fbpx
Wikipedia

Nature (philosophy)

Nature has two inter-related meanings in philosophy and natural philosophy. On the one hand, it means the set of all things which are natural, or subject to the normal working of the laws of nature. On the other hand, it means the essential properties and causes of individual things.

How to understand the meaning and significance of nature has been a consistent theme of discussion within the history of Western Civilization, in the philosophical fields of metaphysics and epistemology, as well as in theology and science. The study of natural things and the regular laws which seem to govern them, as opposed to discussion about what it means to be natural, is the area of natural science.

The word "nature" derives from Latin nātūra, a philosophical term derived from the verb for birth, which was used as a translation for the earlier (pre-Socratic) Greek term phusis, derived from the verb for natural growth. Already in classical times, philosophical use of these words combined two related meanings which have in common that they refer to the way in which things happen by themselves, "naturally", without "interference" from human deliberation, divine intervention, or anything outside what is considered normal for the natural things being considered.

Understandings of nature depend on the subject and age of the work where they appear. For example, Aristotle's explanation of natural properties differs from what is meant by natural properties in modern philosophical and scientific works, which can also differ from other scientific and conventional usage.

Classical nature and Aristotelian metaphysics edit

The Physics (from ta phusika "the natural [things]") is Aristotle's principal work on nature. In Physics II.1, Aristotle defines a nature as "a source or cause of being moved and of being at rest in that to which it belongs primarily".[1] In other words, a nature is the principle within a natural raw material that is the source of tendencies to change or rest in a particular way unless stopped. For example, a rock would fall unless stopped. Natural things stand in contrast to artifacts, which are formed by human artifice, not because of an innate tendency. (The raw materials of a bed have no tendency to become a bed.) In terms of Aristotle's theory of four causes, the word natural is applied both to the innate potential of matter cause and the forms which the matter tends to become naturally.[2]

According to Leo Strauss,[3] the beginning of Western philosophy involved the "discovery or invention of nature" and the "pre-philosophical equivalent of nature" was supplied by "such notions as 'custom' or 'ways'". In ancient Greek philosophy on the other hand, Nature or natures are ways that are "really universal" "in all times and places". What makes nature different is that it presupposes not only that not all customs and ways are equal, but also that one can "find one's bearings in the cosmos" "on the basis of inquiry" (not for example on the basis of traditions or religion). To put this "discovery or invention" into the traditional terminology, what is "by nature" is contrasted to what is "by convention". The concept of nature taken this far remains a strong tradition in modern Western thinking. Science, according to Strauss' commentary of Western history is the contemplation of nature, while technology was or is an attempt to imitate it.[4]

Going further, the philosophical concept of nature or natures as a special type of causation - for example that the way particular humans are is partly caused by something called "human nature" is an essential step towards Aristotle's teaching concerning causation, which became standard in all Western philosophy until the arrival of modern science.

 
Depiction of Aristotle

Whether it was intended or not, Aristotle's inquiries into this subject were long felt to have resolved the discussion about nature in favor of one solution. In this account, there are four different types of cause:

  • The material cause is the "raw material" - the matter which undergoes change. One of the causes of a statue being what it is might be that it is bronze. All meanings of the word nature encompass this simple meaning.
  • The efficient cause is the motion of another thing, which makes a thing change, for example a chisel hitting a rock causes a chip to break off. This is the way which the matter is forming into a form so that it become substance like what Aristotle said that a substance must have a form and matter in order to call it substance. This is the motion of changing a single being into two. This is the most obvious way in which cause and effect works, as in the descriptions of modern science. But according to Aristotle, this does not yet explain that of which the motion is, and we must "apply ourselves to the question whether there is any other cause per se besides matter".[5]
  • The formal cause is the form or idea which serves as a template towards which things develop - for example following an approach based upon Aristotle we could say that a child develops in a way partly determined by a thing called "human nature". Here, nature is a cause.
  • The final cause is the aim towards which something is directed. For example, a human aims at something perceived to be good, as Aristotle says in the opening lines of the Nicomachean Ethics.

The formal and final cause are an essential part of Aristotle's "Metaphysics" - his attempt to go beyond nature and explain nature itself. In practice they imply a human-like consciousness involved in the causation of all things, even things which are not man-made. Nature itself is attributed with having aims.[6]

The artificial, like the conventional therefore, is within this branch of Western thought, traditionally contrasted with the natural. Technology was contrasted with science, as mentioned above. And another essential aspect to this understanding of causation was the distinction between the accidental properties of a thing and the substance - another distinction which has lost favor in the modern era, after having long been widely accepted in medieval Europe.

To describe it another way, Aristotle treated organisms and other natural wholes as existing at a higher level than mere matter in motion. Aristotle's argument for formal and final causes is related to a doctrine about how it is possible that people know things: "If nothing exists apart from individual things, nothing will be intelligible; everything will be sensible, and there will be no knowledge of anything—unless it be maintained that sense-perception is knowledge".[7] Those philosophers who disagree with this reasoning therefore also see knowledge differently from Aristotle.

Aristotle then, described nature or natures as follows, in a way quite different from modern science:[8]

"Nature" means:
(a) in one sense, the genesis of growing things — as would be suggested by pronouncing the υ of φύσις[9] long—and
(b) in another, that immanent thing from which a growing thing first begins to grow.
(c) The source from which the primary motion in every natural object is induced in that object as such. All things are said to grow which gain increase through something else by contact and organic unity (or adhesion, as in the case of embryos). Organic unity differs from contact; for in the latter case there need be nothing except contact, but in both the things which form an organic unity there is some one and the same thing which produces, instead of mere contact, a unity which is organic, continuous and quantitative (but not qualitative). Again, "nature" means
(d) the primary stuff, shapeless and unchangeable from its own potency, of which any natural object consists or from which it is produced; e.g., bronze is called the "nature" of a statue and of bronze articles, and wood that of wooden ones, and similarly in all other cases. For each article consists of these "natures," the primary material persisting. It is in this sense that men call the elements of natural objects the "nature," some calling it fire, others earth or air or water, others something else similar, others some of these, and others all of them. Again in another sense "nature" means
(e) the substance of natural objects; as in the case of those who say that the "nature" is the primary composition of a thing, or as Empedocles says: Of nothing that exists is there nature, but only mixture and separation of what has been mixed; nature is but a name given to these by men. Hence as regards those things which exist or are produced by nature, although that from which they naturally are produced or exist is already present, we say that they have not their nature yet unless they have their form and shape. That which comprises both of these exists by nature; e.g. animals and their parts. And nature is both the primary matter (and this in two senses: either primary in relation to the thing, or primary in general; e.g., in bronze articles the primary matter in relation to those articles is bronze, but in general it is perhaps water—that is if all things which can be melted are water) and the form or essence, i.e. the end of the process, of generation. Indeed from this sense of "nature," by an extension of meaning, every essence in general is called "nature," because the nature of anything is a kind of essence. From what has been said, then, the primary and proper sense of "nature" is the essence of those things which contain in themselves as such a source of motion; for the matter is called "nature" because it is capable of receiving the nature, and the processes of generation and growth are called "nature" because they are motions derived from it. And nature in this sense is the source of motion in natural objects, which is somehow inherent in them, either potentially or actually.

— Metaphysics 1014b-1015a, translated by Hugh Tredennick, emphasis added.[a]

It has been argued, as will be explained below, that this type of theory represented an oversimplifying diversion from the debates within Classical philosophy, possibly even that Aristotle saw it as a simplification or summary of the debates himself. But in any case the theory of the four causes became a standard part of any advanced education in the Middle Ages.

