fbpx
Wikipedia

Epsilon number

In mathematics, the epsilon numbers are a collection of transfinite numbers whose defining property is that they are fixed points of an exponential map. Consequently, they are not reachable from 0 via a finite series of applications of the chosen exponential map and of "weaker" operations like addition and multiplication. The original epsilon numbers were introduced by Georg Cantor in the context of ordinal arithmetic; they are the ordinal numbers ε that satisfy the equation

in which ω is the smallest infinite ordinal.

The least such ordinal is ε0 (pronounced epsilon nought or epsilon zero), which can be viewed as the "limit" obtained by transfinite recursion from a sequence of smaller limit ordinals:

where sup is the supremum, which is equivalent to set union in the case of the von Neumann representation of ordinals.

Larger ordinal fixed points of the exponential map are indexed by ordinal subscripts, resulting in .[1] The ordinal ε0 is still countable, as is any epsilon number whose index is countable (there exist uncountable ordinals, and uncountable epsilon numbers whose index is an uncountable ordinal).

The smallest epsilon number ε0 appears in many induction proofs, because for many purposes transfinite induction is only required up to ε0 (as in Gentzen's consistency proof and the proof of Goodstein's theorem). Its use by Gentzen to prove the consistency of Peano arithmetic, along with Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, show that Peano arithmetic cannot prove the well-foundedness of this ordering (it is in fact the least ordinal with this property, and as such, in proof-theoretic ordinal analysis, is used as a measure of the strength of the theory of Peano arithmetic).

Many larger epsilon numbers can be defined using the Veblen function.

A more general class of epsilon numbers has been identified by John Horton Conway and Donald Knuth in the surreal number system, consisting of all surreals that are fixed points of the base ω exponential map xωx.

Hessenberg (1906) defined gamma numbers (see additively indecomposable ordinal) to be numbers γ > 0 such that α + γ = γ whenever α < γ, and delta numbers (see multiplicatively indecomposable ordinal) to be numbers δ > 1 such that αδ = δ whenever 0 < α < δ, and epsilon numbers to be numbers ε > 2 such that αε = ε whenever 1 < α < ε. His gamma numbers are those of the form ωβ, and his delta numbers are those of the form ωωβ.

Ordinal ε numbers edit

The standard definition of ordinal exponentiation with base α is:

  •  
  •   when   has an immediate predecessor  .
  •  , whenever   is a limit ordinal.

From this definition, it follows that for any fixed ordinal α > 1, the mapping   is a normal function, so it has arbitrarily large fixed points by the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. When  , these fixed points are precisely the ordinal epsilon numbers.

  •  
  •   when   has an immediate predecessor  .
  •  , whenever   is a limit ordinal.

Because

 
 
 

a different sequence with the same supremum,  , is obtained by starting from 0 and exponentiating with base ε0 instead:

 

Generally, the epsilon number   indexed by any ordinal that has an immediate predecessor   can be constructed similarly.

 

In particular, whether or not the index β is a limit ordinal,   is a fixed point not only of base ω exponentiation but also of base δ exponentiation for all ordinals  .

Since the epsilon numbers are an unbounded subclass of the ordinal numbers, they are enumerated using the ordinal numbers themselves. For any ordinal number  ,   is the least epsilon number (fixed point of the exponential map) not already in the set  . It might appear that this is the non-constructive equivalent of the constructive definition using iterated exponentiation; but the two definitions are equally non-constructive at steps indexed by limit ordinals, which represent transfinite recursion of a higher order than taking the supremum of an exponential series.

The following facts about epsilon numbers are straightforward to prove:

  • Although it is quite a large number,   is still countable, being a countable union of countable ordinals; in fact,   is countable if and only if   is countable.
  • The union (or supremum) of any non-empty set of epsilon numbers is an epsilon number; so for instance
     
    is an epsilon number. Thus, the mapping   is a normal function.
  • The initial ordinal of any uncountable cardinal is an epsilon number.
     

