fbpx
Wikipedia

Dialectic

Dialectic (Greek: διαλεκτική, dialektikḗ; related to dialogue; German: Dialektik), also known as the dialectical method, is a discourse between two or more people holding different points of view about a subject but wishing to establish the truth through reasoned argumentation. Dialectic resembles debate, but the concept excludes subjective elements such as emotional appeal and rhetoric (in the modern pejorative sense).[1][2] Dialectic may thus be contrasted with both the eristic, which refers to argument that aims to successfully dispute another's argument (rather than searching for truth), and the didactic method, wherein one side of the conversation teaches the other. Dialectic is alternatively known as minor logic, as opposed to major logic or critique.

Within Hegelianism, the word dialectic has the specialised meaning of a contradiction between ideas that serves as the determining factor in their relationship. Dialectical materialism, a theory or set of theories produced mainly by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, adapted the Hegelian dialectic into arguments regarding traditional materialism. The dialectics of Hegel and Marx were criticized in the twentieth century by the philosophers Karl Popper and Mario Bunge.

Dialectic tends to imply a process of evolution and so does not naturally fit within classical logics, but was given some formalism in the twentieth century. The emphasis on process is particularly marked in Hegelian dialectic, and even more so in Marxist dialectical logic, which tried to account for the evolution of ideas over longer time periods in the real world.

Western dialectical forms

There is a variety of meanings of dialectic or dialectics within Western philosophy.

Classical philosophy

In classical philosophy, dialectic (διαλεκτική) is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter-arguments, advocating propositions (theses) and counter-propositions (antitheses). The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition, or of a synthesis, or a combination of the opposing assertions, or a qualitative improvement of the dialogue.[3][4]

Moreover, the term "dialectic" owes much of its prestige to its role in the philosophies of Socrates and Plato, in the Greek Classical period (5th to 4th centuries BC). Aristotle said that it was the pre-Socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea who invented dialectic, of which the dialogues of Plato are the examples of the Socratic dialectical method.[5]

According to Kant, however, the ancient Greeks used the word "dialectic" to signify the logic of false appearance or semblance. To the Ancients, "it was nothing but the logic of illusion. It was a sophistic art of giving to one's ignorance, indeed even to one's intentional tricks, the outward appearance of truth, by imitating the thorough, accurate method which logic always requires, and by using its topic as a cloak for every empty assertion."[6]

Socratic method

The Socratic dialogues are a particular form of dialectic known as the method of elenchus (literally, "refutation, scrutiny"[7]) whereby a series of questions clarifies a more precise statement of a vague belief, logical consequences of that statement are explored, and a contradiction is discovered. The method is largely destructive, in that false belief is exposed[8] and only constructive in that this exposure may lead to further search for truth. The detection of error does not amount to a proof of the antithesis; for example, a contradiction in the consequences of a definition of piety does not provide a correct definition. The principal aim of Socratic activity may be to improve the soul of the interlocutors, by freeing them from unrecognized errors; or indeed, by teaching them the spirit of inquiry.

In common cases, Socrates used enthymemes as the foundation of his argument.[citation needed]

For example, in the Euthyphro, Socrates asks Euthyphro to provide a definition of piety. Euthyphro replies that the pious is that which is loved by the gods. But, Socrates also has Euthyphro agreeing that the gods are quarrelsome and their quarrels, like human quarrels, concern objects of love or hatred. Therefore, Socrates reasons, at least one thing exists that certain gods love but other gods hate. Again, Euthyphro agrees. Socrates concludes that if Euthyphro's definition of piety is acceptable, then there must exist at least one thing that is both pious and impious (as it is both loved and hated by the gods)—which Euthyphro admits is absurd. Thus, Euthyphro is brought to a realization by this dialectical method that his definition of piety is not sufficiently meaningful.

In another example, in Plato's Gorgias, dialectic occurs between Socrates, the Sophist Gorgias, and two men, Polus and Callicles. Because Socrates' ultimate goal was to reach true knowledge, he was even willing to change his own views in order to arrive at the truth. The fundamental goal of dialectic, in this instance, was to establish a precise definition of the subject (in this case, rhetoric) and with the use of argumentation and questioning, make the subject even more precise. In the Gorgias, Socrates reaches the truth by asking a series of questions and in return, receiving short, clear answers.

Plato

There is another interpretation of dialectic, suggested in The Republic, as a procedure that is both discursive and intuitive.[9] In Platonism and Neoplatonism, dialectic assumes an ontological and metaphysical role in that it becomes the process whereby the intellect passes from sensibles to intelligibles, rising from Idea to Idea until it finally grasps the supreme Idea, the First Principle which is the origin of all. The philosopher is consequently a "dialectician".[10] In this sense, dialectic is a process of enquiry that does away with hypotheses up to the First Principle (Republic, VII, 533 c-d). It slowly embraces the multiplicity in unity. Simon Blackburn writes that the dialectic in this sense is used to understand "the total process of enlightenment, whereby the philosopher is educated so as to achieve knowledge of the supreme good, the Form of the Good".[11]

Aristotle

Aristotle stresses that rhetoric is closely related to dialectic. He offers several formulas to describe this affinity between the two disciplines: first of all, rhetoric is said to be a "counterpart" (antistrophos) to dialectic (Rhet. I.1, 1354a1); (ii) it is also called an "outgrowth" (paraphues ti) of dialectic and the study of character (Rhet. I.2, 1356a25f.); finally, Aristotle says that rhetoric is part of dialectic and resembles it (Rhet. I.2, 1356a30f.). In saying that rhetoric is a counterpart to dialectic, Aristotle obviously alludes to Plato's Gorgias (464bff.), where rhetoric is ironically defined as a counterpart to cookery in the soul. Since, in this passage, Plato uses the word 'antistrophos' to designate an analogy, it is likely that Aristotle wants to express a kind of analogy too: what dialectic is for the (private or academic) practice of attacking and maintaining an argument, rhetoric is for the (public) practice of defending oneself or accusing an opponent. The analogy to dialectic has important implications for the status of rhetoric. Plato argued in his Gorgias that rhetoric cannot be an art (technê), since it is not related to a definite subject, while real arts are defined by their specific subjects, as e.g. medicine or shoemaking are defined by their products, i.e., health and shoes.[12]

Medieval philosophy

Logic, which could be considered to include dialectic, was one of the three liberal arts taught in medieval universities as part of the trivium; the other elements were rhetoric and grammar.[13][14][15][16]

Based mainly on Aristotle, the first medieval philosopher to work on dialectics was Boethius (480–524).[17] After him, many scholastic philosophers also made use of dialectics in their works, such as Abelard,[18] William of Sherwood,[19] Garlandus Compotista,[20] Walter Burley, Roger Swyneshed, William of Ockham,[21] and Thomas Aquinas.[22]

This dialectic (a quaestio disputata) was formed as follows:

  1. The question to be determined ("It is asked whether...");
  2. A provisory answer to the question ("And it seems that...");
  3. The principal arguments in favor of the provisory answer;
  4. An argument against the provisory answer, traditionally a single argument from authority ("On the contrary...");
  5. The determination of the question after weighing the evidence ("I answer that...");
  6. The replies to each of the initial objections. ("To the first, to the second etc., I answer that...")

Modern philosophy

The concept of dialectics was given new life at the start of the 19th century by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (following Johann Gottlieb Fichte), whose dialectical model of nature and of history made dialectic a fundamental aspect of the nature of reality (instead of regarding the contradictions into which dialectics leads as a sign of the sterility of the dialectical method, as the 18th-century philosopher Immanuel Kant tended to do in his Critique of Pure Reason).[23][24]

In the mid-19th century, the concept of dialectics was appropriated by Karl Marx (see, for example, Das Kapital, published in 1867) and Friedrich Engels and retooled in what they considered to be a nonidealistic manner. It would also become a crucial part of later representations of Marxism as a philosophy of dialectical materialism. These representations often contrasted dramatically[25] and led to vigorous debate among different Marxist groupings.

Hegelian dialectic

Hegelian dialectic, usually presented in a threefold manner, was stated by Heinrich Moritz Chalybäus[26] as comprising three dialectical stages of development: a thesis, giving rise to its reaction; an antithesis, which contradicts or negates the thesis; and the tension between the two being resolved by means of a synthesis. Although this model is often named after Hegel, he never used that specific formulation. Hegel ascribed that terminology to Kant.[27] Carrying on Kant's work, Fichte greatly elaborated on the synthesis model and popularized it.

On the other hand, Hegel did use a three-valued logical model that is very similar to the antithesis model, but Hegel's most usual terms were: Abstract-Negative-Concrete. Hegel used this writing model as a backbone to accompany his points in many of his works.[28]

The formula, thesis-antithesis-synthesis, does not explain why the thesis requires an antithesis. However, the formula, abstract-negative-concrete, suggests a flaw, or perhaps an incompleteness, in any initial thesis—it is too abstract and lacks the negative of trial, error, and experience. For Hegel, the concrete, the synthesis, the absolute, must always pass through the phase of the negative, in the journey to completion, that is, mediation. This is the essence of what is popularly called Hegelian dialectics.

