fbpx
Wikipedia

The Phenomenology of Spirit

The Phenomenology of Spirit (German: Phänomenologie des Geistes) is the most widely-discussed philosophical work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel; its German title can be translated as either The Phenomenology of Spirit or The Phenomenology of Mind. Hegel described the work, published in 1807, as an "exposition of the coming to be of knowledge".[1] This is explicated through a necessary self-origination and dissolution of "the various shapes of spirit as stations on the way through which spirit becomes pure knowledge".[1]

The Phenomenology of Spirit
Title page of the first edition
AuthorGeorg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
Original titlePhänomenologie des Geistes
TranslatorJames Black Baillie
CountryGermany
LanguageGerman
SubjectPhilosophy
Published1807
Published in English
1910
Media typePrint
OCLC929308074
193
LC ClassB2928 .E5
Original text
Phänomenologie des Geistes at Project Gutenberg
TranslationThe Phenomenology of Spirit at University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign

The book marked a significant development in German idealism after Immanuel Kant. Focusing on topics in metaphysics, epistemology, ontology, ethics, history, religion, perception, consciousness, existence, logic and political philosophy, it is where Hegel develops his concepts of dialectic (including the lord-bondsman dialectic), absolute idealism, ethical life and Aufhebung. It had a profound effect in Western philosophy, and "has been praised and blamed for the development of existentialism, communism, fascism, death of God theology and historicist nihilism".[2]

Historical context edit

 
"Hegel and Napoleon in Jena" (illustration from Harper's Magazine, 1895)

Hegel was putting the finishing touches to this book as Napoleon engaged Prussian troops on October 14, 1806, in the Battle of Jena on a plateau outside the city. On the day before the battle, Napoleon entered the city of Jena. Later that same day, Hegel wrote a letter to his friend, the theologian Friedrich Immanuel Niethammer:

I saw the Emperor – this world-soul – riding out of the city on reconnaissance. It is indeed a wonderful sensation to see such an individual, who, concentrated here at a single point, astride a horse, reaches out over the world and masters it ... this extraordinary man, whom it is impossible not to admire.[3]

In 2000, Terry Pinkard notes that Hegel's comment to Niethammer "is all the more striking since at that point he had already composed the crucial section of the Phenomenology in which he remarked that the Revolution had now officially passed to another land (Germany) that would complete 'in thought' what the Revolution had only partially accomplished in practice."[4]

Publication history edit

The Phenomenology of Spirit was published with the title “System of Science: First Part: The Phenomenology of Spirit”.[5] Some copies contained either "Science of the Experience of Consciousness", or "Science of the Phenomenology of Spirit" as a subtitle between the "Preface" and the "Introduction".[5] On its initial publication, the work was identified as Part One of a projected "System of Science", which would have contained the Science of Logic "and both the two real sciences of philosophy, the Philosophy of Nature and the Philosophy of Spirit”[6] as its second part. The Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, in its third section (Philosophy of Spirit), contains a second subsection (The Encyclopedia Phenomenology) that recounts in briefer and somewhat altered form the major themes of the original Phenomenology.

Structure edit

The book consists of a Preface (written after the rest was completed), an Introduction, and six major divisions (of greatly varying size).[a]

  • (A) Consciousness is divided into three chapters:
    • (I) Sensuous-Certainty,
    • (II) Perceiving, and
    • (III) Force and the Understanding.
  • (B) Self-Consciousness contains one chapter:
    • (IV) The Truth of Self-Certainty which contains a preliminary discussion of Life and Desire, followed by two subsections: (A) Self-Sufficiency and Non-Self-Sufficiency of Self-Consciousness; Mastery and Servitude and (B) Freedom of Self-Consciousness: Stoicism, Skepticism, and the Unhappy Consciousness. This section contains the dialectic of the lord and bondsman, which has been essential to the work of philosophers such as Frantz Fanon and Alexandre Kojève, among others.
  • (C), (AA) Reason contains one chapter:
    • (V) The Certainty and Truth of Reason which is divided into three chapters: (A) Observing Reason, (B) The Actualization of Rational Self-Consciousness Through Itself, and (C) Individuality, Which, to Itself, is Real in and for Itself.
  • (BB) Spirit contains one chapter:
    • (VI) Spirit or Geist which is again divided into three chapters: (A) True Spirit, Ethical Life, (B) Spirit Alienated from Itself: Cultural Formation, and (C) Spirit Certain of Itself: Morality.
  • (CC) Religion contains one chapter:
    • (VII) Religion, which is divided into three chapters: (A) Natural Religion, (B) The Art-Religion, and (C) Revealed Religion.
  • (DD) Absolute Knowing contains one chapter:
    • (VIII) Absolute Knowing.[b]

Due to its obscure nature and the many works by Hegel that followed its publication, even the structure or core theme of the book itself remains contested. First, Hegel wrote the book under close time constraints with little chance for revision (individual chapters were sent to the publisher before others were written). Furthermore, according to some readers, Hegel may have changed his conception of the project over the course of the writing. Secondly, the book abounds with both highly technical argument in philosophical language, and concrete examples, either imaginary or historical, of developments by people through different states of consciousness. The relationship between these is disputed: whether Hegel meant to prove claims about the development of world history, or simply used it for illustration; whether or not the more conventionally philosophical passages are meant to address specific historical and philosophical positions; and so forth.

