fbpx
Wikipedia

Body politic

The body politic is a polity—such as a city, realm, or state—considered metaphorically as a physical body. Historically, the sovereign is typically portrayed as the body's head, and the analogy may also be extended to other anatomical parts, as in political readings of Aesop's fable of "The Belly and the Members". The image originates in ancient Greek philosophy, beginning in the 6th century BC, and was later extended in Roman philosophy. Following the high and late medieval revival of the Byzantine Corpus Juris Civilis in Latin Europe, the "body politic" took on a jurisprudential significance by being identified with the legal theory of the corporation, gaining salience in political thought from the 13th century on. In English law the image of the body politic developed into the theory of the king's two bodies and the Crown as corporation sole.

The frontispiece of Hobbes's Leviathan shows a body formed of multitudinous citizens, surmounted by a king's head.[1]

The metaphor was elaborated further from the Renaissance on, as medical knowledge based on Galen was challenged by thinkers such as William Harvey. Analogies were drawn between supposed causes of disease and disorder and their equivalents in the political field, viewed as plagues or infections that might be remedied with purges and nostrums.[2] The 17th century writings of Thomas Hobbes developed the image of the body politic into a modern theory of the state as an artificial person. Parallel terms deriving from the Latin corpus politicum exist in other European languages.

Etymology

The term body politic derives from Medieval Latin corpus politicum, which itself developed from corpus mysticum, originally designating the Catholic Church as the mystical body of Christ but extended to politics from the 11th century on in the form corpus reipublicae (mysticum), "(mystical) body of the commonwealth".[3][4] Parallel terms exist in other European languages, such as Italian corpo politico, Polish ciało polityczne, and German Staatskörper ("state body").[3] An equivalent early modern French term is corps-état;[5] contemporary French uses corps politique.[3]

History

 
A visualization of the body politic metaphor in a 14th-century French manuscript.
The king is head. Next, the seneschals, bailiffs, and provosts and other judges are compared to eyes and ears. The counsellors and wise men are linked to the heart. As defenders of the commonwealth, the knights are the hands. Because of their constant voyages, the merchants are associated with the legs. Finally, laborers, who work close to the earth and support the body, are its feet.

Classical philosophy

The Western concept of the "body politic", originally meaning a human society considered as a collective body, originated in classical Greek and Roman philosophy.[6] The general metaphor emerged in the 6th century BC, with the Athenian statesman Solon and the poet Theognis describing cities (poleis) in biological terms as "pregnant" or "wounded".[7] Plato's Republic provided one of its most influential formulations.[8] The term itself, however—in Ancient Greek, τῆς πόλεως σῶμα, tēs poleōs sōma, "the body of the state"—appears as such for the first time in the late 4th century Athenian orators Dinarch and Hypereides at the beginning of the Hellenistic era.[9] In these early formulations, the anatomical detail of the body politic was relatively limited: Greek thinkers typically confined themselves to distinguishing the ruler as head of the body, and comparing political stasis, that is, crises of the state, to biological disease.[10]

The image of the body politic occupied a central place in the political thought of the Roman Republic, and the Romans were the first to develop the anatomy of the "body" in full detail, endowing it with nerves, "blood, breath, limbs, and organs".[11] In its origins, the concept was particularly connected to a politicised version of Aesop's fable of "The Belly and the Members", told in relation to the first secessio plebis, the temporary departure of the plebeian order from Rome in 495–93 BC.[12][13] On the account of the Roman historian Livy, a senator explained the situation to the plebeians by a metaphor: the various members of the Roman body had become angry that the "stomach", the patricians, consumed their labours while providing nothing in return. However, upon their secession, they became feeble and realised that the stomach's digestion had provided them vital energy. Convinced by this story, the plebeians returned to Rome, and the Roman body was made whole and functional. This legend formed a paradigm for "nearly all surviving republican discourse of the body politic".[12]

Late republican orators developed the image further, comparing attacks on Roman institutions to mutilations of the republic's body. During the First Triumvirate in 59 BC, Cicero described the Roman state as "dying of a new sort of disease".[14] Lucan's Pharsalia, written in the early imperial era in the 60s AD, abounded in this kind of imagery. Depicting the dictator Sulla as a surgeon out of control who had butchered the Roman body politic in the process of cutting out its putrefied limbs, Lucan used vivid organic language to portray the decline of the Roman Republic as a literal process of decay, its seas and rivers becoming choked with blood and gore.[15]

Medieval usage

The metaphor of the body politic remained in use after the fall of the Western Roman Empire.[8] The Neoplatonist Islamic philosopher al-Farabi, known in the West as Alpharabius, discussed the image in his work The Perfect State (c. 940), stating, "The excellent city resembles the perfect and healthy body, all of whose limbs cooperate to make the life of the animal perfect".[16] John of Salisbury gave it a definitive Latin high medieval form in his Policraticus around 1159: the king was the body's head; the priest was the soul; the councillors were the heart; the eyes, ears, and tongue were the magistrates of the law; one hand, the army, held a weapon; the other, without a weapon, was the realm's justice. The body's feet were the common people. Each member of the body had its vocation, and each was beholden to work in harmony for the benefit of the whole body.[17]

In the Late Middle Ages, the concept of the corporation, a legal person made up of a group of real individuals, gave the idea of a body politic judicial significance.[18] The corporation had emerged in imperial Roman law under the name universitas, and a formulation of the concept attributed to Ulpian was collected in the 6th century Digest of Justinian I during the early Byzantine era.[19] The Digest, along with the other parts of Justinian's Corpus Juris Civilis, became the bedrock of medieval civil law upon its recovery and annotation by the glossators beginning in the 11th century.[20] It remained for the glossators' 13th century successors, the commentators—especially Baldus de Ubaldis—to develop the idea of the corporation as a persona ficta, a fictive person, and apply the concept to human societies as a whole.[18]

 
The imperial eagle in Dante's Paradiso, depicted by Giovanni di Paolo in the 1440s

