fbpx
Wikipedia

Theory of categories

In ontology, the theory of categories concerns itself with the categories of being: the highest genera or kinds of entities according to Amie Thomasson.[1] To investigate the categories of being, or simply categories, is to determine the most fundamental and the broadest classes of entities.[2] A distinction between such categories, in making the categories or applying them, is called an ontological distinction. Various systems of categories have been proposed, they often include categories for substances, properties, relations, states of affairs or events.[3][4] A representative question within the theory of categories might articulate itself, for example, in a query like, "Are universals prior to particulars?"

Early development edit

The process of abstraction required to discover the number and names of the categories of being has been undertaken by many philosophers since Aristotle and involves the careful inspection of each concept to ensure that there is no higher category or categories under which that concept could be subsumed.[5] The scholars of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries developed Aristotle's ideas.[6] For example, Gilbert of Poitiers divides Aristotle's ten categories into two sets, primary and secondary, according to whether they inhere in the subject or not:

  • Primary categories: Substance, Relation, Quantity and Quality
  • Secondary categories: Place, Time, Situation, Condition, Action, Passion[7]

Furthermore, following Porphyry’s likening of the classificatory hierarchy to a tree, they concluded that the major classes could be subdivided to form subclasses, for example, Substance could be divided into Genus and Species, and Quality could be subdivided into Property and Accident, depending on whether the property was necessary or contingent.[8] An alternative line of development was taken by Plotinus in the second century who by a process of abstraction reduced Aristotle's list of ten categories to five: Substance, Relation, Quantity, Motion and Quality.[9] Plotinus further suggested that the latter three categories of his list, namely Quantity, Motion and Quality correspond to three different kinds of relation and that these three categories could therefore be subsumed under the category of Relation.[10] This was to lead to the supposition that there were only two categories at the top of the hierarchical tree, namely Substance and Relation. Many supposed that relations only exist in the mind. Substance and Relation, then, are closely commutative with Matter and Mind--this is expressed most clearly in the dualism of René Descartes.[11]

Vaisheshika edit

Padārtha is a Sanskrit word for "categories" in Vaisheshika and Nyaya schools of Indian philosophy.[12][13]

Stoic edit

The Stoics held that all beings (ὄντα)—though not all things (τινά)—are material.[14] Besides the existing beings they admitted four incorporeals (asomata): time, place, void, and sayable.[15] They were held to be just 'subsisting' while such a status was denied to universals.[16] Thus, they accepted Anaxagoras's idea (as did Aristotle) that if an object is hot, it is because some part of a universal heat body had entered the object. But, unlike Aristotle, they extended the idea to cover all accidents. Thus, if an object is red, it would be because some part of a universal red body had entered the object.

They held that there were four categories:

  1. Substance (ὑποκείμενον): The primary matter, formless substance, (ousia) that things are made of
  2. Quality (ποιόν): The way matter is organized to form an individual object; in Stoic physics, a physical ingredient (pneuma: air or breath), which informs the matter
  3. Somehow disposed (πως ἔχον): Particular characteristics, not present within the object, such as size, shape, action, and posture
  4. Somehow disposed in relation to something (πρός τί πως ἔχον): Characteristics related to other phenomena, such as the position of an object within time and space relative to other objects

The Stoics outlined that our own actions, thoughts, and reactions are within our control. The opening paragraph of the Enchiridion states the categories as: "Some things in the world are up to us, while others are not. Up to us are our faculties of judgment, motivation, desire, and aversion. In short, whatever is our own doing."[17] These suggest a space that is up to us or within our power. A simple example of the Stoic categories in use is provided by Jacques Brunschwig:

I am a certain lump of matter, and thereby a substance, an existent something (and thus far that is all); I am a man, and this individual man that I am, and thereby qualified by a common quality and a peculiar one; I am sitting or standing, disposed in a certain way; I am the father of my children, the fellow citizen of my fellow citizens, disposed in a certain way in relation to something else.[18]

Aristotle edit

One of Aristotle’s early interests lay in the classification of the natural world, how for example the genus "animal" could be first divided into "two-footed animal" and then into "wingless, two-footed animal".[19] He realised that the distinctions were being made according to the qualities the animal possesses, the quantity of its parts and the kind of motion that it exhibits. To fully complete the proposition "this animal is ..." Aristotle stated in his work on the Categories that there were ten kinds of predicate where ...

"... each signifies either substance or quantity or quality or relation or where or when or being-in-a-position or having or acting or being acted upon".[20]

He realised that predicates could be simple or complex. The simple kinds consist of a subject and a predicate linked together by the "categorical" or inherent type of relation. For Aristotle the more complex kinds were limited to propositions where the predicate is compounded of two of the above categories for example "this is a horse running". More complex kinds of proposition were only discovered after Aristotle by the Stoic, Chrysippus,[21] who developed the "hypothetical" and "disjunctive" types of syllogism and these were terms which were to be developed through the Middle Ages[22] and were to reappear in Kant's system of categories.

Category came into use with Aristotle's essay Categories, in which he discussed univocal and equivocal terms, predication, and ten categories:[23]

  • Substance, essence (ousia) – examples of primary substance: this man, this horse; secondary substance (species, genera): man, horse
  • Quantity (poson, how much), discrete or continuous – examples: two cubits long, number, space, (length of) time.
  • Quality (poion, of what kind or description) – examples: white, black, grammatical, hot, sweet, curved, straight.
  • Relation (pros ti, toward something) – examples: double, half, large, master, knowledge.
  • Place (pou, where) – examples: in a marketplace, in the Lyceum
  • Time (pote, when) – examples: yesterday, last year
  • Position, posture, attitude (keisthai, to lie) – examples: sitting, lying, standing
  • State, condition (echein, to have or be) – examples: shod, armed
  • Action (poiein, to make or do) – examples: to lance, to heat, to cool (something)
  • Affection, passion (paschein, to suffer or undergo) – examples: to be lanced, to be heated, to be cooled

Plotinus edit

Plotinus in writing his Enneads around AD 250 recorded that "Philosophy at a very early age investigated the number and character of the existents ... some found ten, others less ... to some the genera were the first principles, to others only a generic classification of existents."[24] He realised that some categories were reducible to others saying "Why are not Beauty, Goodness and the virtues, Knowledge and Intelligence included among the primary genera?"[25] He concluded that such transcendental categories and even the categories of Aristotle were in some way posterior to the three Eleatic categories first recorded in Plato's dialogue Parmenides and which comprised the following three coupled terms:

  • Unity/Plurality
  • Motion/Stability
  • Identity/Difference[26]