In Eastern philosophy edit

Indian philosophy edit

Jain philosophy attempts to explain the rationale of being and existence, the nature of the Universe and its constituents, the nature of bondage and the means to achieve liberation.[10] Jainism strongly upholds the individualistic nature of soul and personal responsibility for one's decisions; and that self-reliance and individual efforts alone are responsible for one's liberation.[11]

Ajñana was a Śramaṇa school of radical Indian skepticism and a rival of early Buddhism and Jainism. They held that it was impossible to obtain knowledge of metaphysical nature or ascertain the truth value of philosophical propositions;[12] and even if knowledge was possible, it was useless and disadvantageous for final salvation. They were seen as sophists who specialized in refutation without propagating any positive doctrine of their own. Jayarāśi Bhaṭṭa (fl. c. 800), author of the skeptical work entitled Tattvopaplavasiṃha ("The Lion that Devours All Categories"/"The Upsetting of All Principles"), has been seen as an important Ajñana philosopher.[13]

In the Chandogya Upanishad, Aruni asks metaphysical questions concerning the nature of reality and truth, observes constant change, and asks if there is something that is eternal and unchanging. From these questions, embedded in a dialogue with his son, he presents the concept of Ātman (soul, Self) and universal Self.[14][15]

The Ashtavakra Gita, credited to Aṣṭāvakra, examines the metaphysical nature of existence and the meaning of individual freedom, presenting its thesis that there is only one Supreme Reality (Brahman), the entirety of universe is oneness and manifestation of this reality, everything is interconnected, all Self (Atman, soul) are part of that one, and that individual freedom is not the end point but a given, a starting point, innate.[16]

The first book of Yoga Vasistha, attributed to Valmiki, presents Rama's frustration with the nature of life, human suffering and disdain for the world.[17] The second describes, through the character of Rama, the desire for liberation and the nature of those who seek such liberation.[17] The fourth describes the nature of world and many non-dualism ideas with numerous stories.[17][18] It emphasizes free will and human creative power.[17][19]

Ancient Mīmāṃsā's central concern was epistemology (pramana), that is what are the reliable means to knowledge. It debated not only "how does man ever learn or know, whatever he knows", but also whether the nature of all knowledge is inherently circular, whether those such as foundationalists who critique the validity of any "justified beliefs" and knowledge system make flawed presumptions of the very premises they critique, and how to correctly interpret and avoid incorrectly interpreting dharma texts such as the Vedas.[20] To Mīmānsā scholars, the nature of non-empirical knowledge and human means to it are such that one can never demonstrate certainty, one can only falsify knowledge claims, in some cases.[20]

Buddhist philosophy's main concern is soteriological, defined as freedom from dukkha (unease).[21] Because ignorance to the true nature of things is considered one of the roots of suffering, Buddhist thinkers concerned themselves with philosophical questions related to epistemology and the use of reason.[22] Dukkha can be translated as "incapable of satisfying,"[23] "the unsatisfactory nature and the general insecurity of all conditioned phenomena"; or "painful."[24][25] Prajñā is insight or knowledge of the true nature of existence. The Buddhist tradition regards ignorance (avidyā), a fundamental ignorance, misunderstanding or mis-perception of the nature of reality, as one of the basic causes of dukkha and samsara. By overcoming ignorance or misunderstanding one is enlightened and liberated. This overcoming includes awakening to impermanence and the non-self nature of reality,[26][27] and this develops dispassion for the objects of clinging, and liberates a being from dukkha and saṃsāra.[28][29] Pratītyasamutpāda, also called "dependent arising, or dependent origination", is the Buddhist theory to explain the nature and relations of being, becoming, existence and ultimate reality. Buddhism asserts that there is nothing independent, except the state of nirvana.[30] All physical and mental states depend on and arise from other pre-existing states, and in turn from them arise other dependent states while they cease.[31]

East Asian philosophies edit

Confucianism considers the ordinary activities of human life—and especially human relationships—as a manifestation of the sacred,[32] because they are the expression of humanity's moral nature (xìng 性), which has a transcendent anchorage in Heaven (Tiān 天) and unfolds through an appropriate respect for the spirits or gods (shén) of the world.[33] Tiān (天), a key concept in Chinese thought, refers to the God of Heaven, the northern culmen of the skies and its spinning stars,[34] earthly nature and its laws which come from Heaven, to "Heaven and Earth" (that is, "all things"), and to the awe-inspiring forces beyond human control.[35] Confucius used the term in a mystical way.[36] It is similar to what Taoists meant by Dao: "the way things are" or "the regularities of the world",[35] which Stephan Feuchtwang equates with the ancient Greek concept of physis, "nature" as the generation and regenerations of things and of the moral order.[37] Feuchtwang explains that the difference between Confucianism and Taoism primarily lies in the fact that the former focuses on the realisation of the starry order of Heaven in human society, while the latter on the contemplation of the Dao which spontaneously arises in nature.[37]

Modern science and laws of nature: trying to avoid metaphysics edit

 
A Renaissance imagined representation of Democritus, the laughing philosopher, by Agostino Carracci

In contrast, Modern Science took its distinctive turn with Francis Bacon, who rejected the four distinct causes, and saw Aristotle as someone who "did proceed in such a spirit of difference and contradiction towards all antiquity: undertaking not only to frame new words of science at pleasure, but to confound and extinguish all ancient wisdom". He felt that lesser known Greek philosophers such as Democritus "who did not suppose a mind or reason in the frame of things", have been arrogantly dismissed because of Aristotelianism leading to a situation in his time wherein "the search of the physical causes hath been neglected, and passed in silence".[38]

And so Bacon advised...

Physic doth make inquiry, and take consideration of the same natures : but how? Only as to the material and efficient causes of them, and not as to the forms. For example; if the cause of whiteness in snow or froth be inquired, and it be rendered thus, that the subtile intermixture of air and water is the cause, it is well rendered ; but, nevertheless, is this the form of whiteness? No; but it is the efficient, which is ever but vehiculum formæ. This part of metaphysique I do not find laboured and performed...

— Francis Bacon, Advancement of Learning II.VII.6
 
Francis Bacon

In his Novum Organum Bacon argued that the only forms or natures we should hypothesize are the "simple" (as opposed to compound) ones such as the ways in which heat, movement, etc. work. For example, in aphorism 51 he writes:

51. The human understanding is, by its own nature, prone to abstraction, and supposes that which is fluctuating to be fixed. But it is better to dissect than abstract nature; such was the method employed by the school of Democritus, which made greater progress in penetrating nature than the rest. It is best to consider matter, its conformation, and the changes of that conformation, its own action, and the law of this action or motion, for forms are a mere fiction of the human mind, unless you will call the laws of action by that name.

Following Bacon's advice, the scientific search for the formal cause of things is now replaced by the search for "laws of nature" or "laws of physics" in all scientific thinking. To use Aristotle's well-known terminology these are descriptions of efficient cause, and not formal cause or final cause. It means modern science limits its hypothesizing about non-physical things to the assumption that there are regularities to the ways of all things which do not change.

These general laws, in other words, replace thinking about specific "laws", for example "human nature". In modern science, human nature is part of the same general scheme of cause and effect, obeying the same general laws, as all other things. The above-mentioned difference between accidental and substantial properties, and indeed knowledge and opinion, also disappear within this new approach that aimed to avoid metaphysics.

As Bacon knew, the term "laws of nature" was one taken from medieval Aristotelianism. St Thomas Aquinas for example, defined law so that nature really was legislated to consciously achieve aims, like human law: "an ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community and promulgated".[39] In contrast, roughly contemporary with Bacon, Hugo Grotius described the law of nature as "a rule that [can] be deduced from fixed principles by a sure process of reasoning".[40] And later still, Montesquieu was even further from the original legal metaphor, describing laws vaguely as "the necessary relations deriving from the nature of things".[41]

 
Thomas Hobbes

One of the most important implementors of Bacon's proposal was Thomas Hobbes, whose remarks concerning nature are particularly well-known. His most famous work, Leviathan, opens with the word "Nature" and then parenthetically defines it as "the art whereby God hath made and governes the world". Despite this pious description, he follows a Baconian approach. Following his contemporary, Descartes, Hobbes describes life itself as mechanical, caused in the same way as clockwork:

For seeing life is but a motion of Limbs, the beginning whereof is in some principall part within; why may we not say, that all Automata (Engines that move themselves by springs and wheeles as doth a watch) have an artificiall life?

