fbpx
Wikipedia

Zeno's paradoxes

Zeno's paradoxes are a series of philosophical arguments presented by the ancient Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea (c. 490–430 BC),[1][2] primarily known through the works of Plato, Aristotle, and later commentators like Simplicius of Cilicia.[2] Zeno devised these paradoxes to support his teacher Parmenides's philosophy of monism, which posits that despite our sensory experiences, reality is singular and unchanging. The paradoxes famously challenge the notions of plurality (the existence of many things), motion, space, and time by suggesting they lead to logical contradictions.

Zeno's work, primarily known from second-hand accounts since his original texts are lost, comprises forty "paradoxes of plurality," which argue against the coherence of believing in multiple existences, and several arguments against motion and change.[2] Of these, only a few are definitively known today, including the renowned "Achilles Paradox", which illustrates the problematic concept of infinite divisibility in space and time.[1][2] In this paradox, Zeno argues that a swift runner like Achilles cannot overtake a slower moving tortoise with a head start, because the distance between them can be infinitely subdivided, implying Achilles would require an infinite number of steps to catch the tortoise.[1][2]

These paradoxes have stirred extensive philosophical and mathematical discussion throughout history,[1][2] particularly regarding the nature of infinity and the continuity of space and time. Initially, Aristotle's interpretation, suggesting a potential rather than actual infinity, was widely accepted.[1] However, modern solutions leveraging the mathematical framework of calculus have provided a different perspective, highlighting Zeno's significant early insight into the complexities of infinity and continuous motion.[1] Zeno's paradoxes remain a pivotal reference point in the philosophical and mathematical exploration of reality, motion, and the infinite, influencing both ancient thought and modern scientific understanding.[1][2]

History edit

The origins of the paradoxes are somewhat unclear, but they are generally thought to have been developed to support Parmenides' doctrine of monism, that all of reality is one, and that all change is impossible, that is, that nothing ever changes in location or in any other respect.[1][2] Diogenes Laërtius, citing Favorinus, says that Zeno's teacher Parmenides was the first to introduce the paradox of Achilles and the tortoise. But in a later passage, Laërtius attributes the origin of the paradox to Zeno, explaining that Favorinus disagrees.[3] Modern academics attribute the paradox to Zeno.[1][2]

Many of these paradoxes argue that contrary to the evidence of one's senses, motion is nothing but an illusion.[1][2] In Plato's Parmenides (128a–d), Zeno is characterized as taking on the project of creating these paradoxes because other philosophers claimed paradoxes arise when considering Parmenides' view. Zeno's arguments may then be early examples of a method of proof called reductio ad absurdum, also known as proof by contradiction. Thus Plato has Zeno say the purpose of the paradoxes "is to show that their hypothesis that existences are many, if properly followed up, leads to still more absurd results than the hypothesis that they are one."[4] Plato has Socrates claim that Zeno and Parmenides were essentially arguing exactly the same point.[5] They are also credited as a source of the dialectic method used by Socrates.[6]

Paradoxes edit

Some of Zeno's nine surviving paradoxes (preserved in Aristotle's Physics[7][8] and Simplicius's commentary thereon) are essentially equivalent to one another. Aristotle offered a response to some of them.[7] Popular literature often misrepresents Zeno's arguments. For example, Zeno is often said to have argued that the sum of an infinite number of terms must itself be infinite–with the result that not only the time, but also the distance to be travelled, become infinite.[9] However, none of the original ancient sources has Zeno discussing the sum of any infinite series. Simplicius has Zeno saying "it is impossible to traverse an infinite number of things in a finite time". This presents Zeno's problem not with finding the sum, but rather with finishing a task with an infinite number of steps: how can one ever get from A to B, if an infinite number of (non-instantaneous) events can be identified that need to precede the arrival at B, and one cannot reach even the beginning of a "last event"?[10][11][12][13]

Paradoxes of motion edit

Three of the strongest and most famous—that of Achilles and the tortoise, the Dichotomy argument, and that of an arrow in flight—are presented in detail below.

Dichotomy paradox edit

 
The dichotomy

That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal.

— as recounted by Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b10

Suppose Atalanta wishes to walk to the end of a path. Before she can get there, she must get halfway there. Before she can get halfway there, she must get a quarter of the way there. Before traveling a quarter, she must travel one-eighth; before an eighth, one-sixteenth; and so on.

The resulting sequence can be represented as:

 

This description requires one to complete an infinite number of tasks, which Zeno maintains is an impossibility.[14]

This sequence also presents a second problem in that it contains no first distance to run, for any possible (finite) first distance could be divided in half, and hence would not be first after all. Hence, the trip cannot even begin. The paradoxical conclusion then would be that travel over any finite distance can be neither completed nor begun, and so all motion must be an illusion.[15]

This argument is called the "Dichotomy" because it involves repeatedly splitting a distance into two parts. An example with the original sense can be found in an asymptote. It is also known as the Race Course paradox.

Achilles and the tortoise edit

 
Achilles and the tortoise

In a race, the quickest runner can never over­take the slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point whence the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold a lead.

— as recounted by Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b15

In the paradox of Achilles and the tortoise, Achilles is in a footrace with the tortoise. Achilles allows the tortoise a head start of 100 meters, for example. Suppose that each racer starts running at some constant speed, one faster than the other. After some finite time, Achilles will have run 100 meters, bringing him to the tortoise's starting point. During this time, the tortoise has run a much shorter distance, say 2 meters. It will then take Achilles some further time to run that distance, by which time the tortoise will have advanced farther; and then more time still to reach this third point, while the tortoise moves ahead. Thus, whenever Achilles arrives somewhere the tortoise has been, he still has some distance to go before he can even reach the tortoise. As Aristotle noted, this argument is similar to the Dichotomy.[16] It lacks, however, the apparent conclusion of motionlessness.

Arrow paradox edit

 
The arrow

If everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest at that instant of time, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless at that instant of time and at the next instant of time but if both instants of time are taken as the same instant or continuous instant of time then it is in motion.[17]

— as recounted by Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b5

In the arrow paradox, Zeno states that for motion to occur, an object must change the position which it occupies. He gives an example of an arrow in flight. He states that at any one (durationless) instant of time, the arrow is neither moving to where it is, nor to where it is not.[18] It cannot move to where it is not, because no time elapses for it to move there; it cannot move to where it is, because it is already there. In other words, at every instant of time there is no motion occurring. If everything is motionless at every instant, and time is entirely composed of instants, then motion is impossible.

Whereas the first two paradoxes divide space, this paradox starts by dividing time—and not into segments, but into points.[19]

Other paradoxes edit

Aristotle gives three other paradoxes.