Plotinus called these "the hearth of reality"[27] deriving from them not only the three categories of Quantity, Motion and Quality but also what came to be known as "the three moments of the Neoplatonic world process":

  • First, there existed the "One", and his view that "the origin of things is a contemplation"
  • The Second "is certainly an activity ... a secondary phase ... life streaming from life ... energy running through the universe"
  • The Third is some kind of Intelligence concerning which he wrote "Activity is prior to Intellection ... and self knowledge"[28]

Plotinus likened the three to the centre, the radii and the circumference of a circle, and clearly thought that the principles underlying the categories were the first principles of creation. "From a single root all being multiplies." Similar ideas were to be introduced into Early Christian thought by, for example, Gregory of Nazianzus who summed it up saying "Therefore, Unity, having from all eternity arrived by motion at duality, came to rest in Trinity."[29]

Modern development edit

Kant and Hegel accused the Aristotelian table of categories of being 'rhapsodic', derived arbitrarily and in bulk from experience, without any systematic necessity.[30]

The early modern dualism, which has been described above, of Mind and Matter or Subject and Relation, as reflected in the writings of Descartes underwent a substantial revision in the late 18th century. The first objections to this stance were formulated in the eighteenth century by Immanuel Kant who realised that we can say nothing about Substance except through the relation of the subject to other things.[31]

For example: In the sentence "This is a house" the substantive subject "house" only gains meaning in relation to human use patterns or to other similar houses. The category of Substance disappears from Kant's tables, and under the heading of Relation, Kant lists inter alia the three relationship types of Disjunction, Causality and Inherence.[32] The three older concepts of Quantity, Motion and Quality, as Peirce discovered, could be subsumed under these three broader headings in that Quantity relates to the subject through the relation of Disjunction; Motion relates to the subject through the relation of Causality; and Quality relates to the subject through the relation of Inherence.[33] Sets of three continued to play an important part in the nineteenth century development of the categories, most notably in G.W.F. Hegel's extensive tabulation of categories,[34] and in C.S. Peirce's categories set out in his work on the logic of relations. One of Peirce's contributions was to call the three primary categories Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness[35] which both emphasises their general nature, and avoids the confusion of having the same name for both the category itself and for a concept within that category.

In a separate development, and building on the notion of primary and secondary categories introduced by the Scholastics, Kant introduced the idea that secondary or "derivative" categories could be derived from the primary categories through the combination of one primary category with another.[36] This would result in the formation of three secondary categories: the first, "Community" was an example that Kant gave of such a derivative category; the second, "Modality", introduced by Kant, was a term which Hegel, in developing Kant's dialectical method, showed could also be seen as a derivative category;[37] and the third, "Spirit" or "Will" were terms that Hegel[38] and Schopenhauer[39] were developing separately for use in their own systems. Karl Jaspers in the twentieth century, in his development of existential categories, brought the three together, allowing for differences in terminology, as Substantiality, Communication and Will.[40] This pattern of three primary and three secondary categories was used most notably in the nineteenth century by Peter Mark Roget to form the six headings of his Thesaurus of English Words and Phrases. The headings used were the three objective categories of Abstract Relation, Space (including Motion) and Matter and the three subjective categories of Intellect, Feeling and Volition, and he found that under these six headings all the words of the English language, and hence any possible predicate, could be assembled.[41]

Kant edit

In the Critique of Pure Reason (1781), Immanuel Kant argued that the categories are part of our own mental structure and consist of a set of a priori concepts through which we interpret the world around us.[42] These concepts correspond to twelve logical functions of the understanding which we use to make judgements and there are therefore two tables given in the Critique, one of the Judgements and a corresponding one for the Categories.[43] To give an example, the logical function behind our reasoning from ground to consequence (based on the Hypothetical relation) underlies our understanding of the world in terms of cause and effect (the Causal relation). In each table the number twelve arises from, firstly, an initial division into two: the Mathematical and the Dynamical; a second division of each of these headings into a further two: Quantity and Quality, and Relation and Modality respectively; and, thirdly, each of these then divides into a further three subheadings as follows.

Criticism of Kant's system followed, firstly, by Arthur Schopenhauer, who amongst other things was unhappy with the term "Community", and declared that the tables "do open violence to truth, treating it as nature was treated by old-fashioned gardeners",[44] and secondly, by W.T.Stace who in his book The Philosophy of Hegel suggested that in order to make Kant's structure completely symmetrical a third category would need to be added to the Mathematical and the Dynamical.[45] This, he said, Hegel was to do with his category of concept.

Hegel edit

G.W.F. Hegel in his Science of Logic (1812) attempted to provide a more comprehensive system of categories than Kant and developed a structure that was almost entirely triadic.[46] So important were the categories to Hegel that he claimed the first principle of the world, which he called the "absolute", is "a system of categories ... the categories must be the reason of which the world is a consequent".[47]

Using his own logical method of sublation, later called the Hegelian dialectic, reasoning from the abstract through the negative to the concrete, he arrived at a hierarchy of some 270 categories, as explained by W. T. Stace. The three very highest categories were "logic", "nature" and "spirit". The three highest categories of "logic", however, he called "being", "essence", and "notion" which he explained as follows:

  • Being was differentiated from Nothing by containing with it the concept of the "other", an initial internal division that can be compared with Kant's category of disjunction. Stace called the category of Being the sphere of common sense containing concepts such as consciousness, sensation, quantity, quality and measure.
  • Essence. The "other" separates itself from the "one" by a kind of motion, reflected in Hegel's first synthesis of "becoming". For Stace this category represented the sphere of science containing within it firstly, the thing, its form and properties; secondly, cause, effect and reciprocity, and thirdly, the principles of classification, identity and difference.
  • Notion. Having passed over into the "Other" there is an almost neoplatonic return into a higher unity that in embracing the "one" and the "other" enables them to be considered together through their inherent qualities. This according to Stace is the sphere of philosophy proper where we find not only the three types of logical proposition: disjunctive, hypothetical, and categorical but also the three transcendental concepts of beauty, goodness and truth.[48]

Schopenhauer's category that corresponded with "notion" was that of "idea", which in his Four-Fold Root of Sufficient Reason he complemented with the category of the "will".[49] The title of his major work was The World as Will and Idea. The two other complementary categories, reflecting one of Hegel's initial divisions, were those of Being and Becoming. At around the same time, Goethe was developing his colour theories in the Farbenlehre of 1810, and introduced similar principles of combination and complementation, symbolising, for Goethe, "the primordial relations which belong both to nature and vision".[50] Hegel in his Science of Logic accordingly asks us to see his system not as a tree but as a circle.

