if they were produced by external causes alone, without any co-operation, on the part of our wills, with external causes.[80] Virtue and vice are set down as things in our power, for which, consequently, we are responsible.[81] Moral responsibility depends only on freedom of the will, and what emanates from our will is our own, no matter whether it is possible for us to act differently or not.[81] This rather subtle position which attempts to reconcile determinism with human responsibility is known as soft-determinism, or compatibilism.[82]

Divination edit

 
Cleromancy in ancient Greece. Chrysippus accepted divination as part of the causal chain of fate.

Chrysippus also argued for the existence of fate based on divination, which he thought there was good evidence for.[83] It would not be possible for diviners to predict the future if the future itself was accidental.[71] Omens and portents, he believed, are the natural symptoms of certain occurrences.[84] There must be countless indications of the course of providence, for the most part unobserved, the meaning of only a few having become known to humanity.[84] To those who argued that divination was superfluous as all events are foreordained, he replied that both divination and our behaviour under the warnings which it affords are included in the chain of causation.[84]

God edit

The Stoics believed that the universe is God, and Chrysippus affirmed that "the universe itself is God and the universal outpouring of its soul."[85] It is the guiding principle of the universe, "operating in mind and reason, together with the common nature of things and the totality which embraces all existence."[85] Based on these beliefs, physicist and philosopher Max Bernhard Weinstein identified Chrysippus as a Pandeist.[j]

Chrysippus sought to prove the existence of God, making use of a teleological argument:

If there is anything that humanity cannot produce, the being who produces it is better than humanity. But humanity cannot produce the things that are in the universe – the heavenly bodies, etc. The being, therefore, who produces them is superior to humanity. But who is there that is superior to humanity, except God? Therefore, God exists.[87]

Chrysippus spoke of God and gods interchangeably. He interpreted the gods of traditional Greek religion by viewing them as different aspects of the one reality. Cicero tells us that "he further maintained that aether is that which people call Zeus, and that the air which permeates the seas is Poseidon, and that the earth is what is known by the name of Demeter, and he treated in similar style the names of the other gods."[85] In addition, the universe exists for the benefit of the universal god:

We should infer in the case of a beautiful dwelling-place that it was built for its owners and not for mice; we ought, therefore, in the same way to regard the universe as the dwelling-place of the gods.[88]

Theodicy edit

In response to the question of how evil could exist in a good universe, Chrysippus replied "evil cannot be removed, nor is it well that it should be removed."[89] Firstly, he argued, following Plato, that it was impossible for good to exist without evil, for justice could not be known without injustice, courage without cowardice, temperance without intemperance or wisdom without foolishness.[90] Secondly, apparent evils exist as a consequent of nature's goodness, thus it was necessary for the human skull to be made from small and thin bones for reasons of utility, but this superior utility meant that the skull is vulnerable to blows.[90] Thirdly, evils are distributed according to the rational will of Zeus, either to punish the wicked or because they are important to the world-order as a whole.[91] Thus evil is good under disguise, and is ultimately conducive to the best. Chrysippus compared evil to the coarse jest in the comedy; for, just as the jest, though offensive in itself, improves the piece as a whole, "so too you may criticize evil regarded by itself, yet allow that, taken with all else, it has its use."[92]

Mathematics edit

 
The puzzle of Democritus. If a cone is sliced horizontally, are the surfaces produced equal or unequal?

Chrysippus regarded bodies, surfaces, lines, places, the void and time as all being infinitely divisible.[93] He determined one of the principal features of the infinite set: since a man and a finger have an infinite number of parts as do the universe and a man, it cannot be said that a man has more parts than his finger, nor that the universe has more parts than a man.[94]

Chrysippus also responded to a problem first posed by Democritus.[95] If a cone is divided by a plane parallel to its base, are the surfaces of the segments equal or unequal? If they are equal, then the cone becomes a cylinder; if they are unequal, then the surface of the cone must be stepped.[94] The reply of Chrysippus was that the surfaces are both equal and unequal.[96] Chrysippus was, in effect, negating the law of excluded middle with respect to the equal and unequal, and thus he may have anticipated an important principle of modern infinitesimal calculus, namely, the limit and the process of convergence towards a limit.[96]

Chrysippus was notable for claiming that "one" is a number. One was not always considered a number by the ancient Greeks since they viewed one as that by which things are measured. Aristotle in his Metaphysics wrote, "... a measure is not the things measured, but the measure or the One is the beginning of number."[97] Chrysippus asserted that one had "magnitude one" (Greek: πλῆθος ἕν),[98] although this was not generally accepted by the Greeks, and Iamblichus wrote that "magnitude one" was a contradiction in terms.[97]

Ethics edit

 
Greek amphora depicting Euripides' Medea. Chrysippus regarded Medea as a prime example of how bad judgments could give rise to irrational passions.[99][k]

Chrysippus taught that ethics depended on physics. In his Physical Theses, he stated: "for there is no other or more appropriate way of approaching the subject of good and evil on the virtues or happiness than from the nature of all things and the administration of the universe."[100] The goal of life, said Chrysippus, is to live in accordance with one's experience of the actual course of nature.[101] A person's individual nature is part of the nature of the whole universe,[102] and thus life should be lived in accordance with one's own human nature as well as that of the universe.[103] Human nature is ethical, and humanity is akin to the Divine, emanating from the primal fire or aether, which, though material, is the embodiment of reason; and people should conduct themselves accordingly.[104] People have freedom, and this freedom consists in emancipation from irrational desires (lust, riches, position in life, domination, etc.) and in subjecting the will to reason.[104] Chrysippus laid the greatest stress on the worth and dignity of the individual, and on the power of will.[104]

The Stoics admitted between the good and the bad a third class of things – the indifferent (adiaphora).[105] Of things morally indifferent, the best includes health, and riches, and honour, and the worst includes sickness and poverty.[106] Chrysippus accepted that it was normal in ordinary usage to refer to the preferred indifferent things as "good",[105] but the wise person, said Chrysippus, uses such things without requiring them.[106] Practice and habit are necessary to render virtue perfect in the individual – in other words, there is such a thing as moral progress, and character has to be built up.[104]