Representation of ε0 by rooted trees edit

Any epsilon number ε has Cantor normal form  , which means that the Cantor normal form is not very useful for epsilon numbers. The ordinals less than ε0, however, can be usefully described by their Cantor normal forms, which leads to a representation of ε0 as the ordered set of all finite rooted trees, as follows. Any ordinal   has Cantor normal form   where k is a natural number and   are ordinals with  , uniquely determined by  . Each of the ordinals   in turn has a similar Cantor normal form. We obtain the finite rooted tree representing α by joining the roots of the trees representing   to a new root. (This has the consequence that the number 0 is represented by a single root while the number   is represented by a tree containing a root and a single leaf.) An order on the set of finite rooted trees is defined recursively: we first order the subtrees joined to the root in decreasing order, and then use lexicographic order on these ordered sequences of subtrees. In this way the set of all finite rooted trees becomes a well-ordered set which is order isomorphic to ε0.

This representation is related to the proof of the hydra theorem, which represents decreasing sequences of ordinals as a graph-theoretic game.

Veblen hierarchy edit

The fixed points of the "epsilon mapping"   form a normal function, whose fixed points form a normal function; this is known as the Veblen hierarchy (the Veblen functions with base φ0(α) = ωα). In the notation of the Veblen hierarchy, the epsilon mapping is φ1, and its fixed points are enumerated by φ2.

Continuing in this vein, one can define maps φα for progressively larger ordinals α (including, by this rarefied form of transfinite recursion, limit ordinals), with progressively larger least fixed points φα+1(0). The least ordinal not reachable from 0 by this procedure—i. e., the least ordinal α for which φα(0) = α, or equivalently the first fixed point of the map  —is the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0. In a set theory where such an ordinal can be proved to exist, one has a map Γ that enumerates the fixed points Γ0, Γ1, Γ2, ... of  ; these are all still epsilon numbers, as they lie in the image of φβ for every β ≤ Γ0, including of the map φ1 that enumerates epsilon numbers.

Surreal ε numbers edit

In On Numbers and Games, the classic exposition on surreal numbers, John Horton Conway provided a number of examples of concepts that had natural extensions from the ordinals to the surreals. One such function is the  -map  ; this mapping generalises naturally to include all surreal numbers in its domain, which in turn provides a natural generalisation of the Cantor normal form for surreal numbers.

It is natural to consider any fixed point of this expanded map to be an epsilon number, whether or not it happens to be strictly an ordinal number. Some examples of non-ordinal epsilon numbers are

 

and

 

There is a natural way to define   for every surreal number n, and the map remains order-preserving. Conway goes on to define a broader class of "irreducible" surreal numbers that includes the epsilon numbers as a particularly interesting subclass.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Stephen G. Simpson, Subsystems of Second-order Arithmetic (2009, p.387)
  • J.H. Conway, On Numbers and Games (1976) Academic Press ISBN 0-12-186350-6
  • Section XIV.20 of Sierpiński, Wacław (1965), Cardinal and ordinal numbers (2nd ed.), PWN – Polish Scientific Publishers
  • Hessenberg, Gerhard (1906). Grundbegriffe der Mengenlehre. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