Twentieth-century development edit

In the twentieth century the primacy of the division between the subjective and the objective, or between mind and matter, was disputed by, among others, Bertrand Russell[51] and Gilbert Ryle.[52] Philosophy began to move away from the metaphysics of categorisation towards the linguistic problem of trying to differentiate between, and define, the words being used. Ludwig Wittgenstein’s conclusion was that there were no clear definitions which we can give to words and categories but only a "halo" or "corona"[53] of related meanings radiating around each term. Gilbert Ryle thought the problem could be seen in terms of dealing with "a galaxy of ideas" rather than a single idea, and suggested that category mistakes are made when a concept (e.g. "university"), understood as falling under one category (e.g. abstract idea), is used as though it falls under another (e.g. physical object).[54] With regard to the visual analogies being used, Peirce and Lewis,[55] just like Plotinus earlier,[56] likened the terms of propositions to points, and the relations between the terms to lines. Peirce, taking this further, talked of univalent, bivalent and trivalent relations linking predicates to their subject and it is just the number and types of relation linking subject and predicate that determine the category into which a predicate might fall.[57] Primary categories contain concepts where there is one dominant kind of relation to the subject. Secondary categories contain concepts where there are two dominant kinds of relation. Examples of the latter were given by Heidegger in his two propositions "the house is on the creek" where the two dominant relations are spatial location (Disjunction) and cultural association (Inherence), and "the house is eighteenth century" where the two relations are temporal location (Causality) and cultural quality (Inherence).[58] A third example may be inferred from Kant in the proposition "the house is impressive or sublime" where the two relations are spatial or mathematical disposition (Disjunction) and dynamic or motive power (Causality).[59] Both Peirce and Wittgenstein[60] introduced the analogy of colour theory in order to illustrate the shades of meanings of words. Primary categories, like primary colours, are analytical representing the furthest we can go in terms of analysis and abstraction and include Quantity, Motion and Quality. Secondary categories, like secondary colours, are synthetic and include concepts such as Substance, Community and Spirit.

Apart from these, the categorial scheme of Alfred North Whitehead and his Process Philosophy, alongside Nicolai Hartmann and his Critical Realism, remain one of the most detailed and advanced systems in categorial research in metaphysics.

Peirce edit

Charles Sanders Peirce, who had read Kant and Hegel closely, and who also had some knowledge of Aristotle, proposed a system of merely three phenomenological categories: Firstness, Secondness, and Thirdness, which he repeatedly invoked in his subsequent writings. Like Hegel, C.S. Peirce attempted to develop a system of categories from a single indisputable principle, in Peirce's case the notion that in the first instance he could only be aware of his own ideas. "It seems that the true categories of consciousness are first, feeling ... second, a sense of resistance ... and third, synthetic consciousness, or thought".[61] Elsewhere he called the three primary categories: Quality, Reaction and Meaning, and even Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness, saying, "perhaps it is not right to call these categories conceptions, they are so intangible that they are rather tones or tints upon conceptions":[62]

  • Firstness (Quality): "The first is predominant in feeling ... we must think of a quality without parts, e.g. the colour of magenta ... When I say it is a quality I do not mean that it "inheres" in a subject ... The whole content of consciousness is made up of qualities of feeling, as truly as the whole of space is made up of points, or the whole of time by instants".
  • Secondness (Reaction): "This is present even in such a rudimentary fragment of experience as a simple feeling ... an action and reaction between our soul and the stimulus ... The idea of second is predominant in the ideas of causation and of statical force ... the real is active; we acknowledge it by calling it the actual".
  • Thirdness (Meaning): "Thirdness is essentially of a general nature ... ideas in which thirdness predominate [include] the idea of a sign or representation ... Every genuine triadic relation involves meaning ... the idea of meaning is irreducible to those of quality and reaction ... synthetical consciousness is the consciousness of a third or medium".[63]

Although Peirce's three categories correspond to the three concepts of relation given in Kant's tables, the sequence is now reversed and follows that given by Hegel, and indeed before Hegel of the three moments of the world-process given by Plotinus. Later, Peirce gave a mathematical reason for there being three categories in that although monadic, dyadic and triadic nodes are irreducible, every node of a higher valency is reducible to a "compound of triadic relations".[64] Ferdinand de Saussure, who was developing "semiology" in France just as Peirce was developing "semiotics" in the US, likened each term of a proposition to "the centre of a constellation, the point where other coordinate terms, the sum of which is indefinite, converge".[65]

Others edit

Edmund Husserl (1962, 2000) wrote extensively about categorial systems as part of his phenomenology.[66][67]

For Gilbert Ryle (1949), a category (in particular a "category mistake") is an important semantic concept, but one having only loose affinities to an ontological category.[68]

Contemporary systems of categories have been proposed by John G. Bennett (The Dramatic Universe, 4 vols., 1956–65),[69] Wilfrid Sellars (1974),[70] Reinhardt Grossmann (1983, 1992), Johansson (1989), Hoffman and Rosenkrantz (1994), Roderick Chisholm (1996), Barry Smith (ontologist) (2003), and Jonathan Lowe (2006).