Where his jurist predecessor Bartolus of Saxoferrato conceived the corporation in essentially legal terms, Baldus expressly connected the corporation theory to the ancient, biological and political concept of the body politic. For Baldus, not only was man, in Aristotelian terms, a "political animal", but the whole populus, the body of the people, formed a type of political animal in itself: a populus "has government as part of [its] existence, just as every animal is ruled by its own spirit and soul".[21] Baldus equated the body politic with the respublica, the state or realm, stating that it "cannot die, and for this reason it is said that it has no heir, because it always lives on in itself".[22] From here, the image of the body politic became prominent in the medieval imagination. In Canto XVIII of his Paradiso, for instance, Dante, writing in the early 14th century, presents the Roman Empire as a corporate body in the form of an imperial eagle, its body made of souls.[23] The French court writer Christine de Pizan discussed the concept at length in her Book of the Body Politic (1407).[24]

The idea of the body politic, rendered in legal terms through corporation theory, also drew natural comparison to the theological concept of the church as a corpus mysticum, the mystical body of Christ. The concept of the people as a corpus mysticum also featured in Baldus,[25] and the idea that the realm of France was a corpus mysticum formed an important part of late medieval French jurisprudence. Jean de Terrevermeille [fr], around 1418–19, described the French laws of succession as established by the "whole civic or mystical body of the realm", and the Parlement of Paris in 1489 proclaimed itself a "mystical body" composed of both ecclesiastics and laymen, representing the "body of the king".[26] From at least the 14th century, the doctrine developed that the French kings were mystically married to the body politic; at the coronation of Henry II in 1547, he was said to have "solemnly married his realm".[27] The English jurist John Fortescue also invoked the "mystical body" in his De Laudibus Legum Angliae (c. 1470): just as a physical body is "held together by the nerves", the mystical body of the realm is held together by the law, and

Just as the physical body grows out of the embryo, regulated by one head, so does there issue from the people the kingdom, which exists as a corpus mysticum governed by one man as head.[28]

The king's body politic

In England

In Tudor and Stuart England, the concept of the body politic was given a peculiar additional significance through the idea of the king's two bodies, the doctrine discussed by the German-American medievalist Ernst Kantorowicz in his eponymous work. This legal doctrine held that the monarch had two bodies: the physical "king body natural" and the immortal "King body politic". Upon the "demise" of an individual king, his body natural fell away, but the body politic lived on.[29] This was an indigenous development of English law without a precise equivalent in the rest of Europe.[30] Extending the identification of the body politic as a corporation, English jurists argued that the Crown was a "corporation sole": a corporation made up of one body politic that was at the same time the body of the realm and its parliamentary estates, and also the body of the royal dignity itself—two concepts of the body politic that were conflated and fused.[31]

 
Elizabethan jurists held that the immaturity of Edward VI's body natural was expunged by his body politic.

The development of the doctrine of the king's two bodies can be traced in the Reports of Edmund Plowden. In the 1561 Case of the Duchy of Lancaster, which concerned whether an earlier gift of land made by Edward VI could be voided on account of his "nonage", that is, his immaturity, the judges held that it could not: the king's "Body politic, which is annexed to his Body natural, takes away the Imbecility of his Body natural".[32] The king's body politic, then, "that cannot be seen or handled", annexes the body natural and "wipes away" all its defects.[33] What was more, the body politic rendered the king immortal as an individual: as the judges in the case Hill v. Grange argued in 1556, once the king had made an act, "he as King never dies, but the King, in which Name it has Relation to him, does ever continue"—thus, they held, Henry VIII was still "alive", a decade after his physical death.[29]

The doctrine of the two bodies could serve to limit the powers of the real king. When Edward Coke, Chief Justice of the Common Pleas at the time, reported the way in which judges had differentiated the bodies in 1608, he noted that it was the "natural body" of the king that was created by God—the "politic body", by contrast, was "framed by the policy of man".[34] In the Case of Prohibitions of the same year, Coke denied the king "in his own person" any right to administer justice or order arrests.[35] Finally, in its declaration of 27 May 1642 shortly before the start of the English Civil War, Parliament drew on the theory to invoke the powers of the body politic of Charles I against his body natural,[36] stating:

What they [Parliament] do herein, hath the Stamp of Royal Authority, although His Majesty seduced by evil Counsel, do in His own Person, oppose, or interrupt the same. For the King's Supreme Power, and Royal Pleasure, is exercised and declared in this High Court of Law, and Council, after a more eminent and obligatory manner, than it can be by any personal Act or Resolution of His Own.[37]

The 18th century jurist William Blackstone, in Book I of his Commentaries on the Laws of England (1765), summarised the doctrine of the king's body politic as it subsequently developed after the Restoration: the king "in his political capacity" manifests "absolute perfection"; he can "do no wrong", nor even is he capable of "thinking wrong"; he can have no defect, and is never in law "a minor or under age". Indeed, Blackstone says, if an heir to the throne should accede while "attainted of treason or felony", his assumption of the crown "would purge the attainder ipso facto". The king manifests "absolute immortality": "Henry, Edward, or George may die; but the king survives them all".[38] Soon after the appearance of the Commentaries, however, Jeremy Bentham mounted an extensive attack on Blackstone which the historian Quentin Skinner describes as "almost lethal" to the theory: legal fictions like the body politic, Bentham argued, were conducive to royal absolutism and should be entirely avoided in law. Bentham's position dominated later British legal thinking, and though aspects of the theory of the body politic would survive in subsequent jurisprudence, the idea of the Crown as a corporation sole was widely critiqued.[39]

In the late 19th century, Frederic William Maitland revived the legal discourse of the king's two bodies, arguing that the concept of the Crown as corporation sole had originated from the amalgamation of medieval civil law with the law of church property.[40] He proposed, in contrast, to view the Crown as an ordinary corporation aggregate, that is, a corporation of many people, with a view to describing the legal personhood of the state.[41]