epsilon, number, this, article, about, type, ordinal, mathematics, physical, constant, vacuum, permittivity, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, template, messages, this, artic. This article is about a type of ordinal in mathematics For the physical constant e0 see Vacuum permittivity This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations May 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message This article may be too technical for most readers to understand Please help improve it to make it understandable to non experts without removing the technical details January 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Learn how and when to remove this template message In mathematics the epsilon numbers are a collection of transfinite numbers whose defining property is that they are fixed points of an exponential map Consequently they are not reachable from 0 via a finite series of applications of the chosen exponential map and of weaker operations like addition and multiplication The original epsilon numbers were introduced by Georg Cantor in the context of ordinal arithmetic they are the ordinal numbers e that satisfy the equation e w e displaystyle varepsilon omega varepsilon in which w is the smallest infinite ordinal The least such ordinal is e0 pronounced epsilon nought or epsilon zero which can be viewed as the limit obtained by transfinite recursion from a sequence of smaller limit ordinals e 0 w w w sup w w w w w w w w w w displaystyle varepsilon 0 omega omega omega cdot cdot cdot sup omega omega omega omega omega omega omega omega omega omega dots where sup is the supremum which is equivalent to set union in the case of the von Neumann representation of ordinals Larger ordinal fixed points of the exponential map are indexed by ordinal subscripts resulting in e 1 e 2 e w e w 1 e e 0 e e 1 e e e displaystyle varepsilon 1 varepsilon 2 ldots varepsilon omega varepsilon omega 1 ldots varepsilon varepsilon 0 ldots varepsilon varepsilon 1 ldots varepsilon varepsilon varepsilon cdot cdot cdot ldots 1 The ordinal e0 is still countable as is any epsilon number whose index is countable there exist uncountable ordinals and uncountable epsilon numbers whose index is an uncountable ordinal The smallest epsilon number e0 appears in many induction proofs because for many purposes transfinite induction is only required up to e0 as in Gentzen s consistency proof and the proof of Goodstein s theorem Its use by Gentzen to prove the consistency of Peano arithmetic along with Godel s second incompleteness theorem show that Peano arithmetic cannot prove the well foundedness of this ordering it is in fact the least ordinal with this property and as such in proof theoretic ordinal analysis is used as a measure of the strength of the theory of Peano arithmetic Many larger epsilon numbers can be defined using the Veblen function A more general class of epsilon numbers has been identified by John Horton Conway and Donald Knuth in the surreal number system consisting of all surreals that are fixed points of the base w exponential map x wx Hessenberg 1906 defined gamma numbers see additively indecomposable ordinal to be numbers g gt 0 such that a g g whenever a lt g and delta numbers see multiplicatively indecomposable ordinal to be numbers d gt 1 such that ad d whenever 0 lt a lt d and epsilon numbers to be numbers e gt 2 such that ae e whenever 1 lt a lt e His gamma numbers are those of the form wb and his delta numbers are those of the form wwb Contents 1 Ordinal e numbers 2 Representation of e0 by rooted trees 3 Veblen hierarchy 4 Surreal e numbers 5 See also 6 ReferencesOrdinal e numbers editThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message The standard definition of ordinal exponentiation with base a is a 0 1 displaystyle alpha 0 1 nbsp a b a b 1 a displaystyle alpha beta alpha beta 1 cdot alpha nbsp when b displaystyle beta nbsp has an immediate predecessor b 1 displaystyle beta 1 nbsp a b sup a d 0 lt d lt b displaystyle alpha beta sup lbrace alpha delta mid 0 lt delta lt beta rbrace nbsp whenever b displaystyle beta nbsp is a limit ordinal From this definition it follows that for any fixed ordinal a gt 1 the mapping b a b displaystyle beta