According to the German philosopher Walter Kaufmann:

Fichte introduced into German philosophy the three-step of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, using these three terms. Schelling took up this terminology. Hegel did not. He never once used these three terms together to designate three stages in an argument or account in any of his books. And they do not help us understand his Phenomenology, his Logic, or his philosophy of history; they impede any open-minded comprehension of what he does by forcing it into a scheme which was available to him and which he deliberately spurned [...] The mechanical formalism [...] Hegel derides expressly and at some length in the preface to the Phenomenology.[29][30]

Kaufmann also cites Hegel's criticism of the triad model commonly misattributed to him, adding that "the only place where Hegel uses the three terms together occurs in his lectures on the history of philosophy, on the last page but one of the sections on Kant—where Hegel roundly reproaches Kant for having 'everywhere posited thesis, antithesis, synthesis'".[31]

To describe the activity of overcoming the negative, Hegel also often used the term Aufhebung, variously translated into English as "sublation" or "overcoming", to conceive of the working of the dialectic. Roughly, the term indicates preserving the useful portion of an idea, thing, society, etc., while moving beyond its limitations.

In the Logic, for instance, Hegel describes a dialectic of existence: first, existence must be posited as pure Being (Sein); but pure Being, upon examination, is found to be indistinguishable from Nothing (Nichts). When it is realized that what is coming into being is, at the same time, also returning to nothing (in life, for example, one's living is also a dying), both Being and Nothing are united as Becoming.[32]

As in the Socratic dialectic, Hegel claimed to proceed by making implicit contradictions explicit: each stage of the process is the product of contradictions inherent or implicit in the preceding stage. For Hegel, the whole of history is one tremendous dialectic, major stages of which chart a progression from self-alienation as slavery to self-unification and realization as the rational constitutional state of free and equal citizens. The Hegelian dialectic cannot be mechanically applied for any chosen thesis. Critics argue that the selection of any antithesis, other than the logical negation of the thesis, is subjective. Then, if the logical negation is used as the antithesis, there is no rigorous way to derive a synthesis. In practice, when an antithesis is selected to suit the user's subjective purpose, the resulting "contradictions" are rhetorical, not logical, and the resulting synthesis is not rigorously defensible against a multitude of other possible syntheses. The problem with the Fichtean "thesis–antithesis–synthesis" model is that it implies that contradictions or negations come from outside of things. Hegel's point is that they are inherent in and internal to things. This conception of dialectics derives ultimately from Heraclitus.

Hegel stated that the purpose of dialectics is "to study things in their own being and movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories of understanding."[33]

One important dialectical principle for Hegel is the transition from quantity to quality, which he terms the Measure. The measure is the qualitative quantum, the quantum is the existence of quantity.[34]

The identity between quantity and quality, which is found in Measure, is at first only implicit, and not yet explicitly realised. In other words, these two categories, which unite in Measure, each claim an independent authority. On the one hand, the quantitative features of existence may be altered, without affecting its quality. On the other hand, this increase and diminution, immaterial though it be, has its limit, by exceeding which the quality suffers change. [...] But if the quantity present in measure exceeds a certain limit, the quality corresponding to it is also put in abeyance. This however is not a negation of quality altogether, but only of this definite quality, the place of which is at once occupied by another. This process of measure, which appears alternately as a mere change in quantity, and then as a sudden revulsion of quantity into quality, may be envisaged under the figure of a nodal (knotted) line.[35]

As an example, Hegel mentions the states of aggregation of water: "Thus the temperature of water is, in the first place, a point of no consequence in respect of its liquidity: still with the increase or diminution of the temperature of the liquid water, there comes a point where this state of cohesion suffers a qualitative change, and the water is converted into steam or ice".[36] As other examples Hegel mentions the reaching of a point where a single additional grain makes a heap of wheat; or where the bald tail is produced, if we continue plucking out single hairs.

Another important principle for Hegel is the negation of the negation, which he also terms Aufhebung (sublation): Something is only what it is in its relation to another, but by the negation of the negation this something incorporates the other into itself. The dialectical movement involves two moments that negate each other, something and its other. As a result of the negation of the negation, "something becomes its other; this other is itself something; therefore it likewise becomes an other, and so on ad infinitum".[37] Something in its passage into other only joins with itself, it is self-related.[38] In becoming there are two moments:[39] coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be: by sublation, i.e., negation of the negation, being passes over into nothing, it ceases to be, but something new shows up, is coming to be. What is sublated (aufgehoben) on the one hand ceases to be and is put to an end, but on the other hand it is preserved and maintained.[40] In dialectics, a totality transforms itself; it is self-related, then self-forgetful, relieving the original tension.

Marxist dialectic

Marxist dialectic is a form of Hegelian dialectic which applies to the study of historical materialism. It purports to be a reflection of the real world created by man. Dialectic would thus be a robust method under which one could examine personal, social, and economic behaviors. Marxist dialectic is the core foundation of the philosophy of dialectical materialism, which forms the basis of the ideas behind historical materialism.

Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, writing several decades after Hegel's death, proposed that Hegel's dialectic is too abstract:

The mystification which dialectic suffers in Hegel's hands, by no means prevents him from being the first to present its general form of working in a comprehensive and conscious manner. With him it is standing on its head. It must be turned right side up again, if you would discover the rational kernel within the mystical shell.[41]

In contradiction to Hegelian idealism, Marx presented his own dialectic method, which he claims to be "direct opposite" of Hegel's method:

My dialectic method is not only different from the Hegelian, but is its direct opposite. To Hegel, the life-process of the human brain, i.e. the process of thinking, which, under the name of 'the Idea', he even transforms into an independent subject, is the demiurgos of the real world, and the real world is only the external, phenomenal form of 'the Idea'. With me, on the contrary, the ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind, and translated into forms of thought.[42]

In Marxism, the dialectical method of historical study became intertwined with historical materialism, the school of thought exemplified by the works of Marx, Engels, and Vladimir Lenin. In the USSR, under Joseph Stalin, Marxist dialectics became "diamat" (short for dialectical materialism), a theory emphasizing the primacy of the material way of life; social praxis over all forms of social consciousness; and the secondary, dependent character of the "ideal".

The term "dialectical materialism" was coined by the 19th-century social theorist Joseph Dietzgen who used the theory to explain the nature of socialism and social development. The original populariser of Marxism in Russia, Georgi Plekhanov used the terms "dialectical materialism" and "historical materialism" interchangeably. For Lenin, the primary feature of Marx's "dialectical materialism" (Lenin's term) was its application of materialist philosophy to history and social sciences. Lenin's main input in the philosophy of dialectical materialism was his theory of reflection, which presented human consciousness as a dynamic reflection of the objective material world that fully shapes its contents and structure.

Later, Stalin's works on the subject established a rigid and formalistic division of Marxist–Leninist theory in the dialectical materialism and historical materialism parts. While the first was supposed to be the key method and theory of the philosophy of nature, the second was the Soviet version of the philosophy of history.

A dialectical method was fundamental to Western Marxists such as Karl Korsch and Georg Lukács. Certain members of the Frankfurt School also used dialectical thinking, such as Theodor W. Adorno who developed negative dialectics. Soviet academics, notably Evald Ilyenkov and Zaid Orudzhev, continued pursuing unorthodox philosophic study of Marxist dialectics; likewise in the West, notably the philosopher Bertell Ollman at New York University.

Friedrich Engels proposed that Nature is dialectical, thus, in Anti-Dühring he said that the negation of negation is:

A very simple process, which is taking place everywhere and every day, which any child can understand as soon as it is stripped of the veil of mystery in which it was enveloped by the old idealist philosophy.[43]

In Dialectics of Nature, Engels said:

Probably the same gentlemen who up to now have decried the transformation of quantity into quality as mysticism and incomprehensible transcendentalism will now declare that it is indeed something quite self-evident, trivial, and commonplace, which they have long employed, and so they have been taught nothing new. But to have formulated for the first time in its universally valid form a general law of development of Nature, society, and thought, will always remain an act of historic importance.[44]

Marxist dialectics is exemplified in Das Kapital (Capital), which outlines two central theories: (i) surplus value and (ii) the materialist conception of history; Marx explains dialectical materialism:

In its rational form, it is a scandal and abomination to bourgeoisdom and its doctrinaire professors, because it includes in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of things, at the same time, also, the recognition of the negation of that state, of its inevitable breaking up; because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence; because it lets nothing impose upon it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary.[45]

Class struggle is the primary contradiction to be resolved by Marxist dialectics, because of its central role in the social and political lives of a society. Nonetheless, Marx and Marxists developed the concept of class struggle to comprehend the dialectical contradictions between mental and manual labor, and between town and country. Hence, philosophic contradiction is central to the development of dialectics – the progress from quantity to quality, the acceleration of gradual social change; the negation of the initial development of the status quo; the negation of that negation; and the high-level recurrence of features of the original status quo.