On Passions edit

The Stoics sought to be free of the unruly emotions, which they regarded as being contrary to nature. The passions or emotions (pathe) are the disturbing element in right judgment.[104] Chrysippus wrote a whole book, On Passions (Greek: Περὶ παθῶν), concerning the therapy of the emotions.[107] The passions are like diseases which depress and crush the soul, thus he sought to eradicate them (apatheia).[107] Wrong judgements turn into passions when they gather an impetus of their own, just as, when one has started running, it is difficult to stop.[108] One cannot hope to eradicate the passions when one is in the heat of love or anger: this can only be done when one is calm.[109] Therefore, one should prepare in advance, and deal with the passions in the mind as if they were present.[110] By applying reason to passions such as greed, pride, or lust, one can understand the harm which they cause.[110]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ He died according to Apollodorus of Athens (ap. Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 184) at the age of 73 during the 143rd Olympiad (208–204 BC). Thus his date of birth is placed between 281 and 277. The statements in Pseudo-Lucian (Macr. 20) that he died aged 81, and Valerius Maximus that he was still writing at the age of 80 (Val. Max. viii. 7) are considered less credible.[2]
  2. ^ "The loss of so much of Chrysippus' work is the loss of philosophical work of the highest calibre..."[5]
  3. ^ "The first of Chrysippus' partially preserved two or three works is his Logical Questions, contained in PHerc. 307 ... The second work is his On Providence, preserved in PHerc 1038 and 1421 ... A third work, most likely by Chrysippus is preserved in PHerc. 1020."[6]
  4. ^ The king is not named, but Cilicia was contested between Ptolemy II Philadelphus and Antiochus I Soter during this period.[11]
  5. ^ The claim that he studied under Zeno is less likely because Zeno died in 262/1.[13]
  6. ^ Greek: εἰ μὴ γὰρ ἦν Χρύσιππος, οὐκ ἂν ἦν στοά[24]
  7. ^ When Sextus Empiricus reports the different criteria offered by ancient philosophers for the truth of conditional propositions, he does not mention Chrysippus by name, but modern scholars believe that Chrysippus authored, or, at least, held this view.[35]
  8. ^ These Latin names, unknown to Chrysippus, date from the Middle Ages.[42]
  9. ^ "[Stoics] have often been presented as the first nominalists, rejecting the existence of universal concepts altogether. ... For Chrysippus there are no universal entities, whether they be conceived as substantial Platonic Forms or in some other manner."[67][68]
  10. ^ "Dieser Pandeismus, der von Chrysippos (aus Soloi 280–208 v. Chr.) herrühren soll, ist schon eine Verbindung mit dem Emanismus; Gott ist die Welt, insofern als diese aus seiner Substanz durch Verdichtung und Abkühlung entstanden ist und entsteht, und er sich strahlengleich mit seiner Substanz durch sie noch verbreitet."[86]
  11. ^ See also Epictetus, Discourses, i.28.6–10; ii.17.19–23, for an example of this play being discussed in the setting of a Stoic school.

References edit

  1. ^ "Chrysippus". Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary.
  2. ^ a b Cf. Dorandi 1999, p. 40
  3. ^ Dorandi 1999, p. 40
  4. ^ Luhtala 2000, p. 194
  5. ^ Rist 1969, p. vii
  6. ^ a b c Fitzgerald 2004, p. 11
  7. ^ Gould 1970, p. 7, citing Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 179; Galen, Protreptic, 7; de Differentia Pulsuum, 10
  8. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 182
  9. ^ a b c Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 179
  10. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 181.
  11. ^ cf. Green 1993, p. 639
  12. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 179.
  13. ^ cf. Dorandi 1999, p. 40
  14. ^ a b Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 184
  15. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 181
  16. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 180
  17. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 181, x. 26–27
  18. ^ a b c d Davidson 1908, p. 614
  19. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 185
  20. ^ Plutarch, De Stoicorum Repugnantiis; Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 183
  21. ^ Eusebius, Praeparatio Evangelica, 15. 18; Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 35
  22. ^ a b "Chrysippus", J. O. Urmson, Jonathan Rée, The Concise Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy, 2005, pp. 73–74 of 398 pp.
  23. ^ Barnes 1999, p. 65
  24. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 183.
  25. ^ Sharples 2014, p. 24
  26. ^ Ian Mueller (1978) An Introduction to Stoic Logic Rist 1978, pp. 2–13
  27. ^ a b c d e Johansen & Rosenmeier 1998, p. 466
  28. ^ Sharples 2014, pp. 24–25
  29. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 65
  30. ^ Gould 1970, pp. 69–70
  31. ^ a b Gould 1970, p. 71
  32. ^ a b Johansen & Rosenmeier 1998, p. 467
  33. ^ a b Sextus Empiricus, Pyr. Hyp. ii. 110–112; Adv. Math. viii. 112–117
  34. ^ a b Sextus Empiricus, Pyr. Hyp., ii. 110–112
  35. ^ See Gould 1970, pp. 72–82
  36. ^ a b Johansen & Rosenmeier 1998, p. 468
  37. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 79
  38. ^ Kneale & Kneale 1962, pp. 158–174
  39. ^ Susanne Bobzien, Stoic Syllogistic, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 14, 1996, pp. 133–192
  40. ^ Diogenes Laertius, vii. 80-81; Sextus Empiricus, Hyp. Pyr. ii. 156–159; cf. Adv. Math. viii. 223ff.
  41. ^ Mates 1953, pp. 67–73
  42. ^ Sharples 2014, p. 24
  43. ^ Long & Sedley 1987, §36 HIJ
  44. ^ Kneale & Kneale 1962, p. 169
  45. ^ Bobzien, Susanne. "Ancient Logic: Stoic Syllogistic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  46. ^ a b Sharples 2014, p. 26
  47. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, I.69
  48. ^ a b Barnes 1999, p. 71
  49. ^ Stephen Menn, "The Stoic Theory of Categories", in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: Volume XVII: 1999, 215–247.
  50. ^ a b Gould 1970, p. 107
  51. ^ Clement of Alexandria, Stromata, vii. 16
  52. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 180.
  53. ^ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 403
  54. ^ Hicks 1910, p. 70
  55. ^ a b c Gould 1970, p. 90
  56. ^ a b c d Stock 1908, p. 22
  57. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 77
  58. ^ Stock 1908, p. 23
  59. ^ Hicks 1911, p. 946
  60. ^ Hicks 1910, p. 66
  61. ^ Cicero, De Natura Deorum, ii, 19
  62. ^ Plutarch, De Stoicorum Repugnantiis, 41.
  63. ^ Hicks 1911, p. 944
  64. ^ a b O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 431
  65. ^ a b Stock 1908, p. 79
  66. ^ a b c Sharples 2014, p. 67
  67. ^ John Sellars, Stoicism, Routledge, 2014, pp. 84–85
  68. ^ "Chrysippus | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  69. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 178
  70. ^ a b Zeller 1880, p. 176
  71. ^ a b Zeller 1880, p. 175
  72. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 174
  73. ^ Cicero, On Fate, 20–21
  74. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 177
  75. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 181
  76. ^ a b Kenny 2006, p. 195 referencing Cicero, On Fate, 28–29
  77. ^ Zeller 1880, p. 182
  78. ^ Diogenianus in Eusebius, Praeparatio evangelica, vi. 8, quoted in Inwood & Gerson 1997, p. 190
  79. ^ Brunschwig & Sedley 2003, p. 172
  80. ^ a b c Zeller 1880, p. 179
  81. ^ a b Zeller 1880, p. 180
  82. ^ Gould 1970, p. 152, note 3
  83. ^ Gould 1970, pp. 144–145
  84. ^ a b c Hicks 1911, p. 947
  85. ^ a b c Cicero, De Natura Deorum, i. 15
  86. ^ Max Bernhard Weinsten, Welt- und Lebensanschauungen, Hervorgegangen aus Religion, Philosophie und Naturerkenntnis ("World and Life Views, Emerging From Religion, Philosophy and Perception of Nature") (1910), p. 233
  87. ^ Cicero, De Natura Deorum, iii. 10. Cf. ii. 6 for the fuller version of this argument
  88. ^ Cicero, De Natura Deorum, iii. 10
  89. ^ Plutarch, De Stoicorum Repugnantiis, 1051 B
  90. ^ a b Aulus Gellius, vii. 1
  91. ^ Plutarch, De Stoicorum Repugnantiis, 1050 E; De Communibus Notitiis, 1065 B
  92. ^ Plutarch, De Communibus Notitiis, 1065 D
  93. ^ Gould 1970, p. 116
  94. ^ a b Gould 1970, p. 117
  95. ^ Plutarch, De Communibus Notitiis, 1079F
  96. ^ a b Gould 1970, p. 118
  97. ^ a b Heath 1921, p. 69
  98. ^ Iamblichus, in Nicom., ii. 8f; Syrianus, in Arist. Metaph., Kroll 140. 9f.
  99. ^ Galen, On The Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato, iii.3.13–22, iv.2.27, iv.6.19–27.
  100. ^ Stock 1908, p. 13
  101. ^ Gould 1970, p. 163
  102. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 87
  103. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 88
  104. ^ a b c d e Davidson 1908, p. 615
  105. ^ a b Kenny 2006, pp. 282–283
  106. ^ a b Zeller 1880, p. 284
  107. ^ a b Gould 1970, p. 186
  108. ^ Sharples 2014, p. 68
  109. ^ Gould 1970, p. 187
  110. ^ a b Gould 1970, p. 188