Jean Hyppolite famously interpreted the work as a Bildungsroman that follows the progression of its protagonist, Spirit, through the history of consciousness,[9] a characterization that remains prevalent among literary theorists. However, others contest this literary interpretation and instead read the work as a "self-conscious reflective account"[10] that a society must give of itself in order to understand itself and therefore become reflective. Martin Heidegger saw it as the foundation of a larger "System of Science" that Hegel sought to develop,[11] while Alexandre Kojève saw it as akin to a "Platonic Dialogue ... between the great Systems of history."[12] It has also been called "a philosophical roller coaster ... with no more rhyme or reason for any particular transition than that it struck Hegel that such a transition might be fun or illuminating."[13]

Preface edit

The Preface to the text is a preamble to the scientific system and cognition in general. Paraphrased “on scientific cognition" in the table of contents, its intent is to offer a rough idea on scientific cognition, while at the same time aiming "to rid ourselves of a few forms which are only impediments to philosophical cognition".[14] As Hegel’s own announcement noted, it was to explain "what seems to him the need of philosophy in its present state; also about the presumption and mischief of the philosophical formulas that are currently degrading philosophy, and about what is altogether crucial in it and its study".[15] It can thus be seen as a heuristic attempt at creating the need of philosophy (in the present state) and of what philosophy itself in its present state needs. This involves an exposition on the content and standpoint of philosophy, i.e, the true shape of truth and the element of its existence, that is interspersed with polemics aimed at the presumption and mischief of philosophical formulas and what distinguishes it from that of any previous philosophy, especially that of his German Idealist predecessors (Kant, Fichte, and Schelling).[16]

The Hegelian method consists of actually examining consciousness' experience of both itself and of its objects and eliciting the contradictions and dynamic movement that come to light in looking at this experience. Hegel uses the phrase "pure looking at" (reines Zusehen) to describe this method. If consciousness just pays attention to what is actually present in itself and its relation to its objects, it will see that what looks like stable and fixed forms dissolve into a dialectical movement. Thus, philosophy, according to Hegel, cannot just set out arguments based on a flow of deductive reasoning. Rather, it must look at actual consciousness, as it really exists.

Hegel also argues strongly against the epistemological emphasis of modern philosophy from Descartes through Kant, which he describes as having to first establish the nature and criteria of knowledge prior to actually knowing anything, because this would imply an infinite regress, a foundationalism that Hegel maintains is self-contradictory and impossible. Rather, he maintains, one must examine actual knowing as it occurs in real knowledge processes. This is why Hegel uses the term "phenomenology". "Phenomenology" comes from the Greek word for "to appear", and the phenomenology of mind is thus the study of how consciousness or mind appears to itself. In Hegel's dynamic system, it is the study of the successive appearances of the mind to itself, because on examination each one dissolves into a later, more comprehensive and integrated form or structure of mind.

Introduction edit

Whereas the Preface was written after Hegel completed the Phenomenology, the Introduction was written beforehand.

In the Introduction, Hegel addresses the seeming paradox that people cannot evaluate their faculty of knowledge in terms of its ability to know the Absolute without first having a criterion for what the Absolute is, one that is superior to people's knowledge of the Absolute. Yet, people could only have such a criterion if they already had the improved knowledge that they seek.

To resolve this paradox, Hegel adopts a method whereby the knowing that is characteristic of a particular stage of consciousness is evaluated using the criterion presupposed by consciousness itself. At each stage, consciousness knows something, and at the same time distinguishes the object of that knowledge as different from what it knows. Hegel and his readers will simply "look on" while consciousness compares its actual knowledge of the object—what the object is "for consciousness"—with its criterion for what the object must be "in itself". One would expect that, when consciousness finds that its knowledge does not agree with its object, consciousness would adjust its knowledge to conform to its object. However, in a characteristic reversal, Hegel explains that under his method, the opposite occurs.

As just noted, consciousness' criterion for what the object should be is not supplied externally but rather by consciousness itself. Therefore, like its knowledge, the "object" that consciousness distinguishes from its knowledge is really just the object "for consciousness"—it is the object as envisioned by that stage of consciousness. Thus, in attempting to resolve the discord between knowledge and object, consciousness inevitably alters the object as well. In fact, the new "object" for consciousness is developed from consciousness' inadequate knowledge of the previous "object". Thus, what consciousness really does is to modify its "object" to conform to its knowledge. Then the cycle begins anew as consciousness attempts to examine what it knows about this new "object".

The reason for this reversal is that, for Hegel, the separation between consciousness and its object is no more real than consciousness' inadequate knowledge of that object. The knowledge is inadequate only because of that separation. At the end of the process, when the object has been fully "spiritualized" by successive cycles of consciousness' experience, consciousness will fully know the object and at the same time fully recognize that the object is none other than itself.

At each stage of development, Hegel, adds, "we" (Hegel and his readers) see this development of the new object out of the knowledge of the previous one, but the consciousness that they are observing does not. As far as it is concerned, it experiences the dissolution of its knowledge in a mass of contradictions, and the emergence of a new object for knowledge, without understanding how that new object has been born.

Important concepts edit

Hegelian dialectic edit

The famous dialectical process of thesis–antithesis–synthesis has been controversially attributed to Hegel.

Whoever looks for the stereotype of the allegedly Hegelian dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology will not find it. What one does find on looking at the table of contents is a very decided preference for triadic arrangements. ... But these many triads are not presented or deduced by Hegel as so many theses, antitheses, and syntheses. It is not by means of any dialectic of that sort that his thought moves up the ladder to absolute knowledge.

— Walter Kaufmann (1965). Hegel. Reinterpretation, Texts, and Commentary. p. 168.

Regardless of (ongoing) academic controversy regarding the significance of a unique dialectical method in Hegel's writings, it is true, as Professor Howard Kainz (1996) affirms, that there are "thousands of triads" in Hegel's writings. Importantly, instead of using the famous terminology that originated with Kant and was elaborated by J. G. Fichte, Hegel used an entirely different and more accurate terminology for dialectical (or as Hegel called them, "speculative") triads.