In France

A related but contrasting concept in France was the doctrine termed by Sarah Hanley the king's one body, summarised by Jean Bodin in his own 1576 pronouncement that "the king never dies".[42] Rather than distinguishing the immortal body politic from the mortal body natural of the king, as in the English theory, the French doctrine conflated the two, arguing that the Salic law had established a single king body politic and natural that constantly regenerated through the biological reproduction of the royal line.[43] The body politic, on this account, was biological and necessarily male, and 15th century French jurists such as Jean Juvénal des Ursins argued on this basis for the exclusion of female heirs to the crown—since, they argued, the king of France was a "virile office".[44] In the ancien régime, the king's heir was held to assimilate the body politic of the old king in a physical "transfer of corporeality" upon his accession.[45]

In the United States

James I in the second charter for Virginia, as well as both the Plymouth and Massachusetts Charter, grant body politic.[46][47][48]

Hobbesian state theory

 
Thomas Hobbes, c. 1669–70

Aside from the doctrine of the king's two bodies, the conventional image of the whole of the realm as a body politic had also remained in use in Stuart England: James I compared the office of the king to "the office of the head towards the body".[49] Upon the outbreak of the English Civil War in 1642, however, parliamentarians such as William Bridge put forward the argument that the "ruling power" belonged originally to "the whole people or body politicke", who could revoke it from the monarch.[50] The execution of Charles I in 1649 made necessary a radical revision of the whole concept.[51] In 1651, Thomas Hobbes's Leviathan made a decisive contribution to this effect, reviving the concept while endowing it with new features. Against the parliamentarians, Hobbes maintained that sovereignty was absolute and the head could certainly not be "of lesse power" than the body of the people; against the royal absolutists, however, he developed the idea of a social contract, emphasising that the body politic—Leviathan, the "mortal god"—was fictional and artificial rather than natural, derived from an original decision by the people to constitute a sovereign.[52][53]

Hobbes's theory of the body politic exercised an important influence on subsequent political thinkers, who both repeated and modified it. Republican partisans of the Commonwealth presented alternative figurations of the metaphor in defence of the parliamentarian model. James Harrington, in his 1656 Commonwealth of Oceana, argued that "the delivery of a Model Government ... is no less than political Anatomy"; it must "imbrace all those Muscles, Nerves, Arterys and Bones, which are necessary to any Function of a well order'd Commonwealth". Invoking William Harvey's recent discovery of the circulatory system, Harrington presented the body politic as a dynamic system of political circulation, comparing his ideal bicameral legislature, for example, to the ventricles of the human heart. In contrast to Hobbes, the "head" was once more dependent on the people: the execution of the law must follow the law itself, so that "Leviathan may see, that the hand or sword that executeth the Law is in it, and not above it".[54] In Germany, Samuel von Pufendorf recapitulated Hobbes's explanation of the origin of the state as a social contract, but extended his notion of personhood to argue that the state must be a specifically moral person with a rational nature, and not simply coercive power.[55]

In the 18th century, Hobbes's theory of the state as an artificial body politic gained wide acceptance both in Britain and continental Europe.[56] Thomas Pownall, later the British governor of Massachusetts and a proponent of American liberty, drew on Hobbes's theory in his 1752 Principles of Polity to argue that "the whole Body politic" should be conceived as "one Person"; states were "distinct Persons and independent".[57] At around the same time, the Swiss jurist Emer de Vattel pronounced that "states are bodies politic", "moral persons" with their own "understanding and ... will", a statement that would become accepted international law.[58]

The tension between organic understandings of the body politic and theories emphasizing its artificial character formed a theme in English political debates in this period. Writing in 1780, during the American Revolutionary War, the British reformist John Cartwright emphasised the artificial and immortal character of the body politic in order to refute the use of biological analogies in conservative rhetoric. Arguing that it was better conceived as a machine operating by the "due action and re-action of the ... springs of the constitution" than a human body, he termed "the body politic" a "careless figurative expression": "It is not corporeal ... not formed from the dust of the earth. It is purely intellectual; and its life-spring is truth."[59]

Modern law

The English term "body politic" is sometimes used in modern legal contexts to describe a type of legal person, typically the state itself or an entity connected to it. A body politic is a type of taxable legal person in British law, for example,[60] and likewise a class of legal person in Indian law.[61][62]In the United States, a municipal corporation is considered a body politic, as opposed to a private body corporate.[63] The U.S. Supreme Court affirmed the theory of the state as an artificial body politic in the 1851 case Cotton v. United States, declaring that "every sovereign State is of necessity a body politic, or artificial person, and as such capable of making contracts and holding property, both real and personal", and differentiated the United States' powers as a sovereign from its rights as a body politic.[64]