Works cited edit

  • Barnes, Jonathan (1999), "The History of Hellenistic Logic", in Algra, Keimpe; Barnes, Jonathan; Mansfeld, Jaap; Schofield, Malcolm (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521616700
  • Brunschwig, Jacques; Sedley, David (2003), "Hellenistic philosophy", in Sedley, David (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521775035
  • Davidson, William Leslie (1908), "Chrysippus", in Hastings, James (ed.), Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, vol. 3, T. & T. Clark
  • Dorandi, Tiziano (1999), "Chronology", in Algra, Keimpe; Barnes, Jonathan; Mansfeld, Jaap; Schofield, Malcolm (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521616700
  • Fitzgerald, John T. (2004), "Philodemus and the Papyri from Herculaneum", in Fitzgerald, John T.; Obbink, Dirk; Holland, Glenn Stanfield (eds.), Philodemus and the New Testament world Philosophy, Brill, ISBN 9004114602
  • Gould, Josiah (1970), The Philosophy of Chrysippus, SUNY, ISBN 087395064X
  • Green, Peter (1993), Alexander to Actium: the historical evolution of the Hellenistic age, University of California Press, ISBN 0520083490
  • Heath, Thomas Little (1921), A History of Greek Mathematics, Vol 1: From Thales to Euclid, Oxford
  • Hicks, Robert Drew (1910), Stoic and Epicurean, C. Scribner
  • Hicks, Robert Drew (1911). "Stoics" . In Chisholm, Hugh (ed.). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 25 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 942–951.
  • Inwood, Brad; Gerson, Lloyd P. (1997), Hellenistic Philosophy: Introductory Readings, Hackett, ISBN 0872203786
  • Johansen, Karsten Friis; Rosenmeier, Henrik (1998), A History of Ancient Philosophy: From the Beginnings to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 0415127386
  • Kenny, Anthony (2006), Ancient Philosophy, Oxford University Press, ISBN 0198752733
  • Kneale, William; Kneale, Martha (1962). The Development of Logic. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824773-9.
  •   Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). "The Stoics: Zeno" . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:7. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
  •   Laërtius, Diogenes (1925b). "The Stoics: Cleanthes" . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:7. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
  •   Laërtius, Diogenes (1925c). "The Stoics: Chrysippus" . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:7. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
  • Long, A. A.; Sedley, D. N., eds. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge University Press.
  • Luhtala, Anneli (2000), On the Origin of Syntactical Description in Stoic Logic, Nodus Publikationen, ISBN 3893234578
  • Mates, Benson (1953), Stoic Logic, University of California Press
  • O'Toole, Robert R.; Jennings, Raymond E. (2004), "The Megarians and the Stoics", in Gabbay, Dov; Woods, John (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic: Greek, Indian, and Arabic logic, North Holland, ISBN 0444504664
  • Rist, John M. (1969), Stoic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press
  • Rist, John M., ed. (1978). The Stoics. University of California Press. ISBN 0-520-03135-0.
  • Sharples, R. W. (2014), Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics: An Introduction to Hellenistic Philosophy, Routledge, pp. 67–68, ISBN 978-1134836390
  • Stock, St. George William Joseph (1908), Stoicism, Constable
  • Zeller, Eduard (1880), The Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics, Longmans

Further reading edit

  • Bobzien, Susanne (1998), Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy, Oxford University Press, ISBN 0199247676
  • Bobzien, Susanne (1999), Chrysippus' Theory of Causes. In K. Ierodiakonou (ed.), Topics in Stoic Philosophy, Oxford: OUP, 196–242. ISBN 019924880X
  • Bréhier, Émile, (1951), Chrysippe et l'ancien stoicisme. Paris. ISBN 2903925062
  • Dufour, Richard (2004), Chrysippe. Oeuvre philosophique. Textes traduits et commentés par Richard Dufour, Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2 volumes (logic and physics), ISBN 2251742034
  • Hahm, D. E. Chrysippus' solution to the Democritean dilemma of the cone, Isis 63 (217) (1972), 205–220.
  • Holiday, Ryan; Hanselman, Stephen (2020). "Chrysippus the Fighter". Lives of the Stoics. New York: Portfolio/Penguin. pp. 38–49. ISBN 978-0525541875.
  • Ide, H. A. Chrysippus's response to Diodorus's Master Argument, History and Philosophy Logic 13 (2) (1992), 133–148.
  • Jedan, Christoph (2009) Stoic Virtues: Chrysippus and the Theological Foundations of Stoic Ethics. Continuum Studies in Ancient Philosophy. ISBN 1441112529
  • Tieleman, Teun L. (1996) Galen and Chrysippus on the Soul: Argument and Refutation in the "De Placitis" Books II–III. Philosophia Antiqua. Brill. ISBN 9004105204
  • Tieleman, Teun L. (2003) Chrysippus' "on Affections": Reconstruction and Interpretation. Philosophia Antiqua. Brill. ISBN 9004129987