Hegel used two different sets of terms for his triads, namely, "abstract–negative–concrete" (especially in his Phenomenology of 1807), as well as "immediate–mediate–concrete" (especially in his Science of Logic of 1812), depending on the scope of his argumentation.

When one looks for these terms in his writings, one finds so many occurrences that it may become clear that Hegel employed the Kantian using a different terminology.

Hegel explained his change of terminology. The triad terms "abstract–negative–concrete" contain an implicit explanation for the flaws in Kant's terms. The first term, "thesis", deserves its anti-thesis simply because it is too abstract. The third term, "synthesis", has completed the triad, making it concrete and no longer abstract by absorbing the negative.

Sometimes Hegel used the terms "immediate–mediate–concrete" to describe his triads. The most abstract concepts are those that immediately present themselves to human consciousness. For example, the notion of Pure Being for Hegel was the most abstract concept of all. The negative of this infinite abstraction would require an entire Encyclopedia, building category by category, dialectically, until it culminated in the category of Absolute Mind or Spirit (since the German word Geist can mean either 'mind' or 'spirit').

Unfolding of species edit

Hegel describes a sequential progression from inanimate objects to animate creatures to human beings. This is frequently compared to Charles Darwin's evolutionary theory.[citation needed] However, unlike Darwin, Hegel thought that organisms had agency in choosing to develop along this progression by collaborating with other organisms.[17][18] Hegel understood this to be a linear process of natural development with a predetermined end. He viewed this end teleologically as its ultimate purpose and destiny.[17][19][20]

Criticism edit

Walter Kaufmann, on the question of organisation, argued that Hegel's arrangement, "over half a century before Darwin published his Origin of Species and impressed the idea of evolution on almost everybody's mind, was developmental."[21] The idea is supremely suggestive but, in the end, untenable according to Kaufmann: "The idea of arranging all significant points of view in such a single sequence, on a ladder that reaches from the crudest to the most mature, is as dazzling to contemplate as it is mad to try seriously to implement it".[22] While Kaufmann viewed Hegel as right in seeing that the way a view is reached is not necessarily external to the view itself, since, on the contrary, a knowledge of the development, including the prior positions through which a human being passed before adopting a position may make all the difference when it comes to comprehending his or her position, some aspects of the conception are still somewhat absurd and some of the details bizarre.[23] Kaufmann also remarks that the very table of contents of the Phenomenology may be said to "mirror confusion" and that "faults are so easy to find in it that it is not worth while to adduce heaps of them."[citation needed] However, he excuses Hegel since he understands that the author of the Phenomenology "finished the book under an immense strain".[24]

The feminist philosopher Kelly Oliver argues that Hegel’s discussion of women in The Phenomenology of Spirit undermines the entirety of the text. Oliver points out that for Hegel, every element of consciousness must be conceptualizable, but that in Hegel’s discussion of the family, woman is established as in principle unconceptualizable. Oliver writes that “unlike the master or slave, the feminine or woman does not contain the dormant seed of its opposite.” This means that Hegel’s feminine is nothing other than the negation of the masculine and as such it must be excluded from the story of masculine consciousness. Thus, Oliver argues, the Phenomenology of Spirit is a phenomenology of masculine consciousness; the universalist pretensions of the text are not achieved, as it leaves out the phenomenology of feminine consciousness.[25]

Referencing edit

The work is usually abbreviated as PdG (Phänomenologie des Geistes), followed by the pagination or paragraph number of the German original edition. It is also abbreviated as PS (The Phenomenology of Spirit) or as PM (The Phenomenology of Mind), followed by the pagination or paragraph number of the English translation used by each author.

English translations edit

  • G. W. F. Hegel: The Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by Peter Fuss and John Dobbins (University of Notre Dame Press, 2019)
  • Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Phenomenology of Spirit (Cambridge Hegel Translations), translated by Terry Pinkard (Cambridge University Press, 2018) ISBN 0-52185579-9
  • Hegel: The Phenomenology of Spirit: Translated with introduction and commentary, translated by Michael Inwood (Oxford University Press, 2018) ISBN 0-19879062-7
  • Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A. V. Miller with analysis of the text and foreword by J. N. Findlay (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) ISBN 0-19824597-1
  • Phenomenology of Mind, translated by J. B. Baillie (London: Harper & Row, 1967) Baillie (1872-1940) Baillie translation 1910.
  • Hegel's Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, translated with introduction, running commentary and notes by Yirmiyahu Yovel (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004) ISBN 0-69112052-8.
  • Texts and Commentary: Hegel's Preface to His System in a New Translation With Commentary on Facing Pages, and "Who Thinks Abstractly?", translated by Walter Kaufmann (South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977) ISBN 0-26801069-2.
  • "Introduction", "The Phenomenology of Spirit", translated by Kenley R. Dove, in Martin Heidegger, "Hegel's Concept of Experience" (New York: Harper & Row, 1970)
  • "Sense-Certainty", Chapter I, "The Phenomenology of Spirit", translated by Kenley R. Dove, "The Philosophical Forum", Vol. 32, No 4
  • "Stoicism", Chapter IV, B, "The Phenomenology of Spirit", translated by Kenley R. Dove, "The Philosophical Forum", Vol. 37, No 3
  • "Absolute Knowing", Chapter VIII, "The Phenomenology of Spirit", translated by Kenley R. Dove, "The Philosophical Forum", Vol. 32, No 4
  • Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit: Selections Translated and Annotated by Howard P. Kainz. The Pennsylvania State University Press. ISBN 0-27101076-2
  • Phenomenology of Spirit selections translated by Andrea Tschemplik and James H. Stam, in Steven M. Cahn, ed., Classics of Western Philosophy (Hackett, 2007)
  • Hegel's Phenomenology of Self-consciousness: text and commentary [A translation of Chapter IV of the Phenomenology, with accompanying essays and a translation of "Hegel's summary of self-consciousness from 'The Phenomenology of Spirit' in the Philosophical Propaedeutic"], by Leo Rauch and David Sherman. State University of New York Press, 1999.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ The following table of contents follows the Pinkard Translation.[7] Some versions of the book's table of contents also group the last four together as a single section on a level with the first two.
  2. ^ "Absolute Knowing," for Hegel, is not to be confused with foundational knowledge, which is oxymoronic in Hegelian philosophy, instead, the Absolute is an endpoint of History, "spirit knowing itself as spirit" [8]