See also

References

  1. ^ Kenneth Olwig (2002), Landscape, nature, and the body politic, University of Wisconsin Press, p. 87, ISBN 978-0-299-17424-8, The frontispiece to Thomas Hobbes's Leviathan ... is a particularly famous example of the depiction of the body politic ...
  2. ^ Jonathan Harris (1998), Foreign bodies and the body politic: discourses of social pathology in early modern England, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-59405-9
  3. ^ a b c Musolff, Andreas (2017). "Metaphor and Cultural Cognition". In Sharifian, Farzad (ed.). Advances in Cultural Linguistics. Singapore: Springer Nature. pp. 328–29. ISBN 978-9-811-04055-9.
  4. ^ Kantorowicz, Ernst H. (2016). The King's Two Bodies: A Study in Mediaeval Political Theology (Princeton Classics ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press. pp. 207–208. ISBN 978-0-691-16923-1.
  5. ^ de Baecque, Antoine (1997). The Body Politic: Corporeal Metaphor in Revolutionary France, 1770-1800. Trans. Charlotte Mandell. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. p. xv. ISBN 978-0-8047-2817-1.
  6. ^ Dobski, Bernard J.; Gish, Dustin (2013). Dobski, Bernard J.; Gish, Dustin (eds.). Shakespeare and the Body Politic. Plymouth: Lexington Books. p. 6. ISBN 978-0-739-17095-3.
  7. ^ Brock, Roger (2013). Greek Political Imagery from Homer to Aristotle. London & New York: Bloomsbury Academic. p. 69. ISBN 978-1-472-50218-6.
  8. ^ a b MacKinnon, Patricia L. (1988). The analogy of the body politic in St. Augustine, Dante, Petrarch, and Ariosto (PhD). University of California, Santa Cruz. p. 4.
  9. ^ Brock 2013, p. 70.
  10. ^ Brock 2013, pp. 70–71.
  11. ^ Walters, Brian (2020). The Deaths of the Republic: Imagery of the Body Politic in Ciceronian Rome. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-198-83957-6.
  12. ^ a b Walters 2020, pp. 7–9.
  13. ^ Rollo-Koster, Joëlle (2010). "Body Politic". In Bevir, Mark (ed.). Encyclopedia of Political Theory. Vol. 1. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. p. 134. ISBN 978-1-412-95865-3.
  14. ^ Walters 2020, pp. 75–77.
  15. ^ Walters, Brian (2019). "Sulla's Phthiriasis and the Republican Body Politic". Mnemosyne. 72 (6): 964. doi:10.1163/1568525X-12342610. S2CID 211665064.
  16. ^ Rosenwein, Barbara H., ed. (2018). Reading the Middle Ages: Sources from Europe, Byzantium, and the Islamic World (3rd ed.). Toronto: University of Toronto Press. p. 206. ISBN 978-1-442-63674-3.
  17. ^ Dumolyn, Jan (2006). "Justice, Equity and the Common Good: The State Ideology of the Councillors of the Burgundian Dukes". In Boulton, D'Arcy Jonathan Dacre; Veenstra, Jan R. (eds.). The Ideology of Burgundy: The Promotion of National Consciousness, 1364–1565. Leiden: Brill. pp. 12–13. ISBN 978-9-004-15359-2.
  18. ^ a b Canning, Joseph (1996). A History of Medieval Political Thought: 300–1450. Abingdon: Routledge. p. 172. ISBN 978-0-415-39415-4.
  19. ^ Duff, Patrick W. (1938). Personality in Roman Private Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 37.
  20. ^ Canning, Joseph (2011). "Civil (Roman) Law". In Lagerlund, Henrik (ed.). Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy: Philosophy Between 500 and 1500. Dordrecht: Springer. p. 221.
  21. ^ Canning, Joseph (2011). Ideas of Power in the Late Middle Ages, 1296–1417. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 145–46. ISBN 978-1-107-01141-0.
  22. ^ Genet, Jean-Philippe (1998). "Politics: theory and practice". In Allmand, Christopher (ed.). The New Cambridge Medieval History. Volume VII: c. 1415–c. 1500. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 18–19. ISBN 978-0-521-38296-0.
  23. ^ Monateri, Pier Giuseppe (2018). Dominus Mundi: Political Sublime and the World Order. Oxford: Hart. p. 52. ISBN 978-1-509-91176-9.
  24. ^ de Pizan, Christine (1994). Langdon Forhan, Kate (ed.). The Book of the Body Politic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. xviii–xx. ISBN 978-0-521-42259-8.
  25. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, p. 210.
  26. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 219–20.
  27. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 221–22.
  28. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, p. 224.
  29. ^ a b Kantorowicz 2016, p. 13.
  30. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 20, 446.
  31. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 448–49.
  32. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 9–10.
  33. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 4 n5, 11.
  34. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, pp. 14, 423 n362.
  35. ^ Hasanbegović, Jasminka (2021). "On the (Un)Changing Judge Icons and Their Creators: On Deborah, Coke and Montesquieu, Posner and Barak, and Some Others". In Chiassoni, Pier; Spaić, Bojan (eds.). Judges and Adjudication in Constitutional Democracies: A View from Legal Realism. Cham: Springer. p. 76. ISBN 978-3-030-58185-5.
  36. ^ Kantorowicz 2016, p. 21.
  37. ^ Parliament of England (1642). A Declaration of the Lords and Commons in Parliament, concerning his Maiesties Proclamation the 27. of May 1642. London: William Gaye. p. 4 – via Early English Books Online. Spelling modernised.
  38. ^ Blackstone, William (1765). Commentaries on the Laws of England. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 238–42.
  39. ^ McLean, Janet (2012). Searching for the State in British Legal Thought: Competing Conceptions of the Public Sphere. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 4. ISBN 978-1-107-02248-5.
  40. ^ George, Garnett (1996). "The Origins of the Crown". Proceedings of the British Academy. 89: 171–214.
  41. ^ McLean 2012, pp. 4–5.
  42. ^ Hanley, Sarah (1997). "Mapping Rulership in the French Body Politic: Political Identity, Public Law and the 'King's One Body'". Historical Reflections. 23 (2): 134. JSTOR 41299087.
  43. ^ Hanley 1997, p. 136.
  44. ^ Hanley 1997, p. 140.
  45. ^ de Baecque 1997, pp. 100–102.
  46. ^ "The Second Charter of Virginia; May 23, 1609". 18 December 1998.
  47. ^ "Charter of the Colony of New Plymouth Granted to William Bradford and His Associates : 1629". 18 December 1998.
  48. ^ "The Charter of Massachusetts Bay : 1629". 18 December 1998.
  49. ^ Attie, Katherine Bootle (2008). "Re-Membering the Body Politic: Hobbes and the Construction of Civic Immortality". ELH. 75 (3): 497–530. doi:10.1353/elh.0.0011. JSTOR 27654624. S2CID 162034742.
  50. ^ Skinner, Quentin (2009). "A Genealogy of the Modern State" (PDF). Proceedings of the British Academy. 162: 340.
  51. ^ Attie 2008, p. 498.
  52. ^ Skinner 2009, pp. 342–43.
  53. ^ Attie 2008, pp. 500, 502.
  54. ^ Attie 2008, pp. 507–508.
  55. ^ Skinner, Quentin (2018). From Humanism to Hobbes: Studies in Rhetoric and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 365–66. ISBN 978-1-107-12885-9.
  56. ^ Skinner 2018, p. 371.
  57. ^ Skinner 2018, p. 370.
  58. ^ Skinner 2009, p. 352.
  59. ^ Ihalainen, Pasi (2009). "Towards an Immortal Political Body: The State Machine in Eighteenth-Century English Political Discourse". Contributions to the History of Concepts. 5: 34–35. doi:10.1163/187465609X430845.
  60. ^ Harris, Peter (2013). Corporate Tax Law: Structure, Policy and Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 21. ISBN 978-1-107-03353-5.
  61. ^ Bhattacharya, Ananya (7 June 2019). "Birds to holy rivers: A list of everything India considers "legal persons"". Quartz. Retrieved 24 May 2021.
  62. ^ Kanti Ghosh, Sumit (2023-05-18). "Body, Dress, and Symbolic Capital: Multifaceted Presentation of PUGREE in Colonial Governance of British India". TEXTILE: 1–32. doi:10.1080/14759756.2023.2208502. ISSN 1475-9756.
  63. ^ Fippinger, Robert A. (1993). The Securities Law of Public Finance (2nd ed.). Practising Law Institute. p. 2 n6. ISBN 978-0-872-24054-4.
  64. ^ Cotton v. United States, 52 U.S. 229 (1851).