In the USSR, Progress Publishers issued anthologies of dialectical materialism by Lenin, wherein he also quotes Marx and Engels:

As the most comprehensive and profound doctrine of development, and the richest in content, Hegelian dialectics was considered by Marx and Engels the greatest achievement of classical German philosophy.... "The great basic thought", Engels writes, "that the world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready-made things, but as a complex of processes, in which the things, apparently stable no less than their mind images in our heads, the concepts, go through an uninterrupted change of coming into being and passing away... this great fundamental thought has, especially since the time of Hegel, so thoroughly permeated ordinary consciousness that, in its generality, it is now scarcely ever contradicted. But, to acknowledge this fundamental thought in words, and to apply it in reality in detail to each domain of investigation, are two different things.... For dialectical philosophy nothing is final, absolute, sacred. It reveals the transitory character of everything and in everything; nothing can endure before it, except the uninterrupted process of becoming and of passing away, of endless ascendancy from the lower to the higher. And dialectical philosophy, itself, is nothing more than the mere reflection of this process in the thinking brain." Thus, according to Marx, dialectics is "the science of the general laws of motion both of the external world and of human thought".[46]

Lenin describes his dialectical understanding of the concept of development:

A development that repeats, as it were, stages that have already been passed, but repeats them in a different way, on a higher basis ("the negation of the negation"), a development, so to speak, that proceeds in spirals, not in a straight line; a development by leaps, catastrophes, and revolutions; "breaks in continuity"; the transformation of quantity into quality; inner impulses towards development, imparted by the contradiction and conflict of the various forces and tendencies acting on a given body, or within a given phenomenon, or within a given society; the interdependence and the closest and indissoluble connection between all aspects of any phenomenon (history constantly revealing ever new aspects), a connection that provides a uniform, and universal process of motion, one that follows definite laws – these are some of the features of dialectics as a doctrine of development that is richer than the conventional one.[46]

An example of the influence of Marxist dialectic in the European tradition is Jean-Paul Sartre's 1960 book Critique of Dialectical Reason. Sartre stated:

Existentialism, like Marxism, addresses itself to experience in order to discover there concrete syntheses. It can conceive of these syntheses only within a moving, dialectical totalisation, which is nothing else but history or—from the strictly cultural point of view adopted here—'philosophy-becoming-the world'.[47]

Dialectical naturalism

Dialectical naturalism is a term coined by American philosopher Murray Bookchin to describe the philosophical underpinnings of the political program of social ecology. Dialectical naturalism explores the complex interrelationship between social problems, and the direct consequences they have on the ecological impact of human society. Bookchin offered dialectical naturalism as a contrast to what he saw as the "empyrean, basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism" of Hegel, and "the wooden, often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox Marxists".

Theological dialectical forms

Dialectical theology

Neo-orthodoxy, in Europe also known as theology of crisis and dialectical theology,[48][49] is an approach to theology in Protestantism that was developed in the aftermath of the First World War (1914–1918). It is characterized as a reaction against doctrines of 19th-century liberal theology and a more positive reevaluation of the teachings of the Reformation, much of which had been in decline (especially in western Europe) since the late 18th century.[50] It is primarily associated with two Swiss professors and pastors, Karl Barth[51] (1886–1968) and Emil Brunner (1899–1966),[48][49] even though Barth himself expressed his unease in the use of the term.[52]

In dialectical theology the difference and opposition between God and human beings is stressed in such a way that all human attempts at overcoming this opposition through moral, religious or philosophical idealism must be characterized as 'sin'. In the death of Christ humanity is negated and overcome, but this judgment also points forwards to the resurrection in which humanity is reestablished in Christ. For Barth this meant that only through God's 'no' to everything human can his 'yes' be perceived. Applied to traditional themes of Protestant theology, such as double predestination, this means that election and reprobation cannot be viewed as a quantitative limitation of God's action. Rather it must be seen as its "qualitative definition".[53] As Christ bore the rejection as well as the election of God for all humanity, every person is subject to both aspects of God's double predestination.

Dialectic prominently figured in Bernard Lonergan's philosophy, in his books Insight and Method in Theology. Michael Shute wrote about Lonergan's use of dialectic in The Origins of Lonergan's Notion of the Dialectic of History. For Lonergan, dialectic is both individual and operative in community. Simply described, it is a dynamic process that results in something new:

For the sake of greater precision, let us say that a dialectic is a concrete unfolding of linked but opposed principles of change. Thus there will be a dialectic if (1) there is an aggregate of events of a determinate character, (2) the events may be traced to either or both of two principles, (3) the principles are opposed yet bound together, and (4) they are modified by the changes that successively result from them.[54]

Dialectic is one of the eight functional specialties Lonergan envisaged for theology to bring this discipline into the modern world. Lonergan believed that the lack of an agreed method among scholars had inhibited substantive agreement from being reached and progress from being made compared to the natural sciences. Karl Rahner, S.J., however, criticized Lonergan's theological method in a short article entitled "Some Critical Thoughts on 'Functional Specialties in Theology'" where he stated: "Lonergan's theological methodology seems to me to be so generic that it really fits every science, and hence is not the methodology of theology as such, but only a very general methodology of science."[55]

Criticisms

Karl Popper has attacked the dialectic repeatedly. In 1937, he wrote and delivered a paper entitled "What Is Dialectic?" in which he attacked the dialectical method for its willingness "to put up with contradictions".[56] Popper concluded the essay with these words: "The whole development of dialectic should be a warning against the dangers inherent in philosophical system-building. It should remind us that philosophy should not be made a basis for any sort of scientific system and that philosophers should be much more modest in their claims. One task which they can fulfill quite usefully is the study of the critical methods of science" (Ibid., p. 335).

In chapter 12 of volume 2 of The Open Society and Its Enemies (1944; 5th rev. ed., 1966), Popper unleashed a famous attack on Hegelian dialectics in which he held that Hegel's thought was to some degree responsible for facilitating the rise of fascism in Europe by encouraging and justifying irrationalism. (This was unjust in the view of some philosophers, such as Walter Kaufmann.[57]) In section 17 of his 1961 "addenda" to The Open Society, entitled "Facts, Standards and Truth: A Further Criticism of Relativism", Popper refused to moderate his criticism of the Hegelian dialectic, arguing that it "played a major role in the downfall of the liberal movement in Germany [...] by contributing to historicism and to an identification of might and right, encouraged totalitarian modes of thought. [...] [And] undermined and eventually lowered the traditional standards of intellectual responsibility and honesty".[58]

The philosopher of science and physicist Mario Bunge repeatedly criticized Hegelian and Marxian dialectics, calling them "fuzzy and remote from science"[59] and a "disastrous legacy".[60] He concluded: "The so-called laws of dialectics, such as formulated by Engels (1940, 1954) and Lenin (1947, 1981), are false insofar as they are intelligible."[60]

Formalism

Since the late 20th century, European and American logicians have attempted to provide mathematical foundations for dialectic through formalisation,[61]: 201–372  although logic has been related to dialectic since ancient times.[61]: 51–140  There have been pre-formal and partially-formal treatises on argument and dialectic, from authors such as Stephen Toulmin (The Uses of Argument, 1958),[62][63][61]: 203–256  Nicholas Rescher (Dialectics: A Controversy-Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge, 1977),[64][65][61]: 330–336  and Frans H. van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst (pragma-dialectics, 1980s).[61]: 517–614  One can include works of the communities of informal logic and paraconsistent logic.[61]: 373–424 

Defeasibility

Building on theories of defeasible reasoning (see John L. Pollock), systems have been built that define well-formedness of arguments, rules governing the process of introducing arguments based on fixed assumptions, and rules for shifting burden.[61]: 615–675  Many of these logics appear in the special area of artificial intelligence and law, though the computer scientists' interest in formalizing dialectic originates in a desire to build decision support and computer-supported collaborative work systems.[66]

Dialog games

Dialectic itself can be formalised as moves in a game, where an advocate for the truth of a proposition and an opponent argue.[61]: 301–372  Such games can provide a semantics of logic, one that is very general in applicability.[61]: 314 

Mathematics

Mathematician William Lawvere interpreted dialectics in the setting of categorical logic in terms of adjunctions between idempotent monads.[67] This perspective may be useful in the context of theoretical computer science where the duality between syntax and semantics can be interpreted as a dialectic in this sense. For example, the Curry-Howard equivalence is such an adjunction or more generally the duality between closed monoidal categories and their internal logic.[68]