Citations edit

  1. ^ a b Hegel 2018, p. 468, Appendix.
  2. ^ Pinkard 1996, p. 2.
  3. ^ "Hegel to Niethammer; October 13, 1806". marxists.org. Retrieved September 1, 2022.
  4. ^ Pinkard 2001, p. 228–9.
  5. ^ a b Hegel 2018, p. xvi.
  6. ^ Hegel 2015, p. 21.9.
  7. ^ Hegel 2018.
  8. ^ Hegel 2018, p. 467, §807.
  9. ^ Hyppolite 1979, p. 11–12.
  10. ^ Pinkard 1996, p. 8.
  11. ^ Heidegger, Martin, Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit.
  12. ^ Kojève, Alexandre, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, § 1.
  13. ^ Pinkard 1996, p. 2.
  14. ^ Hegel 2018, p. 12, §16.
  15. ^ Harris 1997, p. 30.
  16. ^ Hegel 2018, p. 6, §6.
  17. ^ a b Solomon 1985, p. 233.
  18. ^ Lawler 2014, p. 139.
  19. ^ Rorty 1998, p. 300.
  20. ^ Magee 2010, p. 86.
  21. ^ Kaufmann 1965, p. 148.
  22. ^ Kaufmann 1965, p. 149.
  23. ^ Kaufmann 1965, p. 149.
  24. ^ Kaufmann 1965, p. 152.
  25. ^ Oliver, Kelly (1996). ""Antigone's Ghost: Undoing Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit"". Hypatia. 11 (1): 67–90. doi:10.2979/HYP.1996.11.1.67. JSTOR 3810356.

References edit

Primary edit

  • Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (2018) [1807]. The phenomenology of spirit. Cambridge Hegel Translations. Translated by Pinkard, Terry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781139050494.
  • G. W. Hegel (2015). Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Science of Logic

Secondary edit

Further reading edit

  • Davis, Walter A., 1989. Inwardness and Existence: Subjectivity in/and Hegel, Heidegger, Marx and Freud. University of Wisconsin Press. ISBN 0-29912014-7.
  • Doull, James (2000). "Hegel's "Phenomenology" and Postmodern Thought" (PDF). Animus. 5. ISSN 1209-0689.
  • Doull, James; Jackson, F. L. (2003). "The Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit" (PDF). Animus. 8. ISSN 1209-0689.
  • Heidegger, Martin, 1988. Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. ISBN 0-25332766-0.
  • Kojève, Alexandre. Introduction to the Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the Phenomenology of Spirit. ISBN 0-80149203-3.
  • Taylor, Charles, 1975. Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-52129199-2.
  • Pippin, Robert B., 1989. Hegel's Idealism: the Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. ISBN 0-52137923-7.
  • Forster, Michael N., 1998. Hegel's Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-22625742-8.
  • Harris, H. S., 1995. Hegel: Phenomenology and System. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 0-87220281-X.
  • Kadvany, John, 2001, Imre Lakatos and the Guises of Reason. Duke University Press. ISBN 0-82232659-0.
  • Loewenberg, J., 1965. Hegel's Phenomenology. Dialogues on the Life of Mind. La Salle IL.
  • Pahl, Katrin (2012). Tropes of Transport: Hegel and Emotion. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 9780810165670. OCLC 867784716.
  • Stern, Robert, 2002. Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit London: Routledge. ISBN 0-41521788-1 An introduction for students.
  • Stewart, Jon, 2000. The Unity of Hegel's "Phenomenology of Spirit": A Systematic Interpretation Evanston, Illinois : Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0-810-11693-1
  • Yovel, Yirmiyahu, Hegel's Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit: Translation and Running Commentary, Princeton and Oxford : Princeton University Press, 2005, ISBN 0-69112052-8
  • Westphal, Kenneth R., 2003. Hegel's Epistemology: A Philosophical Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit. Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 0-87220645-9.
  • Westphal, Merold, 1998. History and Truth in Hegel’s Phenomenology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. ISBN 0-25321221-9.
  • Kalkavage, Peter, 2007. The Logic of Desire: An Introduction to Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. Paul Dry Books. ISBN 978-1-589-88037-5.