body, politic, other, uses, disambiguation, body, politic, polity, such, city, realm, state, considered, metaphorically, physical, body, historically, sovereign, typically, portrayed, body, head, analogy, also, extended, other, anatomical, parts, political, re. For other uses see Body politic disambiguation The body politic is a polity such as a city realm or state considered metaphorically as a physical body Historically the sovereign is typically portrayed as the body s head and the analogy may also be extended to other anatomical parts as in political readings of Aesop s fable of The Belly and the Members The image originates in ancient Greek philosophy beginning in the 6th century BC and was later extended in Roman philosophy Following the high and late medieval revival of the Byzantine Corpus Juris Civilis in Latin Europe the body politic took on a jurisprudential significance by being identified with the legal theory of the corporation gaining salience in political thought from the 13th century on In English law the image of the body politic developed into the theory of the king s two bodies and the Crown as corporation sole The frontispiece of Hobbes s Leviathan shows a body formed of multitudinous citizens surmounted by a king s head 1 The metaphor was elaborated further from the Renaissance on as medical knowledge based on Galen was challenged by thinkers such as William Harvey Analogies were drawn between supposed causes of disease and disorder and their equivalents in the political field viewed as plagues or infections that might be remedied with purges and nostrums 2 The 17th century writings of Thomas Hobbes developed the image of the body politic into a modern theory of the state as an artificial person Parallel terms deriving from the Latin corpus politicum exist in other European languages Contents 1 Etymology 2 History 2 1 Classical philosophy 2 2 Medieval usage 2 3 The king s body politic 2 3 1 In England 2 3 2 In France 2 4 In the United States 2 5 Hobbesian state theory 3 Modern law 4 See also 5 ReferencesEtymology EditThe term body politic derives from Medieval Latin corpus politicum which itself developed from corpus mysticum originally designating the Catholic Church as the mystical body of Christ but extended to politics from the 11th century on in the form corpus reipublicae mysticum mystical body of the commonwealth 3 4 Parallel terms exist in other European languages such as Italian corpo politico Polish cialo polityczne and German Staatskorper state body 3 An equivalent early modern French term is corps etat 5 contemporary French uses corps politique 3 History Edit A visualization of the body politic metaphor in a 14th century French manuscript The king is head Next the seneschals bailiffs and provosts and other judges are compared to eyes and ears The counsellors and wise men are linked to the heart As defenders of the commonwealth the knights are the hands Because of their constant voyages the merchants are associated with the legs Finally laborers who work close to the earth and support the body are its feet Classical philosophy Edit The Western concept of the body politic originally meaning a human society considered as a collective body originated in classical Greek and Roman philosophy 6 The general metaphor emerged in the 6th century BC with the Athenian statesman Solon and the poet Theognis describing cities poleis in biological terms as pregnant or wounded 7 Plato s Republic provided one of its most influential formulations 8 The term itself however in Ancient Greek tῆs polews sῶma tes poleōs sōma the body of the state appears as such for the first time in the late 4th century Athenian orators Dinarch and Hypereides at the beginning of the Hellenistic era 9 In these early formulations the anatomical detail of the body politic was relatively limited Greek thinkers typically confined themselves to distinguishing the ruler as head of the body and comparing political stasis that is crises of the state to biological disease 10 The image of the body politic occupied a central place in the political thought of the Roman Republic and the Romans were the first to develop the anatomy of the body in full detail endowing it with nerves blood breath limbs and organs 11 In its origins the concept was particularly connected to a politicised version of Aesop s fable of The Belly and the Members told in relation to the first secessio plebis the temporary departure of the plebeian order from Rome in 495 93 BC 12 13 On the account of the Roman historian Livy a senator explained the situation to the plebeians by a metaphor the various members of the Roman body had become angry that the stomach the patricians consumed their labours while providing nothing in return However upon their secession they became feeble and realised that the stomach s digestion had provided them vital energy Convinced by this story the plebeians returned to Rome and the Roman body was made whole and functional This legend formed a paradigm for nearly all surviving republican discourse of the body politic 12 Late republican orators developed the image further comparing attacks on Roman institutions to mutilations of the republic s body During the First Triumvirate in 59 BC Cicero described the Roman state as dying of a new sort of disease 14 Lucan s Pharsalia written in the early imperial era in the 60s AD abounded in this kind of imagery Depicting the dictator Sulla as a surgeon out of control who had butchered the Roman body politic in the process of cutting out its putrefied limbs Lucan used vivid organic language to portray the decline of the Roman Republic as a literal process of decay its seas and rivers becoming choked with blood and gore 15 Medieval usage Edit The metaphor of the body politic remained in use after the fall of the Western Roman Empire 8 The Neoplatonist Islamic philosopher al Farabi known in the West as Alpharabius discussed the image in his work The Perfect State c 940 stating The excellent city resembles the perfect and healthy body all of whose limbs cooperate to make the life of the animal perfect 16 John of Salisbury gave it a definitive Latin high medieval form in his Policraticus around 1159 the king was the body s head the priest was the soul the councillors were the heart the eyes ears and tongue were the magistrates of the law one hand the army held a weapon the other without a weapon was the realm s justice The body s feet were the common people Each member of the body had its vocation and each was beholden to work in harmony for the benefit of the whole body 17 In the Late Middle Ages the concept of the corporation a legal person made up of a group of real individuals gave the idea of a body politic judicial significance 18 The corporation had emerged in imperial