See also

References

  1. ^ see Gorgias, 449B: "Socrates: Would you be willing then, Gorgias, to continue the discussion as we are now doing [Dialectic], by way of question and answer, and to put off to another occasion the (emotional) speeches [Rhetoric] that [the Sophist] Polus began?"
  2. ^ Corbett, Edward P. J.; Robert J. Connors (1999). Classical Rhetoric For the Modern Student (4th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 1, 18. ISBN 9780195115420.
  3. ^ Ayer, A. J., & O'Grady, J. (1992). A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers. p. 484.
  4. ^ McTaggart, J. M. E. (1964). A commentary on Hegel's logic. New York: Russell & Russell. p. 11
  5. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, IX 25ff and VIII 57 [1].
  6. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 61
  7. ^ "Elenchus - Wiktionary". 8 February 2021.
  8. ^ Wyss, Peter (October 2014). "Socratic Method: Aporeia, Elenchus and Dialectics (Plato: Four Dialogues, Handout 3)" (PDF). open.conted.ox.ac.uk. University of Oxford, Department for Continuing Education.
  9. ^ Popper, K. (1962) The Open Society and its Enemies, Volume 1, London, Routledge, p. 133.
  10. ^ Reale, Giovanni. (1990), History of Ancient Philosophy, 5 vols, trans. by John R. Catan, Albany: State University of New York, vol 2, p. 150
  11. ^ Blackburn, Simon. 1996. The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford
  12. ^ Rapp (2010). Aristotle's Rhetoric. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-rhetoric/
  13. ^ Abelson, P. (1965). The seven liberal arts; a study in mediæval culture. New York: Russell & Russell. Page 82.
  14. ^ Hyman, A., & Walsh, J. J. (1983). Philosophy in the Middle Ages: the Christian, Islamic, and Jewish traditions. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co. Page 164.
  15. ^ Adler, Mortimer Jerome (2000). "Dialectic". Routledge. Page 4. ISBN 0-415-22550-7
  16. ^ Herbermann, C. G. (1913). The Catholic encyclopedia: an international work of reference on the constitution, doctrine, and history of the Catholic church. New York: The Encyclopedia press, inc. Page 760–764.
  17. ^ From topic to tale: logic and narrativity in the Middle Ages, by Eugene Vance, p.43-45
  18. ^ "Catholic Encyclopedia: Peter Abelard". Newadvent.org. 1907-03-01. Retrieved 2011-11-03.
  19. ^ William of Sherwood's Introduction to logic, by Norman Kretzmann, p.69-102
  20. ^ A History of Twelfth-Century Western Philosophy, by Peter Dronke, p.198
  21. ^ Medieval literary politics: shapes of ideology, by Sheila Delany, p.11
  22. ^ "Catholic Encyclopedia: St. Thomas Aquinas". Newadvent.org. 1907-03-01. Retrieved 2015-10-20.
  23. ^ Nicholson, J. A. (1950). Philosophy of religion. New York: Ronald Press Co. Page 108.
  24. ^ Kant, I., Guyer, P., & Wood, A. W. (2003). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Page 495.
  25. ^ Henri Lefebvre's "humanist" dialectical materialism (Dialectical Materialism [1940]) was composed to directly challenge Joseph Stalin's own dogmatic text on dialectical materialism.
  26. ^ Historische Entwicklung der spekulativen Philosophie von Kant bis Hegel, Dresden-Leipzig (1837), p. 367 of the fourth edition (1848).
  27. ^ The Accessible Hegel by Michael Allen Fox. Prometheus Books. 2005. p. 43. Also see Hegel's preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), secs. 50, 51, pp. 29, 30.
  28. ^ See for a discussion of the historical development of the triad. Charles Edward Andrew Lincoln IV, Hegelian Dialectical Analysis of U.S. Voting Laws, 42 U. Dayton L. Rev. 87 (2017).
  29. ^ Hegel: A Reinterpretation, 1966, Anchor Books, p. 154)
  30. ^ G. E. Mueller (June 1958), "The Hegel Legend of 'Thesis-Antithesis-Synthesis", 166ff
  31. ^ Hegel, Werke, ed. Glockner, XIX, 610
  32. ^ Hegel. "Section in question from Hegel's Science of Logic". Marxists.org. Retrieved 2011-11-03.
  33. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1874. The Logic. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. 2nd Edition. London: Oxford University Press. Note to §81
  34. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1874. The Logic. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. 2nd Edition. London: Oxford University Press. §§107–111
  35. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1874. The Logic. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. 2nd Edition. London: Oxford University Press. §§108–109
  36. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1874. The Logic. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. 2nd Edition. London: Oxford University Press. §108
  37. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1874. The Logic. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. 2nd Edition. London: Oxford University Press. §93
  38. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1874. The Logic. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. 2nd Edition. London: Oxford University Press. §95
  39. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1812. Hegel's Science of Logic. London. Allen & Unwin. §§176–179.
  40. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1812. Hegel's Science of Logic. London. Allen & Unwin. §185.
  41. ^ Marx, Karl (1873) Capital Afterword to the Second German Edition, Vol. I [2]
  42. ^ Marx, Karl. "Afterword (Second German Ed.)". Capital. 1: 14. Retrieved 28 December 2014.
  43. ^ Engels, Frederick, (1877) Anti-Dühring, Part I: Philosophy, XIII. Dialectics. Negation of the Negation.
  44. ^ Engels, Frederick (1883). "Dialectics of Nature: II. Dialectics". Marxists.org. Retrieved 2011-11-03.
  45. ^ Marx, Karl, (1873) Capital Vol. I, Afterword to the Second German Edition.
  46. ^ a b Lenin, V. I., On the Question of Dialectics: A Collection, pp. 7–9. Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1980.
  47. ^ Jean-Paul Sartre. "The Search for Method (1st part) Sartre, 1960, in Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre, transl. Hazel Barnes, Vintage Books". Marxists.org. Retrieved 2011-11-03.
  48. ^ a b "Original Britinnica online". Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  49. ^ a b "Britannica Encyclopedia (online)". Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  50. ^ "Merriam-Webster Dictionary(online)". Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  51. ^ . Archived from the original on 2005-05-10. Retrieved 2008-07-26.
  52. ^ See Church Dogmatics III/3, xii.
  53. ^ Karl Barth, The Epistle to the Romans (1933), p. 346
  54. ^ Bernard J.F. Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, Collected Works vol. 3, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1992, pp.217-218).
  55. ^ McShane, S.J., Philip (1972). Foundations of Theology. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press. p. 194.
  56. ^ Karl Popper,Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge [New York: Basic Books, 1962], p. 316.
  57. ^ Walter Kaufmann. "kaufmann". Marxists.org. Retrieved 2011-11-03.
  58. ^ Karl Popper,The Open Society and Its Enemies, 5th rev. ed., vol. 2 [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1966], p. 395
  59. ^ Bunge, Mario Augusto (1981). "A critique of dialectics". Scientific materialism. Episteme. Vol. 9. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 41–63. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-8517-9_4. ISBN 978-9027713049. OCLC 7596139.
  60. ^ a b Bunge, Mario Augusto (2012). Evaluating philosophies. Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. 295. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 84–85. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-4408-0. ISBN 9789400744073. OCLC 806947226.
  61. ^ a b c d e f g h i Eemeren, Frans H. van; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2014). Handbook of argumentation theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5. ISBN 9789048194728. OCLC 871004444.
  62. ^ Toulmin, Stephen (2003) [1958]. The uses of argument (Updated ed.). Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511840005. ISBN 978-0521827485. OCLC 51607421.
  63. ^ Hitchcock, David; Verheij, Bart, eds. (2006). Arguing on the Toulmin model: new essays in argument analysis and evaluation. Argumentation library. Vol. 10. Dordrecht: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-4938-5. ISBN 978-1402049378. OCLC 82229075.
  64. ^ Hetherington, Stephen (2006). "Nicholas Rescher: Philosophical Dialectics". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (2006.07.16).
  65. ^ Jacquette, Dale, ed. (2009). Reason, Method, and Value: A Reader on the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag. doi:10.1515/9783110329056. ISBN 9783110329056.
  66. ^ For surveys of work in this area see, for example: Chesñevar, Carlos Iván; Maguitman, Ana Gabriela; Loui, Ronald Prescott (December 2000). "Logical models of argument". ACM Computing Surveys. 32 (4): 337–383. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.702.8325. doi:10.1145/371578.371581. And: Prakken, Henry; Vreeswijk, Gerard (2005). "Logics for defeasible argumentation". In Gabbay, Dov M.; Guenthner, Franz (eds.). Handbook of philosophical logic. Vol. 4 (2nd ed.). Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 219–318. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.295.2649. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0456-4_3. ISBN 9789048158775.
  67. ^ Lawvere, F. William (1996). "Unity and identity of opposites in calculus and physics". Applied Categorical Structures. 4 (2–3): 167–174. doi:10.1007/BF00122250. S2CID 34109341.
  68. ^ Eilenberg, Samuel; Kelly, G. Max (1966). "Closed Categories". Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra: 421–562. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-99902-4_22. ISBN 978-3-642-99904-8.

Further reading

  • McKeon, Richard (October 1954). "Dialectic and Political Thought and Action". Ethics. 65 (1): 1–33. doi:10.1086/290973. JSTOR 2378780. S2CID 144465113. The essay contains three parts: (1) a brief history of dialectic, designed to focus on these questions by tracing the evolution of various trends of dialectical method in the light of the development of alternative methods; (2) a statement of the nature and varieties of dialectic, designed to bring out differences of methods and to indicate the possibility of common conceptions and common aims; and (3) an examination of the problems of common understanding and common action posed by the difference of dialectical and nondialectical methods of thought today.
  • Postan, Michael M. (April 1962). "Function and Dialectic in Economic History". The Economic History Review. 14 (3): 397–407. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0289.1962.tb00058.x. JSTOR 2591884. The trouble about the dialectic is not that it is wholly inapplicable to history, but that it is so frequently applied to fields in which it happens to be least useful. If function and dialectic are to be reconciled and allowed their proper place in historical work, it will perhaps be necessary to move a stage beyond the philosophical position which Marx took up in the 1840s. Having put the dialectic on its head, and made it materialist, Marx has directed it into regions to which this posture is unsuited. If we complete the somersault and put the dialectic on its feet again, we might thereby return it to where it belongs.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (2007). Dialectics: A Classical Approach to Inquiry. Frankfurt; New Brunswick: Ontos Verlag. ISBN 9783938793763. OCLC 185032382. A broad survey of various conceptions of "dialectic", including disputational, cognitive, methodological, ontological, and philosophical.
  • Spranzi, Marta (2011). The Art of Dialectic between Dialogue and Rhetoric: The Aristotelian Tradition. Controversies. Vol. 9. Amsterdam; Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company. doi:10.1075/cvs.9. ISBN 9789027218896. OCLC 704557514. This book reconstructs the tradition of dialectic from Aristotle's Topics, its founding text, up to its 'renaissance' in 16th century Italy, and focuses on the role of dialectic in the production of knowledge.