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Thomasson, Amie (2019). "Categories". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 4 January 2021.
  2. ^ Mcdaniel, Kris (2010). "A Return to the Analogy of Being". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 81 (3): 688–717. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00378.x. ISSN 1933-1592.
  3. ^ Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (2010). "Ontologie: 4 Aktuelle Debatten und Gesamtentwürfe". . Meiner. Archived from the original on 2021-03-11. Retrieved 2021-01-14.
  4. ^ Borchert, Donald (2006). "Ontology". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
  5. ^ "The Internet Classics Archive | Categories by Aristotle". classics.mit.edu. Retrieved 2022-07-15.
  6. ^ Gracia, Jorge; Newton, Lloyd (2016), "Medieval Theories of the Categories", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-07-15
  7. ^ Reese W.L. Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion (Harvester Press, 1980)
  8. ^ Ibid. cf Evangelou C. Aristotle's Categories and Porphyry (E.J. Brill, Leiden, 1988)
  9. ^ Plotinus Enneads (tr. Mackenna S. & Page B.S., The Medici Society, London, 1930) VI.3.3
  10. ^ Ibid. VI.3.21
  11. ^ Descartes R. The Philosophical Works of Descartes (tr. Haldane E. & Ross G., Dover, New York, 1911) Vol.1
  12. ^ Padārtha, Jonardon Ganeri (2014), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  13. ^ Daniel Henry Holmes Ingalls (1951). Materials for the Study of Navya-nyāya Logic. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 37–39. ISBN 978-81-208-0384-8.
  14. ^ Jacques Brunschwig, Stoic Metaphysics in The Cambridge Companion to Stoics, ed. B. Inwood, Cambridge, 2006, pp. 206–232
  15. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos 10.218. (chronos, topos, kenon, lekton)
  16. ^ Marcelo D. Boeri, The Stoics on Bodies and Incorporeals, The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 54, No. 4 (Jun., 2001), pp. 723–752
  17. ^ Long, Anthony (2018). How to Be Free – An Ancient Guide to the Stoic Life. Princeton, New Jersey, USA: Princeton University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-0691177717.
  18. ^ Jacques Brunschwig "Stoic Metaphysics", p. 228 in Brad Inwood (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 206–232.
  19. ^ Aristotle Metaphysics 1075a
  20. ^ Op.cit.2
  21. ^ Long A. & Sedley D. The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge University Press, 1987) p.206
  22. ^ Peter of Spain (alias John XXI) Summulae Logicales
  23. ^ Categories, translated by E. M. Edghill. For the Greek terms, see The Complete Works of Aristotle in Greek 2010-04-01 at the Wayback Machine (requires DjVu), Book 1 (Organon), Categories Section 4 (DjVu file's page 6).. Archived from the original on 2013-11-02. Retrieved 2010-02-21.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link)
  24. ^ Op.cit.9 VI.1.1
  25. ^ Ibid. VI.2.17
  26. ^ Plato Parmenides (tr. Jowett B., The Dialogues of Plato, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1875) p.162
  27. ^ Op.cit.9 Op.cit.1.4
  28. ^ Ibid. III.8.5
  29. ^ Rawlinson A.E. (ed.) Essays on the Trinity and the Incarnation (Longmans, London, 1928) pp.241-244
  30. ^ Enrico Berti (2008). "Sono ancora utili oggi le categorie di Aristotele?". Nuove Ontologie (in Italian) (39): 57–72. doi:10.4000/estetica.2024.
  31. ^ Op.cit.3 p.87
  32. ^ Ibid. pp.107,113
  33. ^ Op.cit.5 pp.148-179
  34. ^ Stace W.T. The Philosophy of Hegel (Macmillan & Co, London, 1924)
  35. ^ Op.cit.5 pp.148-179
  36. ^ Op.cit.3 p.116
  37. ^ Hegel G.W.F. Logic (tr. Wallace W., Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1975) pp.124ff
  38. ^ Op.cit.15
  39. ^ Schopenhauer A. On the Four-Fold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 1813 (tr. Payne E., La Salle, Illinois, 1974)
  40. ^ Jaspers K. Philosophy 1932 (tr. Ashton E.B., University of Chicago Press, 1970) pp.117ff
  41. ^ Roget P.M. Roget's Thesaurus: The Everyman Edition 1952 (Pan Books, London, 1972)
  42. ^ Op.cit.3 p.87
  43. ^ Ibid. pp.107,113
  44. ^ Schopenhauer A. The World as Will and Representation (tr. Payne A., Dover Publications, London, New York, 1966) p.430
  45. ^ Op.cit.15 p.222
  46. ^ Ibid.
  47. ^ Ibid. pp.63,65
  48. ^ Op.cit.18 pp.124ff
  49. ^ Op.cit.20
  50. ^ Goethe J.W. von, The Theory of Colours (tr. Eastlake C.L., MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1970) p.350
  51. ^ Russell B. The Analysis of Mind (George Allen & Unwin, London, 1921) pp.10,23
  52. ^ Ryle G. The Concept of Mind (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1949) pp.17ff
  53. ^ Wittgenstein L. Philosophical Investigations 1953 (tr. Anscombe G., Blackwell, Oxford, 1978) pp.1x X 4,181
  54. ^ Ryle G. Collected Papers (Hutchinson, London, 1971) Vol.II: Philosophical Arguments 1945, pp.201,202
  55. ^ Op.cit.1 pp.52,82,106
  56. ^ Op.cit.9 VI.5.5
  57. ^ Op.cit.5 Vol I pp.159,176
  58. ^ Op.cit.4 pp.62,187
  59. ^ Kant I. Critique of Judgement 1790 (tr. Meredith J.C., Clarendon Press, Oxford 1952) p.94ff
  60. ^ Op.cit.25 pp.36,152
  61. ^ Op.cit.5 p.200, cf Locke
  62. ^ Ibid. p.179
  63. ^ Ibid. pp.148-179
  64. ^ Ibid. p.176
  65. ^ Saussure F. de,Course in General Linguistics 1916 (tr. Harris R., Duckworth, London, 1983) p.124
  66. ^ Husserl, Edmund (2001). Logical investigations. J. N. Findlay, Michael Dummett, Dermot Moran. London. ISBN 0-415-24189-8. OCLC 45592852.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  67. ^ Husserl, Edmund. Logical investigations. J. N. Findlay, Michael Dummett, Dermot Moran. ISBN 0415241901. OCLC 45592852.
  68. ^ Ryle, Gilbert (2002). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-73296-7. OCLC 49901770.
  69. ^ Bennett, John G. (1987). The dramatic universe. Charles Town, W. Va.: Claymont Communications. ISBN 0-934254-15-X. OCLC 18242460.
  70. ^ deVries, Willem (2021), "Wilfrid Sellars", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-07-15

Selected bibliography edit

  • Aristotle, 1953. . Ross, W. D., trans. Oxford University Press.
  • --------, 2004. Categories, Edghill, E. M., trans. Uni. of Adelaide library.
  • John G. Bennett, 1956–1965. The Dramatic Universe. London, Hodder & Stoughton.
  • Gustav Bergmann, 1992. New Foundations of Ontology. Madison: Uni. of Wisconsin Press.
  • Browning, Douglas, 1990. Ontology and the Practical Arena. Pennsylvania State Uni.
  • Butchvarov, Panayot, 1979. Being qua Being: A Theory of Identity, Existence, and Predication. Indiana Uni. Press.
  • Roderick Chisholm, 1996. A Realistic Theory of Categories. Cambridge Uni. Press.
  • Feibleman, James Kern, 1951. Ontology. The Johns Hopkins Press (reprinted 1968, Greenwood Press, Publishers, New York).
  • Grossmann, Reinhardt, 1983. The Categorial Structure of the World. Indiana Uni. Press.
  • Grossmann, Reinhardt, 1992. The Existence of the World: An Introduction to Ontology. Routledge.
  • Haaparanta, Leila and Koskinen, Heikki J., 2012. Categories of Being: Essays on Metaphysics and Logic. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Hoffman, J., and Rosenkrantz, G. S.,1994. Substance among other Categories. Cambridge Uni. Press.
  • Edmund Husserl, 1962. Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Boyce Gibson, W. R., trans. Collier.
  • ------, 2000. Logical Investigations, 2nd ed. Findlay, J. N., trans. Routledge.
  • Johansson, Ingvar, 1989. Ontological Investigations. Routledge, 2nd ed. Ontos Verlag 2004.
  • Kahn, Charles H., 2009. Essays on Being, Oxford University Press.
  • Immanuel Kant, 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Guyer, Paul, and Wood, A. W., trans. Cambridge Uni. Press.
  • Charles Sanders Peirce, 1992, 1998. The Essential Peirce, vols. 1,2. Houser, Nathan et al., eds. Indiana Uni. Press.
  • Gilbert Ryle, 1949. The Concept of Mind. Uni. of Chicago Press.
  • Wilfrid Sellars, 1974, "Toward a Theory of the Categories" in Essays in Philosophy and Its History. Reidel.
  • Barry Smith, 2003. "Ontology" in Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information. Blackwell.