External links edit

Electronic versions of the English translation of Hegel's Phenomenology of Mind are available at:

  • Marxists Internet Archive: Hegel's Phenomenology of Mind
  • Translating Hegel blog, including a running translation of the Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit
  • Phenomenology of Spirit. Bilingual, with Dictionary
  •   The Phenomenology of Mind public domain audiobook at LibriVox

Detailed audio commentary by an academic:

  • The Bernstein Tapes: Hegel’s Phenomenology of Mind
  • Gregory Sadler, Half Hour Hegel: The Complete Phenomenology of Spirit on YouTube

phenomenology, spirit, german, phänomenologie, geistes, most, widely, discussed, philosophical, work, georg, wilhelm, friedrich, hegel, german, title, translated, either, phenomenology, mind, hegel, described, work, published, 1807, exposition, coming, knowled. The Phenomenology of Spirit German Phanomenologie des Geistes is the most widely discussed philosophical work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel its German title can be translated as either The Phenomenology of Spirit or The Phenomenology of Mind Hegel described the work published in 1807 as an exposition of the coming to be of knowledge 1 This is explicated through a necessary self origination and dissolution of the various shapes of spirit as stations on the way through which spirit becomes pure knowledge 1 The Phenomenology of SpiritTitle page of the first editionAuthorGeorg Wilhelm Friedrich HegelOriginal titlePhanomenologie des GeistesTranslatorJames Black BaillieCountryGermanyLanguageGermanSubjectPhilosophyPublished1807Published in English1910Media typePrintOCLC929308074Dewey Decimal193LC ClassB2928 E5Original textPhanomenologie des Geistes at Project GutenbergTranslationThe Phenomenology of Spirit at University of Illinois Urbana ChampaignThe book marked a significant development in German idealism after Immanuel Kant Focusing on topics in metaphysics epistemology ontology ethics history religion perception consciousness existence logic and political philosophy it is where Hegel develops his concepts of dialectic including the lord bondsman dialectic absolute idealism ethical life and Aufhebung It had a profound effect in Western philosophy and has been praised and blamed for the development of existentialism communism fascism death of God theology and historicist nihilism 2 Contents 1 Historical context 2 Publication history 3 Structure 3 1 Preface 3 2 Introduction 4 Important concepts 4 1 Hegelian dialectic 4 2 Unfolding of species 5 Criticism 6 Referencing 7 English translations 8 See also 9 Notes 10 Citations 11 References 11 1 Primary 11 2 Secondary 12 Further reading 13 External linksHistorical context edit nbsp Hegel and Napoleon in Jena illustration from Harper s Magazine 1895 Hegel was putting the finishing touches to this book as Napoleon engaged Prussian troops on October 14 1806 in the Battle of Jena on a plateau outside the city On the day before the battle Napoleon entered the city of Jena Later that same day Hegel wrote a letter to his friend the theologian Friedrich Immanuel Niethammer I saw the Emperor this world soul riding out of the city on reconnaissance It is indeed a wonderful sensation to see such an individual who concentrated here at a single point astride a horse reaches out over the world and masters it this extraordinary man whom it is impossible not to admire 3 In 2000 Terry Pinkard notes that Hegel s comment to Niethammer is all the more striking since at that point he had already composed the crucial section of the Phenomenology in which he remarked that the Revolution had now officially passed to another land Germany that would complete in thought what the Revolution had only partially accomplished in practice 4 Publication history editThe Phenomenology of Spirit was published with the title System of Science First Part The Phenomenology of Spirit 5 Some copies contained either Science of the Experience of Consciousness or Science of the Phenomenology of Spirit as a subtitle between the Preface and the Introduction 5 On its initial publication the work was identified as Part One of a projected System of Science which would have contained the Science of Logic and both the two real sciences of philosophy the Philosophy of Nature and the Philosophy of Spirit 6 as its second part The Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in its third section Philosophy of Spirit contains a second subsection The Encyclopedia Phenomenology that recounts in briefer and somewhat altered form the major themes of the original Phenomenology Structure editThis section needs expansion with coverage of the content of the book which currently stops at the beginning of ch 1 You can help by adding to it September 2022 The book consists of a Preface written after the rest was completed an Introduction and six major divisions of greatly varying size a A Consciousness is divided into three chapters I Sensuous Certainty II Perceiving and III Force and the Understanding B Self Consciousness contains one chapter IV The Truth of Self Certainty which contains a preliminary discussion of Life and Desire followed by two subsections A Self Sufficiency and Non Self Sufficiency of Self Consciousness Mastery and Servitude and B Freedom of Self Consciousness Stoicism Skepticism and the Unhappy Consciousness This section contains the dialectic of the lord and bondsman which has been essential to the work of philosophers such as Frantz Fanon and Alexandre Kojeve among others C AA Reason contains one chapter V The Certainty and Truth of Reason which is divided into three chapters A Observing Reason B The Actualization of Rational Self Consciousness Through Itself and C Individuality Which to Itself is Real in and for Itself BB Spirit contains one chapter VI Spirit or Geist which is again divided into three chapters A True Spirit Ethical Life B Spirit Alienated from Itself Cultural Formation and C Spirit Certain of Itself Morality CC Religion contains one chapter VII Religion which is divided into three chapters A Natural Religion B The Art Religion and C Revealed Religion DD Absolute Knowing contains one chapter VIII Absolute Knowing b Due to its obscure nature and the many works by Hegel that followed its publication even the structure or core theme of the book itself remains contested First Hegel wrote the book under close time constraints with little chance for revision individual chapters were sent to the publisher before others were written Furthermore according to some readers Hegel may have changed his conception of the project over the course of the writing Secondly the book abounds with both highly technical argument in philosophical language and concrete examples either imaginary or historical of developments by people through different states of consciousness The relationship between these is disputed whether Hegel meant to prove claims about the development