On this basis, already being established in natural science in his lifetime, Hobbes sought to discuss politics and human life in terms of "laws of nature". But in the new modern approach of Bacon and Hobbes, and before them Machiavelli (who however never clothed his criticism of the Aristotelian approach in medieval terms like "laws of nature"),[42] such laws of nature are quite different to human laws: they no longer imply any sense of better or worse, but simply how things really are, and, when in reference to laws of human nature, what sorts of human behavior can be most relied upon.

"Late modern" nature edit

 
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: a civilized man, but a person who questioned whether civilization was according to human nature.

Having disconnected the term "law of nature" from the original medieval metaphor of human-made law, the term "law of nature" is now used less than in early modern times.

To take the critical example of human nature, as discussed in ethics and politics, once early modern philosophers such as Hobbes had described human nature as whatever you could expect from a mechanism called a human, the point of speaking of human nature became problematic in some contexts.

In the late 18th century, Rousseau took a critical step in his Second Discourse, reasoning that human nature as we know it, rational, and with language, and so on, is a result of historical accidents, and the specific up-bringing of an individual. The consequences of this line of reasoning were to be enormous. It was all about the question of nature. In effect it was being claimed that human nature, one of the most important types of nature in Aristotelian thinking, did not exist as it had been understood to exist.

The survival of metaphysics edit

The approach of modern science, like the approach of Aristotelianism, is apparently not universally accepted by all people who accept the concept of nature as a reality which we can pursue with reason.

Bacon and other opponents of Metaphysics claim that all attempts to go beyond nature are bound to fall into the same errors, but Metaphysicians themselves see differences between different approaches.

Immanuel Kant for example, expressed the need for a Metaphysics in quite similar terms to Aristotle.

...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.

— Critique of Pure Reason pp. Bxxvi-xxvii

As in Aristotelianism then, Kantianism claims that the human mind must itself have characteristics which are beyond nature, metaphysical, in some way. Specifically, Kant argued that the human mind comes ready-made with a priori programming, so to speak, which allows it to make sense of nature.

The study of nature without metaphysics edit

Authors from Nietzsche to Richard Rorty have claimed that science, the study of nature, can and should exist without metaphysics. But this claim has always been controversial. Authors like Bacon and Hume never denied that their use of the word "nature" implied metaphysics, but tried to follow Machiavelli's approach of talking about what works, instead of claiming to understand what seems impossible to understand.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Greek, with emphasis added as a guide: φύσις λέγεται ἕνα μὲν τρόπον ἡ τῶν φυομένων γένεσις, οἷον εἴ τις ἐπεκτείνας λέγοι τὸ υ, ἕνα δὲ ἐξ οὗ φύεται πρώτου τὸ φυόμενον ἐνυπάρχοντος: ἔτι ὅθεν ἡ κίνησις ἡ πρώτη ἐν ἑκάστῳ τῶν φύσει ὄντων ἐν αὐτῷ ᾗ αὐτὸ [20] ὑπάρχει: φύεσθαι δὲ λέγεται ὅσα αὔξησιν ἔχει δι᾽ ἑτέρου τῷ ἅπτεσθαι καὶ συμπεφυκέναι ἢ προσπεφυκέναι ὥσπερ τὰ ἔμβρυα: διαφέρει δὲ σύμφυσις ἁφῆς, ἔνθα μὲν γὰρ οὐδὲν παρὰ τὴν ἁφὴν ἕτερον ἀνάγκη εἶναι, ἐν δὲ τοῖς συμπεφυκόσιν ἔστι τι ἓν τὸ αὐτὸ ἐν ἀμφοῖν ὃ ποιεῖ ἀντὶ τοῦ [25] ἅπτεσθαι συμπεφυκέναι καὶ εἶναι ἓν κατὰ τὸ συνεχὲς καὶ ποσόν, ἀλλὰ μὴ κατὰ τὸ ποιόν. ἔτι δὲ φύσις λέγεται ἐξ οὗ πρώτου ἢ ἔστιν ἢ γίγνεταί τι τῶν φύσει ὄντων, ἀρρυθμίστου ὄντος καὶ ἀμεταβλήτου ἐκ τῆς δυνάμεως τῆς αὑτοῦ, οἷον ἀνδριάντος καὶ τῶν σκευῶν τῶν χαλκῶν ὁ χαλκὸς ἡ [30] φύσις λέγεται, τῶν δὲ ξυλίνων ξύλον: ὁμοίως δὲ καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν ἄλλων: ἐκ τούτων γάρ ἐστιν ἕκαστον διασωζομένης τῆς πρώτης ὕλης: τοῦτον γὰρ τὸν τρόπον καὶ τῶν φύσει ὄντων τὰ στοιχεῖά φασιν εἶναι φύσιν, οἱ μὲν πῦρ οἱ δὲ γῆν οἱ δ᾽ ἀέρα οἱ δ᾽ ὕδωρ οἱ δ᾽ ἄλλο τι τοιοῦτον λέγοντες, οἱ δ᾽ [35] ἔνια τούτων οἱ δὲ πάντα ταῦτα. ἔτι δ᾽ ἄλλον τρόπον λέγεται ἡ φύσις ἡ τῶν φύσει ὄντων οὐσία, οἷον οἱ λέγοντες τὴν φύσιν εἶναι τὴν πρώτην σύνθεσιν, ἢ ὥσπερ Ἐμπεδοκλῆς λέγει ὅτι "φύσις οὐδενὸς ἔστιν ἐόντων, ἀλλὰ μόνον μῖξίς τε διάλλαξίς τε μιγέντων ἔστι, φύσις δ᾽ ἐπὶ τοῖς ὀνομάζεται ἀνθρώποισιν. "Empedocles Fr. 8 διὸ καὶ ὅσα φύσει ἔστιν ἢ γίγνεται, ἤδη ὑπάρχοντος ἐξ οὗ πέφυκε γίγνεσθαι ἢ εἶναι, οὔπω φαμὲν [5] τὴν φύσιν ἔχειν ἐὰν μὴ ἔχῃ τὸ εἶδος καὶ τὴν μορφήν. φύσει μὲν οὖν τὸ ἐξ ἀμφοτέρων τούτων ἐστίν, οἷον τὰ ζῷα καὶ τὰ μόρια αὐτῶν: φύσις δὲ ἥ τε πρώτη ὕλη (καὶ αὕτη διχῶς, ἢ ἡ πρὸς αὐτὸ πρώτη ἢ ἡ ὅλως πρώτη, οἷον τῶν χαλκῶν ἔργων πρὸς αὐτὰ μὲν πρῶτος ὁ χαλκός, ὅλως δ᾽ [10] ἴσως ὕδωρ, εἰ πάντα τὰ τηκτὰ ὕδωρ) καὶ τὸ εἶδος καὶ ἡ οὐσία: τοῦτο δ᾽ ἐστὶ τὸ τέλος τῆς γενέσεως. μεταφορᾷ δ᾽ ἤδη καὶ ὅλως πᾶσα οὐσία φύσις λέγεται διὰ ταύτην, ὅτι καὶ ἡ φύσις οὐσία τίς ἐστιν. ἐκ δὴ τῶν εἰρημένων ἡ πρώτη φύσις καὶ κυρίως λεγομένη ἐστὶν ἡ οὐσία ἡ τῶν ἐχόντων [15] ἀρχὴν κινήσεως ἐν αὑτοῖς ᾗ αὐτά: ἡ γὰρ ὕλη τῷ ταύτης δεκτικὴ εἶναι λέγεται φύσις, καὶ αἱ γενέσεις καὶ τὸ φύεσθαι τῷ ἀπὸ ταύτης εἶναι κινήσεις. καὶ ἡ ἀρχὴ τῆς κινήσεως τῶν φύσει ὄντων αὕτη ἐστίν, ἐνυπάρχουσά πως ἢ δυνάμει ἢ ἐντελεχείᾳ.