External links edit

theory, categories, confused, with, category, theory, ontology, theory, categories, concerns, itself, with, categories, being, highest, genera, kinds, entities, according, amie, thomasson, investigate, categories, being, simply, categories, determine, most, fu. Not to be confused with Category theory In ontology the theory of categories concerns itself with the categories of being the highest genera or kinds of entities according to Amie Thomasson 1 To investigate the categories of being or simply categories is to determine the most fundamental and the broadest classes of entities 2 A distinction between such categories in making the categories or applying them is called an ontological distinction Various systems of categories have been proposed they often include categories for substances properties relations states of affairs or events 3 4 A representative question within the theory of categories might articulate itself for example in a query like Are universals prior to particulars Contents 1 Early development 1 1 Vaisheshika 1 2 Stoic 1 3 Aristotle 1 4 Plotinus 2 Modern development 2 1 Kant 2 2 Hegel 3 Twentieth century development 3 1 Peirce 3 2 Others 4 See also 5 References 6 Selected bibliography 7 External linksEarly development editThe process of abstraction required to discover the number and names of the categories of being has been undertaken by many philosophers since Aristotle and involves the careful inspection of each concept to ensure that there is no higher category or categories under which that concept could be subsumed 5 The scholars of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries developed Aristotle s ideas 6 For example Gilbert of Poitiers divides Aristotle s ten categories into two sets primary and secondary according to whether they inhere in the subject or not Primary categories Substance Relation Quantity and Quality Secondary categories Place Time Situation Condition Action Passion 7 Furthermore following Porphyry s likening of the classificatory hierarchy to a tree they concluded that the major classes could be subdivided to form subclasses for example Substance could be divided into Genus and Species and Quality could be subdivided into Property and Accident depending on whether the property was necessary or contingent 8 An alternative line of development was taken by Plotinus in the second century who by a process of abstraction reduced Aristotle s list of ten categories to five Substance Relation Quantity Motion and Quality 9 Plotinus further suggested that the latter three categories of his list namely Quantity Motion and Quality correspond to three different kinds of relation and that these three categories could therefore be subsumed under the category of Relation 10 This was to lead to the supposition that there were only two categories at the top of the hierarchical tree namely Substance and Relation Many supposed that relations only exist in the mind Substance and Relation then are closely commutative with Matter and Mind this is expressed most clearly in the dualism of Rene Descartes 11 Vaisheshika edit These paragraphs are an excerpt from Padartha edit Padartha is a Sanskrit word for categories in Vaisheshika and Nyaya schools of Indian philosophy 12 13 Stoic edit This section is an excerpt from Stoicism Categories edit The Stoics held that all beings ὄnta though not all things tina are material 14 Besides the existing beings they admitted four incorporeals asomata time place void and sayable 15 They were held to be just subsisting while such a status was denied to universals 16 Thus they accepted Anaxagoras s idea as did Aristotle that if an object is hot it is because some part of a universal heat body had entered the object But unlike Aristotle they extended the idea to cover all accidents Thus if an object is red it would be because some part of a universal red body had entered the object They held that there were four categories Substance ὑpokeimenon The primary matter formless substance ousia that things are made of Quality poion The way matter is organized to form an individual object in Stoic physics a physical ingredient pneuma air or breath which informs the matter Somehow disposed pws ἔxon Particular characteristics not present within the object such as size shape action and posture Somehow disposed in relation to something pros ti pws ἔxon Characteristics related to other phenomena such as the position of an object within time and space relative to other objects The Stoics outlined that our own actions thoughts and reactions are within our control The opening paragraph of the Enchiridion states the categories as Some things in the world are up to us while others are not Up to us are our faculties of judgment motivation desire and aversion In short whatever is our own doing 17 These suggest a space that is up to us or within our power A simple example of the Stoic categories in use is provided by Jacques Brunschwig I am a certain lump of matter and thereby a substance an existent something and thus far that is all I am a man and this individual man that I am and thereby qualified by a common quality and a peculiar one I am sitting or standing disposed in a certain way I am the father of my children the fellow citizen of my fellow citizens disposed in a certain way in relation to something else 18 Aristotle edit Main article Categories Aristotle One of Aristotle s early interests lay in the classification of the natural world how for example the genus animal could be first divided into two footed animal and then into wingless two footed animal 19 He realised that the distinctions were being made according to the qualities the animal possesses the quantity of its parts and the kind of motion that it exhibits To fully complete the proposition this animal is Aristotle stated in his work on the Categories that there were ten kinds of predicate where each signifies either substance or quantity or quality or relation or where or when or being in a position or having or acting or being acted upon 20 He realised that predicates could be simple or complex The simple kinds consist of a subject and a predicate linked together by the categorical or inherent type of relation For Aristotle the more complex kinds were limited to propositions where the predicate is compounded of two of the above categories for example this is a horse running More complex kinds of proposition were only discovered after Aristotle by the Stoic Chrysippus 21 who developed the hypothetical and disjunctive types of syllogism and these were terms which were to be developed through the Middle Ages 22 and were to reappear in Kant s system of categories Category came into use with Aristotle s essay Categories in which he discussed univocal and equivocal terms predication and ten categories 23 Substance essence ousia examples of primary substance this man this horse secondary substance species genera man horse Quantity poson how much discrete or continuous examples two cubits long number space length of time Quality poion of what kind or description examples white black grammatical hot sweet curved straight Relation pros ti toward something examples double half large master knowledge Place pou where examples in a marketplace in the Lyceum Time pote when examples yesterday last year Position posture attitude keisthai to lie examples sitting lying standing State condition echein to have or be examples shod armed Action poiein to make or do examples to lance to heat to cool something Affection passion paschein to suffer or undergo examples to be lanced to be heated to be cooled Plotinus edit Plotinus in writing