Paradox of place edit

From Aristotle:

If everything that exists has a place, place too will have a place, and so on ad infinitum.[20]

Paradox of the grain of millet edit

Description of the paradox from the Routledge Dictionary of Philosophy:

The argument is that a single grain of millet makes no sound upon falling, but a thousand grains make a sound. Hence a thousand nothings become something, an absurd conclusion.[21]

Aristotle's response:

Zeno's reasoning is false when he argues that there is no part of the millet that does not make a sound: for there is no reason why any such part should not in any length of time fail to move the air that the whole bushel moves in falling. In fact it does not of itself move even such a quantity of the air as it would move if this part were by itself: for no part even exists otherwise than potentially.[22]

Description from Nick Huggett:

This is a Parmenidean argument that one cannot trust one's sense of hearing. Aristotle's response seems to be that even inaudible sounds can add to an audible sound.[23]

The moving rows (or stadium) edit

 
The moving rows

From Aristotle:

... concerning the two rows of bodies, each row being composed of an equal number of bodies of equal size, passing each other on a race-course as they proceed with equal velocity in opposite directions, the one row originally occupying the space between the goal and the middle point of the course and the other that between the middle point and the starting-post. This...involves the conclusion that half a given time is equal to double that time.[24]

An expanded account of Zeno's arguments, as presented by Aristotle, is given in Simplicius's commentary On Aristotle's Physics.[25][2][1]

Proposed solutions edit

In classical antiquity edit

According to Simplicius, Diogenes the Cynic said nothing upon hearing Zeno's arguments, but stood up and walked, in order to demonstrate the falsity of Zeno's conclusions.[25][2] To fully solve any of the paradoxes, however, one needs to show what is wrong with the argument, not just the conclusions. Throughout history several solutions have been proposed, among the earliest recorded being those of Aristotle and Archimedes.

Aristotle (384 BC–322 BC) remarked that as the distance decreases, the time needed to cover those distances also decreases, so that the time needed also becomes increasingly small.[26][failed verification][27] Aristotle also distinguished "things infinite in respect of divisibility" (such as a unit of space that can be mentally divided into ever smaller units while remaining spatially the same) from things (or distances) that are infinite in extension ("with respect to their extremities").[28] Aristotle's objection to the arrow paradox was that "Time is not composed of indivisible nows any more than any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles."[29] Thomas Aquinas, commenting on Aristotle's objection, wrote "Instants are not parts of time, for time is not made up of instants any more than a magnitude is made of points, as we have already proved. Hence it does not follow that a thing is not in motion in a given time, just because it is not in motion in any instant of that time."[30][31][32]

In modern mathematics edit

Some mathematicians and historians, such as Carl Boyer, hold that Zeno's paradoxes are simply mathematical problems, for which modern calculus provides a mathematical solution.[33] Infinite processes remained theoretically troublesome in mathematics until the late 19th century. With the epsilon-delta definition of limit, Weierstrass and Cauchy developed a rigorous formulation of the logic and calculus involved. These works resolved the mathematics involving infinite processes.[34][35]

Some philosophers, however, say that Zeno's paradoxes and their variations (see Thomson's lamp) remain relevant metaphysical problems.[10][11][12] While mathematics can calculate where and when the moving Achilles will overtake the Tortoise of Zeno's paradox, philosophers such as Kevin Brown[10] and Francis Moorcroft[11] hold that mathematics does not address the central point in Zeno's argument, and that solving the mathematical issues does not solve every issue the paradoxes raise. Brown concludes "Given the history of 'final resolutions', from Aristotle onwards, it's probably foolhardy to think we've reached the end. It may be that Zeno's arguments on motion, because of their simplicity and universality, will always serve as a kind of 'Rorschach image' onto which people can project their most fundamental phenomenological concerns (if they have any)."[10]

Henri Bergson edit

An alternative conclusion, proposed by Henri Bergson in his 1896 book Matter and Memory, is that, while the path is divisible, the motion is not.[36][37]

Peter Lynds edit

In 2003, Peter Lynds argued that all of Zeno's motion paradoxes are resolved by the conclusion that instants in time and instantaneous magnitudes do not physically exist.[38][39][40] Lynds argues that an object in relative motion cannot have an instantaneous or determined relative position (for if it did, it could not be in motion), and so cannot have its motion fractionally dissected as if it does, as is assumed by the paradoxes. Nick Huggett argues that Zeno is assuming the conclusion when he says that objects that occupy the same space as they do at rest must be at rest.[19]

Bertrand Russell edit

Based on the work of Georg Cantor,[41] Bertrand Russell offered a solution to the paradoxes, what is known as the "at-at theory of motion". It agrees that there can be no motion "during" a durationless instant, and contends that all that is required for motion is that the arrow be at one point at one time, at another point another time, and at appropriate points between those two points for intervening times. In this view motion is just change in position over time.[42][43]

Hermann Weyl edit

Another proposed solution is to question one of the assumptions Zeno used in his paradoxes (particularly the Dichotomy), which is that between any two different points in space (or time), there is always another point. Without this assumption there are only a finite number of distances between two points, hence there is no infinite sequence of movements, and the paradox is resolved. According to Hermann Weyl, the assumption that space is made of finite and discrete units is subject to a further problem, given by the "tile argument" or "distance function problem".[44][45] According to this, the length of the hypotenuse of a right angled triangle in discretized space is always equal to the length of one of the two sides, in contradiction to geometry. Jean Paul Van Bendegem has argued that the Tile Argument can be resolved, and that discretization can therefore remove the paradox.[33][46]

Applications edit

Quantum Zeno effect edit

In 1977,[47] physicists E. C. George Sudarshan and B. Misra discovered that the dynamical evolution (motion) of a quantum system can be hindered (or even inhibited) through observation of the system.[48] This effect is usually called the "quantum Zeno effect" as it is strongly reminiscent of Zeno's arrow paradox. This effect was first theorized in 1958.[49]

Zeno behaviour edit

In the field of verification and design of timed and hybrid systems, the system behaviour is called Zeno if it includes an infinite number of discrete steps in a finite amount of time.[50] Some formal verification techniques exclude these behaviours from analysis, if they are not equivalent to non-Zeno behaviour.[51][52] In systems design these behaviours will also often be excluded from system models, since they cannot be implemented with a digital controller.[53]

In popular culture edit

A humorous take is offered by Tom Stoppard in his 1972 play Jumpers, in which the principal protagonist, the philosophy professor George Moore, suggests that according to Zeno's paradox, Saint Sebastian, a 3rd Century Christian saint martyred by being shot with arrows, died of fright.

In 1969, The Firesign Theatre used a version of Zeno's dichotomy paradox when speaking road signs for an approaching exit continued to divide in half, with the destination never being reached by the driver, on their second LP, "How Can You Be In Two Places at Once, When You're Not Anywhere At All."