References edit

  1. ^ Aristotle Physics 192b21
  2. ^ Aristotle Physics 193b21
  3. ^ "Progress or Return" in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. (Expanded version of Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, 1975.) Ed. Hilail Gilden. Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1989.
  4. ^ Strauss and Cropsey eds. History of Political Philosophy, Third edition, p.209.
  5. ^ Metaphysics 995b, translated by Hugh Tredennick. Greek: μάλιστα δὲ ζητητέον καὶ πραγματευτέον πότερον ἔστι τι παρὰ τὴν ὕλην αἴτιον καθ᾽ αὑτὸ ἢ οὔ
  6. ^ As for example Aristotle Politics 1252b.1: "Thus the female and the slave are by nature distinct (for nature makes nothing as the cutlers make the Delphic knife, in a niggardly way, but one thing for one purpose; for so each tool will be turned out in the finest perfection, if it serves not many uses but one"
  7. ^ Metaphysics 999b, translated by Hugh Tredennick. Greek: εἰ μὲν οὖν μηδέν ἐστι παρὰ τὰ καθ᾽ ἕκαστα, οὐθὲν ἂν εἴη νοητὸν ἀλλὰ πάντα αἰσθητὰ καὶ ἐπιστήμη οὐδενός, εἰ μή τις εἶναι λέγει τὴν αἴσθησιν ἐπιστήμην.
  8. ^ Ducarme, Frédéric; Couvet, Denis (2020). "What does 'nature' mean?". Palgrave Communications. Springer Nature. 6 (14). doi:10.1057/s41599-020-0390-y.
  9. ^ Phusis is the Greek word for Nature, and Aristotle is drawing attention to the similarity it has to the verb used to describe natural growth in a plant, phusei. Indeed the first use of the word involves a plant: ὣς ἄρα φωνήσας πόρε φάρμακον ἀργεϊφόντης ἐκ γαίης ἐρύσας, καί μοι φύσιν αὐτοῦ ἔδειξε. "So saying, Argeiphontes [=Hermes] gave me the herb, drawing it from the ground, and showed me its nature." Odyssey 10.302-3 (ed. A.T. Murray).
  10. ^ Warren, Herbert (2001). Jainism. Delhi: Crest Publishing House. ISBN 978-81-242-0037-7.
  11. ^ Carrithers, Michael (June 1989). "Naked Ascetics in Southern Digambar Jainism". Man. New Series. 24 (2): 219–235. doi:10.2307/2803303. JSTOR 2803303. p. 220
  12. ^ Jayatilleke, K.N. (1963). Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge (PDF) (1st ed.). London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. pp. 112–113.
  13. ^ Salunkhe, AH (2009). Astikshiromani Charvaka (in Marathi). Satara: Lokayat Prakashan. p. 36.
  14. ^ Ben-Ami Scharfstein (1998). A Comparative History of World Philosophy: From the Upanishads to Kant. State University of New York Press. pp. 56–61. ISBN 978-0-7914-3683-7.
  15. ^ Ben-Ami Scharfstein (1998), A comparative history of world philosophy: from the Upanishads to Kant, Albany: State University of New York Press, pp. 9-11
  16. ^ James G. Lochtefeld (2002). The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism: A-M. The Rosen Publishing Group. p. 66. ISBN 978-0-8239-3179-8.
  17. ^ a b c d Chapple, Christopher (1984). "Introduction". The Concise Yoga Vāsiṣṭha. Translated by Venkatesananda, Swami. Albany: State University of New York Press. pp. 11–12. ISBN 0-87395-955-8. OCLC 11044869.
  18. ^ Venkatesananda, S (Translator) (1984). The Concise Yoga Vāsiṣṭha. Albany: State University of New York Press. pp. 117–158. ISBN 0-87395-955-8. {{cite book}}: |first= has generic name (help)
  19. ^ Surendranath Dasgupta, A History of Indian Philosophy, Volume 2, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0521047791, pages 252-253
  20. ^ a b Daniel Arnold (2001). "Of Intrinsic Validity: A Study on the Relevance of Pūrva Mīmāṃsā". Philosophy East and West. University of Hawai'i Press. 51 (1): 27–32. doi:10.1353/pew.2001.0002. JSTOR 1400034. S2CID 144863536.
  21. ^ Gunnar Skirbekk, Nils Gilje, A history of Western thought: from ancient Greece to the twentieth century. 7th edition published by Routledge, 2001, p. 25.
  22. ^ Siderits, Mark. Buddhism as philosophy, 2007, p. 6
  23. ^ Ajahn Sumedho, The First Noble Truth (nb: links to index-page; click "The First Noble Truth" for correct page.
  24. ^ Nyanatiloka (1980), Buddhist Dictionary, p.65, Buddhist Publication Society
  25. ^ Emmanuel, Steven M. (2015), A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy, pp.26–31, John Wiley & Sons
  26. ^ Trainor, Kevin (2004), Buddhism: The Illustrated Guide, Oxford University Press, p. 74, ISBN 978-0195173987
  27. ^ Conze, Edward (2013), Buddhist Thought in India: Three Phases of Buddhist Philosophy, Routledge, pp. 39–40, ISBN 978-1134542314
  28. ^ Merv Fowler (1999). Buddhism: Beliefs and Practices. Sussex Academic Press. pp. 49–52. ISBN 978-1-898723-66-0.
  29. ^ Joseph Mitsuo Kitagawa; Frank E. Reynolds; Theodore M. Ludwig (1980). Transitions and Transformations in the History of Religions: Essays in Honor of Joseph M. Kitagawa. Brill Academic. pp. 56–58. ISBN 978-90-04-06112-5., Quote: Suffering describes the condition of samsaric (this worldly) existence that arises from actions generated by ignorance of anatta and anicca. The doctrines of no-self and impermanence are thus the keystones of dhammic order."
  30. ^ Harvey, Peter (1990), An Introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, History and Practices, Cambridge University Press, p. 54, ISBN 978-0521313339
  31. ^ John Bowker, The Oxford Dictionary of World Religions (1997), Oxford University Press, ISBN 0-19-213965-7
  32. ^ Adler, Joseph A. (2014), Confucianism as a Religious Tradition: Linguistic and Methodological Problems (PDF), Gambier, Ohio, USA: Kenyon College, p. 12
  33. ^ Littlejohn, Ronnie (2010), Confucianism: An Introduction, I.B. Tauris, pp. 34–36, ISBN 978-1-84885-174-0
  34. ^ Didier, John C. (2009). "In and Outside the Square: The Sky and the Power of Belief in Ancient China and the World, c. 4500 BC – AD 200". Sino-Platonic Papers (192). Volume I: The Ancient Eurasian World and the Celestial Pivot, Volume II: Representations and Identities of High Powers in Neolithic and Bronze China, Volume III: Terrestrial and Celestial Transformations in Zhou and Early-Imperial China.
  35. ^ a b Hagen, Kurtis. . State University of New York at Plattsburgh. Archived from the original on 3 December 2014.
  36. ^ Hsu, Promise (16 November 2014). "The Civil Theology of Confucius' "Tian" Symbol". Voegelin View.
  37. ^ a b Feuchtwang, Stephan (2016), "Chinese religions", in Woodhead, Linda; Kawanami, Hiroko; Partridge, Christopher H. (eds.), Religions in the Modern World: Traditions and Transformations (3nd ed.), London: Routledge, p. 146, ISBN 978-1-317-43960-8
  38. ^ Bacon (1905). "II.VII.7". Advancement of Learning. p. 90.
  39. ^ Summa Theologiae I-II Q90, A4
  40. ^ On the Law of War and Peace, Proleg. 40
  41. ^ The Spirit of the Laws, opening lines
  42. ^ The Prince 15:- "...since my intent is to write something useful to whoever understands it, it has appeared to me more fitting to go directly to the effectual truth of the thing than to the imagination of it. And many have imagined republics and principalities that have never been seen or known to exist in truth; for it is so far from how one lives to how one should live that he who lets go of what is done for what should be done learns his ruin rather than his preservation. For a man who wants to make a profession of good in all regards must come to ruin among so many who are not good. Hence it is necessary to a prince, if he wants to maintain himself, to learn to be able not to be good, and to use this and not use it according to necessity."