his Enneads around AD 250 recorded that Philosophy at a very early age investigated the number and character of the existents some found ten others less to some the genera were the first principles to others only a generic classification of existents 24 He realised that some categories were reducible to others saying Why are not Beauty Goodness and the virtues Knowledge and Intelligence included among the primary genera 25 He concluded that such transcendental categories and even the categories of Aristotle were in some way posterior to the three Eleatic categories first recorded in Plato s dialogue Parmenides and which comprised the following three coupled terms Unity Plurality Motion Stability Identity Difference 26 Plotinus called these the hearth of reality 27 deriving from them not only the three categories of Quantity Motion and Quality but also what came to be known as the three moments of the Neoplatonic world process First there existed the One and his view that the origin of things is a contemplation The Second is certainly an activity a secondary phase life streaming from life energy running through the universe The Third is some kind of Intelligence concerning which he wrote Activity is prior to Intellection and self knowledge 28 Plotinus likened the three to the centre the radii and the circumference of a circle and clearly thought that the principles underlying the categories were the first principles of creation From a single root all being multiplies Similar ideas were to be introduced into Early Christian thought by for example Gregory of Nazianzus who summed it up saying Therefore Unity having from all eternity arrived by motion at duality came to rest in Trinity 29 Modern development editKant and Hegel accused the Aristotelian table of categories of being rhapsodic derived arbitrarily and in bulk from experience without any systematic necessity 30 The early modern dualism which has been described above of Mind and Matter or Subject and Relation as reflected in the writings of Descartes underwent a substantial revision in the late 18th century The first objections to this stance were formulated in the eighteenth century by Immanuel Kant who realised that we can say nothing about Substance except through the relation of the subject to other things 31 For example In the sentence This is a house the substantive subject house only gains meaning in relation to human use patterns or to other similar houses The category of Substance disappears from Kant s tables and under the heading of Relation Kant lists inter alia the three relationship types of Disjunction Causality and Inherence 32 The three older concepts of Quantity Motion and Quality as Peirce discovered could be subsumed under these three broader headings in that Quantity relates to the subject through the relation of Disjunction Motion relates to the subject through the relation of Causality and Quality relates to the subject through the relation of Inherence 33 Sets of three continued to play an important part in the nineteenth century development of the categories most notably in G W F Hegel s extensive tabulation of categories 34 and in C S Peirce s categories set out in his work on the logic of relations One of Peirce s contributions was to call the three primary categories Firstness Secondness and Thirdness 35 which both emphasises their general nature and avoids the confusion of having the same name for both the category itself and for a concept within that category In a separate development and building on the notion of primary and secondary categories introduced by the Scholastics Kant introduced the idea that secondary or derivative categories could be derived from the primary categories through the combination of one primary category with another 36 This would result in the formation of three secondary categories the first Community was an example that Kant gave of such a derivative category the second Modality introduced by Kant was a term which Hegel in developing Kant s dialectical method showed could also be seen as a derivative category 37 and the third Spirit or Will were terms that Hegel 38 and Schopenhauer 39 were developing separately for use in their own systems Karl Jaspers in the twentieth century in his development of existential categories brought the three together allowing for differences in terminology as Substantiality Communication and Will 40 This pattern of three primary and three secondary categories was used most notably in the nineteenth century by Peter Mark Roget to form the six headings of his Thesaurus of English Words and Phrases The headings used were the three objective categories of Abstract Relation Space including Motion and Matter and the three subjective categories of Intellect Feeling and Volition and he found that under these six headings all the words of the English language and hence any possible predicate could be assembled 41 Kant edit Main article Category Kant In the Critique of Pure Reason 1781 Immanuel Kant argued that the categories are part of our own mental structure and consist of a set of a priori concepts through which we interpret the world around us 42 These concepts correspond to twelve logical functions of the understanding which we use to make judgements and there are therefore two tables given in the Critique one of the Judgements and a corresponding one for the Categories 43 To give an example the logical function behind our reasoning from ground to consequence based on the Hypothetical relation underlies our understanding of the world in terms of cause and effect the Causal relation In each table the number twelve arises from firstly an initial division into two the Mathematical and the Dynamical a second division of each of these headings into a further two Quantity and Quality and Relation and Modality respectively and thirdly each of these then divides into a further three subheadings as follows Table of JudgementsMathematical Quantity Universal Particular Singular Quality Affirmative Negative Infinite Dynamical Relation Categorical Hypothetical Disjunctive Modality Problematic Assertoric Apodictic Table of CategoriesMathematical Quantity Unity Plurality Totality Quality Reality Negation Limitation Dynamical Relation Inherence and Subsistence substance and accident Causality and Dependence cause and effect Community reciprocity Modality Possibility Existence Necessity Criticism of Kant s system followed firstly by Arthur Schopenhauer who amongst other things was unhappy with the term Community and declared that the tables do open violence to truth treating it as nature was treated by old fashioned gardeners 44 and secondly by W T Stace who in his book The Philosophy of Hegel suggested that in order to make Kant s structure completely symmetrical a third category would need to be added to the Mathematical and the Dynamical 45 This he said Hegel was to do with his category of concept Hegel edit G W F Hegel in his Science of Logic 1812 attempted to provide a more comprehensive system of categories than Kant and developed a structure that was almost entirely triadic 46 So important were the categories to Hegel that he claimed the first principle of the world which he called the absolute is a system of categories the categories must be the reason of which the world is a consequent 47 Using his own logical method of sublation later called the Hegelian dialectic reasoning from the abstract through the negative to the concrete he arrived at a hierarchy of some 270 categories as explained by W T Stace The three very highest categories were logic nature and spirit The three highest categories of logic however he