fbpx
Wikipedia

Categories (Aristotle)

The Categories (Greek Κατηγορίαι Katēgoriai; Latin Categoriae or Praedicamenta) is a text from Aristotle's Organon that enumerates all the possible kinds of things that can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition. They are "perhaps the single most heavily discussed of all Aristotelian notions".[1] The work is brief enough to be divided, not into books as is usual with Aristotle's works, but into fifteen chapters.

The Categories places every object of human apprehension under one of ten categories (known to medieval writers as the Latin term praedicamenta). Aristotle intended them to enumerate everything that can be expressed without composition or structure, thus anything that can be either the subject or the predicate of a proposition.

The text Edit

The antepraedicamenta Edit

The text begins with an explication of what Aristotle means by "synonymous", or univocal words, what is meant by "homonymous", or equivocal words, and what is meant by "paronymous", or denominative (sometimes translated "derivative") words.

It then divides forms of speech as being:

  • Either simple, without composition or structure, such as "man", "horse", "fights".
  • Or having composition and structure, such as "a man argued", "the horse runs".

Only composite forms of speech can be true or false.

Next, he distinguishes between what is said "of" a subject and what is "in" a subject. What is said "of" a subject describes the kind of thing that it is as a whole, answering the question "what is it?" What is said to be "in" a subject is a predicate that does not describe it as a whole but cannot exist without the subject, such as the shape of something. The latter has come to be known as inherence.

Of all the things that exist,

  1. Some may be predicated (that is, said) of a subject, but are in no subject; as man may be predicated of James or John (one may say "John is a man"), but is not in any subject.
  2. Some are in a subject, but cannot be predicated of any subject. Thus, a certain individual point of grammatical knowledge is in me as in a subject, but it cannot be predicated of any subject; because it is an individual thing.
  3. Some are both in a subject and able to be predicated of a subject, for example science, which is in the mind as in a subject, and may be predicated of geometry as of a subject ("Geometry is science").
  4. Last, some things neither can be in any subject nor can be predicated of any subject. These are individual substances, which cannot be predicated, because they are individuals; and cannot be in a subject, because they are substances.

The praedicamenta Edit

Then we come to the categories themselves, whose definitions depend upon these four forms of predication.[2][3] Aristotle's own text in Ackrill's standard English version is:[4][page needed]

Of things said without any combination, each signifies either substance or quantity or qualification or a relative or where or when or being-in-a-position or having or doing or being-affected. To give a rough idea, examples of substance are man, horse; of quantity: four-foot, five-foot; of qualification: white, grammatical; of a relative: double, half, larger; of where: in the Lyceum, in the market-place; of when: yesterday, last-year; of being-in-a-position: is-lying, is-sitting; of having: has-shoes-on, has-armour-on; of doing: cutting, burning; of being-affected: being-cut, being-burned. (1b25-2a4)

A brief explanation (with some alternative translations) is as follows:[5]

  1. Substance (οὐσία, ousia, essence or substance).[6] Substance is that which cannot be predicated of anything or be said to be in anything. Hence, this particular man or that particular tree are substances. Later in the text, Aristotle calls these particulars “primary substances”, to distinguish them from secondary substances, which are universals and can be predicated. Hence, Socrates is a primary substance, while man is a secondary substance. Man is predicated of Socrates, and therefore all that is predicated of man is predicated of Socrates.
  2. Quantity (ποσόν, poson, how much). This is the extension of an object, and may be either discrete or continuous. Further, its parts may or may not have relative positions to each other. All medieval discussions about the nature of the continuum, of the infinite and the infinitely divisible, are a long footnote to this text. It is of great importance in the development of mathematical ideas in the medieval and late Scholastic period. Examples: two cubits long, number, space, (length of) time.
  3. Qualification or quality (ποιόν, poion, of what kind or quality). This determination characterizes the nature of an object. Examples: white, black, grammatical, hot, sweet, curved, straight.
  4. Relative (πρός τι, pros ti, toward something). This is the way one object may be related to another. Examples: double, half, large, master, knowledge.
  5. Where or place (ποῦ, pou, where). Position in relation to the surrounding environment. Examples: in a marketplace, in the Lyceum.
  6. When or time (πότε, pote, when). Position in relation to the course of events. Examples: yesterday, last year.
  7. Relative position, posture, attitude (κεῖσθαι, keisthai, to lie). The examples Aristotle gives indicate that he meant a condition of rest resulting from an action: ‘Lying’, ‘sitting’, ‘standing’. Thus position may be taken as the end point for the corresponding action. The term is, however, frequently taken to mean the relative position of the parts of an object (usually a living object), given that the position of the parts is inseparable from the state of rest implied.
  8. Having or state, condition (ἔχειν, echein, to have or be). The examples Aristotle gives indicate that he meant a condition of rest resulting from an affection (i.e. being acted on): ‘shod’, ‘armed’. The term is, however, frequently taken to mean the determination arising from the physical accoutrements of an object: one's shoes, one's arms, etc. Traditionally, this category is also called a habitus (from Latin habere, to have).
  9. Doing or action (ποιεῖν, poiein, to make or do). The production of change in some other object (or in the agent itself qua other).
  10. Being affected or affection (πάσχειν, paschein, to suffer or undergo). The reception of change from some other object (or from the affected object itself qua other). Aristotle's name paschein for this category has traditionally been translated into English as "affection" and "passion" (also "passivity"), easily misinterpreted to refer only or mainly to affection as an emotion or to emotional passion. For action he gave the example, ‘to lance’, ‘to cauterize’; for affection, ‘to be lanced’, ‘to be cauterized.’ His examples make clear that action is to affection as the active voice is to the passive voice — as acting is to being acted on.