Roman law under the name universitas and a formulation of the concept attributed to Ulpian was collected in the 6th century Digest of Justinian I during the early Byzantine era 19 The Digest along with the other parts of Justinian s Corpus Juris Civilis became the bedrock of medieval civil law upon its recovery and annotation by the glossators beginning in the 11th century 20 It remained for the glossators 13th century successors the commentators especially Baldus de Ubaldis to develop the idea of the corporation as a persona ficta a fictive person and apply the concept to human societies as a whole 18 The imperial eagle in Dante s Paradiso depicted by Giovanni di Paolo in the 1440s Where his jurist predecessor Bartolus of Saxoferrato conceived the corporation in essentially legal terms Baldus expressly connected the corporation theory to the ancient biological and political concept of the body politic For Baldus not only was man in Aristotelian terms a political animal but the whole populus the body of the people formed a type of political animal in itself a populus has government as part of its existence just as every animal is ruled by its own spirit and soul 21 Baldus equated the body politic with the respublica the state or realm stating that it cannot die and for this reason it is said that it has no heir because it always lives on in itself 22 From here the image of the body politic became prominent in the medieval imagination In Canto XVIII of his Paradiso for instance Dante writing in the early 14th century presents the Roman Empire as a corporate body in the form of an imperial eagle its body made of souls 23 The French court writer Christine de Pizan discussed the concept at length in her Book of the Body Politic 1407 24 The idea of the body politic rendered in legal terms through corporation theory also drew natural comparison to the theological concept of the church as a corpus mysticum the mystical body of Christ The concept of the people as a corpus mysticum also featured in Baldus 25 and the idea that the realm of France was a corpus mysticum formed an important part of late medieval French jurisprudence Jean de Terrevermeille fr around 1418 19 described the French laws of succession as established by the whole civic or mystical body of the realm and the Parlement of Paris in 1489 proclaimed itself a mystical body composed of both ecclesiastics and laymen representing the body of the king 26 From at least the 14th century the doctrine developed that the French kings were mystically married to the body politic at the coronation of Henry II in 1547 he was said to have solemnly married his realm 27 The English jurist John Fortescue also invoked the mystical body in his De Laudibus Legum Angliae c 1470 just as a physical body is held together by the nerves the mystical body of the realm is held together by the law and Just as the physical body grows out of the embryo regulated by one head so does there issue from the people the kingdom which exists as a corpus mysticum governed by one man as head 28 The king s body politic Edit In England Edit In Tudor and Stuart England the concept of the body politic was given a peculiar additional significance through the idea of the king s two bodies the doctrine discussed by the German American medievalist Ernst Kantorowicz in his eponymous work This legal doctrine held that the monarch had two bodies the physical king body natural and the immortal King body politic Upon the demise of an individual king his body natural fell away but the body politic lived on 29 This was an indigenous development of English law without a precise equivalent in the rest of Europe 30 Extending the identification of the body politic as a corporation English jurists argued that the Crown was a corporation sole a corporation made up of one body politic that was at the same time the body of the realm and its parliamentary estates and also the body of the royal dignity itself two concepts of the body politic that were conflated and fused 31 Elizabethan jurists held that the immaturity of Edward VI s body natural was expunged by his body politic The development of the doctrine of the king s two bodies can be traced in the Reports of Edmund Plowden In the 1561 Case of the Duchy of Lancaster which concerned whether an earlier gift of land made by Edward VI could be voided on account of his nonage that is his immaturity the judges held that it could not the king s Body politic which is annexed to his Body natural takes away the Imbecility of his Body natural 32 The king s body politic then that cannot be seen or handled annexes the body natural and wipes away all its defects 33 What was more the body politic rendered the king immortal as an individual as the judges in the case Hill v Grange argued in 1556 once the king had made an act he as King never dies but the King in which Name it has Relation to him does ever continue thus they held Henry VIII was still alive a decade after his physical death 29 The doctrine of the two bodies could serve to limit the powers of the real king When Edward Coke Chief Justice of the Common Pleas at the time reported the way in which judges had differentiated the bodies in 1608 he noted that it was the natural body of the king that was created by God the politic body by contrast was framed by the policy of man 34 In the Case of Prohibitions of the same year Coke denied the king in his own person any right to administer justice or order arrests 35 Finally in its declaration of 27 May 1642 shortly before the start of the English Civil War Parliament drew on the theory to invoke the powers of the body politic of Charles I against his body natural 36 stating What they Parliament do herein hath the Stamp of Royal Authority although His Majesty seduced by evil Counsel do in His own Person oppose or interrupt the same For the King s Supreme Power and Royal Pleasure is exercised and declared in this High Court of Law and Council after a more eminent and obligatory manner than it can be by any personal Act or Resolution of His Own 37 The 18th century jurist William Blackstone in Book I of his Commentaries on the Laws of England 1765 summarised the doctrine of the king s body politic as it subsequently developed after the Restoration the king in his political capacity manifests absolute perfection he can do no wrong nor even is he capable of thinking wrong he can have no defect and is never in law a minor or under age Indeed Blackstone says if an heir to the throne should accede while attainted of treason or felony his assumption of the crown would purge the attainder ipso facto The king manifests absolute immortality Henry Edward or George may die but the king survives them all 38 Soon after the appearance of the Commentaries however Jeremy