mapsto alpha beta nbsp is a normal function so it has arbitrarily large fixed points by the fixed point lemma for normal functions When a w displaystyle alpha omega nbsp these fixed points are precisely the ordinal epsilon numbers e 0 sup 1 w w w w w w w w w w displaystyle varepsilon 0 sup lbrace 1 omega omega omega omega omega omega omega omega omega omega ldots rbrace nbsp e b sup e b 1 1 w e b 1 1 w w e b 1 1 w w w e b 1 1 displaystyle varepsilon beta sup lbrace varepsilon beta 1 1 omega varepsilon beta 1 1 omega omega varepsilon beta 1 1 omega omega omega varepsilon beta 1 1 ldots rbrace nbsp when b displaystyle beta nbsp has an immediate predecessor b 1 displaystyle beta 1 nbsp e b sup e d d lt b displaystyle varepsilon beta sup lbrace varepsilon delta mid delta lt beta rbrace nbsp whenever b displaystyle beta nbsp is a limit ordinal Because w e 0 1 w e 0 w 1 e 0 w displaystyle omega varepsilon 0 1 omega varepsilon 0 cdot omega 1 varepsilon 0 cdot omega nbsp w w e 0 1 w e 0 w w e 0 w e 0 w displaystyle omega omega varepsilon 0 1 omega varepsilon 0 cdot omega omega varepsilon 0 omega varepsilon 0 omega nbsp w w w e 0 1 w e 0 w w e 0 1 w w e 0 e 0 w w e 0 e 0 w e 0 e 0 w displaystyle omega omega omega varepsilon 0 1 omega varepsilon 0 omega omega varepsilon 0 1 omega omega varepsilon 0 cdot varepsilon 0 omega omega varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 omega varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 omega nbsp a different sequence with the same supremum e 1 displaystyle varepsilon 1 nbsp is obtained by starting from 0 and exponentiating with base e0 instead e 1 sup 1 e 0 e 0 e 0 e 0 e 0 e 0 displaystyle varepsilon 1 sup 1 varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 varepsilon 0 ldots nbsp Generally the epsilon number e b displaystyle varepsilon beta nbsp indexed by any ordinal that has an immediate predecessor b 1 displaystyle beta 1 nbsp can be constructed similarly e b sup 1 e b 1 e b 1 e b 1 e b 1 e b 1 e b 1 displaystyle varepsilon beta sup 1 varepsilon beta 1 varepsilon beta 1 varepsilon beta 1 varepsilon beta 1 varepsilon beta 1 varepsilon beta 1 dots nbsp In particular whether or not the index b is a limit ordinal e b displaystyle varepsilon beta nbsp is a fixed point not only of base w exponentiation but also of base d exponentiation for all ordinals 1 lt d lt e b displaystyle 1 lt delta lt varepsilon beta nbsp Since the epsilon numbers are an unbounded subclass of the ordinal numbers they are enumerated using the ordinal numbers themselves For any ordinal number b displaystyle beta nbsp e b displaystyle varepsilon beta nbsp is the least epsilon number fixed point of the exponential map not already in the set e d d lt b displaystyle varepsilon delta mid delta lt beta nbsp It might appear that this is the non constructive equivalent of the constructive definition using iterated exponentiation but the two definitions are equally non constructive at steps indexed by limit ordinals which represent transfinite recursion of a higher order than taking the supremum of an exponential series The following facts about epsilon numbers are straightforward to prove Although it is quite a large number e 0 displaystyle varepsilon 0 nbsp is still countable being a countable union of countable ordinals in fact e b displaystyle varepsilon beta nbsp is countable if and only if b displaystyle beta nbsp is countable The union or supremum of any non empty set of epsilon numbers is an epsilon number so for instance e w sup e 0 e 1 e 2 displaystyle varepsilon omega sup varepsilon 0 varepsilon 1 varepsilon 2 ldots nbsp is an epsilon number Thus the mapping b e b displaystyle beta mapsto varepsilon beta nbsp is a normal function The initial ordinal of any uncountable cardinal is an epsilon number a 1 e w a w a displaystyle alpha geq 1 Rightarrow varepsilon omega alpha omega alpha nbsp Representation of e0 by rooted trees editAny epsilon number e has Cantor normal form e w e displaystyle varepsilon omega varepsilon nbsp which means that the Cantor normal form is not very useful for epsilon numbers The ordinals less than e0 however can be usefully described by their Cantor normal forms which leads to a representation of e0 as the ordered set of all