The first four are given a detailed treatment in four chapters, doing and being-affected are discussed briefly in a single small chapter, the remaining four are passed over lightly, as being clear in themselves. Later texts by scholastic philosophers also reflect this disparity of treatment[citation needed].

The postpraedicamenta Edit

In this part,[7] Aristotle sets forth four ways things can be said to be opposed. Next, the work discusses five senses wherein a thing may be considered prior to another, followed by a short section on simultaneity. Six forms of movement are then defined: generation, destruction, increase, diminution, alteration, and change of place. The work ends with a brief consideration of the word 'have' and its usage.

See also Edit

Notes Edit

  1. ^ Smith, Robin 1995 "Logic". In J. Barnes (ed) The Cambridge companion to Aristotle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 55.
  2. ^ The forms of predication were called by the medieval scholastic philosophers the antepraedicamenta.
  3. ^ Note, however, that although Aristotle has apparently distinguished between “being in a subject”, and “being predicated truly of a subject”, in the Prior Analytics these are treated as synonymous. This has led some to suspect that Aristotle was not the author of the Categories[citation needed].
  4. ^ Ackrill (1963).
  5. ^ Thomasson, Amie (2019), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Categories", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-01-17
  6. ^ Note that while Aristotle's use of ousia is ambiguous between 'essence' and substance' there is a close link between them. See his Metaphysics
  7. ^ This part was probably not part of the original text, but added by some unknown editor, Ackrill (1963) pp. 69—70

References Edit

External links Edit

Text and translations Edit

  •   Works related to Categories (Owen) at Wikisource
  •   Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article: Κατηγορίαι
  • 1930 "Oxford" translation by E. M. Edghill
    • Classical Library HTML
    • MIT Classical Archive HTML
  • 1963 translation by J. L. Ackrill, Chapters 1-5 PDF
  •   Categories public domain audiobook at LibriVox