External links

dialectic, varieties, language, dialect, electrical, insulators, dielectric, greek, διαλεκτική, dialektikḗ, related, dialogue, german, dialektik, also, known, dialectical, method, discourse, between, more, people, holding, different, points, view, about, subje. For varieties of language see dialect For electrical insulators see dielectric Dialectic Greek dialektikh dialektikḗ related to dialogue German Dialektik also known as the dialectical method is a discourse between two or more people holding different points of view about a subject but wishing to establish the truth through reasoned argumentation Dialectic resembles debate but the concept excludes subjective elements such as emotional appeal and rhetoric in the modern pejorative sense 1 2 Dialectic may thus be contrasted with both the eristic which refers to argument that aims to successfully dispute another s argument rather than searching for truth and the didactic method wherein one side of the conversation teaches the other Dialectic is alternatively known as minor logic as opposed to major logic or critique Within Hegelianism the word dialectic has the specialised meaning of a contradiction between ideas that serves as the determining factor in their relationship Dialectical materialism a theory or set of theories produced mainly by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels adapted the Hegelian dialectic into arguments regarding traditional materialism The dialectics of Hegel and Marx were criticized in the twentieth century by the philosophers Karl Popper and Mario Bunge Dialectic tends to imply a process of evolution and so does not naturally fit within classical logics but was given some formalism in the twentieth century The emphasis on process is particularly marked in Hegelian dialectic and even more so in Marxist dialectical logic which tried to account for the evolution of ideas over longer time periods in the real world Contents 1 Western dialectical forms 1 1 Classical philosophy 1 1 1 Socratic method 1 1 2 Plato 1 1 3 Aristotle 1 2 Medieval philosophy 1 3 Modern philosophy 1 3 1 Hegelian dialectic 1 3 2 Marxist dialectic 1 3 3 Dialectical naturalism 2 Theological dialectical forms 2 1 Dialectical theology 3 Criticisms 4 Formalism 4 1 Defeasibility 4 2 Dialog games 4 3 Mathematics 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksWestern dialectical forms EditThere is a variety of meanings of dialectic or dialectics within Western philosophy Classical philosophy Edit In classical philosophy dialectic dialektikh is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter arguments advocating propositions theses and counter propositions antitheses The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition or of a synthesis or a combination of the opposing assertions or a qualitative improvement of the dialogue 3 4 Moreover the term dialectic owes much of its prestige to its role in the philosophies of Socrates and Plato in the Greek Classical period 5th to 4th centuries BC Aristotle said that it was the pre Socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea who invented dialectic of which the dialogues of Plato are the examples of the Socratic dialectical method 5 According to Kant however the ancient Greeks used the word dialectic to signify the logic of false appearance or semblance To the Ancients it was nothing but the logic of illusion It was a sophistic art of giving to one s ignorance indeed even to one s intentional tricks the outward appearance of truth by imitating the thorough accurate method which logic always requires and by using its topic as a cloak for every empty assertion 6 Socratic method Edit Main article Socratic method The Socratic dialogues are a particular form of dialectic known as the method of elenchus literally refutation scrutiny 7 whereby a series of questions clarifies a more precise statement of a vague belief logical consequences of that statement are explored and a contradiction is discovered The method is largely destructive in that false belief is exposed 8 and only constructive in that this exposure may lead to further search for truth The detection of error does not amount to a proof of the antithesis for example a contradiction in the consequences of a definition of piety does not provide a correct definition The principal aim of Socratic activity may be to improve the soul of the interlocutors by freeing them from unrecognized errors or indeed by teaching them the spirit of inquiry In common cases Socrates used enthymemes as the foundation of his argument citation needed For example in the Euthyphro Socrates asks Euthyphro to provide a definition of piety Euthyphro replies that the pious is that which is loved by the gods But Socrates also has Euthyphro agreeing that the gods are quarrelsome and their quarrels like human quarrels concern objects of love or hatred Therefore Socrates reasons at least one thing exists that certain gods love but other gods hate Again Euthyphro agrees Socrates concludes that if Euthyphro s definition of piety is acceptable then there must exist at least one thing that is both pious and impious as it is both loved and hated by the gods which Euthyphro admits is absurd Thus Euthyphro is brought to a realization by this dialectical method that his definition of piety is not sufficiently meaningful In another example in Plato s Gorgias dialectic occurs between Socrates the Sophist Gorgias and two men Polus and Callicles Because Socrates ultimate goal was to reach true knowledge he was even willing to change his own views in order to arrive at the truth The fundamental goal of dialectic in this instance was to establish a precise definition of the subject in this case rhetoric and with the use of argumentation and questioning make the subject even more precise In the Gorgias Socrates reaches the truth by asking a series of questions and in return receiving short clear answers Plato Edit There is another interpretation of dialectic suggested in The Republic as a procedure that is both discursive and intuitive 9 In Platonism and Neoplatonism dialectic assumes an ontological and metaphysical role in that it becomes the process whereby the intellect passes from sensibles to intelligibles rising from Idea to Idea until it finally grasps the supreme Idea the First Principle which is the origin of all The philosopher is consequently a dialectician 10 In this sense dialectic is a process of enquiry that does away with hypotheses up to the First Principle Republic VII 533 c d It slowly embraces the multiplicity in unity Simon Blackburn writes that the dialectic in this sense is used to understand the total process of enlightenment whereby the philosopher is educated so as to achieve knowledge of the supreme good the Form of the Good 11 Aristotle Edit Aristotle stresses that rhetoric is closely related to dialectic He offers several formulas to describe this affinity between the two disciplines first of all rhetoric is said to be a counterpart antistrophos to dialectic Rhet I 1 1354a1 ii it is also called an outgrowth paraphues ti of dialectic and the study of character Rhet I 2 1356a25f finally Aristotle says that rhetoric is part of dialectic and resembles it Rhet I 2 1356a30f In saying that rhetoric is a counterpart to dialectic Aristotle obviously alludes to Plato s Gorgias 464bff where rhetoric is ironically defined as a counterpart to cookery in the soul Since in this passage Plato uses the word antistrophos to designate an analogy it is likely that Aristotle wants to express a kind of analogy too what dialectic is for the private or academic practice of attacking and maintaining an argument rhetoric is for the public practice of defending oneself or accusing an opponent The analogy to dialectic has important implications for the status of rhetoric Plato argued in his Gorgias that rhetoric cannot be an art techne since it is not related to a definite subject while real arts are defined by their specific subjects as e g medicine or shoemaking are defined by their products i e health and shoes 12 Medieval philosophy Edit Logic which could be considered to include dialectic was one of the three liberal arts taught in medieval universities as part of the trivium the other elements were rhetoric and grammar 13 14 15 16 Based mainly on Aristotle the first medieval philosopher to work on dialectics was Boethius 480 524 17 After him many scholastic philosophers also made use of dialectics in their works such as Abelard 18 William of Sherwood 19 Garlandus Compotista 20 Walter Burley Roger Swyneshed William of Ockham 21 and Thomas Aquinas 22 This dialectic a quaestio disputata was formed as follows The question to be determined It is asked whether A provisory answer to the question And it seems that The principal arguments in favor of the provisory answer An argument against the provisory answer traditionally a single argument from authority On the contrary The determination of the question after weighing the evidence I answer that The replies to each of the initial objections To the first to the second etc I answer that Modern philosophy Edit The concept of dialectics was given new life at the start of the 19th century by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel following Johann Gottlieb Fichte whose dialectical model of nature and of history made dialectic a fundamental aspect of the nature of reality instead of regarding the contradictions into which dialectics leads as a sign of the sterility of the dialectical method as the 18th century philosopher Immanuel Kant tended to do in his Critique of Pure Reason 23 24 In the mid 19th century the concept of dialectics was appropriated by Karl Marx see for example Das Kapital published in 1867 and Friedrich Engels and retooled in what they considered to be a nonidealistic manner It would also become a crucial part of later representations of Marxism as a philosophy of dialectical materialism These representations often contrasted dramatically 25 and led to vigorous debate among different Marxist groupings Hegelian dialectic Edit Hegelian dialectic redirects here For the Prodigy album see Hegelian Dialectic The Book of Revelation See also Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Dialectics speculation idealism Hegelian dialectic usually presented in a threefold manner was stated by Heinrich Moritz Chalybaus 26 as comprising three dialectical stages of development a thesis giving rise to its reaction an antithesis which contradicts or negates the thesis and the tension between the two being resolved by means of a synthesis Although this model is often named after Hegel he never used that specific formulation Hegel ascribed that terminology to Kant 27 Carrying on Kant s work Fichte greatly elaborated on the synthesis model and popularized it On the other hand Hegel did use a three valued logical model that is very similar to the antithesis model but Hegel s most usual terms were Abstract Negative Concrete Hegel used this writing model as a backbone to accompany his points in many of his works 28 The formula thesis antithesis synthesis does not explain why the thesis requires an antithesis However the formula abstract negative concrete suggests a flaw or perhaps an incompleteness in any initial thesis it is too abstract and lacks the negative of trial error and experience For Hegel the concrete the synthesis