fbpx
Wikipedia

Aleph number

In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets that can be well-ordered. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor[1] and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter aleph ().[2][a]

Aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null, the smallest infinite cardinal number

The cardinality of the natural numbers is (read aleph-nought or aleph-zero; the term aleph-null is also sometimes used), the next larger cardinality of a well-orderable set is aleph-one then and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define a cardinal number for every ordinal number as described below.

The concept and notation are due to Georg Cantor,[5] who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities.

The aleph numbers differ from the infinity () commonly found in algebra and calculus, in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets, while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the real number line (applied to a function or sequence that "diverges to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or as an extreme point of the extended real number line.

Aleph-nought

  (aleph-nought, also aleph-zero or aleph-null) is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is an infinite cardinal. The set of all finite ordinals, called   or   (where   is the lowercase Greek letter omega), has cardinality  . A set has cardinality   if and only if it is countably infinite, that is, there is a bijection (one-to-one correspondence) between it and the natural numbers. Examples of such sets are

These infinite ordinals:           and   are among the countably infinite sets.[6] For example, the sequence (with ordinality  ) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers

 

is an ordering of the set (with cardinality  ) of positive integers.

If the axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the axiom of choice) holds, then   is smaller than any other infinite cardinal.

Aleph-one

  is the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinal numbers, called   or sometimes  . This   is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an uncountable set. Therefore,   is distinct from  . The definition of   implies (in ZF, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between   and  . If the axiom of choice is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered, and thus   is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. Using the axiom of choice, one can show one of the most useful properties of the set  : any countable subset of   has an upper bound in  . (This follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable – one of the most common applications of the axiom of choice.) This fact is analogous to the situation in   : every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and finite unions of finite sets are finite.

 is actually a useful concept, if somewhat exotic-sounding. An example application is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e.g. Borel hierarchy). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (vector spaces, groups, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations – sums, products, and the like. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible countable unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of  .

Continuum hypothesis

The cardinality of the set of real numbers (cardinality of the continuum) is   It cannot be determined from ZFC (Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory augmented with the axiom of choice) where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy, but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis, CH, is equivalent to the identity

 [7]

The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers.[8] CH is independent of ZFC: it can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that ZFC is consistent). That CH is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by Kurt Gödel in 1940, when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC. That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by Paul Cohen in 1963, when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC – by the (then-novel) method of forcing.[7]

Aleph-omega

Aleph-omega is

 

where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted ω. That is, the cardinal number   is the least upper bound of

 

  is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers; for any positive integer n we can consistently assume that   and moreover it is possible to assume   is as large as we like. We are only forced to avoid setting it to certain special cardinals with cofinality   meaning there is an unbounded function from   to it (see Easton's theorem).

Aleph-α for general α

To define   for arbitrary ordinal number   we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number   the next larger well-ordered cardinal   (if the axiom of choice holds, this is the next larger cardinal).

We can then define the aleph numbers as follows:

 
 

and for λ, an infinite limit ordinal,

 

The α-th infinite initial ordinal is written  . Its cardinality is written   In ZFC, the aleph function   is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals.[9]

Fixed points of omega

For any ordinal α we have

 

In many cases   is strictly greater than α. For example, for any successor ordinal α this holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence

 

Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function.[10] This can be shown in ZFC as follows. Suppose   is a weakly inaccessible cardinal. If   were a successor ordinal, then   would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible. If   were a limit ordinal less than   then its cofinality (and thus the cofinality of  ) would be less than   and so   would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible. Thus   and consequently   which makes it a fixed point.

Role of axiom of choice

The cardinality of any infinite ordinal number is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its initial ordinal. Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well-orderable.

Each finite set is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.

The assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent over ZF to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.

When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define card(S) to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank. This has the property that card(S) = card(T) if and only if S and T have the same cardinality. (The set card(S) does not have the same cardinality of S in general, but all its elements do.)

See also

Notes

  1. ^ In older mathematics books, the letter aleph is often printed upside down by accident – for example, in Sierpiński (1958)[3]: 402  the letter aleph appears both the right way up and upside down – partly because a monotype matrix for aleph was mistakenly constructed the wrong way up.[4]

Citations

  1. ^ "Aleph". Encyclopedia of Mathematics.
  2. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Aleph". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-12.
  3. ^ Sierpiński, Wacław (1958). Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers. Polska Akademia Nauk Monografie Matematyczne. Vol. 34. Warsaw, PL: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. MR 0095787.
  4. ^ Swanson, Ellen; O'Sean, Arlene Ann; Schleyer, Antoinette Tingley (1999) [1979]. Mathematics into type: Copy editing and proofreading of mathematics for editorial assistants and authors (updated ed.). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society. p. 16. ISBN 0-8218-0053-1. MR 0553111.
  5. ^ Miller, Jeff. "Earliest uses of symbols of set theory and logic". jeff560.tripod.com. Retrieved 2016-05-05; who quotes Dauben, Joseph Warren (1990). Georg Cantor: His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite. ISBN 9780691024479. His new numbers deserved something unique. ... Not wishing to invent a new symbol himself, he chose the aleph, the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet ... the aleph could be taken to represent new beginnings ...
  6. ^ Jech, Thomas (2003). Set Theory. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag.
  7. ^ a b Szudzik, Mattew (31 July 2018). "Continuum Hypothesis". Wolfram Mathworld. Wolfram Web Resources. Retrieved 15 August 2018.
  8. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Continuum Hypothesis". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-12.
  9. ^ aleph numbers at PlanetMath.
  10. ^ Harris, Kenneth A. (April 6, 2009). (PDF). Department of Mathematics. kaharris.org. Intro to Set Theory. University of Michigan. Math 582. Archived from the original (PDF) on March 4, 2016. Retrieved September 1, 2012.