called being essence and notion which he explained as follows Being was differentiated from Nothing by containing with it the concept of the other an initial internal division that can be compared with Kant s category of disjunction Stace called the category of Being the sphere of common sense containing concepts such as consciousness sensation quantity quality and measure Essence The other separates itself from the one by a kind of motion reflected in Hegel s first synthesis of becoming For Stace this category represented the sphere of science containing within it firstly the thing its form and properties secondly cause effect and reciprocity and thirdly the principles of classification identity and difference Notion Having passed over into the Other there is an almost neoplatonic return into a higher unity that in embracing the one and the other enables them to be considered together through their inherent qualities This according to Stace is the sphere of philosophy proper where we find not only the three types of logical proposition disjunctive hypothetical and categorical but also the three transcendental concepts of beauty goodness and truth 48 Schopenhauer s category that corresponded with notion was that of idea which in his Four Fold Root of Sufficient Reason he complemented with the category of the will 49 The title of his major work was The World as Will and Idea The two other complementary categories reflecting one of Hegel s initial divisions were those of Being and Becoming At around the same time Goethe was developing his colour theories in the Farbenlehre of 1810 and introduced similar principles of combination and complementation symbolising for Goethe the primordial relations which belong both to nature and vision 50 Hegel in his Science of Logic accordingly asks us to see his system not as a tree but as a circle Twentieth century development editIn the twentieth century the primacy of the division between the subjective and the objective or between mind and matter was disputed by among others Bertrand Russell 51 and Gilbert Ryle 52 Philosophy began to move away from the metaphysics of categorisation towards the linguistic problem of trying to differentiate between and define the words being used Ludwig Wittgenstein s conclusion was that there were no clear definitions which we can give to words and categories but only a halo or corona 53 of related meanings radiating around each term Gilbert Ryle thought the problem could be seen in terms of dealing with a galaxy of ideas rather than a single idea and suggested that category mistakes are made when a concept e g university understood as falling under one category e g abstract idea is used as though it falls under another e g physical object 54 With regard to the visual analogies being used Peirce and Lewis 55 just like Plotinus earlier 56 likened the terms of propositions to points and the relations between the terms to lines Peirce taking this further talked of univalent bivalent and trivalent relations linking predicates to their subject and it is just the number and types of relation linking subject and predicate that determine the category into which a predicate might fall 57 Primary categories contain concepts where there is one dominant kind of relation to the subject Secondary categories contain concepts where there are two dominant kinds of relation Examples of the latter were given by Heidegger in his two propositions the house is on the creek where the two dominant relations are spatial location Disjunction and cultural association Inherence and the house is eighteenth century where the two relations are temporal location Causality and cultural quality Inherence 58 A third example may be inferred from Kant in the proposition the house is impressive or sublime where the two relations are spatial or mathematical disposition Disjunction and dynamic or motive power Causality 59 Both Peirce and Wittgenstein 60 introduced the analogy of colour theory in order to illustrate the shades of meanings of words Primary categories like primary colours are analytical representing the furthest we can go in terms of analysis and abstraction and include Quantity Motion and Quality Secondary categories like secondary colours are synthetic and include concepts such as Substance Community and Spirit Apart from these the categorial scheme of Alfred North Whitehead and his Process Philosophy alongside Nicolai Hartmann and his Critical Realism remain one of the most detailed and advanced systems in categorial research in metaphysics Peirce edit Main article Categories Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce who had read Kant and Hegel closely and who also had some knowledge of Aristotle proposed a system of merely three phenomenological categories Firstness Secondness and Thirdness which he repeatedly invoked in his subsequent writings Like Hegel C S Peirce attempted to develop a system of categories from a single indisputable principle in Peirce s case the notion that in the first instance he could only be aware of his own ideas It seems that the true categories of consciousness are first feeling second a sense of resistance and third synthetic consciousness or thought 61 Elsewhere he called the three primary categories Quality Reaction and Meaning and even Firstness Secondness and Thirdness saying perhaps it is not right to call these categories conceptions they are so intangible that they are rather tones or tints upon conceptions 62 Firstness Quality The first is predominant in feeling we must think of a quality without parts e g the colour of magenta When I say it is a quality I do not mean that it inheres in a subject The whole content of consciousness is made up of qualities of feeling as truly as the whole of space is made up of points or the whole of time by instants Secondness Reaction This is present even in such a rudimentary fragment of experience as a simple feeling an action and reaction between our soul and the stimulus The idea of second is predominant in the ideas of causation and of statical force the real is active we acknowledge it by calling it the actual Thirdness Meaning Thirdness is essentially of a general nature ideas in which thirdness predominate include the idea of a sign or representation Every genuine triadic relation involves meaning the idea of meaning is irreducible to those of quality and reaction synthetical consciousness is the consciousness of a third or medium 63 Although Peirce s three categories correspond to the three concepts of relation given in Kant s tables the sequence is now reversed and follows that given by Hegel and indeed before Hegel of the three moments of the world process given by Plotinus Later Peirce gave a mathematical reason for there being three categories in that although monadic dyadic and triadic nodes are irreducible every node of a higher valency is reducible to a compound of triadic relations 64 Ferdinand de Saussure who was developing semiology in France just as Peirce was developing semiotics in the US likened each term of a proposition to the centre of a constellation the point where other coordinate terms the sum of which is indefinite converge 65 Others edit Edmund Husserl 1962 2000 wrote extensively about categorial systems as part of his phenomenology 66 67 For Gilbert Ryle 1949 a category in particular a category mistake is an important semantic concept but one having only loose affinities to an ontological category 68 Contemporary systems of categories have been proposed by John G Bennett The Dramatic Universe 4 vols 1956 65 69 Wilfrid Sellars 1974 70 Reinhardt Grossmann 1983 1992 Johansson 1989 Hoffman and