Folk musicians Lou and Peter Berryman provide a humorous variation in their song "An Hour Away", in which the driver of a car keeps encountering construction that requires a slower speed, so that even as they keep driving, their destination remains an hour away and they can't reach their romantic interest.

Similar paradoxes edit

School of Names edit

 
Diagram of Hui Shi's stick paradox

Roughly contemporaneously during the Warring States period (475–221 BCE), ancient Chinese philosophers from the School of Names, a school of thought similarly concerned with logic and dialectics, developed paradoxes similar to those of Zeno. The works of the School of Names have largely been lost, with the exception of portions of the Gongsun Longzi. The second of the Ten Theses of Hui Shi suggests knowledge of infinitesimals:That which has no thickness cannot be piled up; yet it is a thousand li in dimension. Among the many puzzles of his recorded in the Zhuangzi is one very similar to Zeno's Dichotomy:

"If from a stick a foot long you every day take the half of it, in a myriad ages it will not be exhausted."

— Zhuangzi, chapter 33 (Legge translation)[54]

The Mohist canon appears to propose a solution to this paradox by arguing that in moving across a measured length, the distance is not covered in successive fractions of the length, but in one stage. Due to the lack of surviving works from the School of Names, most of the other paradoxes listed are difficult to interpret.[55]

Lewis Carroll's What the Tortoise Said to Achilles edit

"What the Tortoise Said to Achilles",[56] written in 1895 by Lewis Carroll, which described a paradoxical infinite regress argument in the realm of pure logic, used Achilles and the Tortoise as characters, in a clear reference to Zeno's paradox of Achilles.[57]