Further reading edit

  • Gerard Naddaf, The Greek Concept of Nature, New York, State University of New York Press, 2005.
  • Ducarme, Frédéric; Couvet, Denis (2020). "What does 'nature' mean?". Palgrave Communications. Springer Nature. 6 (14). doi:10.1057/s41599-020-0390-y.

nature, philosophy, further, information, nature, nature, inter, related, meanings, philosophy, natural, philosophy, hand, means, things, which, natural, subject, normal, working, laws, nature, other, hand, means, essential, properties, causes, individual, thi. Further information Nature Nature has two inter related meanings in philosophy and natural philosophy On the one hand it means the set of all things which are natural or subject to the normal working of the laws of nature On the other hand it means the essential properties and causes of individual things How to understand the meaning and significance of nature has been a consistent theme of discussion within the history of Western Civilization in the philosophical fields of metaphysics and epistemology as well as in theology and science The study of natural things and the regular laws which seem to govern them as opposed to discussion about what it means to be natural is the area of natural science The word nature derives from Latin natura a philosophical term derived from the verb for birth which was used as a translation for the earlier pre Socratic Greek term phusis derived from the verb for natural growth Already in classical times philosophical use of these words combined two related meanings which have in common that they refer to the way in which things happen by themselves naturally without interference from human deliberation divine intervention or anything outside what is considered normal for the natural things being considered Understandings of nature depend on the subject and age of the work where they appear For example Aristotle s explanation of natural properties differs from what is meant by natural properties in modern philosophical and scientific works which can also differ from other scientific and conventional usage Contents 1 Classical nature and Aristotelian metaphysics 2 In Eastern philosophy 2 1 Indian philosophy 2 2 East Asian philosophies 3 Modern science and laws of nature trying to avoid metaphysics 4 Late modern nature 5 The survival of metaphysics 6 The study of nature without metaphysics 7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 10 Further readingClassical nature and Aristotelian metaphysics editMain article Physis The Physics from ta phusika the natural things is Aristotle s principal work on nature In Physics II 1 Aristotle defines a nature as a source or cause of being moved and of being at rest in that to which it belongs primarily 1 In other words a nature is the principle within a natural raw material that is the source of tendencies to change or rest in a particular way unless stopped For example a rock would fall unless stopped Natural things stand in contrast to artifacts which are formed by human artifice not because of an innate tendency The raw materials of a bed have no tendency to become a bed In terms of Aristotle s theory of four causes the word natural is applied both to the innate potential of matter cause and the forms which the matter tends to become naturally 2 According to Leo Strauss 3 the beginning of Western philosophy involved the discovery or invention of nature and the pre philosophical equivalent of nature was supplied by such notions as custom or ways In ancient Greek philosophy on the other hand Nature or natures are ways that are really universal in all times and places What makes nature different is that it presupposes not only that not all customs and ways are equal but also that one can find one s bearings in the cosmos on the basis of inquiry not for example on the basis of traditions or religion To put this discovery or invention into the traditional terminology what is by nature is contrasted to what is by convention The concept of nature taken this far remains a strong tradition in modern Western thinking Science according to Strauss commentary of Western history is the contemplation of nature while technology was or is an attempt to imitate it 4 Going further the philosophical concept of nature or natures as a special type of causation for example that the way particular humans are is partly caused by something called human nature is an essential step towards Aristotle s teaching concerning causation which became standard in all Western philosophy until the arrival of modern science nbsp Depiction of AristotleWhether it was intended or not Aristotle s inquiries into this subject were long felt to have resolved the discussion about nature in favor of one solution In this account there are four different types of cause The material cause is the raw material the matter which undergoes change One of the causes of a statue being what it is might be that it is bronze All meanings of the word nature encompass this simple meaning The efficient cause is the motion of another thing which makes a thing change for example a chisel hitting a rock causes a chip to break off This is the way which the matter is forming into a form so that it become substance like what Aristotle said that a substance must have a form and matter in order to call it substance This is the motion of changing a single being into two This is the most obvious way in which cause and effect works as in the descriptions of modern science But according to Aristotle this does not yet explain that of which the motion is and we must apply ourselves to the question whether there is any other cause per se besides matter 5 The formal cause is the form or idea which serves as a template towards which things develop for example following an approach based upon Aristotle we could say that a child develops in a way partly determined by a thing called human nature Here nature is a cause The final cause is the aim towards which something is directed For example a human aims at something perceived to be good as Aristotle says in the opening lines of the Nicomachean Ethics The formal and final cause are an essential part of Aristotle s Metaphysics his attempt to go beyond nature and explain nature itself In practice they imply a human like consciousness involved in the causation of all things even things which are not man made Nature itself is attributed with having aims 6 The artificial like the conventional therefore is within this branch of Western thought traditionally contrasted with the natural Technology was contrasted with science as mentioned above And another essential aspect to this understanding of causation was the distinction between the accidental properties of a thing and the substance another distinction which has lost favor in the modern era after having long been widely accepted in medieval Europe To describe it another way Aristotle treated organisms and other natural wholes as existing at a higher level than mere matter in motion Aristotle s argument for formal and final causes is related to a doctrine about how it is possible that people know things If nothing exists apart from individual things nothing will be intelligible everything will be sensible and there will be no knowledge of anything unless it be maintained that sense perception is knowledge 7 Those philosophers who disagree with this reasoning therefore also see knowledge differently from Aristotle Aristotle then described nature or natures as follows in a way quite different from modern science 8 Nature means a in one sense the genesis of growing things as would be suggested by pronouncing the y of fysis 9 long and b in another that immanent thing from which a growing thing first begins to grow c The source from which the primary motion in every natural object is induced in that object as such All things are said to grow which gain increase through something else by contact and organic unity or adhesion as in the case of embryos Organic unity differs from contact for in the latter case there need be nothing except contact but in both the things which form an organic unity there is some one and the same thing which produces instead of mere contact a unity which is organic continuous and quantitative but not qualitative Again nature means d the primary