of world history or simply used it for illustration whether or not the more conventionally philosophical passages are meant to address specific historical and philosophical positions and so forth Jean Hyppolite famously interpreted the work as a Bildungsroman that follows the progression of its protagonist Spirit through the history of consciousness 9 a characterization that remains prevalent among literary theorists However others contest this literary interpretation and instead read the work as a self conscious reflective account 10 that a society must give of itself in order to understand itself and therefore become reflective Martin Heidegger saw it as the foundation of a larger System of Science that Hegel sought to develop 11 while Alexandre Kojeve saw it as akin to a Platonic Dialogue between the great Systems of history 12 It has also been called a philosophical roller coaster with no more rhyme or reason for any particular transition than that it struck Hegel that such a transition might be fun or illuminating 13 Preface edit The Preface to the text is a preamble to the scientific system and cognition in general Paraphrased on scientific cognition in the table of contents its intent is to offer a rough idea on scientific cognition while at the same time aiming to rid ourselves of a few forms which are only impediments to philosophical cognition 14 As Hegel s own announcement noted it was to explain what seems to him the need of philosophy in its present state also about the presumption and mischief of the philosophical formulas that are currently degrading philosophy and about what is altogether crucial in it and its study 15 It can thus be seen as a heuristic attempt at creating the need of philosophy in the present state and of what philosophy itself in its present state needs This involves an exposition on the content and standpoint of philosophy i e the true shape of truth and the element of its existence that is interspersed with polemics aimed at the presumption and mischief of philosophical formulas and what distinguishes it from that of any previous philosophy especially that of his German Idealist predecessors Kant Fichte and Schelling 16 The Hegelian method consists of actually examining consciousness experience of both itself and of its objects and eliciting the contradictions and dynamic movement that come to light in looking at this experience Hegel uses the phrase pure looking at reines Zusehen to describe this method If consciousness just pays attention to what is actually present in itself and its relation to its objects it will see that what looks like stable and fixed forms dissolve into a dialectical movement Thus philosophy according to Hegel cannot just set out arguments based on a flow of deductive reasoning Rather it must look at actual consciousness as it really exists Hegel also argues strongly against the epistemological emphasis of modern philosophy from Descartes through Kant which he describes as having to first establish the nature and criteria of knowledge prior to actually knowing anything because this would imply an infinite regress a foundationalism that Hegel maintains is self contradictory and impossible Rather he maintains one must examine actual knowing as it occurs in real knowledge processes This is why Hegel uses the term phenomenology Phenomenology comes from the Greek word for to appear and the phenomenology of mind is thus the study of how consciousness or mind appears to itself In Hegel s dynamic system it is the study of the successive appearances of the mind to itself because on examination each one dissolves into a later more comprehensive and integrated form or structure of mind Introduction edit Whereas the Preface was written after Hegel completed the Phenomenology the Introduction was written beforehand In the Introduction Hegel addresses the seeming paradox that people cannot evaluate their faculty of knowledge in terms of its ability to know the Absolute without first having a criterion for what the Absolute is one that is superior to people s knowledge of the Absolute Yet people could only have such a criterion if they already had the improved knowledge that they seek To resolve this paradox Hegel adopts a method whereby the knowing that is characteristic of a particular stage of consciousness is evaluated using the criterion presupposed by consciousness itself At each stage consciousness knows something and at the same time distinguishes the object of that knowledge as different from what it knows Hegel and his readers will simply look on while consciousness compares its actual knowledge of the object what the object is for consciousness with its criterion for what the object must be in itself One would expect that when consciousness finds that its knowledge does not agree with its object consciousness would adjust its knowledge to conform to its object However in a characteristic reversal Hegel explains that under his method the opposite occurs As just noted consciousness criterion for what the object should be is not supplied externally but rather by consciousness itself Therefore like its knowledge the object that consciousness distinguishes from its knowledge is really just the object for consciousness it is the object as envisioned by that stage of consciousness Thus in attempting to resolve the discord between knowledge and object consciousness inevitably alters the object as well In fact the new object for consciousness is developed from consciousness inadequate knowledge of the previous object Thus what consciousness really does is to modify its object to conform to its knowledge Then the cycle begins anew as consciousness attempts to examine what it knows about this new object The reason for this reversal is that for Hegel the separation between consciousness and its object is no more real than consciousness inadequate knowledge of that object The knowledge is inadequate only because of that separation At the end of the process when the object has been fully spiritualized by successive cycles of consciousness experience consciousness will fully know the object and at the same time fully recognize that the object is none other than itself At each stage of development Hegel adds we Hegel and his readers see this development of the new object out of the knowledge of the previous one but the consciousness that they are observing does not As far as it is concerned it experiences the dissolution of its knowledge in a mass of contradictions and the emergence of a new object for knowledge without understanding how that new object has been born Important concepts editHegelian dialectic edit See also Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Dialectics speculation idealism The famous dialectical process of thesis antithesis synthesis has been controversially attributed to Hegel Whoever looks for the stereotype of the allegedly Hegelian dialectic in Hegel s Phenomenology will not