External links

aleph, number, redirects, here, letter, aleph, other, uses, aleph, disambiguation, alef, disambiguation, mathematics, particularly, theory, aleph, numbers, sequence, numbers, used, represent, cardinality, size, infinite, sets, that, well, ordered, they, were, . ℵ redirects here For the letter see Aleph For other uses see Aleph disambiguation and Alef disambiguation In mathematics particularly in set theory the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality or size of infinite sets that can be well ordered They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor 1 and are named after the symbol he used to denote them the Hebrew letter aleph ℵ displaystyle aleph 2 a Aleph nought aleph zero or aleph null the smallest infinite cardinal number The cardinality of the natural numbers is ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 read aleph nought or aleph zero the term aleph null is also sometimes used the next larger cardinality of a well orderable set is aleph one ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 then ℵ 2 displaystyle aleph 2 and so on Continuing in this manner it is possible to define a cardinal number ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha for every ordinal number a displaystyle alpha as described below The concept and notation are due to Georg Cantor 5 who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities The aleph numbers differ from the infinity displaystyle infty commonly found in algebra and calculus in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the real number line applied to a function or sequence that diverges to infinity or increases without bound or as an extreme point of the extended real number line Contents 1 Aleph nought 2 Aleph one 3 Continuum hypothesis 4 Aleph omega 5 Aleph a for general a 6 Fixed points of omega 7 Role of axiom of choice 8 See also 9 Notes 10 Citations 11 External linksAleph nought Editℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 aleph nought also aleph zero or aleph null is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers and is an infinite cardinal The set of all finite ordinals called w displaystyle omega or w 0 displaystyle omega 0 where w displaystyle omega is the lowercase Greek letter omega has cardinality ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 A set has cardinality ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 if and only if it is countably infinite that is there is a bijection one to one correspondence between it and the natural numbers Examples of such sets are the set of all integers any infinite subset of the integers such as the set of all square numbers or the set of all prime numbers the set of all rational numbers the set of all constructible numbers in the geometric sense the set of all algebraic numbers the set of all computable numbers the set of all binary strings of finite length and the set of all finite subsets of any given countably infinite set These infinite ordinals w displaystyle omega w 1 displaystyle omega 1 w 2 displaystyle omega cdot 2 w 2 displaystyle omega 2 w w displaystyle omega omega and e 0 displaystyle varepsilon 0 are among the countably infinite sets 6 For example the sequence with ordinality w 2 displaystyle omega cdot 2 of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers 1 3 5 7 9 2 4 6 8 10 displaystyle 1 3 5 7 9 2 4 6 8 10 is an ordering of the set with cardinality ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 of positive integers If the axiom of countable choice a weaker version of the axiom of choice holds then ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 is smaller than any other infinite cardinal Aleph one EditThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed October 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Aleph One redirects here For other uses see Aleph One disambiguation ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 is the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinal numbers called w 1 displaystyle omega 1 or sometimes W displaystyle Omega This w 1 displaystyle omega 1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones so it is an uncountable set Therefore ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 is distinct from ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 The definition of ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 implies in ZF Zermelo Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice that no cardinal number is between ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 and ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 If the axiom of choice is used it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered and thus ℵ 1 displaystyle aleph 1 is the second smallest infinite cardinal number Using the axiom of choice one can show one of the most useful properties of the set w 1 displaystyle omega 1 any countable subset of w 1 displaystyle omega 1 has an upper bound in w 1 displaystyle omega 1 This follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable one of the most common applications of the axiom of choice This fact is analogous to the situation in ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number and finite unions of finite sets are finite w 1 displaystyle omega 1 is actually a useful concept if somewhat exotic sounding An example application is closing with respect to countable operations e g trying to explicitly describe the s algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets see e g Borel hierarchy This is harder than most explicit descriptions of generation in algebra vector spaces groups etc because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations sums products and the like The process involves defining for each countable ordinal via transfinite induction a set by throwing in all possible countable unions and complements and taking the union of all that over all of w 1 displaystyle omega 1 Continuum hypothesis EditMain article Continuum hypothesis See also Beth number The cardinality of the set of real numbers cardinality of the continuum is 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 It cannot be determined from ZFC Zermelo Fraenkel set theory augmented with the axiom of choice where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis CH is equivalent to the identity 2 ℵ 0 ℵ 1 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 aleph 1 7 The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers 8 CH is independent of ZFC it can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system provided that ZFC is