stuff shapeless and unchangeable from its own potency of which any natural object consists or from which it is produced e g bronze is called the nature of a statue and of bronze articles and wood that of wooden ones and similarly in all other cases For each article consists of these natures the primary material persisting It is in this sense that men call the elements of natural objects the nature some calling it fire others earth or air or water others something else similar others some of these and others all of them Again in another sense nature means e the substance of natural objects as in the case of those who say that the nature is the primary composition of a thing or as Empedocles says Of nothing that exists is there nature but only mixture and separation of what has been mixed nature is but a name given to these by men Hence as regards those things which exist or are produced by nature although that from which they naturally are produced or exist is already present we say that they have not their nature yet unless they have their form and shape That which comprises both of these exists by nature e g animals and their parts And nature is both the primary matter and this in two senses either primary in relation to the thing or primary in general e g in bronze articles the primary matter in relation to those articles is bronze but in general it is perhaps water that is if all things which can be melted are water and the form or essence i e the end of the process of generation Indeed from this sense of nature by an extension of meaning every essence in general is called nature because the nature of anything is a kind of essence From what has been said then the primary and proper sense of nature is the essence of those things which contain in themselves as such a source of motion for the matter is called nature because it is capable of receiving the nature and the processes of generation and growth are called nature because they are motions derived from it And nature in this sense is the source of motion in natural objects which is somehow inherent in them either potentially or actually Metaphysics 1014b 1015a translated by Hugh Tredennick emphasis added a It has been argued as will be explained below that this type of theory represented an oversimplifying diversion from the debates within Classical philosophy possibly even that Aristotle saw it as a simplification or summary of the debates himself But in any case the theory of the four causes became a standard part of any advanced education in the Middle Ages In Eastern philosophy editThis section needs expansion You can help by adding to it June 2019 Indian philosophy edit Jain philosophy attempts to explain the rationale of being and existence the nature of the Universe and its constituents the nature of bondage and the means to achieve liberation 10 Jainism strongly upholds the individualistic nature of soul and personal responsibility for one s decisions and that self reliance and individual efforts alone are responsible for one s liberation 11 Ajnana was a Sramaṇa school of radical Indian skepticism and a rival of early Buddhism and Jainism They held that it was impossible to obtain knowledge of metaphysical nature or ascertain the truth value of philosophical propositions 12 and even if knowledge was possible it was useless and disadvantageous for final salvation They were seen as sophists who specialized in refutation without propagating any positive doctrine of their own Jayarasi Bhaṭṭa fl c 800 author of the skeptical work entitled Tattvopaplavasiṃha The Lion that Devours All Categories The Upsetting of All Principles has been seen as an important Ajnana philosopher 13 In the Chandogya Upanishad Aruni asks metaphysical questions concerning the nature of reality and truth observes constant change and asks if there is something that is eternal and unchanging From these questions embedded in a dialogue with his son he presents the concept of Atman soul Self and universal Self 14 15 The Ashtavakra Gita credited to Aṣṭavakra examines the metaphysical nature of existence and the meaning of individual freedom presenting its thesis that there is only one Supreme Reality Brahman the entirety of universe is oneness and manifestation of this reality everything is interconnected all Self Atman soul are part of that one and that individual freedom is not the end point but a given a starting point innate 16 The first book of Yoga Vasistha attributed to Valmiki presents Rama s frustration with the nature of life human suffering and disdain for the world 17 The second describes through the character of Rama the desire for liberation and the nature of those who seek such liberation 17 The fourth describes the nature of world and many non dualism ideas with numerous stories 17 18 It emphasizes free will and human creative power 17 19 Ancient Mimaṃsa s central concern was epistemology pramana that is what are the reliable means to knowledge It debated not only how does man ever learn or know whatever he knows but also whether the nature of all knowledge is inherently circular whether those such as foundationalists who critique the validity of any justified beliefs and knowledge system make flawed presumptions of the very premises they critique and how to correctly interpret and avoid incorrectly interpreting dharma texts such as the Vedas 20 To Mimansa scholars the nature of non empirical knowledge and human means to it are such that one can never demonstrate certainty one can only falsify knowledge claims in some cases 20 Buddhist philosophy s main concern is soteriological defined as freedom from dukkha unease 21 Because ignorance to the true nature of things is considered one of the roots of suffering Buddhist thinkers concerned themselves with philosophical questions related to epistemology and the use of reason 22 Dukkha can be translated as incapable of satisfying 23 the unsatisfactory nature and the general insecurity of all conditioned phenomena or painful 24 25 Prajna is insight or knowledge of the true nature of existence The Buddhist tradition regards ignorance avidya a fundamental ignorance misunderstanding or mis perception of the nature of reality as one of the basic causes of dukkha and samsara By overcoming ignorance or misunderstanding one is enlightened and liberated This overcoming includes awakening to impermanence and the non self nature of reality 26 27 and this develops dispassion for the objects of clinging and liberates a being from dukkha and saṃsara 28 29 Pratityasamutpada also called dependent arising or dependent origination is the Buddhist theory to explain the nature and relations of being becoming existence and ultimate reality Buddhism asserts that there is nothing independent except the state of nirvana 30 All physical and mental states depend on and arise from other pre existing states and in turn from them arise other dependent states while they cease 31 East Asian philosophies edit Confucianism considers the ordinary activities of human life and especially human relationships as a manifestation of the sacred 32 because they are the expression of humanity s moral nature xing 性 which has a transcendent anchorage in Heaven Tian 天 and unfolds through an appropriate respect for the spirits or gods shen of the world 33 Tian 天 a key concept in Chinese thought refers to the God of Heaven the northern culmen of the skies and its spinning stars 34 earthly nature and its laws which come from Heaven to Heaven and Earth that is all things and to the awe inspiring forces beyond human control 35 Confucius used the term in a mystical way 36 It is similar to what Taoists meant by Dao the way things are or the regularities of the world 35 which Stephan Feuchtwang equates with the ancient Greek concept of physis nature as the generation and regenerations of things and of the moral order 37 Feuchtwang explains that the difference between Confucianism and Taoism primarily lies in the fact that the former focuses on the realisation of the starry order of Heaven in human society while the latter on the contemplation of the Dao which spontaneously arises in nature 37 Modern science and laws of nature trying to avoid metaphysics edit nbsp A Renaissance imagined representation of Democritus the laughing philosopher by Agostino