the absolute must always pass through the phase of the negative in the journey to completion that is mediation This is the essence of what is popularly called Hegelian dialectics According to the German philosopher Walter Kaufmann Fichte introduced into German philosophy the three step of thesis antithesis and synthesis using these three terms Schelling took up this terminology Hegel did not He never once used these three terms together to designate three stages in an argument or account in any of his books And they do not help us understand his Phenomenology his Logic or his philosophy of history they impede any open minded comprehension of what he does by forcing it into a scheme which was available to him and which he deliberately spurned The mechanical formalism Hegel derides expressly and at some length in the preface to the Phenomenology 29 30 Kaufmann also cites Hegel s criticism of the triad model commonly misattributed to him adding that the only place where Hegel uses the three terms together occurs in his lectures on the history of philosophy on the last page but one of the sections on Kant where Hegel roundly reproaches Kant for having everywhere posited thesis antithesis synthesis 31 To describe the activity of overcoming the negative Hegel also often used the term Aufhebung variously translated into English as sublation or overcoming to conceive of the working of the dialectic Roughly the term indicates preserving the useful portion of an idea thing society etc while moving beyond its limitations In the Logic for instance Hegel describes a dialectic of existence first existence must be posited as pure Being Sein but pure Being upon examination is found to be indistinguishable from Nothing Nichts When it is realized that what is coming into being is at the same time also returning to nothing in life for example one s living is also a dying both Being and Nothing are united as Becoming 32 As in the Socratic dialectic Hegel claimed to proceed by making implicit contradictions explicit each stage of the process is the product of contradictions inherent or implicit in the preceding stage For Hegel the whole of history is one tremendous dialectic major stages of which chart a progression from self alienation as slavery to self unification and realization as the rational constitutional state of free and equal citizens The Hegelian dialectic cannot be mechanically applied for any chosen thesis Critics argue that the selection of any antithesis other than the logical negation of the thesis is subjective Then if the logical negation is used as the antithesis there is no rigorous way to derive a synthesis In practice when an antithesis is selected to suit the user s subjective purpose the resulting contradictions are rhetorical not logical and the resulting synthesis is not rigorously defensible against a multitude of other possible syntheses The problem with the Fichtean thesis antithesis synthesis model is that it implies that contradictions or negations come from outside of things Hegel s point is that they are inherent in and internal to things This conception of dialectics derives ultimately from Heraclitus Hegel stated that the purpose of dialectics is to study things in their own being and movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories of understanding 33 One important dialectical principle for Hegel is the transition from quantity to quality which he terms the Measure The measure is the qualitative quantum the quantum is the existence of quantity 34 The identity between quantity and quality which is found in Measure is at first only implicit and not yet explicitly realised In other words these two categories which unite in Measure each claim an independent authority On the one hand the quantitative features of existence may be altered without affecting its quality On the other hand this increase and diminution immaterial though it be has its limit by exceeding which the quality suffers change But if the quantity present in measure exceeds a certain limit the quality corresponding to it is also put in abeyance This however is not a negation of quality altogether but only of this definite quality the place of which is at once occupied by another This process of measure which appears alternately as a mere change in quantity and then as a sudden revulsion of quantity into quality may be envisaged under the figure of a nodal knotted line 35 As an example Hegel mentions the states of aggregation of water Thus the temperature of water is in the first place a point of no consequence in respect of its liquidity still with the increase or diminution of the temperature of the liquid water there comes a point where this state of cohesion suffers a qualitative change and the water is converted into steam or ice 36 As other examples Hegel mentions the reaching of a point where a single additional grain makes a heap of wheat or where the bald tail is produced if we continue plucking out single hairs Another important principle for Hegel is the negation of the negation which he also terms Aufhebung sublation Something is only what it is in its relation to another but by the negation of the negation this something incorporates the other into itself The dialectical movement involves two moments that negate each other something and its other As a result of the negation of the negation something becomes its other this other is itself something therefore it likewise becomes an other and so on ad infinitum 37 Something in its passage into other only joins with itself it is self related 38 In becoming there are two moments 39 coming to be and ceasing to be by sublation i e negation of the negation being passes over into nothing it ceases to be but something new shows up is coming to be What is sublated aufgehoben on the one hand ceases to be and is put to an end but on the other hand it is preserved and maintained 40 In dialectics a totality transforms itself it is self related then self forgetful relieving the original tension Marxist dialectic Edit This section contains too many or overly lengthy quotations for an encyclopedic entry Please help improve the article by presenting facts as a neutrally worded summary with appropriate citations Consider transferring direct quotations to Wikiquote or for entire works to Wikisource January 2019 Marxist dialectic is a form of Hegelian dialectic which applies to the study of historical materialism It purports to be a reflection of the real world created by man Dialectic would thus be a robust method under which one could examine personal social and economic behaviors Marxist dialectic is the core foundation of the philosophy of dialectical materialism which forms the basis of the ideas behind historical materialism Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels writing several decades after Hegel s death proposed that Hegel s dialectic is too abstract The mystification which dialectic suffers in Hegel s hands by no means prevents him from being the first to present its general form of working in a comprehensive and conscious manner With him it is standing on its head It must be turned right side up again if you would discover the rational kernel within the mystical shell 41 In contradiction to Hegelian idealism Marx presented his own dialectic method which he claims to be direct opposite of Hegel s method My dialectic method is not only different from the Hegelian but is its direct opposite To Hegel the life process of the human brain i e the process of thinking which under the name of the Idea he even transforms into an independent subject is the demiurgos of the real world and the real world is only the external phenomenal form of the Idea With me on the contrary the ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind and translated into forms of thought 42 In Marxism the dialectical method of historical study became intertwined with historical materialism the school of thought exemplified by the works of Marx Engels and Vladimir Lenin In the USSR under Joseph Stalin Marxist dialectics became diamat short for dialectical materialism a theory emphasizing the primacy of the material way of life social praxis over all forms of social consciousness and the secondary dependent character of the ideal The term dialectical materialism was coined by the 19th century social theorist Joseph Dietzgen who used the theory to explain the nature of socialism and social development The original populariser of Marxism in Russia Georgi Plekhanov used the terms dialectical materialism and historical materialism interchangeably For Lenin the primary feature of Marx s dialectical materialism Lenin s term was its application of materialist philosophy to history and social sciences Lenin s main input in the philosophy of dialectical materialism was his theory of reflection which presented human consciousness as a dynamic reflection of the objective material world that fully shapes its contents and structure Later Stalin s works on the subject established a rigid and formalistic division of Marxist Leninist theory in the dialectical materialism and historical materialism parts While the first was supposed to be the key method and theory of the philosophy of nature the second was the Soviet version of the philosophy of history A dialectical method was fundamental to Western Marxists such as Karl Korsch and Georg Lukacs Certain members of the Frankfurt School also used dialectical thinking such as Theodor W Adorno who developed negative dialectics Soviet academics notably Evald Ilyenkov and Zaid Orudzhev continued pursuing unorthodox philosophic study of Marxist dialectics likewise in the West notably the philosopher Bertell Ollman at New York University Friedrich Engels proposed that Nature is dialectical thus in Anti Duhring he said that the negation of negation is A very simple process which is taking place everywhere and every day which any child can understand as soon as it is stripped of the veil of mystery in which it was enveloped by the old idealist philosophy 43 In Dialectics of Nature Engels said Probably the same gentlemen who up to now have decried the transformation of quantity into quality as mysticism and incomprehensible transcendentalism will now declare that it is indeed something quite self evident trivial and commonplace which they have long employed and so they have been taught nothing new But to have formulated for the first time in its universally valid form a general law of development of Nature society and thought will always remain an act of historic importance 44 Marxist dialectics is exemplified in Das Kapital Capital which outlines two central theories i surplus value and ii the materialist conception of history Marx explains dialectical materialism In its rational form it is a scandal and abomination to bourgeoisdom and its doctrinaire professors because it includes in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of things at the same time also the recognition of the negation of that state of its inevitable breaking up because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence because it lets nothing impose upon it and is in its essence critical and revolutionary 45 Class struggle is the primary contradiction to be resolved by Marxist dialectics because of its central role in the social and political lives of a society Nonetheless Marx and Marxists developed