Bentham mounted an extensive attack on Blackstone which the historian Quentin Skinner describes as almost lethal to the theory legal fictions like the body politic Bentham argued were conducive to royal absolutism and should be entirely avoided in law Bentham s position dominated later British legal thinking and though aspects of the theory of the body politic would survive in subsequent jurisprudence the idea of the Crown as a corporation sole was widely critiqued 39 In the late 19th century Frederic William Maitland revived the legal discourse of the king s two bodies arguing that the concept of the Crown as corporation sole had originated from the amalgamation of medieval civil law with the law of church property 40 He proposed in contrast to view the Crown as an ordinary corporation aggregate that is a corporation of many people with a view to describing the legal personhood of the state 41 In France Edit A related but contrasting concept in France was the doctrine termed by Sarah Hanley the king s one body summarised by Jean Bodin in his own 1576 pronouncement that the king never dies 42 Rather than distinguishing the immortal body politic from the mortal body natural of the king as in the English theory the French doctrine conflated the two arguing that the Salic law had established a single king body politic and natural that constantly regenerated through the biological reproduction of the royal line 43 The body politic on this account was biological and necessarily male and 15th century French jurists such as Jean Juvenal des Ursins argued on this basis for the exclusion of female heirs to the crown since they argued the king of France was a virile office 44 In the ancien regime the king s heir was held to assimilate the body politic of the old king in a physical transfer of corporeality upon his accession 45 In the United States Edit James I in the second charter for Virginia as well as both the Plymouth and Massachusetts Charter grant body politic 46 47 48 Hobbesian state theory Edit Thomas Hobbes c 1669 70 Aside from the doctrine of the king s two bodies the conventional image of the whole of the realm as a body politic had also remained in use in Stuart England James I compared the office of the king to the office of the head towards the body 49 Upon the outbreak of the English Civil War in 1642 however parliamentarians such as William Bridge put forward the argument that the ruling power belonged originally to the whole people or body politicke who could revoke it from the monarch 50 The execution of Charles I in 1649 made necessary a radical revision of the whole concept 51 In 1651 Thomas Hobbes s Leviathan made a decisive contribution to this effect reviving the concept while endowing it with new features Against the parliamentarians Hobbes maintained that sovereignty was absolute and the head could certainly not be of lesse power than the body of the people against the royal absolutists however he developed the idea of a social contract emphasising that the body politic Leviathan the mortal god was fictional and artificial rather than natural derived from an original decision by the people to constitute a sovereign 52 53 Hobbes s theory of the body politic exercised an important influence on subsequent political thinkers who both repeated and modified it Republican partisans of the Commonwealth presented alternative figurations of the metaphor in defence of the parliamentarian model James Harrington in his 1656 Commonwealth of Oceana argued that the delivery of a Model Government is no less than political Anatomy it must imbrace all those Muscles Nerves Arterys and Bones which are necessary to any Function of a well order d Commonwealth Invoking William Harvey s recent discovery of the circulatory system Harrington presented the body politic as a dynamic system of political circulation comparing his ideal bicameral legislature for example to the ventricles of the human heart In contrast to Hobbes the head was once more dependent on the people the execution of the law must follow the law itself so that Leviathan may see that the hand or sword that executeth the Law is in it and not above it 54 In Germany Samuel von Pufendorf recapitulated Hobbes s explanation of the origin of the state as a social contract but extended his notion of personhood to argue that the state must be a specifically moral person with a rational nature and not simply coercive power 55 In the 18th century Hobbes s theory of the state as an artificial body politic gained wide acceptance both in Britain and continental Europe 56 Thomas Pownall later the British governor of Massachusetts and a proponent of American liberty drew on Hobbes s theory in his 1752 Principles of Polity to argue that the whole Body politic should be conceived as one Person states were distinct Persons and independent 57 At around the same time the Swiss jurist Emer de Vattel pronounced that states are bodies politic moral persons with their own understanding and will a statement that would become accepted international law 58 The tension between organic understandings of the body politic and theories emphasizing its artificial character formed a theme in English political debates in this period Writing in 1780 during the American Revolutionary War the British reformist John Cartwright emphasised the artificial and immortal character of the body politic in order to refute the use of biological analogies in conservative rhetoric Arguing that it was better conceived as a machine operating by the due action and re action of the springs of the constitution than a human body he termed the body politic a careless figurative expression It is not corporeal not formed from the dust of the earth It is purely intellectual and its life spring is truth 59 Modern law EditThe English term body politic is sometimes used in modern legal contexts to describe a type of legal person typically the state itself or an entity connected to it A body politic is a type of taxable legal person in British law for example 60 and likewise a class of legal person in Indian law 61 62 In the United States a municipal corporation is considered a body politic as opposed to a private body corporate 63 The U S Supreme Court affirmed the theory of the state as an artificial body politic in the 1851 case Cotton v United States declaring that every sovereign State is of necessity a body politic or artificial person and as such capable of making contracts and holding property both real and personal and differentiated the United States powers as a sovereign from its rights as a body politic 64 See also EditSocial organism the concept in sociology Volkskorper the German national body Lex animata the king as the living law Kokutai a related Japanese concept Royal weReferences