CarracciIn contrast Modern Science took its distinctive turn with Francis Bacon who rejected the four distinct causes and saw Aristotle as someone who did proceed in such a spirit of difference and contradiction towards all antiquity undertaking not only to frame new words of science at pleasure but to confound and extinguish all ancient wisdom He felt that lesser known Greek philosophers such as Democritus who did not suppose a mind or reason in the frame of things have been arrogantly dismissed because of Aristotelianism leading to a situation in his time wherein the search of the physical causes hath been neglected and passed in silence 38 And so Bacon advised Physic doth make inquiry and take consideration of the same natures but how Only as to the material and efficient causes of them and not as to the forms For example if the cause of whiteness in snow or froth be inquired and it be rendered thus that the subtile intermixture of air and water is the cause it is well rendered but nevertheless is this the form of whiteness No but it is the efficient which is ever but vehiculum formae This part of metaphysique I do not find laboured and performed Francis Bacon Advancement of Learning II VII 6 nbsp Francis BaconIn his Novum Organum Bacon argued that the only forms or natures we should hypothesize are the simple as opposed to compound ones such as the ways in which heat movement etc work For example in aphorism 51 he writes 51 The human understanding is by its own nature prone to abstraction and supposes that which is fluctuating to be fixed But it is better to dissect than abstract nature such was the method employed by the school of Democritus which made greater progress in penetrating nature than the rest It is best to consider matter its conformation and the changes of that conformation its own action and the law of this action or motion for forms are a mere fiction of the human mind unless you will call the laws of action by that name Following Bacon s advice the scientific search for the formal cause of things is now replaced by the search for laws of nature or laws of physics in all scientific thinking To use Aristotle s well known terminology these are descriptions of efficient cause and not formal cause or final cause It means modern science limits its hypothesizing about non physical things to the assumption that there are regularities to the ways of all things which do not change These general laws in other words replace thinking about specific laws for example human nature In modern science human nature is part of the same general scheme of cause and effect obeying the same general laws as all other things The above mentioned difference between accidental and substantial properties and indeed knowledge and opinion also disappear within this new approach that aimed to avoid metaphysics As Bacon knew the term laws of nature was one taken from medieval Aristotelianism St Thomas Aquinas for example defined law so that nature really was legislated to consciously achieve aims like human law an ordinance of reason for the common good made by him who has care of the community and promulgated 39 In contrast roughly contemporary with Bacon Hugo Grotius described the law of nature as a rule that can be deduced from fixed principles by a sure process of reasoning 40 And later still Montesquieu was even further from the original legal metaphor describing laws vaguely as the necessary relations deriving from the nature of things 41 nbsp Thomas HobbesOne of the most important implementors of Bacon s proposal was Thomas Hobbes whose remarks concerning nature are particularly well known His most famous work Leviathan opens with the word Nature and then parenthetically defines it as the art whereby God hath made and governes the world Despite this pious description he follows a Baconian approach Following his contemporary Descartes Hobbes describes life itself as mechanical caused in the same way as clockwork For seeing life is but a motion of Limbs the beginning whereof is in some principall part within why may we not say that all Automata Engines that move themselves by springs and wheeles as doth a watch have an artificiall life On this basis already being established in natural science in his lifetime Hobbes sought to discuss politics and human life in terms of laws of nature But in the new modern approach of Bacon and Hobbes and before them Machiavelli who however never clothed his criticism of the Aristotelian approach in medieval terms like laws of nature 42 such laws of nature are quite different to human laws they no longer imply any sense of better or worse but simply how things really are and when in reference to laws of human nature what sorts of human behavior can be most relied upon Late modern nature edit nbsp Jean Jacques Rousseau a civilized man but a person who questioned whether civilization was according to human nature Having disconnected the term law of nature from the original medieval metaphor of human made law the term law of nature is now used less than in early modern times To take the critical example of human nature as discussed in ethics and politics once early modern philosophers such as Hobbes had described human nature as whatever you could expect from a mechanism called a human the point of speaking of human nature became problematic in some contexts In the late 18th century Rousseau took a critical step in his Second Discourse reasoning that human nature as we know it rational and with language and so on is a result of historical accidents and the specific up bringing of an individual The consequences of this line of reasoning were to be enormous It was all about the question of nature In effect it was being claimed that human nature one of the most important types of nature in Aristotelian thinking did not exist as it had been understood to exist The survival of metaphysics editThe approach of modern science like the approach of Aristotelianism is apparently not universally accepted by all people who accept the concept of nature as a reality which we can pursue with reason Bacon and other opponents of Metaphysics claim that all attempts to go beyond nature are bound to fall into the same errors but Metaphysicians themselves see differences between different approaches Immanuel Kant for example expressed the need for a Metaphysics in quite similar terms to Aristotle though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears Critique of Pure Reason pp Bxxvi xxvii As in Aristotelianism then Kantianism claims that the human mind must itself have characteristics which are beyond nature metaphysical in some way Specifically Kant argued that the human mind comes ready made with a priori programming so to speak which allows it to make sense of nature The study of nature without metaphysics editAuthors from Nietzsche to Richard Rorty have claimed that science the study of nature can and should exist without metaphysics But this claim has always been controversial Authors like Bacon and Hume never denied that their use of the word nature implied metaphysics but tried to follow Machiavelli s approach of talking about what works instead of claiming to understand what seems impossible to understand See also editA priori and a posteriori Aristotelianism Causality Empiricism Human nature Idealism Metaphysical naturalism Natural philosophy Nature Saṃsara Naturphilosophie Philosophical naturalism Platonism Reality TruthNotes edit Greek with emphasis added as a guide fysis legetai ἕna mὲn tropon ἡ tῶn fyomenwn genesis oἷon eἴ tis ἐpekteinas legoi tὸ y ἕna dὲ ἐ3 oὗ fyetai prwtoy tὸ fyomenon ἐnyparxontos ἔti ὅ8en ἡ kinhsis ἡ prwth ἐn ἑkastῳ tῶn fysei ὄntwn ἐn aὐtῷ ᾗ aὐtὸ 20 ὑparxei fyes8ai dὲ legetai ὅsa aὔ3hsin ἔxei di ἑteroy tῷ ἅptes8ai kaὶ sympefykenai ἢ prospefykenai ὥsper tὰ ἔmbrya diaferei dὲ symfysis ἁfῆs ἔn8a mὲn gὰr oὐdὲn parὰ tὴn ἁfὴn ἕteron ἀnagkh eἶnai ἐn dὲ toῖs sympefykosin ἔsti ti ἓn tὸ aὐtὸ ἐn ἀmfoῖn ὃ poieῖ ἀntὶ toῦ 25 ἅptes8ai sympefykenai kaὶ eἶnai ἓn katὰ tὸ synexὲs kaὶ poson ἀllὰ mὴ katὰ tὸ poion ἔti dὲ fysis legetai ἐ3 oὗ prwtoy ἢ ἔstin ἢ gignetai ti tῶn fysei ὄntwn ἀrry8mistoy ὄntos kaὶ ἀmetablhtoy ἐk tῆs dynamews tῆs aὑtoῦ oἷon ἀndriantos kaὶ tῶn skeyῶn tῶn xalkῶn ὁ xalkὸs ἡ 30 fysis legetai tῶn dὲ 3ylinwn 3ylon ὁmoiws dὲ kaὶ ἐpὶ tῶn ἄllwn ἐk toytwn gar