find it What one does find on looking at the table of contents is a very decided preference for triadic arrangements But these many triads are not presented or deduced by Hegel as so many theses antitheses and syntheses It is not by means of any dialectic of that sort that his thought moves up the ladder to absolute knowledge Walter Kaufmann 1965 Hegel Reinterpretation Texts and Commentary p 168 Regardless of ongoing academic controversy regarding the significance of a unique dialectical method in Hegel s writings it is true as Professor Howard Kainz 1996 affirms that there are thousands of triads in Hegel s writings Importantly instead of using the famous terminology that originated with Kant and was elaborated by J G Fichte Hegel used an entirely different and more accurate terminology for dialectical or as Hegel called them speculative triads Hegel used two different sets of terms for his triads namely abstract negative concrete especially in his Phenomenology of 1807 as well as immediate mediate concrete especially in his Science of Logic of 1812 depending on the scope of his argumentation When one looks for these terms in his writings one finds so many occurrences that it may become clear that Hegel employed the Kantian using a different terminology Hegel explained his change of terminology The triad terms abstract negative concrete contain an implicit explanation for the flaws in Kant s terms The first term thesis deserves its anti thesis simply because it is too abstract The third term synthesis has completed the triad making it concrete and no longer abstract by absorbing the negative Sometimes Hegel used the terms immediate mediate concrete to describe his triads The most abstract concepts are those that immediately present themselves to human consciousness For example the notion of Pure Being for Hegel was the most abstract concept of all The negative of this infinite abstraction would require an entire Encyclopedia building category by category dialectically until it culminated in the category of Absolute Mind or Spirit since the German word Geist can mean either mind or spirit Unfolding of species edit Further information Spiritual evolution Hegel describes a sequential progression from inanimate objects to animate creatures to human beings This is frequently compared to Charles Darwin s evolutionary theory citation needed However unlike Darwin Hegel thought that organisms had agency in choosing to develop along this progression by collaborating with other organisms 17 18 Hegel understood this to be a linear process of natural development with a predetermined end He viewed this end teleologically as its ultimate purpose and destiny 17 19 20 Criticism editWalter Kaufmann on the question of organisation argued that Hegel s arrangement over half a century before Darwin published his Origin of Species and impressed the idea of evolution on almost everybody s mind was developmental 21 The idea is supremely suggestive but in the end untenable according to Kaufmann The idea of arranging all significant points of view in such a single sequence on a ladder that reaches from the crudest to the most mature is as dazzling to contemplate as it is mad to try seriously to implement it 22 While Kaufmann viewed Hegel as right in seeing that the way a view is reached is not necessarily external to the view itself since on the contrary a knowledge of the development including the prior positions through which a human being passed before adopting a position may make all the difference when it comes to comprehending his or her position some aspects of the conception are still somewhat absurd and some of the details bizarre 23 Kaufmann also remarks that the very table of contents of the Phenomenology may be said to mirror confusion and that faults are so easy to find in it that it is not worth while to adduce heaps of them citation needed However he excuses Hegel since he understands that the author of the Phenomenology finished the book under an immense strain 24 The feminist philosopher Kelly Oliver argues that Hegel s discussion of women in The Phenomenology of Spirit undermines the entirety of the text Oliver points out that for Hegel every element of consciousness must be conceptualizable but that in Hegel s discussion of the family woman is established as in principle unconceptualizable Oliver writes that unlike the master or slave the feminine or woman does not contain the dormant seed of its opposite This means that Hegel s feminine is nothing other than the negation of the masculine and as such it must be excluded from the story of masculine consciousness Thus Oliver argues the Phenomenology of Spirit is a phenomenology of masculine consciousness the universalist pretensions of the text are not achieved as it leaves out the phenomenology of feminine consciousness 25 Referencing editThe work is usually abbreviated as PdG Phanomenologie des Geistes followed by the pagination or paragraph number of the German original edition It is also abbreviated as PS The Phenomenology of Spirit or as PM The Phenomenology of Mind followed by the pagination or paragraph number of the English translation used by each author English translations editG W F Hegel The Phenomenology of Spirit translated by Peter Fuss and John Dobbins University of Notre Dame Press 2019 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel The Phenomenology of Spirit Cambridge Hegel Translations translated by Terry Pinkard Cambridge University Press 2018 ISBN 0 52185579 9 Hegel The Phenomenology of Spirit Translated with introduction and commentary translated by Michael Inwood Oxford University Press 2018 ISBN 0 19879062 7 Phenomenology of Spirit translated by A V Miller with analysis of the text and foreword by J N Findlay Oxford Clarendon Press 1977 ISBN 0 19824597 1 Phenomenology of Mind translated by J B Baillie London Harper amp Row 1967 Baillie 1872 1940 Baillie translation 1910 Hegel s Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit translated with introduction running commentary and notes by Yirmiyahu Yovel Princeton Princeton University Press 2004 ISBN 0 69112052 8 Texts and Commentary Hegel s Preface to His System in a New Translation With Commentary on Facing Pages and Who Thinks Abstractly translated by Walter Kaufmann South Bend University of Notre Dame Press 1977 ISBN 0 26801069 2 Introduction The Phenomenology of Spirit translated by Kenley R Dove in Martin Heidegger Hegel s Concept of Experience New York Harper amp Row 1970 Sense Certainty Chapter I The Phenomenology of Spirit translated by Kenley R Dove The Philosophical Forum Vol 32 No 4 Stoicism Chapter IV B The Phenomenology of Spirit translated by Kenley R Dove The Philosophical Forum Vol 37 No 3 Absolute Knowing Chapter VIII The Phenomenology of Spirit translated by Kenley R Dove The Philosophical Forum Vol 32 No 4 Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit Selections Translated and Annotated by