External links edit

Preceded by Leader of the Stoic school
230–206 BC
Succeeded by

chrysippus, this, article, about, philosopher, other, people, named, disambiguation, soli, greek, Χρύσιππος, Σολεύς, chrysippos, soleus, greek, stoic, philosopher, native, soli, cilicia, moved, athens, young, where, became, pupil, stoic, philosopher, cleanthes. This article is about the philosopher For other people named Chrysippus see Chrysippus disambiguation Chrysippus of Soli k r aɪ ˈ s ɪ p e s k r ɪ 1 Greek Xrysippos ὁ Soleys Chrysippos ho Soleus c 279 c 206 BC a was a Greek Stoic philosopher He was a native of Soli Cilicia but moved to Athens as a young man where he became a pupil of the Stoic philosopher Cleanthes When Cleanthes died around 230 BC Chrysippus became the third head of the Stoic school A prolific writer Chrysippus expanded the fundamental doctrines of Cleanthes mentor Zeno of Citium the founder and first head of the school which earned him the title of the Second Founder of Stoicism 3 Chrysippus of SoliRoman copy of a Hellenistic bust ofChrysippus British Museum Bornc 279 BCESoli Cilicia now Mezitli Mersin Turkey Diedc 206 BC aged 73 Athens GreeceCause of deathDeath from laughter uncertain EraHellenistic philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolStoicismMain interestsLogicPhysicsEthicsNotable ideasSystemization of Stoicism Pneuma NominalismChrysippus excelled in logic the theory of knowledge ethics and physics He created an original system of propositional logic in order to better understand the workings of the universe and role of humanity within it He adhered to a fatalistic view of fate but nevertheless sought a role for personal agency in thought and action Ethics he thought depended on understanding the nature of the universe and he taught a therapy of extirpating the unruly passions which depress and crush the soul He initiated the success of Stoicism as one of the most influential philosophical movements for centuries in the Greek and Roman world The linguistic orientation of Chrysippus work made it difficult for its students even within the Stoic school 4 Of his several written works none have survived except as fragments b Recently segments of some of his works were discovered among the Herculaneum papyri c Contents 1 Life 2 Study 3 Logic 3 1 Propositions 3 2 Conditional propositions 3 3 Syllogistic 3 4 Other logical work 3 5 Later reception 4 Epistemology 5 Physics 5 1 Fate 5 2 Divination 5 3 God 5 4 Theodicy 6 Mathematics 7 Ethics 7 1 On Passions 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Works cited 12 Further reading 13 External linksLife editChrysippus was the son of Apollonius of Tarsus and he was born at Soli Cilicia 7 He was slight in stature 8 and is reputed to have trained as a long distance runner 9 While still young he lost his substantial inherited property when it was confiscated to the king s treasury 10 d Chrysippus moved to Athens where he became the disciple of Cleanthes who was then the head scholarch of the Stoic school 12 e He is believed to have attended the courses of Arcesilaus and his successor Lacydes in the Platonic Academy 14 Chrysippus threw himself eagerly into the study of the Stoic system His reputation for learning among his contemporaries was considerable 9 He was noted for intellectual audacity and self confidence and his reliance on his own ability was shown among other things in the request he is supposed to have made to Cleanthes Give me the principles and I will find the proofs myself 9 He succeeded Cleanthes as head of the Stoic school when Cleanthes died in around 230 BC Chrysippus was a prolific writer He is said to rarely have gone without writing 500 lines a day 15 and he composed more than 705 works 16 His desire to be comprehensive meant that he would take both sides of an argument 14 and his opponents accused him of filling his books with the quotations of others 17 He was considered diffuse and obscure in his utterances and careless in his style but his abilities were highly regarded and he came to be seen as a preeminent authority for the school 18 nbsp Final moments in the life of Chrysippus Engraving from 1606 He died during the 143rd Olympiad 208 204 BC at the age of 73 2 Diogenes Laertius gives two different accounts of his death 19 In the first account Chrysippus was seized with dizziness having drunk undiluted wine at a feast and died soon after In the second account he was watching a donkey eat some figs and cried out Now give the donkey a drink of pure wine to wash down the figs whereupon he died in a fit of laughter His nephew Aristocreon erected a statue in his honour in the Kerameikos 20 Chrysippus was succeeded as head of the Stoic school by his pupil Zeno of Tarsus 21 Of his written works none survived except as fragments quoted in the works of later authors like Cicero Seneca Galen Plutarch and others Recently segments from Logical Questions and On Providence were discovered among the Herculaneum papyri 6 A third work by Chrysippus may also be among them 6 Study editChrysippus had a long and successful career of resisting the attacks of the Academy 22 and hoped not simply to defend Stoicism against the assaults of the past but also against all possible attack in the future He took the doctrines of Zeno and Cleanthes and crystallized them into what became the definitive system of Stoicism 22 He elaborated the physical doctrines of the Stoics and their theory of knowledge 18 and he created much of their formal logic 23 In short Chrysippus made the Stoic system what it was It was said that without Chrysippus there would have been no Stoa f Logic editSee also Stoic logic Chrysippus wrote much on the subject of logic and created a system of propositional logic Aristotle s term logic had been concerned with the interrelations of terms such as Socrates or man all men are mortal Socrates is a man so Socrates is mortal Stoic logic on the other hand was concerned with the interrelations of propositions such as it is day if it is day it is light but it is day so it is light 25 26 Though the earlier Megarian dialecticians Diodorus Cronus and Philo had worked in this field and the pupils of Aristotle Theophrastus and Eudemus had investigated hypothetical syllogisms 27 it was Chrysippus who developed these principles into a coherent system of propositional logic 27 28 Propositions edit Chrysippus defined a proposition as that which is capable of being denied or affirmed as it is in itself and gave examples of propositions such as it is day and Dion is walking 29 30 He distinguished between simple and non simple propositions which in modern terminology are known as atomic and molecular propositions 27 A simple proposition is an elementary statement such as it is day 31 Simple propositions are linked together to form non simple propositions by the use of logical connectives Chrysippus enumerated five kinds of molecular propositions according to the connective used 31 Logical connectivesType Exampleif if it is day it is lightand it is day and it is lighteither or either it is day or it is nightbecause because it is day it is lightmore less likely than more likely it is day than it is nightThus several types of molecular propositions familiar to modern logic were listed by Chrysippus including the conjunction the disjunction and the conditional 32 and Chrysippus studied their criteria of truth closely 32 Conditional propositions edit The first logicians to debate conditional