Douglas Hofstadter's Gödel, Escher, Bach edit

Notably,[58] Douglas Hofstadter's Gödel, Escher, Bach, inspired by Carroll, features the same characters in dialogues throughout the book,[58] which is a popular, award-winning 742-page book on the foundations of mathematics and its relationship to artificial intelligence.[58]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k "Zeno's Paradoxes | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2024-03-25.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Huggett, Nick (2024), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Zeno's Paradoxes", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-03-25
  3. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, Lives, 9.23 and 9.29.
  4. ^ Parmenides 128d
  5. ^ Parmenides 128a–b
  6. ^ ([fragment 65], Diogenes Laërtius. IX 2010-12-12 at the Wayback Machine 25ff and VIII 57).
  7. ^ a b Aristotle's Physics 2011-01-06 at the Wayback Machine "Physics" by Aristotle translated by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye
  8. ^ . Archived from the original on 2008-05-16.
  9. ^ Benson, Donald C. (1999). The Moment of Proof : Mathematical Epiphanies. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 14. ISBN 978-0195117219.
  10. ^ a b c d Brown, Kevin. "Zeno and the Paradox of Motion". Reflections on Relativity. Archived from the original on 2012-12-05. Retrieved 2010-06-06.
  11. ^ a b c Moorcroft, Francis. . Archived from the original on 2010-04-18.
  12. ^ a b Papa-Grimaldi, Alba (1996). "Why Mathematical Solutions of Zeno's Paradoxes Miss the Point: Zeno's One and Many Relation and Parmenides' Prohibition" (PDF). The Review of Metaphysics. 50: 299–314. (PDF) from the original on 2012-06-09. Retrieved 2012-03-06.
  13. ^ Huggett, Nick (2010). "Zeno's Paradoxes: 5. Zeno's Influence on Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2022-03-01. Retrieved 2011-03-07.
  14. ^ Lindberg, David (2007). The Beginnings of Western Science (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press. p. 33. ISBN 978-0-226-48205-7.
  15. ^ Huggett, Nick (2010). "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.1 The Dichotomy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2022-03-01. Retrieved 2011-03-07.
  16. ^ Huggett, Nick (2010). "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.2 Achilles and the Tortoise". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2022-03-01. Retrieved 2011-03-07.
  17. ^ Aristotle. "Physics". The Internet Classics Archive. from the original on 2008-05-15. Retrieved 2012-08-21. Zeno's reasoning, however, is fallacious, when he says that if everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. This is false, for time is not composed of indivisible moments any more than any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles.
  18. ^ Laërtius, Diogenes (c. 230). "Pyrrho". Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. Vol. IX. passage 72. ISBN 1-116-71900-2. Archived from the original on 2011-08-22. Retrieved 2011-03-05.
  19. ^ a b Huggett, Nick (2010). "Zeno's Paradoxes: 3.3 The Arrow". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2022-03-01. Retrieved 2011-03-07.
  20. ^ Aristotle Physics IV:1, 209a25 2008-05-09 at the Wayback Machine
  21. ^ The Michael Proudfoot, A.R. Lace. Routledge Dictionary of Philosophy. Routledge 2009, p. 445
  22. ^ Aristotle Physics VII:5, 250a20 2008-05-11 at the Wayback Machine
  23. ^ Huggett, Nick, "Zeno's Paradoxes", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/#GraMil 2022-03-01 at the Wayback Machine
  24. ^ Aristotle Physics VI:9, 239b33 2008-05-15 at the Wayback Machine
  25. ^ a b Simplikios; Konstan, David; Simplikios (1989). Simplicius on Aristotle's Physics 6. Ancient commentators on Aristotle. Ithaca N.Y: Cornell Univ. Pr. ISBN 978-0-8014-2238-6.
  26. ^ Aristotle. Physics 6.9
  27. ^ Aristotle's observation that the fractional times also get shorter does not guarantee, in every case, that the task can be completed. One case in which it does not hold is that in which the fractional times decrease in a harmonic series, while the distances decrease geometrically, such as: 1/2 s for 1/2 m gain, 1/3 s for next 1/4 m gain, 1/4 s for next 1/8 m gain, 1/5 s for next 1/16 m gain, 1/6 s for next 1/32 m gain, etc. In this case, the distances form a convergent series, but the times form a divergent series, the sum of which has no limit. [original research?] Archimedes developed a more explicitly mathematical approach than Aristotle.
  28. ^ Aristotle. Physics 6.9; 6.2, 233a21-31
  29. ^ Aristotle. Physics. Vol. VI. Part 9 verse: 239b5. ISBN 0-585-09205-2. from the original on 2008-05-15. Retrieved 2008-08-11.
  30. ^ Aquinas. Commentary on Aristotle's Physics, Book 6.861
  31. ^ Kiritsis, Paul (2020-04-01). A Critical Investigation into Precognitive Dreams (1 ed.). Cambridge Scholars Publishing. p. 19. ISBN 978-1527546332.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  32. ^ Aquinas, Thomas. "Commentary on Aristotle's Physics". aquinas.cc. Retrieved 2024-03-25.
  33. ^ a b Boyer, Carl (1959). The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development. Dover Publications. p. 295. ISBN 978-0-486-60509-8. Retrieved 2010-02-26. If the paradoxes are thus stated in the precise mathematical terminology of continuous variables (...) the seeming contradictions resolve themselves.
  34. ^ Lee, Harold (1965). "Are Zeno's Paradoxes Based on a Mistake?". Mind. 74 (296). Oxford University Press: 563–570. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXIV.296.563. JSTOR 2251675.
  35. ^ B Russell (1956) Mathematics and the metaphysicians in "The World of Mathematics" (ed. J R Newman), pp 1576-1590.
  36. ^ Bergson, Henri (1896). Matière et Mémoire [Matter and Memory] (PDF). Translation 1911 by Nancy Margaret Paul & W. Scott Palmer. George Allen and Unwin. pp. 77–78 of the PDF. (PDF) from the original on 2019-10-15. Retrieved 2019-10-15.
  37. ^ Massumi, Brian (2002). Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation (1st ed.). Durham, NC: Duke University Press Books. pp. 5–6. ISBN 978-0822328971.
  38. ^ "Zeno's Paradoxes: A Timely Solution". January 2003. from the original on 2012-08-13. Retrieved 2012-07-02.
  39. ^ Lynds, Peter. Time and Classical and Quantum Mechanics: Indeterminacy vs. Discontinuity. Foundations of Physics Letter s (Vol. 16, Issue 4, 2003). doi:10.1023/A:1025361725408
  40. ^ Time’s Up, Einstein 2012-12-30 at the Wayback Machine, Josh McHugh, Wired Magazine, June 2005
  41. ^ Russell, Bertrand (2002) [First published in 1914 by The Open Court Publishing Company]. "Lecture 6. The Problem of Infinity Considered Historically". Our Knowledge of the External World: As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy. Routledge. p. 169. ISBN 0-415-09605-7.
  42. ^ Huggett, Nick (1999). Space From Zeno to Einstein. MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-08271-3.
  43. ^ Salmon, Wesley C. (1998). Causality and Explanation. Oxford University Press. p. 198. ISBN 978-0-19-510864-4. from the original on 2023-12-29. Retrieved 2020-11-21.
  44. ^ Van Bendegem, Jean Paul (17 March 2010). "Finitism in Geometry". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 2008-05-12. Retrieved 2012-01-03.
  45. ^ Cohen, Marc (11 December 2000). . History of Ancient Philosophy, University of Washington. Archived from the original on July 12, 2010. Retrieved 2012-01-03.
  46. ^ van Bendegem, Jean Paul (1987). "Discussion:Zeno's Paradoxes and the Tile Argument". Philosophy of Science. 54 (2). Belgium: 295–302. doi:10.1086/289379. JSTOR 187807. S2CID 224840314.
  47. ^ Sudarshan, E. C. G.; Misra, B. (1977). "The Zeno's paradox in quantum theory" (PDF). Journal of Mathematical Physics. 18 (4): 756–763. Bibcode:1977JMP....18..756M. doi:10.1063/1.523304. OSTI 7342282. (PDF) from the original on 2013-05-14. Retrieved 2018-04-20.
  48. ^ W.M.Itano; D.J. Heinsen; J.J. Bokkinger; D.J. Wineland (1990). (PDF). Physical Review A. 41 (5): 2295–2300. Bibcode:1990PhRvA..41.2295I. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.41.2295. PMID 9903355. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2004-07-20. Retrieved 2004-07-23.
  49. ^ Khalfin, L.A. (1958). "Contribution to the Decay Theory of a Quasi-Stationary State". Soviet Phys. JETP. 6: 1053. Bibcode:1958JETP....6.1053K.
  50. ^ Paul A. Fishwick, ed. (1 June 2007). "15.6 "Pathological Behavior Classes" in chapter 15 "Hybrid Dynamic Systems: Modeling and Execution" by Pieter J. Mosterman, The Mathworks, Inc.". Handbook of dynamic system modeling. Chapman & Hall/CRC Computer and Information Science (hardcover ed.). Boca Raton, Florida, USA: CRC Press. pp. 15–22 to 15–23. ISBN 978-1-58488-565-8. from the original on 2023-12-29. Retrieved 2010-03-05.
  51. ^ Lamport, Leslie (2002). Specifying Systems (PDF). Addison-Wesley. p. 128. ISBN 0-321-14306-X. (PDF) from the original on 2010-11-16. Retrieved 2010-03-06. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  52. ^ Zhang, Jun; Johansson, Karl; Lygeros, John; Sastry, Shankar (2001). (PDF). International Journal for Robust and Nonlinear Control. 11 (5): 435. doi:10.1002/rnc.592. S2CID 2057416. Archived from the original (PDF) on August 11, 2011. Retrieved 2010-02-28.
  53. ^ Franck, Cassez; Henzinger, Thomas; Raskin, Jean-Francois (2002). . Archived from the original on May 28, 2008. Retrieved 2010-03-02. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  54. ^ Müller, Max, ed. (1891). "The Writings of Kwang Tse". Sacred Books of the East. Vol. 40. Translated by Legge, James. Oxford University Press.
  55. ^ "School of Names > Miscellaneous Paradoxes (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu. from the original on 2016-12-11. Retrieved 2020-01-30.
  56. ^ Carroll, Lewis (1895-04-01). "What the Tortoise Said to Achilles". Mind. IV (14): 278–280. doi:10.1093/mind/IV.14.278. ISSN 0026-4423. from the original on 2020-07-20. Retrieved 2020-07-20.
  57. ^ Tsilipakos, Leonidas (2021). Clarity and confusion in social theory: taking concepts seriously. Philosophy and method in the social sciences. Abingdon New York (N.Y.): Routledge. p. 48. ISBN 978-1-032-09883-8.
  58. ^ a b c Bunch, Bryan H. (1997). Mathematical fallacies and paradoxes. Mineola, N.Y: Dover Publ. p. 204. ISBN 978-0-486-29664-7.