Howard P Kainz The Pennsylvania State University Press ISBN 0 27101076 2 Phenomenology of Spirit selections translated by Andrea Tschemplik and James H Stam in Steven M Cahn ed Classics of Western Philosophy Hackett 2007 Hegel s Phenomenology of Self consciousness text and commentary A translation of Chapter IV of the Phenomenology with accompanying essays and a translation of Hegel s summary of self consciousness from The Phenomenology of Spirit in the Philosophical Propaedeutic by Leo Rauch and David Sherman State University of New York Press 1999 See also editProcess theology Sittlichkeit The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Weltgeist De divisione naturaeNotes edit The following table of contents follows the Pinkard Translation 7 Some versions of the book s table of contents also group the last four together as a single section on a level with the first two Absolute Knowing for Hegel is not to be confused with foundational knowledge which is oxymoronic in Hegelian philosophy instead the Absolute is an endpoint of History spirit knowing itself as spirit 8 Citations edit a b Hegel 2018 p 468 Appendix Pinkard 1996 p 2 Hegel to Niethammer October 13 1806 marxists org Retrieved September 1 2022 Pinkard 2001 p 228 9 a b Hegel 2018 p xvi Hegel 2015 p 21 9 Hegel 2018 Hegel 2018 p 467 807 Hyppolite 1979 p 11 12 Pinkard 1996 p 8 Heidegger Martin Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit Kojeve Alexandre Introduction to the Reading of Hegel 1 Pinkard 1996 p 2 Hegel 2018 p 12 16 Harris 1997 p 30 Hegel 2018 p 6 6 a b Solomon 1985 p 233 Lawler 2014 p 139 Rorty 1998 p 300 Magee 2010 p 86 Kaufmann 1965 p 148 Kaufmann 1965 p 149 Kaufmann 1965 p 149 Kaufmann 1965 p 152 Oliver Kelly 1996 Antigone s Ghost Undoing Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit Hypatia 11 1 67 90 doi 10 2979 HYP 1996 11 1 67 JSTOR 3810356 References editPrimary edit Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 2018 1807 The phenomenology of spirit Cambridge Hegel Translations Translated by Pinkard Terry Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 9781139050494 G W Hegel 2015 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel The Science of LogicSecondary edit Lawler James 2014 Chapter 8 They re Not Just Goddamn Trees Hegel s Philosophy of Nature and the Avatar of Spirit In Dunn G A Irwin W eds Avatar and Philosophy Learning to See The Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series Wiley pp 104 114 ISBN 978 1 118 88676 2 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint date and year link H S Harris 1997 Hegel s Ladder Vol 1 amp 2 Hyppolite Jean 1979 1974 Genesis and Structure of Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit John Heckman Samuel Cherniak trans reprint ed Evanston Illinois Northwestern University Press ISBN 0 81010594 2 Kaufmann Walter Arnold 1965 Hegel Reinterpretation Texts and Commentary New York City Doubleday Magee G A 2010 Evolution The Hegel Dictionary Bloomsbury Philosophy Dictionaries Bloomsbury Academic ISBN 978 1 847 06591 9 Pinkard Terry 1996 Hegel s Phenomenology The Sociality of Reason Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 56834 0 Pinkard Terry 2001 2000 Hegel A Biography Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 00387 2 Rorty R 1998 Truth and Progress Philosophical Papers Philosophical papers Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 55686 6 Russon John Edward 2004 Reading Hegel s Phenomenology Bloomington Indiana Indiana University Press ISBN 978 0 253 21692 2 Schopenhauer Arthur 1974 Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real Appendix Parerga and Paralipomena Volume 1 Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN 0 19824508 4 Solomon R C 1985 In the Spirit of Hegel Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 195 36512 2 Further reading editDavis Walter A 1989 Inwardness and Existence Subjectivity in and Hegel Heidegger Marx and Freud University of Wisconsin Press ISBN 0 29912014 7 Doull James 2000 Hegel s Phenomenology and Postmodern Thought PDF Animus 5 ISSN 1209 0689 Doull James Jackson F L 2003 The Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit PDF Animus 8 ISSN 1209 0689 Heidegger Martin 1988 Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit Bloomington Indiana University Press ISBN 0 25332766 0 Kojeve Alexandre Introduction to the Reading of Hegel Lectures on the Phenomenology of Spirit ISBN 0 80149203 3 Taylor Charles 1975 Hegel Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 52129199 2 Pippin Robert B 1989 Hegel s Idealism the Satisfactions of Self Consciousness Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1989 ISBN 0 52137923 7 Forster Michael N 1998 Hegel s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit University of Chicago Press ISBN 0 22625742 8 Harris H S 1995 Hegel Phenomenology and System Indianapolis Hackett ISBN 0 87220281 X Kadvany John 2001 Imre Lakatos and the Guises of Reason Duke University Press ISBN 0 82232659 0 Loewenberg J 1965 Hegel s Phenomenology Dialogues on the Life of Mind La Salle IL Pahl Katrin 2012 Tropes of Transport Hegel and Emotion Evanston Ill Northwestern University Press ISBN 9780810165670 OCLC 867784716 Stern Robert 2002 Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit London Routledge ISBN 0 41521788 1 An introduction for students Stewart Jon 2000 The Unity of Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit A Systematic Interpretation Evanston Illinois Northwestern University Press ISBN 978 0 810 11693 1 Yovel Yirmiyahu Hegel s Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit Translation and Running Commentary Princeton and Oxford Princeton University Press 2005 ISBN 0 69112052 8 Westphal Kenneth R 2003 Hegel s Epistemology A Philosophical Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit Indianapolis Hackett ISBN 0 87220645 9 Westphal Merold 1998 History and Truth in Hegel s Phenomenology Bloomington Indiana University Press ISBN 0 25321221 9 Kalkavage Peter 2007 The Logic of Desire An Introduction to Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit Paul Dry Books ISBN 978 1 589 88037 5 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to The Phenomenology of Spirit Electronic versions of the English translation of Hegel s Phenomenology of Mind are available at Marxists Internet Archive Hegel s Phenomenology of Mind Translating Hegel blog including a running translation of the Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit Phenomenology of Spirit Bilingual with Dictionary nbsp The Phenomenology of Mind public domain audiobook at LibriVoxDetailed audio commentary by an academic The Bernstein Tapes Hegel s Phenomenology of Mind Gregory Sadler Half Hour Hegel The Complete Phenomenology of Spirit on YouTube Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title The Phenomenology of Spirit amp oldid 1205000596 Self Consciousness, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.