the concept of class struggle to comprehend the dialectical contradictions between mental and manual labor and between town and country Hence philosophic contradiction is central to the development of dialectics the progress from quantity to quality the acceleration of gradual social change the negation of the initial development of the status quo the negation of that negation and the high level recurrence of features of the original status quo In the USSR Progress Publishers issued anthologies of dialectical materialism by Lenin wherein he also quotes Marx and Engels As the most comprehensive and profound doctrine of development and the richest in content Hegelian dialectics was considered by Marx and Engels the greatest achievement of classical German philosophy The great basic thought Engels writes that the world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready made things but as a complex of processes in which the things apparently stable no less than their mind images in our heads the concepts go through an uninterrupted change of coming into being and passing away this great fundamental thought has especially since the time of Hegel so thoroughly permeated ordinary consciousness that in its generality it is now scarcely ever contradicted But to acknowledge this fundamental thought in words and to apply it in reality in detail to each domain of investigation are two different things For dialectical philosophy nothing is final absolute sacred It reveals the transitory character of everything and in everything nothing can endure before it except the uninterrupted process of becoming and of passing away of endless ascendancy from the lower to the higher And dialectical philosophy itself is nothing more than the mere reflection of this process in the thinking brain Thus according to Marx dialectics is the science of the general laws of motion both of the external world and of human thought 46 Lenin describes his dialectical understanding of the concept of development A development that repeats as it were stages that have already been passed but repeats them in a different way on a higher basis the negation of the negation a development so to speak that proceeds in spirals not in a straight line a development by leaps catastrophes and revolutions breaks in continuity the transformation of quantity into quality inner impulses towards development imparted by the contradiction and conflict of the various forces and tendencies acting on a given body or within a given phenomenon or within a given society the interdependence and the closest and indissoluble connection between all aspects of any phenomenon history constantly revealing ever new aspects a connection that provides a uniform and universal process of motion one that follows definite laws these are some of the features of dialectics as a doctrine of development that is richer than the conventional one 46 An example of the influence of Marxist dialectic in the European tradition is Jean Paul Sartre s 1960 book Critique of Dialectical Reason Sartre stated Existentialism like Marxism addresses itself to experience in order to discover there concrete syntheses It can conceive of these syntheses only within a moving dialectical totalisation which is nothing else but history or from the strictly cultural point of view adopted here philosophy becoming the world 47 Dialectical naturalism Edit Dialectical naturalism is a term coined by American philosopher Murray Bookchin to describe the philosophical underpinnings of the political program of social ecology Dialectical naturalism explores the complex interrelationship between social problems and the direct consequences they have on the ecological impact of human society Bookchin offered dialectical naturalism as a contrast to what he saw as the empyrean basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism of Hegel and the wooden often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox Marxists Theological dialectical forms EditDialectical theology Edit Neo orthodoxy in Europe also known as theology of crisis and dialectical theology 48 49 is an approach to theology in Protestantism that was developed in the aftermath of the First World War 1914 1918 It is characterized as a reaction against doctrines of 19th century liberal theology and a more positive reevaluation of the teachings of the Reformation much of which had been in decline especially in western Europe since the late 18th century 50 It is primarily associated with two Swiss professors and pastors Karl Barth 51 1886 1968 and Emil Brunner 1899 1966 48 49 even though Barth himself expressed his unease in the use of the term 52 In dialectical theology the difference and opposition between God and human beings is stressed in such a way that all human attempts at overcoming this opposition through moral religious or philosophical idealism must be characterized as sin In the death of Christ humanity is negated and overcome but this judgment also points forwards to the resurrection in which humanity is reestablished in Christ For Barth this meant that only through God s no to everything human can his yes be perceived Applied to traditional themes of Protestant theology such as double predestination this means that election and reprobation cannot be viewed as a quantitative limitation of God s action Rather it must be seen as its qualitative definition 53 As Christ bore the rejection as well as the election of God for all humanity every person is subject to both aspects of God s double predestination Dialectic prominently figured in Bernard Lonergan s philosophy in his books Insight and Method in Theology Michael Shute wrote about Lonergan s use of dialectic in The Origins of Lonergan s Notion of the Dialectic of History For Lonergan dialectic is both individual and operative in community Simply described it is a dynamic process that results in something new For the sake of greater precision let us say that a dialectic is a concrete unfolding of linked but opposed principles of change Thus there will be a dialectic if 1 there is an aggregate of events of a determinate character 2 the events may be traced to either or both of two principles 3 the principles are opposed yet bound together and 4 they are modified by the changes that successively result from them 54 Dialectic is one of the eight functional specialties Lonergan envisaged for theology to bring this discipline into the modern world Lonergan believed that the lack of an agreed method among scholars had inhibited substantive agreement from being reached and progress from being made compared to the natural sciences Karl Rahner S J however criticized Lonergan s theological method in a short article entitled Some Critical Thoughts on Functional Specialties in Theology where he stated Lonergan s theological methodology seems to me to be so generic that it really fits every science and hence is not the methodology of theology as such but only a very general methodology of science 55 Criticisms EditSee also Category Critics of dialectical materialism Karl Popper has attacked the dialectic repeatedly In 1937 he wrote and delivered a paper entitled What Is Dialectic in which he attacked the dialectical method for its willingness to put up with contradictions 56 Popper concluded the essay with these words The whole development of dialectic should be a warning against the dangers inherent in philosophical system building It should remind us that philosophy should not be made a basis for any sort of scientific system and that philosophers should be much more modest in their claims One task which they can fulfill quite usefully is the study of the critical methods of science Ibid p 335 In chapter 12 of volume 2 of The Open Society and Its Enemies 1944 5th rev ed 1966 Popper unleashed a famous attack on Hegelian dialectics in which he held that Hegel s thought was to some degree responsible for facilitating the rise of fascism in Europe by encouraging and justifying irrationalism This was unjust in the view of some philosophers such as Walter Kaufmann 57 In section 17 of his 1961 addenda to The Open Society entitled Facts Standards and Truth A Further Criticism of Relativism Popper refused to moderate his criticism of the Hegelian dialectic arguing that it played a major role in the downfall of the liberal movement in Germany by contributing to historicism and to an identification of might and right encouraged totalitarian modes of thought And undermined and eventually lowered the traditional standards of intellectual responsibility and honesty 58 The philosopher of science and physicist Mario Bunge repeatedly criticized Hegelian and Marxian dialectics calling them fuzzy and remote from science 59 and a disastrous legacy 60 He concluded The so called laws of dialectics such as formulated by Engels 1940 1954 and Lenin 1947 1981 are false insofar as they are intelligible 60 Formalism EditThis section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic History edit history Since the late 20th century European and American logicians have attempted to provide mathematical foundations for dialectic through formalisation 61 201 372 although logic has been related to dialectic since ancient times 61 51 140 There have been pre formal and partially formal treatises on argument and dialectic from authors such as Stephen Toulmin The Uses of Argument 1958 62 63 61 203 256 Nicholas Rescher Dialectics A Controversy Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge 1977 64 65 61 330 336 and Frans H van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst pragma dialectics 1980s 61 517 614 One can include works of the communities of informal logic and paraconsistent logic 61 373 424 Defeasibility Edit This section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic Defeasibility edit history Building on theories of defeasible reasoning see John L Pollock systems have been built that define well formedness of arguments rules governing the process of introducing arguments based on fixed assumptions and rules for shifting burden 61 615 675 Many of these logics appear in the special area of artificial intelligence and law though the computer scientists interest in formalizing dialectic originates in a desire to build decision support and computer supported collaborative work systems 66 Dialog games Edit This section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic Dialog games edit history Main articles Game semantics and Dialogical logic Dialectic itself can be formalised as moves in a game where an advocate for the truth of a proposition and an opponent argue 61 301 372 Such games can provide a semantics of logic one that is very general in applicability 61 314 Mathematics Edit Mathematician William Lawvere interpreted dialectics in the setting of categorical logic in terms of adjunctions between idempotent monads 67 This perspective may be useful in the context of theoretical computer science where the duality between syntax and semantics can be interpreted as a dialectic in this sense For example the Curry Howard equivalence is such an adjunction or more generally the duality between closed monoidal categories and their internal logic 68 See also Edit Philosophy portal Psychology portalDialectical behavior therapy Psychotherapy for emotional dysregulation Dialectical research Form of qualitative research which utilizes the