Edit Kenneth Olwig 2002 Landscape nature and the body politic University of Wisconsin Press p 87 ISBN 978 0 299 17424 8 The frontispiece to Thomas Hobbes s Leviathan is a particularly famous example of the depiction of the body politic Jonathan Harris 1998 Foreign bodies and the body politic discourses of social pathology in early modern England Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 59405 9 a b c Musolff Andreas 2017 Metaphor and Cultural Cognition In Sharifian Farzad ed Advances in Cultural Linguistics Singapore Springer Nature pp 328 29 ISBN 978 9 811 04055 9 Kantorowicz Ernst H 2016 The King s Two Bodies A Study in Mediaeval Political Theology Princeton Classics ed Princeton Princeton University Press pp 207 208 ISBN 978 0 691 16923 1 de Baecque Antoine 1997 The Body Politic Corporeal Metaphor in Revolutionary France 1770 1800 Trans Charlotte Mandell Stanford CA Stanford University Press p xv ISBN 978 0 8047 2817 1 Dobski Bernard J Gish Dustin 2013 Dobski Bernard J Gish Dustin eds Shakespeare and the Body Politic Plymouth Lexington Books p 6 ISBN 978 0 739 17095 3 Brock Roger 2013 Greek Political Imagery from Homer to Aristotle London amp New York Bloomsbury Academic p 69 ISBN 978 1 472 50218 6 a b MacKinnon Patricia L 1988 The analogy of the body politic in St Augustine Dante Petrarch and Ariosto PhD University of California Santa Cruz p 4 Brock 2013 p 70 Brock 2013 pp 70 71 Walters Brian 2020 The Deaths of the Republic Imagery of the Body Politic in Ciceronian Rome Oxford Oxford University Press p 1 ISBN 978 0 198 83957 6 a b Walters 2020 pp 7 9 Rollo Koster Joelle 2010 Body Politic In Bevir Mark ed Encyclopedia of Political Theory Vol 1 Thousand Oaks SAGE p 134 ISBN 978 1 412 95865 3 Walters 2020 pp 75 77 Walters Brian 2019 Sulla s Phthiriasis and the Republican Body Politic Mnemosyne 72 6 964 doi 10 1163 1568525X 12342610 S2CID 211665064 Rosenwein Barbara H ed 2018 Reading the Middle Ages Sources from Europe Byzantium and the Islamic World 3rd ed Toronto University of Toronto Press p 206 ISBN 978 1 442 63674 3 Dumolyn Jan 2006 Justice Equity and the Common Good The State Ideology of the Councillors of the Burgundian Dukes In Boulton D Arcy Jonathan Dacre Veenstra Jan R eds The Ideology of Burgundy The Promotion of National Consciousness 1364 1565 Leiden Brill pp 12 13 ISBN 978 9 004 15359 2 a b Canning Joseph 1996 A History of Medieval Political Thought 300 1450 Abingdon Routledge p 172 ISBN 978 0 415 39415 4 Duff Patrick W 1938 Personality in Roman Private Law Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 37 Canning Joseph 2011 Civil Roman Law In Lagerlund Henrik ed Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy Philosophy Between 500 and 1500 Dordrecht Springer p 221 Canning Joseph 2011 Ideas of Power in the Late Middle Ages 1296 1417 Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 145 46 ISBN 978 1 107 01141 0 Genet Jean Philippe 1998 Politics theory and practice In Allmand Christopher ed The New Cambridge Medieval History Volume VII c 1415 c 1500 Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 18 19 ISBN 978 0 521 38296 0 Monateri Pier Giuseppe 2018 Dominus Mundi Political Sublime and the World Order Oxford Hart p 52 ISBN 978 1 509 91176 9 de Pizan Christine 1994 Langdon Forhan Kate ed The Book of the Body Politic Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp xviii xx ISBN 978 0 521 42259 8 Kantorowicz 2016 p 210 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 219 20 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 221 22 Kantorowicz 2016 p 224 a b Kantorowicz 2016 p 13 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 20 446 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 448 49 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 9 10 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 4 n5 11 Kantorowicz 2016 pp 14 423 n362 Hasanbegovic Jasminka 2021 On the Un Changing Judge Icons and Their Creators On Deborah Coke and Montesquieu Posner and Barak and Some Others In Chiassoni Pier Spaic Bojan eds Judges and Adjudication in Constitutional Democracies A View from Legal Realism Cham Springer p 76 ISBN 978 3 030 58185 5 Kantorowicz 2016 p 21 Parliament of England 1642 A Declaration of the Lords and Commons in Parliament concerning his Maiesties Proclamation the 27 of May 1642 London William Gaye p 4 via Early English Books Online Spelling modernised Blackstone William 1765 Commentaries on the Laws of England Oxford Clarendon Press pp 238 42 McLean Janet 2012 Searching for the State in British Legal Thought Competing Conceptions of the Public Sphere Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 4 ISBN 978 1 107 02248 5 George Garnett 1996 The Origins of the Crown Proceedings of the British Academy 89 171 214 McLean 2012 pp 4 5 Hanley Sarah 1997 Mapping Rulership in the French Body Politic Political Identity Public Law and the King s One Body Historical Reflections 23 2 134 JSTOR 41299087 Hanley 1997 p 136 Hanley 1997 p 140 de Baecque 1997 pp 100 102 The Second Charter of Virginia May 23 1609 18 December 1998 Charter of the Colony of New Plymouth Granted to William Bradford and His Associates 1629 18 December 1998 The Charter of Massachusetts Bay 1629 18 December 1998 Attie Katherine Bootle 2008 Re Membering the Body Politic Hobbes and the Construction of Civic Immortality ELH 75 3 497 530 doi 10 1353 elh 0 0011 JSTOR 27654624 S2CID 162034742 Skinner Quentin 2009 A Genealogy of the Modern State PDF Proceedings of the British Academy 162 340 Attie 2008 p 498 Skinner 2009 pp 342 43 Attie 2008 pp 500 502 Attie 2008 pp 507 508 Skinner Quentin 2018 From Humanism to Hobbes Studies in Rhetoric and Politics Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 365 66 ISBN 978 1 107 12885 9 Skinner 2018 p 371 Skinner 2018 p 370 Skinner 2009 p 352 Ihalainen Pasi 2009 Towards an Immortal Political Body The State Machine in Eighteenth Century English Political Discourse Contributions to the History of Concepts 5 34 35 doi 10 1163 187465609X430845 Harris Peter 2013 Corporate Tax Law Structure Policy and Practice Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 21 ISBN 978 1 107 03353 5 Bhattacharya Ananya 7 June 2019 Birds to holy rivers A list of everything India considers legal persons Quartz Retrieved 24 May 2021 Kanti Ghosh Sumit 2023 05 18 Body Dress and Symbolic Capital Multifaceted Presentation of PUGREE in Colonial Governance of British India TEXTILE 1 32 doi 10 1080 14759756 2023 2208502 ISSN 1475 9756 Fippinger Robert A 1993 The Securities Law of Public Finance 2nd ed Practising Law Institute p 2 n6 ISBN 978 0 872 24054 4 Cotton v United States 52 U S 229 1851 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Body politic amp oldid 1157566989, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.