statements were Diodorus Cronus and his pupil Philo Writing five hundred years later Sextus Empiricus refers to a debate between Diodorus and Philo 33 Philo regarded all conditionals as true except those which with a correct antecedent had an incorrect consequent and this meant a proposition such as if it is day then I am talking is true unless it is day and I fall silent 34 But Diodorus argued that a true conditional is one in which the antecedent clause could never lead to an untrue conclusion thus because the proposition if it is day then I am talking can be false it is invalid 33 However paradoxical propositions were still possible such as if atomic elements of things do not exist atomic elements exists 34 Chrysippus adopted a much stricter view regarding conditional propositions which made such paradoxes impossible g to him a conditional is true if denial of the consequent is logically incompatible with the antecedent 36 This corresponds to the modern day strict conditional 36 Syllogistic edit Chrysippus developed a syllogistic or system of deduction in which he made use of five types of basic arguments or argument forms called indemonstrable syllogisms 37 which played the role of axioms and four inference rules called themata by means of which complex syllogisms could be reduced to these axioms 38 39 The forms of the five indemonstrables were 40 41 Name h Description ExampleModus ponens If A then B A Therefore B If it is day it is light It is day Therefore it is light Modus tollens If A then B Not B Therefore not A If it is day it is light It is not light Therefore it is not day Modus ponendo tollens i Not both A and B A Therefore not B It is not both day and night It is day Therefore it is not night ii Either A or B A Therefore not B It is either day or night It is day Therefore it is not night Modus tollendo ponens Either A or B Not A Therefore B It is either day or night It is not day Therefore it is night Of the four inference rules themata 8emata 43 only two survived One the so called first thema was a rule of antilogism The other the third thema was a cut rule by which chain syllogisms could be reduced to simple syllogisms 44 45 The purpose of Stoic syllogistic was not merely to create a formal system It was also understood as the study of the operations of reason the divine reason logos which governs the universe of which human beings are a part 46 The goal was to find valid rules of inference and forms of proof to help people find their way in life 27 nbsp Chrysippus argued dogs reason According to Sextus Empiricus Chrysippus held that dogs use disjunctive syllogism such as when using scent to pick which path to run down This was in contrast to a tradition since Aristotle who saw reasoning and reasoning deductively as man s defining aspect 47 Other logical work edit Chrysippus analyzed speech and the handling of names and terms 18 He also devoted much effort in refuting fallacies and paradoxes 18 According to Diogenes Laertius Chrysippus wrote twelve works in 23 books on the Liar paradox seven works in 17 books on amphiboly and another nine works in 26 books on other conundrums 48 In all 28 works or 66 books were given over to puzzles or paradoxes 48 Chrysippus is the first Stoic for whom the third of the four Stoic categories i e the category somehow disposed is attested 49 In the surviving evidence Chrysippus frequently makes use of the categories of substance and quality but makes little use of the other two Stoic categories somehow disposed and somehow disposed in relation to something 50 It is not clear whether the categories had any special significance for Chrysippus and a clear doctrine of categories may be the work of later Stoics 50 Later reception edit Chrysippus came to be renowned as one of the foremost logicians of ancient Greece When Clement of Alexandria wanted to mention one who was master among logicians as Homer was master among poets it was Chrysippus not Aristotle he chose 51 Diogenes Laertius wrote If the gods use dialectic they would use none other than that of Chrysippus 52 The logical work by Chrysippus came to be neglected and forgotten Aristotle s logic prevailed partly because it was seen as more practical and partly because it was taken up by the Neoplatonists 46 As recently as the 19th century Stoic logic was treated with contempt a barren formulaic system which was merely clothing the logic of Aristotle with new terminology 53 It was not until the 20th century with the advances in logic and the modern propositional calculus that it became clear that Stoic logic constituted a significant achievement 27 Epistemology editFor the Stoics truth is distinguished from error by the sage who possesses right reason 54 Chrysippus s theory of knowledge was empirical 55 The senses transmit messages from the external world and their reports are controlled not by referring them to innate ideas but by comparing them to previous reports stored in the mind 55 Zeno had defined impressions of sense as an impression in the soul 56 and this was interpreted literally by Cleanthes who compared the impression on the soul to the impression made by a seal on wax 57 Chrysippus preferred to regard it as an alteration or change in the soul 56 that is the soul receives a modification from every external object that acts upon it just as the air receives countless strokes when many people are speaking at once 56 In the receipt of an impression the soul is purely passive and the impression reveals not only its own existence but that also of its cause just as light displays itself and the elements that are in it 56 The power to name the object resides in the understanding First must come the impression and the understanding having the power of utterance expresses in speech the affection it receives from the object 58 True presentations are distinguished from those that are false by the use of memory classification and comparison 55 If the sense organ and the mind are healthy and provided that an external object can be really seen or heard the presentation due to its clearness and distinctness has the power to extort the assent that always lies in our power to give or to withhold 59 In a context in which people are understood to be rational beings reason is developed out of these notions 60 Physics edit nbsp A partial marble bust of Chrysippus that is a Roman copy of a Hellenistic original Louvre Museum Chrysippus insisted on the organic unity of the universe as well as the correlation and mutual interdependence of all of its parts 61 He said the universe is the soul and guide of itself 62 Following Zeno Chrysippus determined fiery breath or aether to be the primitive substance of the universe 63 Objects are made up of inert formless matter and an informing soul pneuma provides form to the undifferentiated matter 64 The pneuma pervades all of substance and maintains the unity of the universe and constitutes the soul of the human being 64 The classical elements change into one another by a process of condensation and rarefaction 65 Fire first becomes solidified into air then air into water and lastly water into earth The process of dissolution takes place in the reverse order earth being rarefied into water water into air and air into fire 65 The human soul was divided by Chrysippus into eight faculties the five senses the power of reproduction the power of speech and the ruling part that is located in the chest rather than the head 66 Individual souls are