Rosenkrantz 1994 Roderick Chisholm 1996 Barry Smith ontologist 2003 and Jonathan Lowe 2006 See also editCategories Aristotle Categories Peirce Categories Stoic Category Kant Metaphysics Modal logic Ontology Schema Kant Similarity philosophy References edit Thomasson Amie 2019 Categories The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 4 January 2021 Mcdaniel Kris 2010 A Return to the Analogy of Being Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 3 688 717 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2010 00378 x ISSN 1933 1592 Sandkuhler Hans Jorg 2010 Ontologie 4 Aktuelle Debatten und Gesamtentwurfe Enzyklopadie Philosophie Meiner Archived from the original on 2021 03 11 Retrieved 2021 01 14 Borchert Donald 2006 Ontology Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan The Internet Classics Archive Categories by Aristotle classics mit edu Retrieved 2022 07 15 Gracia Jorge Newton Lloyd 2016 Medieval Theories of the Categories in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2022 07 15 Reese W L Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion Harvester Press 1980 Ibid cf Evangelou C Aristotle s Categories and Porphyry E J Brill Leiden 1988 Plotinus Enneads tr Mackenna S amp Page B S The Medici Society London 1930 VI 3 3 Ibid VI 3 21 Descartes R The Philosophical Works of Descartes tr Haldane E amp Ross G Dover New York 1911 Vol 1 Padartha Jonardon Ganeri 2014 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Daniel Henry Holmes Ingalls 1951 Materials for the Study of Navya nyaya Logic Motilal Banarsidass pp 37 39 ISBN 978 81 208 0384 8 Jacques Brunschwig Stoic Metaphysics in The Cambridge Companion to Stoics ed B Inwood Cambridge 2006 pp 206 232 Sextus Empiricus Adversus Mathematicos 10 218 chronos topos kenon lekton Marcelo D Boeri The Stoics on Bodies and Incorporeals The Review of Metaphysics Vol 54 No 4 Jun 2001 pp 723 752 Long Anthony 2018 How to Be Free An Ancient Guide to the Stoic Life Princeton New Jersey USA Princeton University Press p 3 ISBN 978 0691177717 Jacques Brunschwig Stoic Metaphysics p 228 in Brad Inwood ed The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics Cambridge University Press 2003 pp 206 232 Aristotle Metaphysics 1075a Op cit 2 Long A amp Sedley D The Hellenistic Philosophers Cambridge University Press 1987 p 206 Peter of Spain alias John XXI Summulae Logicales Categories translated by E M Edghill For the Greek terms see The Complete Works of Aristotle in Greek Archived 2010 04 01 at the Wayback Machine requires DjVu Book 1 Organon Categories Section 4 DjVu file s page 6 The Project Gutenberg E text of the Categories by Aristotle Archived from the original on 2013 11 02 Retrieved 2010 02 21 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint bot original URL status unknown link Op cit 9 VI 1 1 Ibid VI 2 17 Plato Parmenides tr Jowett B The Dialogues of Plato Clarendon Press Oxford 1875 p 162 Op cit 9 Op cit 1 4 Ibid III 8 5 Rawlinson A E ed Essays on the Trinity and the Incarnation Longmans London 1928 pp 241 244 Enrico Berti 2008 Sono ancora utili oggi le categorie di Aristotele Nuove Ontologie in Italian 39 57 72 doi 10 4000 estetica 2024 Op cit 3 p 87 Ibid pp 107 113 Op cit 5 pp 148 179 Stace W T The Philosophy of Hegel Macmillan amp Co London 1924 Op cit 5 pp 148 179 Op cit 3 p 116 Hegel G W F Logic tr Wallace W Clarendon Press Oxford 1975 pp 124ff Op cit 15 Schopenhauer A On the Four Fold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 1813 tr Payne E La Salle Illinois 1974 Jaspers K Philosophy 1932 tr Ashton E B University of Chicago Press 1970 pp 117ff Roget P M Roget s Thesaurus The Everyman Edition 1952 Pan Books London 1972 Op cit 3 p 87 Ibid pp 107 113 Schopenhauer A The World as Will and Representation tr Payne A Dover Publications London New York 1966 p 430 Op cit 15 p 222 Ibid Ibid pp 63 65 Op cit 18 pp 124ff Op cit 20 Goethe J W von The Theory of Colours tr Eastlake C L MIT Press Cambridge Mass 1970 p 350 Russell B The Analysis of Mind George Allen amp Unwin London 1921 pp 10 23 Ryle G The Concept of Mind Penguin Harmondsworth 1949 pp 17ff Wittgenstein L Philosophical Investigations 1953 tr Anscombe G Blackwell Oxford 1978 pp 1x X 4 181 Ryle G Collected Papers Hutchinson London 1971 Vol II Philosophical Arguments 1945 pp 201 202 Op cit 1 pp 52 82 106 Op cit 9 VI 5 5 Op cit 5 Vol I pp 159 176 Op cit 4 pp 62 187 Kant I Critique of Judgement 1790 tr Meredith J C Clarendon Press Oxford 1952 p 94ff Op cit 25 pp 36 152 Op cit 5 p 200 cf Locke Ibid p 179 Ibid pp 148 179 Ibid p 176 Saussure F de Course in General Linguistics 1916 tr Harris R Duckworth London 1983 p 124 Husserl Edmund 2001 Logical investigations J N Findlay Michael Dummett Dermot Moran London ISBN 0 415 24189 8 OCLC 45592852 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Husserl Edmund Logical investigations J N Findlay Michael Dummett Dermot Moran ISBN 0415241901 OCLC 45592852 Ryle Gilbert 2002 The concept of mind Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 0 226 73296 7 OCLC 49901770 Bennett John G 1987 The dramatic universe Charles Town W Va Claymont Communications ISBN 0 934254 15 X OCLC 18242460 deVries Willem 2021 Wilfrid Sellars in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2021 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2022 07 15Selected bibliography editAristotle 1953 Metaphysics Ross W D trans Oxford University Press 2004 Categories Edghill E M trans Uni of Adelaide library John G Bennett 1956 1965 The Dramatic Universe London Hodder amp Stoughton Gustav Bergmann 1992 New Foundations of Ontology Madison Uni of Wisconsin Press Browning Douglas 1990 Ontology and the Practical Arena Pennsylvania State Uni Butchvarov Panayot 1979 Being qua Being A Theory of Identity Existence and Predication Indiana Uni Press Roderick Chisholm 1996 A Realistic Theory of Categories Cambridge Uni Press Feibleman James Kern 1951 Ontology The Johns Hopkins Press reprinted 1968 Greenwood Press Publishers New York Grossmann Reinhardt 1983 The Categorial Structure of the World Indiana Uni Press Grossmann Reinhardt 1992 The Existence of the World An Introduction to Ontology Routledge Haaparanta Leila and Koskinen Heikki J 2012 Categories of Being Essays on Metaphysics and Logic New York Oxford University Press Hoffman J and Rosenkrantz G S 1994 Substance among other Categories Cambridge Uni Press Edmund Husserl 1962 Ideas General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology Boyce Gibson W R trans Collier 2000 Logical Investigations 2nd ed Findlay J N trans Routledge Johansson Ingvar 1989 Ontological Investigations Routledge 2nd ed Ontos Verlag 2004 Kahn Charles H 2009 Essays on Being Oxford University Press Immanuel Kant 1998 Critique of Pure Reason Guyer Paul and Wood A W trans Cambridge Uni Press Charles Sanders Peirce 1992 1998 The Essential Peirce vols 1 2 Houser Nathan et al eds Indiana Uni Press Gilbert Ryle 1949 The Concept of Mind Uni of Chicago Press Wilfrid Sellars 1974 Toward a Theory of the Categories in Essays in Philosophy and Its History Reidel Barry Smith 2003 Ontology in Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information Blackwell External links edit nbsp Wikisource has the text of the 1911 Encyclopaedia Britannica article Category Aristotle s Categories at MIT Thomasson Amie Categories In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Ontological Categories and How to Use Them Amie Thomasson Recent Advances in Metaphysics E J Lowe Theory and History of Ontology Raul Corazzon Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Theory of categories amp oldid 1220532482, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.