Commentary Edit

categories, aristotle, categories, greek, Κατηγορίαι, katēgoriai, latin, categoriae, praedicamenta, text, from, aristotle, organon, that, enumerates, possible, kinds, things, that, subject, predicate, proposition, they, perhaps, single, most, heavily, discusse. The Categories Greek Kathgoriai Kategoriai Latin Categoriae or Praedicamenta is a text from Aristotle s Organon that enumerates all the possible kinds of things that can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition They are perhaps the single most heavily discussed of all Aristotelian notions 1 The work is brief enough to be divided not into books as is usual with Aristotle s works but into fifteen chapters The Categories places every object of human apprehension under one of ten categories known to medieval writers as the Latin term praedicamenta Aristotle intended them to enumerate everything that can be expressed without composition or structure thus anything that can be either the subject or the predicate of a proposition Contents 1 The text 1 1 The antepraedicamenta 1 2 The praedicamenta 1 3 The postpraedicamenta 2 See also 3 Notes 4 References 5 External links 5 1 Text and translations 5 2 CommentaryThe text EditThe antepraedicamenta Edit The text begins with an explication of what Aristotle means by synonymous or univocal words what is meant by homonymous or equivocal words and what is meant by paronymous or denominative sometimes translated derivative words It then divides forms of speech as being Either simple without composition or structure such as man horse fights Or having composition and structure such as a man argued the horse runs Only composite forms of speech can be true or false Next he distinguishes between what is said of a subject and what is in a subject What is said of a subject describes the kind of thing that it is as a whole answering the question what is it What is said to be in a subject is a predicate that does not describe it as a whole but cannot exist without the subject such as the shape of something The latter has come to be known as inherence Of all the things that exist Some may be predicated that is said of a subject but are in no subject as man may be predicated of James or John one may say John is a man but is not in any subject Some are in a subject but cannot be predicated of any subject Thus a certain individual point of grammatical knowledge is in me as in a subject but it cannot be predicated of any subject because it is an individual thing Some are both in a subject and able to be predicated of a subject for example science which is in the mind as in a subject and may be predicated of geometry as of a subject Geometry is science Last some things neither can be in any subject nor can be predicated of any subject These are individual substances which cannot be predicated because they are individuals and cannot be in a subject because they are substances The praedicamenta Edit Then we come to the categories themselves whose definitions depend upon these four forms of predication 2 3 Aristotle s own text in Ackrill s standard English version is 4 page needed Of things said without any combination each signifies either substance or quantity or qualification or a relative or where or when or being in a position or having or doing or being affected To give a rough idea examples of substance are man horse of quantity four foot five foot of qualification white grammatical of a relative double half larger of where in the Lyceum in the market place of when yesterday last year of being in a position is lying is sitting of having has shoes on has armour on of doing cutting burning of being affected being cut being burned 1b25 2a4 A brief explanation with some alternative translations is as follows 5 Substance oὐsia ousia essence or substance 6 Substance is that which cannot be predicated of anything or be said to be in anything Hence this particular man or that particular tree are substances Later in the text Aristotle calls these particulars primary substances to distinguish them from secondary substances which are universals and can be predicated Hence Socrates is a primary substance while man is a secondary substance Man is predicated of Socrates and therefore all that is predicated of man is predicated of Socrates Quantity poson poson how much This is the extension of an object and may be either discrete or continuous Further its parts may or may not have relative positions to each other All medieval discussions about the nature of the continuum of the infinite and the infinitely divisible are a long footnote to this text It is of great importance in the development of mathematical ideas in the medieval and late Scholastic period Examples two cubits long number space length of time Qualification or quality poion poion of what kind or quality This determination characterizes the nature of an object Examples white black grammatical hot sweet curved straight Relative pros ti pros ti toward something This is the way one object may be related to another Examples double half large master knowledge Where or place poῦ pou where Position in relation to the surrounding environment Examples in a marketplace in the Lyceum When or time pote pote when Position in relation to the course of events Examples yesterday last year Relative position posture attitude keῖs8ai keisthai to lie The examples Aristotle gives indicate that he meant a condition of rest resulting from an action Lying sitting standing Thus position may be taken as the end point for the corresponding action The term is however frequently taken to mean the relative position of the parts of an object usually a living object given that the position of the parts is inseparable from the state of rest implied Having or state condition ἔxein echein to have or be The examples Aristotle gives indicate that he meant a condition of rest resulting from an affection i e being acted on shod armed The term is however frequently taken to mean the determination arising from the physical accoutrements of an object one s shoes one s arms etc Traditionally this category is also called a habitus from Latin habere to have Doing or action poieῖn poiein to make or do The production of change in some other object or in the agent itself qua other Being affected or affection pasxein paschein to suffer or undergo The reception of change from some other object or from the affected object itself qua other Aristotle s name paschein for this category has traditionally been translated into English as affection and passion also passivity easily misinterpreted to refer only or mainly to affection as an emotion or to emotional passion For action he gave the example to lance to cauterize for affection to be lanced to be cauterized His examples make clear that action is to affection as the active voice is to the passive voice as acting is to being acted on The first four are given a detailed treatment in four chapters doing and being affected are discussed briefly in a single small chapter the remaining four are passed over lightly as being clear in themselves Later texts by scholastic philosophers also reflect this disparity of treatment citation needed The postpraedicamenta Edit In this part 7 Aristotle sets forth four ways things can be said to be opposed Next the work discusses five senses wherein a thing may be considered prior to another followed by a short section on simultaneity Six forms of movement are then defined generation destruction increase diminution alteration and change of place The work ends with a brief consideration of the word have and its usage See also EditCategory of being Categorization Category Kant Schema Kant Categories Stoic Category disambiguation Simplicius of CiliciaNotes Edit Smith Robin 1995 Logic In J Barnes ed The Cambridge companion to Aristotle Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 55 The forms of predication were called by the medieval scholastic philosophers the antepraedicamenta Note however that although Aristotle has apparently distinguished between being in a subject and being predicated truly of a subject in the Prior Analytics these are treated as synonymous This has led some to suspect that Aristotle was not the author of the Categories citation needed Ackrill 1963 Thomasson Amie 2019 Zalta Edward N ed Categories The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2020 01 17 Note that while Aristotle s use of ousia is ambiguous between essence and substance there is a close link between them See his Metaphysics This part was probably not part of the original text but added by some unknown editor Ackrill 1963 pp 69 70References EditAckrill John 1963 Aristotle Categories and De Interpretatione pdf Oxford At the Clarendon Press ISBN 0198720866 Aristotle 2014 Categories In Barnes Jonathan ed The Complete Works of Aristotle 2 vols One Volume Digital Edition Transl J L Ackrill Princeton Princeton University Press p 2510 ISBN 9781400852765 Aristotle 1936 L Minio Paluello ed Categoriae et Liber de Interpretatione Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198145073 Aristotle 1938 H P Cooke Hugh Tredennick ed Categories On Interpretation Prior Analytics Loeb Classical Library 325 Cambridge MA Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674993594 External links Edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Categories Aristotle nbsp Wikisource has the text of the 1911 Encyclopaedia Britannica article Category Text and translations Edit nbsp Works related to Categories Owen at Wikisource nbsp Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article Kathgoriai 1930 Oxford translation by E M Edghill Classical Library HTML MIT Classical Archive HTML 1963 translation by J L Ackrill Chapters 1 5 PDF nbsp Categories public domain audiobook at LibriVoxCommentary Edit Aristotle s Theory of Categories with an extensive bibliography Studtmann Paul Aristotle s Categories In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Categories Aristotle amp oldid 1136059121, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.