finite rooted trees as follows Any ordinal a lt e 0 displaystyle alpha lt varepsilon 0 nbsp has Cantor normal form a w b 1 w b 2 w b k displaystyle alpha omega beta 1 omega beta 2 cdots omega beta k nbsp where k is a natural number and b 1 b k displaystyle beta 1 ldots beta k nbsp are ordinals with a gt b 1 b k displaystyle alpha gt beta 1 geq cdots geq beta k nbsp uniquely determined by a displaystyle alpha nbsp Each of the ordinals b 1 b k displaystyle beta 1 ldots beta k nbsp in turn has a similar Cantor normal form We obtain the finite rooted tree representing a by joining the roots of the trees representing b 1 b k displaystyle beta 1 ldots beta k nbsp to a new root This has the consequence that the number 0 is represented by a single root while the number 1 w 0 displaystyle 1 omega 0 nbsp is represented by a tree containing a root and a single leaf An order on the set of finite rooted trees is defined recursively we first order the subtrees joined to the root in decreasing order and then use lexicographic order on these ordered sequences of subtrees In this way the set of all finite rooted trees becomes a well ordered set which is order isomorphic to e0 This representation is related to the proof of the hydra theorem which represents decreasing sequences of ordinals as a graph theoretic game Veblen hierarchy editMain article Veblen function The fixed points of the epsilon mapping x e x displaystyle x mapsto varepsilon x nbsp form a normal function whose fixed points form a normal function this is known as the Veblen hierarchy the Veblen functions with base f0 a wa In the notation of the Veblen hierarchy the epsilon mapping is f1 and its fixed points are enumerated by f2 Continuing in this vein one can define maps fa for progressively larger ordinals a including by this rarefied form of transfinite recursion limit ordinals with progressively larger least fixed points fa 1 0 The least ordinal not reachable from 0 by this procedure i e the least ordinal a for which fa 0 a or equivalently the first fixed point of the map a f a 0 displaystyle alpha mapsto varphi alpha 0 nbsp is the Feferman Schutte ordinal G0 In a set theory where such an ordinal can be proved to exist one has a map G that enumerates the fixed points G0 G1 G2 of a f a 0 displaystyle alpha mapsto varphi alpha 0 nbsp these are all still epsilon numbers as they lie in the image of fb for every b G0 including of the map f1 that enumerates epsilon numbers Surreal e numbers editIn On Numbers and Games the classic exposition on surreal numbers John Horton Conway provided a number of examples of concepts that had natural extensions from the ordinals to the surreals One such function is the w displaystyle omega nbsp map n w n displaystyle n mapsto omega n nbsp this mapping generalises naturally to include all surreal numbers in its domain which in turn provides a natural generalisation of the Cantor normal form for surreal numbers It is natural to consider any fixed point of this expanded map to be an epsilon number whether or not it happens to be strictly an ordinal number Some examples of non ordinal epsilon numbers are e 1 0 1 w w w e 0 1 w e 0 1 displaystyle varepsilon 1 0 1 omega omega omega ldots mid varepsilon 0 1 omega varepsilon 0 1 ldots nbsp and e 1 2 e 0 1 w e 0 1 e 1 1 w e 1 1 displaystyle varepsilon 1 2 varepsilon 0 1 omega varepsilon 0 1 ldots mid varepsilon 1 1 omega varepsilon 1 1 ldots nbsp There is a natural way to define e n displaystyle varepsilon n nbsp for every surreal number n and the map remains order preserving Conway goes on to define a broader class of irreducible surreal numbers that includes the epsilon numbers as a particularly interesting subclass See also editOrdinal arithmetic Large countable ordinalReferences edit Stephen G Simpson Subsystems of Second order Arithmetic 2009 p 387 J H Conway On Numbers and Games 1976 Academic Press ISBN 0 12 186350 6 Section XIV 20 of Sierpinski Waclaw 1965 Cardinal and ordinal numbers 2nd ed PWN Polish Scientific Publishers Hessenberg Gerhard 1906 Grundbegriffe der Mengenlehre Gottingen Vandenhoeck amp Ruprecht Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Epsilon number amp oldid 1220427549, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.