perishable but according to the view originated by Chrysippus the souls of wise people survive longer after their death 66 No individual soul can however survive beyond the periodic conflagration when the universe is renewed 66 There were no universals or abstract objects for Chrysippus making him a kind of nominalist i Fate edit For Chrysippus all things happen according to fate what seems to be accidental has always some hidden cause 69 The unity of the world consists in the chain like dependence of cause upon cause 70 Nothing can take place without a sufficient cause 71 According to Chrysippus every proposition is either true or false and this must apply to future events as well 72 If any motion exists without a cause then not every proposition will be either true or false For that which has not efficient causes is neither true nor false But every proposition is either true or false Therefore there is no motion without a cause And if this is so then all effects owe their existence to prior causes And if this is so all things happen by fate It follows therefore that whatever happens happens by fate 73 The Stoic view of fate is entirely based on a view of the universe as a whole Individual things and persons only come into consideration as dependent parts of this whole 74 Everything is in every respect determined by this relation and is consequently subject to the general order of the world 70 If his opponents objected that if everything is determined by destiny there is no individual responsibility since what has been once foreordained must happen come what may Chrysippus replied that there is a distinction to be made between simple and complex predestination 75 Becoming ill may be fated whatever happens but if a person s recovery is linked to consulting a doctor then consulting the doctor is fated to occur together with that person s recovery and this becomes a complex fact 76 All human actions in fact our destiny are decided by our relation to things 77 or as Chrysippus put it events are co fated to occur 76 The non destruction of one s coat he says is not fated simply but co fated with its being taken care of and someone s being saved from his enemies is co fated with his fleeing those enemies and having children is co fated with being willing to lie with a woman For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and zeal for these things since he says it was fated for these things to occur in conjunction with this personal effort But it will be in our power he says with what is in our power being included in fate 78 Thus our actions are predetermined and are causally related to the overarching network of fate but nevertheless the moral responsibility of how we respond to impressions remains our own 79 The one all determining power is active everywhere working in each particular being according to its nature whether in rational or irrational creatures or in inorganic objects 80 Every action is brought about by the co operation of causes depending on the nature of things and the character of the agent 80 Our actions would only be involuntary if they were produced by external causes alone without any co operation on the part of our wills with external causes 80 Virtue and vice are set down as things in our power for which consequently we are responsible 81 Moral responsibility depends only on freedom of the will and what emanates from our will is our own no matter whether it is possible for us to act differently or not 81 This rather subtle position which attempts to reconcile determinism with human responsibility is known as soft determinism or compatibilism 82 Divination edit nbsp Cleromancy in ancient Greece Chrysippus accepted divination as part of the causal chain of fate Chrysippus also argued for the existence of fate based on divination which he thought there was good evidence for 83 It would not be possible for diviners to predict the future if the future itself was accidental 71 Omens and portents he believed are the natural symptoms of certain occurrences 84 There must be countless indications of the course of providence for the most part unobserved the meaning of only a few having become known to humanity 84 To those who argued that divination was superfluous as all events are foreordained he replied that both divination and our behaviour under the warnings which it affords are included in the chain of causation 84 God edit The Stoics believed that the universe is God and Chrysippus affirmed that the universe itself is God and the universal outpouring of its soul 85 It is the guiding principle of the universe operating in mind and reason together with the common nature of things and the totality which embraces all existence 85 Based on these beliefs physicist and philosopher Max Bernhard Weinstein identified Chrysippus as a Pandeist j Chrysippus sought to prove the existence of God making use of a teleological argument If there is anything that humanity cannot produce the being who produces it is better than humanity But humanity cannot produce the things that are in the universe the heavenly bodies etc The being therefore who produces them is superior to humanity But who is there that is superior to humanity except God Therefore God exists 87 Chrysippus spoke of God and gods interchangeably He interpreted the gods of traditional Greek religion by viewing them as different aspects of the one reality Cicero tells us that he further maintained that aether is that which people call Zeus and that the air which permeates the seas is Poseidon and that the earth is what is known by the name of Demeter and he treated in similar style the names of the other gods 85 In addition the universe exists for the benefit of the universal god We should infer in the case of a beautiful dwelling place that it was built for its owners and not for mice we ought therefore in the same way to regard the universe as the dwelling place of the gods 88 Theodicy edit In response to the question of how evil could exist in a good universe Chrysippus replied evil cannot be removed nor is it well that it should be removed 89 Firstly he argued following Plato that it was impossible for good to exist without evil for justice could not be known without injustice courage without cowardice temperance without intemperance or wisdom without foolishness 90 Secondly apparent evils exist as a consequent of nature s goodness thus it was necessary for the human skull to be made from small and thin bones for reasons of utility but this superior utility meant that the skull is vulnerable to blows 90 Thirdly evils are distributed according to the rational will of Zeus either to punish the wicked or because they are important to the world order as a whole 91 Thus evil is good under disguise and is ultimately conducive to the best Chrysippus compared evil to the coarse jest in the comedy for just as the jest though offensive in itself improves the piece as a whole so too you may criticize evil regarded by itself yet allow that taken with all else it has its use 92 Mathematics edit nbsp The puzzle of Democritus If a cone is sliced horizontally are the surfaces produced equal or unequal Chrysippus regarded bodies surfaces lines places the void and time as all being infinitely divisible 93 He determined one of the principal features of the infinite set since a man and a finger have an infinite number of parts as do the universe and a man it cannot be said that a man has more parts than his