References edit

External links edit

zeno, paradoxes, arrow, paradox, redirects, here, other, uses, arrow, paradox, disambiguation, this, article, relies, excessively, references, primary, sources, please, improve, this, article, adding, secondary, tertiary, sources, find, sources, news, newspape. Arrow paradox redirects here For other uses see Arrow paradox disambiguation This article relies excessively on references to primary sources Please improve this article by adding secondary or tertiary sources Find sources Zeno s paradoxes news newspapers books scholar JSTOR March 2023 Learn how and when to remove this message Zeno s paradoxes are a series of philosophical arguments presented by the ancient Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea c 490 430 BC 1 2 primarily known through the works of Plato Aristotle and later commentators like Simplicius of Cilicia 2 Zeno devised these paradoxes to support his teacher Parmenides s philosophy of monism which posits that despite our sensory experiences reality is singular and unchanging The paradoxes famously challenge the notions of plurality the existence of many things motion space and time by suggesting they lead to logical contradictions Zeno s work primarily known from second hand accounts since his original texts are lost comprises forty paradoxes of plurality which argue against the coherence of believing in multiple existences and several arguments against motion and change 2 Of these only a few are definitively known today including the renowned Achilles Paradox which illustrates the problematic concept of infinite divisibility in space and time 1 2 In this paradox Zeno argues that a swift runner like Achilles cannot overtake a slower moving tortoise with a head start because the distance between them can be infinitely subdivided implying Achilles would require an infinite number of steps to catch the tortoise 1 2 These paradoxes have stirred extensive philosophical and mathematical discussion throughout history 1 2 particularly regarding the nature of infinity and the continuity of space and time Initially Aristotle s interpretation suggesting a potential rather than actual infinity was widely accepted 1 However modern solutions leveraging the mathematical framework of calculus have provided a different perspective highlighting Zeno s significant early insight into the complexities of infinity and continuous motion 1 Zeno s paradoxes remain a pivotal reference point in the philosophical and mathematical exploration of reality motion and the infinite influencing both ancient thought and modern scientific understanding 1 2 Contents 1 History 2 Paradoxes 2 1 Paradoxes of motion 2 1 1 Dichotomy paradox 2 1 2 Achilles and the tortoise 2 1 3 Arrow paradox 2 2 Other paradoxes 2 2 1 Paradox of place 2 2 2 Paradox of the grain of millet 2 2 3 The moving rows or stadium 3 Proposed solutions 3 1 In classical antiquity 3 2 In modern mathematics 3 2 1 Henri Bergson 3 2 2 Peter Lynds 3 2 3 Bertrand Russell 3 2 4 Hermann Weyl 3 3 Applications 3 3 1 Quantum Zeno effect 3 3 2 Zeno behaviour 3 4 In popular culture 4 Similar paradoxes 4 1 School of Names 4 2 Lewis Carroll s What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 4 3 Douglas Hofstadter s Godel Escher Bach 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 External linksHistory editThe origins of the paradoxes are somewhat unclear but they are generally thought to have been developed to support Parmenides doctrine of monism that all of reality is one and that all change is impossible that is that nothing ever changes in location or in any other respect 1 2 Diogenes Laertius citing Favorinus says that Zeno s teacher Parmenides was the first to introduce the paradox of Achilles and the tortoise But in a later passage Laertius attributes the origin of the paradox to Zeno explaining that Favorinus disagrees 3 Modern academics attribute the paradox to Zeno 1 2 Many of these paradoxes argue that contrary to the evidence of one s senses motion is nothing but an illusion 1 2 In Plato s Parmenides 128a d Zeno is characterized as taking on the project of creating these paradoxes because other philosophers claimed paradoxes arise when considering Parmenides view Zeno s arguments may then be early examples of a method of proof called reductio ad absurdum also known as proof by contradiction Thus Plato has Zeno say the purpose of the paradoxes is to show that their hypothesis that existences are many if properly followed up leads to still more absurd results than the hypothesis that they are one 4 Plato has Socrates claim that Zeno and Parmenides were essentially arguing exactly the same point 5 They are also credited as a source of the dialectic method used by Socrates 6 Paradoxes editSome of Zeno s nine surviving paradoxes preserved in Aristotle s Physics 7 8 and Simplicius s commentary thereon are essentially equivalent to one another Aristotle offered a response to some of them 7 Popular literature often misrepresents Zeno s arguments For example Zeno is often said to have argued that the sum of an infinite number of terms must itself be infinite with the result that not only the time but also the distance to be travelled become infinite 9 However none of the original ancient sources has Zeno discussing the sum of any infinite series Simplicius has Zeno saying it is impossible to traverse an infinite number of things in a finite time This presents Zeno s problem not with finding the sum but rather with finishing a task with an infinite number of steps how can one ever get from A to B if an infinite number of non instantaneous events can be identified that need to precede the arrival at B and one cannot reach even the beginning of a last event 10 11 12 13 Paradoxes of motion edit Three of the strongest and most famous that of Achilles and the tortoise the Dichotomy argument and that of an arrow in flight are presented in detail below Dichotomy paradox edit nbsp The dichotomy That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half way stage before it arrives at the goal as recounted by Aristotle Physics VI 9 239b10 Suppose Atalanta wishes to walk to the end of a path Before she can get there she must get halfway there Before she can get halfway there she must get a quarter of the way there Before traveling a quarter she must travel one eighth before an eighth one sixteenth and so on The resulting sequence can be represented as 1 16 1 8 1 4 1 2 1 displaystyle left cdots frac 1 16 frac 1 8 frac 1 4 frac 1 2 1 right nbsp This description requires one to complete an infinite number of tasks which Zeno maintains is an impossibility 14 This sequence also presents a second problem in that it contains no first distance to run for any possible finite first distance could be divided in half and hence would not be first after all Hence the trip cannot even begin The paradoxical conclusion then would be that travel over any finite distance can be neither completed nor begun and so all motion must be an illusion 15 This argument is called the Dichotomy because it involves repeatedly splitting a distance into two parts An example with the original sense can be found in an asymptote It is also known as the Race Course paradox Achilles and the tortoise edit Achilles and the Tortoise redirects here For other uses see Achilles and the Tortoise disambiguation See also Infinity Zeno Achilles and the tortoise nbsp Achilles and the tortoise In a race the quickest runner can never over take the slowest since the pursuer must first reach the point whence the pursued started so that the slower must always hold a lead as recounted by Aristotle Physics VI 9 239b15 In the paradox of Achilles and the tortoise Achilles is in a footrace with the tortoise Achilles allows the tortoise a head