method of dialectic Dialogic Use of conversation to explore the meaning of something Doublethink Simultaneously accepting two mutually contradictory beliefs as correct False dilemma Informal fallacy involving falsely limited alternatives Reflective equilibrium State of balance among a set of beliefs arrived at by considering general principles Relational dialectics Interpersonal communication theory Tarka sastra Unity of opposites Central category of dialectics said to be related to non duality in a deep sense Universal dialecticReferences Edit see Gorgias 449B Socrates Would you be willing then Gorgias to continue the discussion as we are now doing Dialectic by way of question and answer and to put off to another occasion the emotional speeches Rhetoric that the Sophist Polus began Corbett Edward P J Robert J Connors 1999 Classical Rhetoric For the Modern Student 4th ed New York Oxford University Press pp 1 18 ISBN 9780195115420 Ayer A J amp O Grady J 1992 A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations Oxford UK Blackwell Publishers p 484 McTaggart J M E 1964 A commentary on Hegel s logic New York Russell amp Russell p 11 Diogenes Laertius IX 25ff and VIII 57 1 Critique of Pure Reason A 61 Elenchus Wiktionary 8 February 2021 Wyss Peter October 2014 Socratic Method Aporeia Elenchus and Dialectics Plato Four Dialogues Handout 3 PDF open conted ox ac uk University of Oxford Department for Continuing Education Popper K 1962 The Open Society and its Enemies Volume 1 London Routledge p 133 Reale Giovanni 1990 History of Ancient Philosophy 5 vols trans by John R Catan Albany State University of New York vol 2 p 150 Blackburn Simon 1996 The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford Oxford Rapp 2010 Aristotle s Rhetoric Retrieved from http plato stanford edu entries aristotle rhetoric Abelson P 1965 The seven liberal arts a study in mediaeval culture New York Russell amp Russell Page 82 Hyman A amp Walsh J J 1983 Philosophy in the Middle Ages the Christian Islamic and Jewish traditions Indianapolis Hackett Pub Co Page 164 Adler Mortimer Jerome 2000 Dialectic Routledge Page 4 ISBN 0 415 22550 7 Herbermann C G 1913 The Catholic encyclopedia an international work of reference on the constitution doctrine and history of the Catholic church New York The Encyclopedia press inc Page 760 764 From topic to tale logic and narrativity in the Middle Ages by Eugene Vance p 43 45 Catholic Encyclopedia Peter Abelard Newadvent org 1907 03 01 Retrieved 2011 11 03 William of Sherwood s Introduction to logic by Norman Kretzmann p 69 102 A History of Twelfth Century Western Philosophy by Peter Dronke p 198 Medieval literary politics shapes of ideology by Sheila Delany p 11 Catholic Encyclopedia St Thomas Aquinas Newadvent org 1907 03 01 Retrieved 2015 10 20 Nicholson J A 1950 Philosophy of religion New York Ronald Press Co Page 108 Kant I Guyer P amp Wood A W 2003 Critique of pure reason Cambridge Cambridge University Press Page 495 Henri Lefebvre s humanist dialectical materialism Dialectical Materialism 1940 was composed to directly challenge Joseph Stalin s own dogmatic text on dialectical materialism Historische Entwicklung der spekulativen Philosophie von Kant bis Hegel Dresden Leipzig 1837 p 367 of the fourth edition 1848 The Accessible Hegel by Michael Allen Fox Prometheus Books 2005 p 43 Also see Hegel s preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit trans A V Miller Oxford Clarendon Press 1977 secs 50 51 pp 29 30 See for a discussion of the historical development of the triad Charles Edward Andrew Lincoln IV Hegelian Dialectical Analysis of U S Voting Laws 42 U Dayton L Rev 87 2017 Hegel A Reinterpretation 1966 Anchor Books p 154 G E Mueller June 1958 The Hegel Legend of Thesis Antithesis Synthesis 166ff Hegel Werke ed Glockner XIX 610 Hegel Section in question from Hegel s Science of Logic Marxists org Retrieved 2011 11 03 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd Edition London Oxford University Press Note to 81 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd Edition London Oxford University Press 107 111 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd Edition London Oxford University Press 108 109 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd Edition London Oxford University Press 108 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd Edition London Oxford University Press 93 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd Edition London Oxford University Press 95 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1812 Hegel s Science of Logic London Allen amp Unwin 176 179 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1812 Hegel s Science of Logic London Allen amp Unwin 185 Marx Karl 1873 Capital Afterword to the Second German Edition Vol I 2 Marx Karl Afterword Second German Ed Capital 1 14 Retrieved 28 December 2014 Engels Frederick 1877 Anti Duhring Part I Philosophy XIII Dialectics Negation of the Negation Engels Frederick 1883 Dialectics of Nature II Dialectics Marxists org Retrieved 2011 11 03 Marx Karl 1873 Capital Vol I Afterword to the Second German Edition a b Lenin V I On the Question of Dialectics A Collection pp 7 9 Progress Publishers Moscow 1980 Jean Paul Sartre The Search for Method 1st part Sartre 1960 in Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre transl Hazel Barnes Vintage Books Marxists org Retrieved 2011 11 03 a b Original Britinnica online Retrieved 2008 07 26 a b Britannica Encyclopedia online Retrieved 2008 07 26 Merriam Webster Dictionary online Retrieved 2008 07 26 American Heritage Dictionary online Archived from the original on 2005 05 10 Retrieved 2008 07 26 See Church Dogmatics III 3 xii Karl Barth The Epistle to the Romans 1933 p 346 Bernard J F Lonergan Insight A Study of Human Understanding Collected Works vol 3 ed Frederick E Crowe and Robert M Doran Toronto University of Toronto 1992 pp 217 218 McShane S J Philip 1972 Foundations of Theology Notre Dame Indiana University of Notre Dame Press p 194 Karl Popper Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge New York Basic Books 1962 p 316 Walter Kaufmann kaufmann Marxists org Retrieved 2011 11 03 Karl Popper The Open Society and Its Enemies 5th rev ed vol 2 Princeton Princeton University Press 1966 p 395 Bunge Mario Augusto 1981 A critique of dialectics Scientific materialism Episteme Vol 9 Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 41 63 doi 10 1007 978 94 009 8517 9 4 ISBN 978 9027713049 OCLC 7596139 a b Bunge Mario Augusto 2012 Evaluating philosophies Boston studies in the philosophy of science Vol 295 New York Springer Verlag pp 84 85 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 4408 0 ISBN 9789400744073 OCLC 806947226 a b c d e f g h i Eemeren Frans H van Garssen Bart Krabbe Erik C W Snoeck Henkemans A Francisca Verheij Bart Wagemans Jean H M 2014 Handbook of argumentation theory New York Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 978 90 481 9473 5 ISBN 9789048194728 OCLC 871004444 Toulmin Stephen 2003 1958 The uses of argument Updated ed Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 CBO9780511840005 ISBN 978 0521827485 OCLC 51607421 Hitchcock David Verheij Bart eds 2006 Arguing on the Toulmin model new essays in argument analysis and evaluation Argumentation library Vol 10 Dordrecht Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 4938 5 ISBN 978 1402049378 OCLC 82229075 Hetherington Stephen 2006 Nicholas Rescher Philosophical Dialectics Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 07 16 Jacquette Dale ed 2009 Reason Method and Value A Reader on the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher Frankfurt Ontos Verlag doi 10 1515 9783110329056 ISBN 9783110329056 For surveys of work in this area see for example Chesnevar Carlos Ivan Maguitman Ana Gabriela Loui Ronald Prescott December 2000 Logical models of argument ACM Computing Surveys 32 4 337 383 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 702 8325 doi 10 1145 371578 371581 And Prakken Henry Vreeswijk Gerard 2005 Logics for defeasible argumentation In Gabbay Dov M Guenthner Franz eds Handbook of philosophical logic Vol 4 2nd ed Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 219 318 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 295 2649 doi 10 1007 978 94 017 0456 4 3 ISBN 9789048158775 Lawvere F William 1996 Unity and identity of opposites in calculus and physics Applied Categorical Structures 4 2 3 167 174 doi 10 1007 BF00122250 S2CID 34109341 Eilenberg Samuel Kelly G Max 1966 Closed Categories Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra 421 562 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 99902 4 22 ISBN 978 3 642 99904 8 Further reading EditMcKeon Richard October 1954 Dialectic and Political Thought and Action Ethics 65 1 1 33 doi 10 1086 290973 JSTOR 2378780 S2CID 144465113 The essay contains three parts 1 a brief history of dialectic designed to focus on these questions by tracing the evolution of various trends of dialectical method in the light of the development of alternative methods 2 a statement of the nature and varieties of dialectic designed to bring out differences of methods and to indicate the possibility of common conceptions and common aims and 3 an examination of the problems of common understanding and common action posed by the difference of dialectical and nondialectical methods of thought today Postan Michael M April 1962 Function and Dialectic in Economic History The Economic History Review 14 3 397 407 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0289 1962 tb00058 x JSTOR 2591884 The trouble about the dialectic is not that it is wholly inapplicable to history but that it is so frequently applied to fields in which it happens to be least useful If function and dialectic are to be reconciled and allowed their proper place in historical work it will perhaps be necessary to move a stage beyond the philosophical position which Marx took up in the 1840s Having put the dialectic on its head and made it materialist Marx has directed it into regions to which this posture is unsuited If we complete the somersault and put the dialectic on its feet again we might thereby return it to where it belongs Rescher Nicholas 2007 Dialectics A Classical Approach to Inquiry Frankfurt New Brunswick Ontos Verlag ISBN 9783938793763 OCLC 185032382 A broad survey of various conceptions of dialectic including disputational cognitive methodological ontological and philosophical Spranzi Marta 2011 The Art of Dialectic between Dialogue and Rhetoric The Aristotelian Tradition Controversies Vol 9 Amsterdam Philadelphia John Benjamins Publishing Company doi 10 1075 cvs 9 ISBN 9789027218896 OCLC 704557514 This book reconstructs the tradition of dialectic from Aristotle s Topics its founding text up to its renaissance in 16th century Italy and focuses on the role of dialectic in the production of knowledge External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Dialectic Look up dialectic in Wiktionary the free dictionary v Dialectic algorithm An algorithm based on the principles of classical dialectics Hegel s Dialectics entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Dialectic Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 8 11th ed 1911 p 156 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Dialectic amp oldid 1132744860, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.