finger nor that the universe has more parts than a man 94 Chrysippus also responded to a problem first posed by Democritus 95 If a cone is divided by a plane parallel to its base are the surfaces of the segments equal or unequal If they are equal then the cone becomes a cylinder if they are unequal then the surface of the cone must be stepped 94 The reply of Chrysippus was that the surfaces are both equal and unequal 96 Chrysippus was in effect negating the law of excluded middle with respect to the equal and unequal and thus he may have anticipated an important principle of modern infinitesimal calculus namely the limit and the process of convergence towards a limit 96 Chrysippus was notable for claiming that one is a number One was not always considered a number by the ancient Greeks since they viewed one as that by which things are measured Aristotle in his Metaphysics wrote a measure is not the things measured but the measure or the One is the beginning of number 97 Chrysippus asserted that one had magnitude one Greek plῆ8os ἕn 98 although this was not generally accepted by the Greeks and Iamblichus wrote that magnitude one was a contradiction in terms 97 Ethics edit nbsp Greek amphora depicting Euripides Medea Chrysippus regarded Medea as a prime example of how bad judgments could give rise to irrational passions 99 k Chrysippus taught that ethics depended on physics In his Physical Theses he stated for there is no other or more appropriate way of approaching the subject of good and evil on the virtues or happiness than from the nature of all things and the administration of the universe 100 The goal of life said Chrysippus is to live in accordance with one s experience of the actual course of nature 101 A person s individual nature is part of the nature of the whole universe 102 and thus life should be lived in accordance with one s own human nature as well as that of the universe 103 Human nature is ethical and humanity is akin to the Divine emanating from the primal fire or aether which though material is the embodiment of reason and people should conduct themselves accordingly 104 People have freedom and this freedom consists in emancipation from irrational desires lust riches position in life domination etc and in subjecting the will to reason 104 Chrysippus laid the greatest stress on the worth and dignity of the individual and on the power of will 104 The Stoics admitted between the good and the bad a third class of things the indifferent adiaphora 105 Of things morally indifferent the best includes health and riches and honour and the worst includes sickness and poverty 106 Chrysippus accepted that it was normal in ordinary usage to refer to the preferred indifferent things as good 105 but the wise person said Chrysippus uses such things without requiring them 106 Practice and habit are necessary to render virtue perfect in the individual in other words there is such a thing as moral progress and character has to be built up 104 On Passions edit Main article On Passions The Stoics sought to be free of the unruly emotions which they regarded as being contrary to nature The passions or emotions pathe are the disturbing element in right judgment 104 Chrysippus wrote a whole book On Passions Greek Perὶ pa8ῶn concerning the therapy of the emotions 107 The passions are like diseases which depress and crush the soul thus he sought to eradicate them apatheia 107 Wrong judgements turn into passions when they gather an impetus of their own just as when one has started running it is difficult to stop 108 One cannot hope to eradicate the passions when one is in the heat of love or anger this can only be done when one is calm 109 Therefore one should prepare in advance and deal with the passions in the mind as if they were present 110 By applying reason to passions such as greed pride or lust one can understand the harm which they cause 110 See also editApocatastasis Deixis History of logic Lazy argument List of unusual deathsNotes edit He died according to Apollodorus of Athens ap Diogenes Laertius vii 184 at the age of 73 during the 143rd Olympiad 208 204 BC Thus his date of birth is placed between 281 and 277 The statements in Pseudo Lucian Macr 20 that he died aged 81 and Valerius Maximus that he was still writing at the age of 80 Val Max viii 7 are considered less credible 2 The loss of so much of Chrysippus work is the loss of philosophical work of the highest calibre 5 The first of Chrysippus partially preserved two or three works is his Logical Questions contained in PHerc 307 The second work is his On Providence preserved in PHerc 1038 and 1421 A third work most likely by Chrysippus is preserved in PHerc 1020 6 The king is not named but Cilicia was contested between Ptolemy II Philadelphus and Antiochus I Soter during this period 11 The claim that he studied under Zeno is less likely because Zeno died in 262 1 13 Greek eἰ mὴ gὰr ἦn Xrysippos oὐk ἂn ἦn stoa 24 When Sextus Empiricus reports the different criteria offered by ancient philosophers for the truth of conditional propositions he does not mention Chrysippus by name but modern scholars believe that Chrysippus authored or at least held this view 35 These Latin names unknown to Chrysippus date from the Middle Ages 42 Stoics have often been presented as the first nominalists rejecting the existence of universal concepts altogether For Chrysippus there are no universal entities whether they be conceived as substantial Platonic Forms or in some other manner 67 68 Dieser Pandeismus der von Chrysippos aus Soloi 280 208 v Chr herruhren soll ist schon eine Verbindung mit dem Emanismus Gott ist die Welt insofern als diese aus seiner Substanz durch Verdichtung und Abkuhlung entstanden ist und entsteht und er sich strahlengleich mit seiner Substanz durch sie noch verbreitet 86 See also Epictetus Discourses i 28 6 10 ii 17 19 23 for an example of this play being discussed in the setting of a Stoic school References edit Chrysippus Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary a b Cf Dorandi 1999 p 40 Dorandi 1999 p 40 Luhtala 2000 p 194 Rist 1969 p vii a b c Fitzgerald 2004 p 11 Gould 1970 p 7 citing Diogenes Laertius vii 179 Galen Protreptic 7 de Differentia Pulsuum 10 Diogenes Laertius vii 182 a b c Diogenes Laertius vii 179 Diogenes Laertius vii 181 cf Green 1993 p 639 Diogenes Laertius vii 179 cf Dorandi 1999 p 40 a b Diogenes Laertius vii 184 Diogenes Laertius vii 181 Diogenes Laertius vii 180 Diogenes Laertius vii 181 x 26 27 a b c d Davidson 1908 p 614 Diogenes Laertius vii 185 Plutarch De Stoicorum Repugnantiis Diogenes Laertius vii 183 Eusebius Praeparatio Evangelica 15 18 Diogenes Laertius vii 35 a b Chrysippus J O Urmson Jonathan Ree The Concise Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy 2005 pp 73 74 of 398 pp Barnes 1999 p 65 Diogenes Laertius vii 183 Sharples 2014 p 24 Ian Mueller 1978 An Introduction to Stoic Logic Rist 1978 pp 2 13 a b c d e Johansen amp Rosenmeier 1998 p 466 Sharples 2014 pp 24 25 Diogenes Laertius vii 65 Gould 1970 pp 69 70 a b Gould 1970 p 71 a b Johansen amp Rosenmeier 1998 p 467 a b Sextus Empiricus Pyr Hyp ii 110 112 Adv Math viii 112 117 a b Sextus Empiricus Pyr Hyp ii 110 112 See Gould 1970 pp 72 82 a b Johansen amp Rosenmeier 1998 p 468 Diogenes Laertius vii 79 Kneale amp Kneale 1962 pp 158 174 Susanne Bobzien Stoic Syllogistic Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 14 1996 pp 133 192 Diogenes Laertius vii 80 81 Sextus Empiricus Hyp Pyr