start of 100 meters for example Suppose that each racer starts running at some constant speed one faster than the other After some finite time Achilles will have run 100 meters bringing him to the tortoise s starting point During this time the tortoise has run a much shorter distance say 2 meters It will then take Achilles some further time to run that distance by which time the tortoise will have advanced farther and then more time still to reach this third point while the tortoise moves ahead Thus whenever Achilles arrives somewhere the tortoise has been he still has some distance to go before he can even reach the tortoise As Aristotle noted this argument is similar to the Dichotomy 16 It lacks however the apparent conclusion of motionlessness Arrow paradox edit nbsp The arrow Not to be confused with other paradoxes of the same name If everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest at that instant of time and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment the flying arrow is therefore motionless at that instant of time and at the next instant of time but if both instants of time are taken as the same instant or continuous instant of time then it is in motion 17 as recounted by Aristotle Physics VI 9 239b5 In the arrow paradox Zeno states that for motion to occur an object must change the position which it occupies He gives an example of an arrow in flight He states that at any one durationless instant of time the arrow is neither moving to where it is nor to where it is not 18 It cannot move to where it is not because no time elapses for it to move there it cannot move to where it is because it is already there In other words at every instant of time there is no motion occurring If everything is motionless at every instant and time is entirely composed of instants then motion is impossible Whereas the first two paradoxes divide space this paradox starts by dividing time and not into segments but into points 19 Other paradoxes edit Aristotle gives three other paradoxes Paradox of place edit From Aristotle If everything that exists has a place place too will have a place and so on ad infinitum 20 Paradox of the grain of millet edit Description of the paradox from the Routledge Dictionary of Philosophy The argument is that a single grain of millet makes no sound upon falling but a thousand grains make a sound Hence a thousand nothings become something an absurd conclusion 21 Aristotle s response Zeno s reasoning is false when he argues that there is no part of the millet that does not make a sound for there is no reason why any such part should not in any length of time fail to move the air that the whole bushel moves in falling In fact it does not of itself move even such a quantity of the air as it would move if this part were by itself for no part even exists otherwise than potentially 22 Description from Nick Huggett This is a Parmenidean argument that one cannot trust one s sense of hearing Aristotle s response seems to be that even inaudible sounds can add to an audible sound 23 The moving rows or stadium edit nbsp The moving rows From Aristotle concerning the two rows of bodies each row being composed of an equal number of bodies of equal size passing each other on a race course as they proceed with equal velocity in opposite directions the one row originally occupying the space between the goal and the middle point of the course and the other that between the middle point and the starting post This involves the conclusion that half a given time is equal to double that time 24 An expanded account of Zeno s arguments as presented by Aristotle is given in Simplicius s commentary On Aristotle s Physics 25 2 1 Proposed solutions editIn classical antiquity edit According to Simplicius Diogenes the Cynic said nothing upon hearing Zeno s arguments but stood up and walked in order to demonstrate the falsity of Zeno s conclusions 25 2 To fully solve any of the paradoxes however one needs to show what is wrong with the argument not just the conclusions Throughout history several solutions have been proposed among the earliest recorded being those of Aristotle and Archimedes Aristotle 384 BC 322 BC remarked that as the distance decreases the time needed to cover those distances also decreases so that the time needed also becomes increasingly small 26 failed verification 27 Aristotle also distinguished things infinite in respect of divisibility such as a unit of space that can be mentally divided into ever smaller units while remaining spatially the same from things or distances that are infinite in extension with respect to their extremities 28 Aristotle s objection to the arrow paradox was that Time is not composed of indivisible nows any more than any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles 29 Thomas Aquinas commenting on Aristotle s objection wrote Instants are not parts of time for time is not made up of instants any more than a magnitude is made of points as we have already proved Hence it does not follow that a thing is not in motion in a given time just because it is not in motion in any instant of that time 30 31 32 In modern mathematics edit Some mathematicians and historians such as Carl Boyer hold that Zeno s paradoxes are simply mathematical problems for which modern calculus provides a mathematical solution 33 Infinite processes remained theoretically troublesome in mathematics until the late 19th century With the epsilon delta definition of limit Weierstrass and Cauchy developed a rigorous formulation of the logic and calculus involved These works resolved the mathematics involving infinite processes 34 35 Some philosophers however say that Zeno s paradoxes and their variations see Thomson s lamp remain relevant metaphysical problems 10 11 12 While mathematics can calculate where and when the moving Achilles will overtake the Tortoise of Zeno s paradox philosophers such as Kevin Brown 10 and Francis Moorcroft 11 hold that mathematics does not address the central point in Zeno s argument and that solving the mathematical issues does not solve every issue the paradoxes raise Brown concludes Given the history of final resolutions from Aristotle onwards it s probably foolhardy to think we ve reached the end It may be that Zeno s arguments on motion because of their simplicity and universality will always serve as a kind of Rorschach image onto which people can project their most fundamental phenomenological concerns if they have any 10 Henri Bergson edit An alternative conclusion proposed by Henri Bergson in his 1896 book Matter and Memory is that while the path is divisible the motion is not 36 37 Peter Lynds edit In 2003 Peter Lynds argued that all of Zeno s motion paradoxes are resolved by the conclusion that instants in time and instantaneous magnitudes do not physically exist 38 39 40 Lynds argues that an object in relative motion cannot have an instantaneous or determined relative position for if it did it could not be in motion and so cannot have its motion fractionally dissected as if it does as is assumed by the paradoxes Nick Huggett argues that Zeno is assuming the conclusion when he says that objects that occupy the same space as they do at rest must be at rest 19 Bertrand Russell edit Based on the work of Georg Cantor 41 Bertrand Russell offered a solution to the paradoxes what is known as the at at theory of motion It agrees that there can be no motion during a durationless instant and contends that all that is required for motion is that the arrow be at one point at one time at another point another time and at appropriate points between those two points for intervening times In this view motion is just change in position over time 42 43 Hermann Weyl edit Another proposed solution is to question one of the assumptions