ἐstin ἕkaston diaswzomenhs tῆs prwths ὕlhs toῦton gὰr tὸn tropon kaὶ tῶn fysei ὄntwn tὰ stoixeῖa fasin eἶnai fysin oἱ mὲn pῦr oἱ dὲ gῆn oἱ d ἀera oἱ d ὕdwr oἱ d ἄllo ti toioῦton legontes oἱ d 35 ἔnia toytwn oἱ dὲ panta taῦta ἔti d ἄllon tropon legetai ἡ fysis ἡ tῶn fysei ὄntwn oὐsia oἷon oἱ legontes tὴn fysin eἶnai tὴn prwthn syn8esin ἢ ὥsper Ἐmpedoklῆs legei ὅti fysis oὐdenὸs ἔstin ἐontwn ἀllὰ monon mῖ3is te dialla3is te migentwn ἔsti fysis d ἐpὶ toῖs ὀnomazetai ἀn8rwpoisin Empedocles Fr 8 diὸ kaὶ ὅsa fysei ἔstin ἢ gignetai ἤdh ὑparxontos ἐ3 oὗ pefyke gignes8ai ἢ eἶnai oὔpw famὲn 5 tὴn fysin ἔxein ἐὰn mὴ ἔxῃ tὸ eἶdos kaὶ tὴn morfhn fysei mὲn oὖn tὸ ἐ3 ἀmfoterwn toytwn ἐstin oἷon tὰ zῷa kaὶ tὰ moria aὐtῶn fysis dὲ ἥ te prwth ὕlh kaὶ aὕth dixῶs ἢ ἡ prὸs aὐtὸ prwth ἢ ἡ ὅlws prwth oἷon tῶn xalkῶn ἔrgwn prὸs aὐtὰ mὲn prῶtos ὁ xalkos ὅlws d 10 ἴsws ὕdwr eἰ panta tὰ thktὰ ὕdwr kaὶ tὸ eἶdos kaὶ ἡ oὐsia toῦto d ἐstὶ tὸ telos tῆs genesews metaforᾷ d ἤdh kaὶ ὅlws pᾶsa oὐsia fysis legetai diὰ taythn ὅti kaὶ ἡ fysis oὐsia tis ἐstin ἐk dὴ tῶn eἰrhmenwn ἡ prwth fysis kaὶ kyriws legomenh ἐstὶn ἡ oὐsia ἡ tῶn ἐxontwn 15 ἀrxὴn kinhsews ἐn aὑtoῖs ᾗ aὐta ἡ gὰr ὕlh tῷ tayths dektikὴ eἶnai legetai fysis kaὶ aἱ geneseis kaὶ tὸ fyes8ai tῷ ἀpὸ tayths eἶnai kinhseis kaὶ ἡ ἀrxὴ tῆs kinhsews tῶn fysei ὄntwn aὕth ἐstin ἐnyparxoysa pws ἢ dynamei ἢ ἐntelexeiᾳ References edit Aristotle Physics 192b21 Aristotle Physics 193b21 Progress or Return in An Introduction to Political Philosophy Ten Essays by Leo Strauss Expanded version of Political Philosophy Six Essays by Leo Strauss 1975 Ed Hilail Gilden Detroit Wayne State UP 1989 Strauss and Cropsey eds History of Political Philosophy Third edition p 209 Metaphysics 995b translated by Hugh Tredennick Greek malista dὲ zhthteon kaὶ pragmateyteon poteron ἔsti ti parὰ tὴn ὕlhn aἴtion ka8 aὑtὸ ἢ oὔ As for example Aristotle Politics 1252b 1 Thus the female and the slave are by nature distinct for nature makes nothing as the cutlers make the Delphic knife in a niggardly way but one thing for one purpose for so each tool will be turned out in the finest perfection if it serves not many uses but one Metaphysics 999b translated by Hugh Tredennick Greek eἰ mὲn oὖn mhden ἐsti parὰ tὰ ka8 ἕkasta oὐ8ὲn ἂn eἴh nohtὸn ἀllὰ panta aἰs8htὰ kaὶ ἐpisthmh oὐdenos eἰ mh tis eἶnai legei tὴn aἴs8hsin ἐpisthmhn Ducarme Frederic Couvet Denis 2020 What does nature mean Palgrave Communications Springer Nature 6 14 doi 10 1057 s41599 020 0390 y Phusis is the Greek word for Nature and Aristotle is drawing attention to the similarity it has to the verb used to describe natural growth in a plant phusei Indeed the first use of the word involves a plant ὣs ἄra fwnhsas pore farmakon ἀrgeifonths ἐk gaihs ἐrysas kai moi fysin aὐtoῦ ἔdei3e So saying Argeiphontes Hermes gave me the herb drawing it from the ground and showed me its nature Odyssey 10 302 3 ed A T Murray Warren Herbert 2001 Jainism Delhi Crest Publishing House ISBN 978 81 242 0037 7 Carrithers Michael June 1989 Naked Ascetics in Southern Digambar Jainism Man New Series 24 2 219 235 doi 10 2307 2803303 JSTOR 2803303 p 220 Jayatilleke K N 1963 Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge PDF 1st ed London George Allen amp Unwin Ltd pp 112 113 Salunkhe AH 2009 Astikshiromani Charvaka in Marathi Satara Lokayat Prakashan p 36 Ben Ami Scharfstein 1998 A Comparative History of World Philosophy From the Upanishads to Kant State University of New York Press pp 56 61 ISBN 978 0 7914 3683 7 Ben Ami Scharfstein 1998 A comparative history of world philosophy from the Upanishads to Kant Albany State University of New York Press pp 9 11 James G Lochtefeld 2002 The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism A M The Rosen Publishing Group p 66 ISBN 978 0 8239 3179 8 a b c d Chapple Christopher 1984 Introduction The Concise Yoga Vasiṣṭha Translated by Venkatesananda Swami Albany State University of New York Press pp 11 12 ISBN 0 87395 955 8 OCLC 11044869 Venkatesananda S Translator 1984 The Concise Yoga Vasiṣṭha Albany State University of New York Press pp 117 158 ISBN 0 87395 955 8 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a first has generic name help Surendranath Dasgupta A History of Indian Philosophy Volume 2 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521047791 pages 252 253 a b Daniel Arnold 2001 Of Intrinsic Validity A Study on the Relevance of Purva Mimaṃsa Philosophy East and West University of Hawai i Press 51 1 27 32 doi 10 1353 pew 2001 0002 JSTOR 1400034 S2CID 144863536 Gunnar Skirbekk Nils Gilje A history of Western thought from ancient Greece to the twentieth century 7th edition published by Routledge 2001 p 25 Siderits Mark Buddhism as philosophy 2007 p 6 Ajahn Sumedho The First Noble Truth nb links to index page click The First Noble Truth for correct page Nyanatiloka 1980 Buddhist Dictionary p 65 Buddhist Publication Society Emmanuel Steven M 2015 A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy pp 26 31 John Wiley amp Sons Trainor Kevin 2004 Buddhism The Illustrated Guide Oxford University Press p 74 ISBN 978 0195173987 Conze Edward 2013 Buddhist Thought in India Three Phases of Buddhist Philosophy Routledge pp 39 40 ISBN 978 1134542314 Merv Fowler 1999 Buddhism Beliefs and Practices Sussex Academic Press pp 49 52 ISBN 978 1 898723 66 0 Joseph Mitsuo Kitagawa Frank E Reynolds Theodore M Ludwig 1980 Transitions and Transformations in the History of Religions Essays in Honor of Joseph M Kitagawa Brill Academic pp 56 58 ISBN 978 90 04 06112 5 Quote Suffering describes the condition of samsaric this worldly existence that arises from actions generated by ignorance of anatta and anicca The doctrines of no self and impermanence are thus the keystones of dhammic order Harvey Peter 1990 An Introduction to Buddhism Teachings History and Practices Cambridge University Press p 54 ISBN 978 0521313339 John Bowker The Oxford Dictionary of World Religions 1997 Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 213965 7 Adler Joseph A 2014 Confucianism as a Religious Tradition Linguistic and Methodological Problems PDF Gambier Ohio USA Kenyon College p 12 Littlejohn Ronnie 2010 Confucianism An Introduction I B Tauris pp 34 36 ISBN 978 1 84885 174 0 Didier John C 2009 In and Outside the Square The Sky and the Power of Belief in Ancient China and the World c 4500 BC AD 200 Sino Platonic Papers 192 Volume I The Ancient Eurasian World and the Celestial Pivot Volume II Representations and Identities of High Powers in Neolithic and Bronze China Volume III Terrestrial and Celestial Transformations in Zhou and Early Imperial China a b Hagen Kurtis Confucian Key Terms Tian 天 State University of New York at Plattsburgh Archived from the original on 3 December 2014 Hsu Promise 16 November 2014 The Civil Theology of Confucius Tian Symbol Voegelin View a b Feuchtwang Stephan 2016 Chinese religions in Woodhead Linda Kawanami Hiroko Partridge Christopher H eds Religions in the Modern World Traditions and Transformations 3nd ed London Routledge p 146 ISBN 978 1 317 43960 8 Bacon 1905 II VII 7 Advancement of Learning p 90 Summa Theologiae I II Q90 A4 On the Law of War and Peace Proleg 40 The Spirit of the Laws opening lines The Prince 15 since my intent is to write something useful to whoever understands it it has appeared to me more fitting to go directly to the effectual truth of the thing than to the imagination of it And many have imagined republics and principalities that have never been seen or known to exist in truth for it is so far from how one lives to how one should live that he who lets go of what is done for what should be done learns his ruin rather than his preservation For a man who wants to make a profession of good in all regards must come to ruin among so many who are not good Hence it is necessary to a prince if he wants to maintain himself to learn to be able not to be good and to use this and not use it according to necessity Further reading editGerard Naddaf The Greek Concept of Nature New York State University of New York Press 2005 Ducarme Frederic Couvet Denis 2020 What does nature mean Palgrave Communications Springer Nature 6 14 doi 10 1057 s41599 020 0390 y Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Nature philosophy amp oldid 1167264934, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.