ii 156 159 cf Adv Math viii 223ff Mates 1953 pp 67 73 Sharples 2014 p 24 Long amp Sedley 1987 36 HIJ Kneale amp Kneale 1962 p 169 Bobzien Susanne Ancient Logic Stoic Syllogistic In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Sharples 2014 p 26 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism I 69 a b Barnes 1999 p 71 Stephen Menn The Stoic Theory of Categories in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Volume XVII 1999 215 247 a b Gould 1970 p 107 Clement of Alexandria Stromata vii 16 Diogenes Laertius vii 180 O Toole amp Jennings 2004 p 403 Hicks 1910 p 70 a b c Gould 1970 p 90 a b c d Stock 1908 p 22 Zeller 1880 p 77 Stock 1908 p 23 Hicks 1911 p 946 Hicks 1910 p 66 Cicero De Natura Deorum ii 19 Plutarch De Stoicorum Repugnantiis 41 Hicks 1911 p 944 a b O Toole amp Jennings 2004 p 431 a b Stock 1908 p 79 a b c Sharples 2014 p 67 John Sellars Stoicism Routledge 2014 pp 84 85 Chrysippus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Zeller 1880 p 178 a b Zeller 1880 p 176 a b Zeller 1880 p 175 Zeller 1880 p 174 Cicero On Fate 20 21 Zeller 1880 p 177 Zeller 1880 p 181 a b Kenny 2006 p 195 referencing Cicero On Fate 28 29 Zeller 1880 p 182 Diogenianus in Eusebius Praeparatio evangelica vi 8 quoted in Inwood amp Gerson 1997 p 190 Brunschwig amp Sedley 2003 p 172 a b c Zeller 1880 p 179 a b Zeller 1880 p 180 Gould 1970 p 152 note 3 Gould 1970 pp 144 145 a b c Hicks 1911 p 947 a b c Cicero De Natura Deorum i 15 Max Bernhard Weinsten Welt und Lebensanschauungen Hervorgegangen aus Religion Philosophie und Naturerkenntnis World and Life Views Emerging From Religion Philosophy and Perception of Nature 1910 p 233 Cicero De Natura Deorum iii 10 Cf ii 6 for the fuller version of this argument Cicero De Natura Deorum iii 10 Plutarch De Stoicorum Repugnantiis 1051 B a b Aulus Gellius vii 1 Plutarch De Stoicorum Repugnantiis 1050 E De Communibus Notitiis 1065 B Plutarch De Communibus Notitiis 1065 D Gould 1970 p 116 a b Gould 1970 p 117 Plutarch De Communibus Notitiis 1079F a b Gould 1970 p 118 a b Heath 1921 p 69 Iamblichus in Nicom ii 8f Syrianus in Arist Metaph Kroll 140 9f Galen On The Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato iii 3 13 22 iv 2 27 iv 6 19 27 Stock 1908 p 13 Gould 1970 p 163 Diogenes Laertius vii 87 Diogenes Laertius vii 88 a b c d e Davidson 1908 p 615 a b Kenny 2006 pp 282 283 a b Zeller 1880 p 284 a b Gould 1970 p 186 Sharples 2014 p 68 Gould 1970 p 187 a b Gould 1970 p 188 Works cited edit Barnes Jonathan 1999 The History of Hellenistic Logic in Algra Keimpe Barnes Jonathan Mansfeld Jaap Schofield Malcolm eds The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 0521616700 Brunschwig Jacques Sedley David 2003 Hellenistic philosophy in Sedley David ed The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 0521775035 Davidson William Leslie 1908 Chrysippus in Hastings James ed Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics vol 3 T amp T Clark Dorandi Tiziano 1999 Chronology in Algra Keimpe Barnes Jonathan Mansfeld Jaap Schofield Malcolm eds The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 0521616700 Fitzgerald John T 2004 Philodemus and the Papyri from Herculaneum in Fitzgerald John T Obbink Dirk Holland Glenn Stanfield eds Philodemus and the New Testament world Philosophy Brill ISBN 9004114602 Gould Josiah 1970 The Philosophy of Chrysippus SUNY ISBN 087395064X Green Peter 1993 Alexander to Actium the historical evolution of the Hellenistic age University of California Press ISBN 0520083490 Heath Thomas Little 1921 A History of Greek Mathematics Vol 1 From Thales to Euclid Oxford Hicks Robert Drew 1910 Stoic and Epicurean C Scribner Hicks Robert Drew 1911 Stoics In Chisholm Hugh ed Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 25 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 942 951 Inwood Brad Gerson Lloyd P 1997 Hellenistic Philosophy Introductory Readings Hackett ISBN 0872203786 Johansen Karsten Friis Rosenmeier Henrik 1998 A History of Ancient Philosophy From the Beginnings to Augustine Routledge ISBN 0415127386 Kenny Anthony 2006 Ancient Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 0198752733 Kneale William Kneale Martha 1962 The Development of Logic Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824773 9 nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925 The Stoics Zeno Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 2 7 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925b The Stoics Cleanthes Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 2 7 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library nbsp Laertius Diogenes 1925c The Stoics Chrysippus Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 2 7 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library Long A A Sedley D N eds 1987 The Hellenistic Philosophers Cambridge University Press Luhtala Anneli 2000 On the Origin of Syntactical Description in Stoic Logic Nodus Publikationen ISBN 3893234578 Mates Benson 1953 Stoic Logic University of California Press O Toole Robert R Jennings Raymond E 2004 The Megarians and the Stoics in Gabbay Dov Woods John eds Handbook of the History of Logic Greek Indian and Arabic logic North Holland ISBN 0444504664 Rist John M 1969 Stoic Philosophy Cambridge University Press Rist John M ed 1978 The Stoics University of California Press ISBN 0 520 03135 0 Sharples R W 2014 Stoics Epicureans and Sceptics An Introduction to Hellenistic Philosophy Routledge pp 67 68 ISBN 978 1134836390 Stock St George William Joseph 1908 Stoicism Constable Zeller Eduard 1880 The Stoics Epicureans and Sceptics LongmansFurther reading edit Bobzien Susanne 1998 Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 0199247676 Bobzien Susanne 1999 Chrysippus Theory of Causes In K Ierodiakonou ed Topics in Stoic Philosophy Oxford OUP 196 242 ISBN 019924880X Brehier Emile 1951 Chrysippe et l ancien stoicisme Paris ISBN 2903925062 Dufour Richard 2004 Chrysippe Oeuvre philosophique Textes traduits et commentes par Richard Dufour Paris Les Belles Lettres 2 volumes logic and physics ISBN 2251742034 Hahm D E Chrysippus solution to the Democritean dilemma of the cone Isis 63 217 1972 205 220 Holiday Ryan Hanselman Stephen 2020 Chrysippus the Fighter Lives of the Stoics New York Portfolio Penguin pp 38 49 ISBN 978 0525541875 Ide H A Chrysippus s response to Diodorus s Master Argument History and Philosophy Logic 13 2 1992 133 148 Jedan Christoph 2009 Stoic Virtues Chrysippus and the Theological Foundations of Stoic Ethics Continuum Studies in Ancient Philosophy ISBN 1441112529 Tieleman Teun L 1996 Galen and Chrysippus on the Soul Argument and Refutation in the De Placitis Books II III Philosophia Antiqua Brill ISBN 9004105204 Tieleman Teun L 2003 Chrysippus on Affections Reconstruction and Interpretation Philosophia Antiqua Brill ISBN 9004129987External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Chrysippus nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Chrysippus of Soli Kirby Jeremy Chrysippus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F Chrysippus MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews Early Stoic Logic Zeno of Citium Cleanthes of Assos Chrysippus of Soli an annotated bibliography on the logic of ChrysippusPreceded byCleanthes Leader of the Stoic school230 206 BC Succeeded byZeno of Tarsus Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Chrysippus amp oldid 1183972125, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.