consistent That CH is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by Kurt Godel in 1940 when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by Paul Cohen in 1963 when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC by the then novel method of forcing 7 Aleph omega EditAleph omega is ℵ w sup ℵ n n w sup ℵ n n 0 1 2 displaystyle aleph omega sup aleph n n in omega sup aleph n n in left 0 1 2 dots right where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted w That is the cardinal number ℵ w displaystyle aleph omega is the least upper bound of ℵ n n 0 1 2 displaystyle left aleph n n in left 0 1 2 dots right right ℵ w displaystyle aleph omega is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers for any positive integer n we can consistently assume that 2 ℵ 0 ℵ n displaystyle 2 aleph 0 aleph n and moreover it is possible to assume 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 is as large as we like We are only forced to avoid setting it to certain special cardinals with cofinality ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 meaning there is an unbounded function from ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 to it see Easton s theorem Aleph a for general a EditTo define ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha for arbitrary ordinal number a displaystyle alpha we must define the successor cardinal operation which assigns to any cardinal number r displaystyle rho the next larger well ordered cardinal r displaystyle rho if the axiom of choice holds this is the next larger cardinal We can then define the aleph numbers as follows ℵ 0 w displaystyle aleph 0 omega ℵ a 1 ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha 1 aleph alpha and for l an infinite limit ordinal ℵ l b lt l ℵ b displaystyle aleph lambda bigcup beta lt lambda aleph beta The a th infinite initial ordinal is written w a displaystyle omega alpha Its cardinality is written ℵ a displaystyle aleph alpha In ZFC the aleph function ℵ displaystyle aleph is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals 9 Fixed points of omega EditFor any ordinal a we have a w a displaystyle alpha leq omega alpha In many cases w a displaystyle omega alpha is strictly greater than a For example for any successor ordinal a this holds There are however some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function because of the fixed point lemma for normal functions The first such is the limit of the sequence w w w w w w displaystyle omega omega omega omega omega omega ldots Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function 10 This can be shown in ZFC as follows Suppose k ℵ l displaystyle kappa aleph lambda is a weakly inaccessible cardinal If l displaystyle lambda were a successor ordinal then ℵ l displaystyle aleph lambda would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible If l displaystyle lambda were a limit ordinal less than k displaystyle kappa then its cofinality and thus the cofinality of ℵ l displaystyle aleph lambda would be less than k displaystyle kappa and so k displaystyle kappa would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible Thus l k displaystyle lambda geq kappa and consequently l k displaystyle lambda kappa which makes it a fixed point Role of axiom of choice EditThe cardinality of any infinite ordinal number is an aleph number Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal The least of these is its initial ordinal Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well orderable Each finite set is well orderable but does not have an aleph as its cardinality The assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent over ZF to the existence of a well ordering of every set which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice ZFC set theory which includes the axiom of choice implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality i e is equinumerous with its initial ordinal and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well ordered The method of Scott s trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF For example one can define card S to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank This has the property that card S card T if and only if S and T have the same cardinality The set card S does not have the same cardinality of S in general but all its elements do See also EditBeth number Gimel function Regular cardinal Transfinite number Ordinal numberNotes Edit In older mathematics books the letter aleph is often printed upside down by accident for example in Sierpinski 1958 3 402 the letter aleph appears both the right way up and upside down partly because a monotype matrix for aleph was mistakenly constructed the wrong way up 4 Citations Edit Aleph Encyclopedia of Mathematics Weisstein Eric W Aleph mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2020 08 12 Sierpinski Waclaw 1958 Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers Polska Akademia Nauk Monografie Matematyczne Vol 34 Warsaw PL Panstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe MR 0095787 Swanson Ellen O Sean Arlene Ann Schleyer Antoinette Tingley 1999 1979 Mathematics into type Copy editing and proofreading of mathematics for editorial assistants and authors updated ed Providence RI American Mathematical Society p 16 ISBN 0 8218 0053 1 MR 0553111 Miller Jeff Earliest uses of symbols of set theory and logic jeff560 tripod com Retrieved 2016 05 05 who quotes Dauben Joseph Warren 1990 Georg Cantor His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite ISBN 9780691024479 His new numbers deserved something unique Not wishing to invent a new symbol himself he chose the aleph the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet the aleph could be taken to represent new beginnings Jech Thomas 2003 Set Theory Springer Monographs in Mathematics Berlin New York Springer Verlag a b Szudzik Mattew 31 July 2018 Continuum Hypothesis Wolfram Mathworld Wolfram Web Resources Retrieved 15 August 2018 Weisstein Eric W Continuum Hypothesis mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2020 08 12 aleph numbers at PlanetMath Harris Kenneth A April 6 2009 Lecture 31 PDF Department of Mathematics kaharris org Intro to Set Theory University of Michigan Math 582 Archived from the original PDF on March 4 2016 Retrieved September 1 2012 External links Edit Aleph zero Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Weisstein Eric W Aleph 0 MathWorld Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Aleph number amp oldid 1129613826 Aleph one, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.