Zeno used in his paradoxes particularly the Dichotomy which is that between any two different points in space or time there is always another point Without this assumption there are only a finite number of distances between two points hence there is no infinite sequence of movements and the paradox is resolved According to Hermann Weyl the assumption that space is made of finite and discrete units is subject to a further problem given by the tile argument or distance function problem 44 45 According to this the length of the hypotenuse of a right angled triangle in discretized space is always equal to the length of one of the two sides in contradiction to geometry Jean Paul Van Bendegem has argued that the Tile Argument can be resolved and that discretization can therefore remove the paradox 33 46 Applications edit Quantum Zeno effect edit Main article Quantum Zeno effect In 1977 47 physicists E C George Sudarshan and B Misra discovered that the dynamical evolution motion of a quantum system can be hindered or even inhibited through observation of the system 48 This effect is usually called the quantum Zeno effect as it is strongly reminiscent of Zeno s arrow paradox This effect was first theorized in 1958 49 Zeno behaviour edit In the field of verification and design of timed and hybrid systems the system behaviour is called Zeno if it includes an infinite number of discrete steps in a finite amount of time 50 Some formal verification techniques exclude these behaviours from analysis if they are not equivalent to non Zeno behaviour 51 52 In systems design these behaviours will also often be excluded from system models since they cannot be implemented with a digital controller 53 In popular culture edit A humorous take is offered by Tom Stoppard in his 1972 play Jumpers in which the principal protagonist the philosophy professor George Moore suggests that according to Zeno s paradox Saint Sebastian a 3rd Century Christian saint martyred by being shot with arrows died of fright In 1969 The Firesign Theatre used a version of Zeno s dichotomy paradox when speaking road signs for an approaching exit continued to divide in half with the destination never being reached by the driver on their second LP How Can You Be In Two Places at Once When You re Not Anywhere At All Folk musicians Lou and Peter Berryman provide a humorous variation in their song An Hour Away in which the driver of a car keeps encountering construction that requires a slower speed so that even as they keep driving their destination remains an hour away and they can t reach their romantic interest Similar paradoxes editSchool of Names edit nbsp Diagram of Hui Shi s stick paradoxRoughly contemporaneously during the Warring States period 475 221 BCE ancient Chinese philosophers from the School of Names a school of thought similarly concerned with logic and dialectics developed paradoxes similar to those of Zeno The works of the School of Names have largely been lost with the exception of portions of the Gongsun Longzi The second of the Ten Theses of Hui Shi suggests knowledge of infinitesimals That which has no thickness cannot be piled up yet it is a thousand li in dimension Among the many puzzles of his recorded in the Zhuangzi is one very similar to Zeno s Dichotomy If from a stick a foot long you every day take the half of it in a myriad ages it will not be exhausted Zhuangzi chapter 33 Legge translation 54 The Mohist canon appears to propose a solution to this paradox by arguing that in moving across a measured length the distance is not covered in successive fractions of the length but in one stage Due to the lack of surviving works from the School of Names most of the other paradoxes listed are difficult to interpret 55 Lewis Carroll s What the Tortoise Said to Achilles edit Main article What the Tortoise Said to Achilles What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 56 written in 1895 by Lewis Carroll which described a paradoxical infinite regress argument in the realm of pure logic used Achilles and the Tortoise as characters in a clear reference to Zeno s paradox of Achilles 57 Douglas Hofstadter s Godel Escher Bach edit Main article Godel Escher Bach Notably 58 Douglas Hofstadter s Godel Escher Bach inspired by Carroll features the same characters in dialogues throughout the book 58 which is a popular award winning 742 page book on the foundations of mathematics and its relationship to artificial intelligence 58 See also editIncommensurable magnitudes Infinite regress Philosophy of space and time Renormalization Ross Littlewood paradox Supertask Zeno machine List of paradoxesNotes edit a b c d e f g h i j k Zeno s Paradoxes Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2024 03 25 a b c d e f g h i j k l Huggett Nick 2024 Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds Zeno s Paradoxes The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2024 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2024 03 25 Diogenes Laertius Lives 9 23 and 9 29 Parmenides 128d Parmenides 128a b fragment 65 Diogenes Laertius IX Archived 2010 12 12 at the Wayback Machine 25ff and VIII 57 a b Aristotle s Physics Archived 2011 01 06 at the Wayback Machine Physics by Aristotle translated by R P Hardie and R K Gaye Greek text of Physics by Aristotle refer to 4 at the top of the visible screen area Archived from the original on 2008 05 16 Benson Donald C 1999 The Moment of Proof Mathematical Epiphanies New York Oxford University Press p 14 ISBN 978 0195117219 a b c d Brown Kevin Zeno and the Paradox of Motion Reflections on Relativity Archived from the original on 2012 12 05 Retrieved 2010 06 06 a b c Moorcroft Francis Zeno s Paradox Archived from the original on 2010 04 18 a b Papa Grimaldi Alba 1996 Why Mathematical Solutions of Zeno s Paradoxes Miss the Point Zeno s One and Many Relation and Parmenides Prohibition PDF The Review of Metaphysics 50 299 314 Archived PDF from the original on 2012 06 09 Retrieved 2012 03 06 Huggett Nick 2010 Zeno s Paradoxes 5 Zeno s Influence on Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2022 03 01 Retrieved 2011 03 07 Lindberg David 2007 The Beginnings of Western Science 2nd ed University of Chicago Press p 33 ISBN 978 0 226 48205 7 Huggett Nick 2010 Zeno s Paradoxes 3 1 The Dichotomy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2022 03 01 Retrieved 2011 03 07 Huggett Nick 2010 Zeno s Paradoxes 3 2 Achilles and the Tortoise Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2022 03 01 Retrieved 2011 03 07 Aristotle Physics The Internet Classics Archive Archived from the original on 2008 05 15 Retrieved 2012 08 21 Zeno s reasoning however is fallacious when he says that if everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment the flying arrow is therefore motionless This is false for time is not composed of indivisible moments any more than any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles Laertius Diogenes c 230 Pyrrho Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers Vol IX passage 72 ISBN 1 116 71900 2 Archived from the original on 2011 08 22 Retrieved 2011 03 05 a b Huggett Nick 2010 Zeno s Paradoxes 3 3 The Arrow Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2022 03 01 Retrieved 2011 03 07 Aristotle Physics IV 1 209a25 Archived 2008 05 09 at the Wayback Machine The Michael Proudfoot A R Lace Routledge Dictionary of Philosophy Routledge 2009 p 445 Aristotle Physics VII 5 250a20 Archived 2008 05 11 at the Wayback Machine Huggett Nick Zeno s Paradoxes The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2010 Edition Edward N Zalta ed http plato stanford edu entries paradox zeno GraMil Archived 2022 03 01 at the Wayback Machine Aristotle Physics VI 9 239b33 Archived 2008 05 15 at the Wayback Machine a b Simplikios Konstan David Simplikios 1989 Simplicius on Aristotle s Physics 6 Ancient commentators on Aristotle Ithaca N Y Cornell Univ Pr ISBN 978 0 8014 2238 6 Aristotle Physics 6 9 Aristotle s observation that the fractional times also get shorter does not guarantee in every case that the task can be completed One case in which it does not hold is that in which the fractional times decrease in a harmonic series while the distances decrease geometrically such as 1 2 s for 1 2 m gain 1 3 s for next 1 4 m gain 1 4 s for next 1 8 m gain 1 5 s for next 1 16 m gain 1 6 s for next 1 32 m gain etc In this case the distances form a convergent series but the times form a divergent series the sum of which has no limit original research Archimedes developed a more explicitly mathematical approach than Aristotle Aristotle Physics 6 9 6 2 233a21 31 Aristotle Physics Vol VI Part 9 verse 239b5 ISBN 0 585 09205 2 Archived from the original on 2008 05 15 Retrieved 2008 08 11 Aquinas Commentary on Aristotle s Physics Book 6 861 Kiritsis Paul 2020 04 01 A Critical Investigation into Precognitive Dreams 1 ed Cambridge Scholars Publishing p 19 ISBN 978 1527546332 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint date and year link Aquinas Thomas Commentary on Aristotle s Physics aquinas cc Retrieved 2024 03 25 a b Boyer Carl 1959 The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development Dover Publications p 295 ISBN 978 0 486 60509 8 Retrieved 2010 02 26 If the paradoxes are thus stated in the precise mathematical terminology of continuous variables the seeming contradictions resolve themselves Lee Harold 1965 Are Zeno s Paradoxes Based on a Mistake Mind 74 296 Oxford University Press 563 570 doi 10 1093 mind LXXIV 296 563 JSTOR 2251675 B Russell 1956 Mathematics and the metaphysicians in The World of Mathematics ed J R Newman pp 1576 1590 Bergson Henri 1896 Matiere et Memoire Matter and Memory PDF Translation 1911 by Nancy Margaret Paul amp W Scott Palmer George Allen and Unwin pp 77 78 of the PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2019 10 15 Retrieved 2019 10 15 Massumi Brian 2002 Parables for the Virtual Movement Affect Sensation 1st ed Durham NC Duke University Press Books pp 5 6 ISBN 978 0822328971 Zeno s Paradoxes A Timely Solution January 2003 Archived from the original on 2012 08 13 Retrieved 2012 07 02 Lynds Peter Time and Classical and Quantum Mechanics Indeterminacy vs Discontinuity Foundations of Physics Letter s Vol 16 Issue 4 2003 doi 10 1023 A 1025361725408 Time s Up Einstein Archived 2012 12 30 at the Wayback Machine Josh McHugh Wired Magazine June 2005 Russell Bertrand 2002 First published in 1914 by The Open Court Publishing Company Lecture 6 The Problem of Infinity Considered Historically Our Knowledge of the External World As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy Routledge p 169 ISBN 0 415 09605 7 Huggett Nick 1999 Space From Zeno to Einstein MIT Press ISBN 0 262 08271 3 Salmon Wesley C 1998 Causality and Explanation Oxford University Press p 198 ISBN 978 0 19 510864 4 Archived from the original on 2023 12 29 Retrieved 2020 11 21 Van Bendegem Jean Paul 17 March 2010 Finitism in Geometry Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2008 05 12 Retrieved 2012 01 03 Cohen Marc 11 December 2000 ATOMISM History of Ancient Philosophy University of Washington Archived from the original on July 12 2010 Retrieved 2012 01 03 van Bendegem Jean Paul 1987 Discussion Zeno s Paradoxes and the Tile Argument Philosophy of Science 54 2 Belgium 295 302 doi 10 1086 289379 JSTOR 187807 S2CID 224840314 Sudarshan E C G Misra B 1977 The Zeno s paradox in quantum theory PDF Journal of Mathematical Physics 18 4 756 763 Bibcode 1977JMP 18 756M doi 10 1063 1 523304 OSTI 7342282 Archived PDF from the original on 2013 05 14 Retrieved 2018 04 20 W M Itano D J Heinsen J J Bokkinger D J Wineland 1990 Quantum Zeno effect PDF Physical Review A 41 5 2295 2300 Bibcode 1990PhRvA 41 2295I doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 41 2295 PMID 9903355 Archived from the original PDF on 2004 07 20 Retrieved 2004 07 23 Khalfin L A 1958 Contribution to the Decay Theory of a Quasi Stationary State Soviet Phys JETP 6 1053 Bibcode 1958JETP 6 1053K Paul A Fishwick ed 1 June 2007 15 6 Pathological Behavior Classes in chapter 15 Hybrid Dynamic Systems Modeling and Execution by Pieter J Mosterman The Mathworks Inc Handbook of dynamic system modeling Chapman amp Hall CRC Computer and Information Science hardcover ed Boca Raton Florida USA CRC Press pp 15 22 to 15 23 ISBN 978 1 58488 565 8 Archived from the original on 2023 12 29 Retrieved 2010 03 05 Lamport Leslie 2002 Specifying Systems PDF Addison Wesley p 128 ISBN 0 321 14306 X Archived PDF from the original on 2010 11 16 Retrieved 2010 03 06 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help Zhang Jun Johansson Karl Lygeros John Sastry Shankar 2001 Zeno hybrid systems PDF International Journal for Robust and Nonlinear Control 11 5 435 doi 10 1002 rnc 592 S2CID 2057416 Archived from the original PDF on August 11 2011 Retrieved 2010 02 28 Franck Cassez Henzinger Thomas Raskin Jean Francois 2002 A Comparison of Control Problems for Timed and Hybrid Systems Archived from the original on May 28 2008 Retrieved 2010 03 02 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Muller Max ed 1891 The Writings of Kwang Tse Sacred Books of the East Vol 40 Translated by Legge James Oxford University Press School of Names gt Miscellaneous Paradoxes Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy plato stanford edu Archived from the original on 2016 12 11 Retrieved 2020 01 30 Carroll Lewis 1895 04 01 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles Mind IV 14 278 280 doi 10 1093 mind IV 14 278 ISSN 0026 4423 Archived from the original on 2020 07 20 Retrieved 2020 07 20 Tsilipakos Leonidas 2021 Clarity and confusion in social theory taking concepts seriously Philosophy and method in the social sciences Abingdon New York N Y Routledge p 48 ISBN 978 1 032 09883 8 a b c Bunch Bryan H 1997 Mathematical fallacies and paradoxes Mineola N Y Dover Publ p 204 ISBN 978 0 486 29664 7 References editKirk G S J E Raven M Schofield 1984 The Presocratic Philosophers A Critical History with a Selection of Texts 2nd ed Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 27455 9 Huggett Nick 2010 Zeno s Paradoxes Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2022 03 01 Retrieved 2011 03 07 Plato 1926 Plato Cratylus Parmenides Greater Hippias Lesser Hippias H N Fowler Translator Loeb Classical Library ISBN 0 674 99185 0 Sainsbury R M 2003 Paradoxes 2nd ed Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 48347 6 Skyrms Brian 1983 Zeno s Paradox of Measure In Cohen R S Laudan L eds Physics Philosophy and Psychoanalysis Dordrecht Reidel pp 223 254 ISBN 90 277 1533 5 External links edit nbsp Wikisource has original text related to this article Zeno of Elea Dowden Bradley Zeno s Paradoxes Entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Antinomy Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy Ludwig Maximilians Universitat Munchen Silagadze Z K Zeno meets modern science Zeno s Paradox Achilles and the Tortoise by Jon McLoone Wolfram Demonstrations Project Kevin Brown on Zeno and the Paradox of Motion Palmer John 2008 Zeno of Elea Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy This article incorporates material from Zeno s paradox on PlanetMath which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution Share Alike License Grime James Zeno s Paradox Numberphile Brady Haran Archived from the original on 2018 10 03 Retrieved 2013 04 13 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Zeno 27s paradoxes amp oldid 1219666488 Achilles and the tortoise, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.